You are on page 1of 39

THINKING ABOUT THINKING:

Learning How to Learn


Compiled by Marc Imhotep Cray, M.D. [12-13-V1] For Imhotep Virtual Medical School

PDF generated using the open source mwlib toolkit. See http://code.pediapress.com/ for more information. PDF generated at: Wed, 18 Dec 2013 02:08:09 UTC

Contents
Articles
Metacognition Deductive reasoning Inductive reasoning Problem solving Decision-making Logical reasoning 1 8 11 16 25 33

References
Article Sources and Contributors Image Sources, Licenses and Contributors 34 36

Article Licenses
License 37

Metacognition

Metacognition
Metacognition is defined as "cognition about cognition", or "knowing about knowing".[1] It can take many forms; it includes knowledge about when and how to use particular strategies for learning or for problem solving. There are generally two components of metacognition: knowledge about cognition, and regulation of cognition. Metamemory, defined as knowing about memory and mnemonic strategies, is an especially important form of metacognition.[2] Differences in metacognitive processing across cultures have not been widely studied, but could provide better outcomes in cross-cultural learning between teachers and students.[3] Some evolutionary psychologists hypothesize that metacognition is used as a survival tool, which would make metacognition the same across cultures. Writings on metacognition can be traced back at least as far as De Anima and the Parva Naturalia of the Greek philosopher Aristotle.[4]

Definitions
J. H. Flavell first used the word "metacognition".[5] He describes it in these words: Metacognition refers to ones knowledge concerning one's own cognitive processes and products or anything related to them, e.g., the learning-relevant properties of information or data. For example, I am engaging in metacognition if I notice that I am having more trouble learning A than B; [or] if it strikes me that I should double check C before accepting it as fact. J. H. Flavell (1976, p. 232). A. Demetriou, in his theory, one of the neo-Piagetian theories of cognitive development, used the term hypercognition to refer to self-monitoring, self-representation, and self-regulation processes, which are regarded as integral components of the human mind.[6] Moreover, with his colleagues, he showed that these processes participate in general intelligence, together with processing efficiency and reasoning, which have traditionally been considered to compose fluid intelligence. Metacognition also thinks about one's own thinking process such as study skills, memory capabilities, and the ability to monitor learning. This concept needs to be explicitly taught along with content instruction. Metacognitive knowledge is about our own cognitive processes and our understanding of how to regulate those processes to maximize learning. Some types of metacognitive knowledge would include: 1. Person knowledge (declarative knowledge) which is understanding one's own capabilities. 2. Task knowledge (procedural knowledge) which is how one perceives the difficulty of a task which is the content, length, and the type of assignment. 3. Strategic knowledge (conditional knowledge) which is one's own capability for using strategies to learn information. Young children are not particularly good at this; it is not until upper elementary where students start to develop the understanding of strategies that will be effective. Different fields define metacognition very differently. Metacognition variously refers to the study of memory-monitoring and self-regulation, meta-reasoning, consciousness/awareness and auto-consciousness/self-awareness. In practice these capacities are used to regulate one's own cognition, to maximize one's potential to think, learn and to the evaluation of proper ethical/moral rules. In the domain of experimental psychology, an influential distinction in metacognition (proposed by T. O. Nelson & L. Narens) is between Monitoringmaking judgments about the strength of one's memoriesand Controlusing those judgments to guide behavior (in particular, to guide study choices). Dunlosky, Serra, and Baker (2007) covered this distinction in a review of metamemory research that focused on how findings from this domain can be applied to other areas of applied research. In the domain of cognitive neuroscience, metacognitive monitoring and control has been viewed as a function of the prefrontal cortex, which receives (monitors) sensory signals from other cortical regions and through feedback loops

Metacognition implements control (see chapters by Schwartz & Bacon and Shimamura, in Dunlosky & Bjork, 2008). Metacognition is studied in the domain of artificial intelligence and modelling. Therefore, it is the domain of interest of emergent systemics. It has been used, albeit off the original definition, to describe one's own knowledge that we will die. Writers in the 1990s involved with the musical "grunge" scene often used the term to describe self-awareness of mortality.[citation needed]

Components
Metacognition is classified into three components: 1. Metacognitive knowledge (also called metacognitive awareness) is what individuals know about themselves and others as cognitive processors. 2. Metacognitive regulation is the regulation of cognition and learning experiences through a set of activities that help people control their learning. 3. Metacognitive experiences are those experiences that have something to do with the current, on-going cognitive endeavor. Metacognition refers to a level of thinking that involves active control over the process of thinking that is used in learning situations. Planning the way to approach a learning task, monitoring comprehension, and evaluating the progress towards the completion of a task: these are skills that are metacognitive in their nature. Metacognition includes at least three different types of metacognitive awareness when considering metacognitive knowledge: 1. Declarative Knowledge: refers to knowledge about oneself as a learner and about what factors can influence one's performance. Declarative knowledge can also be referred to as "world knowledge". 2. Procedural Knowledge: refers to knowledge about doing things. This type of knowledge is displayed as heuristics and strategies. A high degree of procedural knowledge can allow individuals to perform tasks more automatically. This is achieved through a large variety of strategies that can be accessed more efficiently. 3. Conditional knowledge: refers to knowing when and why to use declarative and procedural knowledge. It allows students to allocate their resources when using strategies. This in turn allows the strategies to become more effective. Similar to metacognitive knowledge, metacognitive regulation or "regulation of cognition" contains three skills that are essential. 1. Planning: refers to the appropriate selection of strategies and the correct allocation of resources that affect task performance. 2. Monitoring: refers to one's awareness of comprehension and task performance 3. Evaluating: refers to appraising the final product of a task and the efficiency at which the task was performed. This can include re-evaluating strategies that were used. Similarly, maintaining motivation to see a task to completion is also a metacognitive skill. The ability to become aware of distracting stimuli both internal and external and sustain effort over time also involves metacognitive or executive functions. The theory that metacognition has a critical role to play in successful learning means it is important that it be demonstrated by both students and teachers. Students who demonstrate a wide range of metacognitive skills perform better on exams and complete work more efficiently. They are self-regulated learners who utilize the "right tool for the job" and modify learning strategies and skills based on their awareness of effectiveness. Individuals with a high level of metacognitive knowledge and skill identify blocks to learning as early as possible and change "tools" or strategies to ensure goal attainment. Swanson (1990) found that metacognitive knowledge can compensate for IQ and lack of prior knowledge when comparing fifth and sixth grade students' problem solving. Students with a high-metacognition were reported to have used fewer strategies, but solved problems more effectively than low-metacognition students, regardless of IQ or prior

Metacognition knowledge. Metacognologists are aware of their own strengths and weaknesses, the nature of the task at hand, and available "tools" or skills. A broader repertoire of "tools" also assists in goal attainment. When "tools" are general, generic, and context independent, they are more likely to be useful in different types of learning situations. Another distinction in metacognition is executive management and strategic knowledge. Executive management processes involve planning, monitoring, evaluating and revising one's own thinking processes and products. Strategic knowledge involves knowing what (factual or declarative knowledge), knowing when and why (conditional or contextual knowledge) and knowing how (procedural or methodological knowledge). Both executive management and strategic knowledge metacognition are needed to self-regulate one's own thinking and learning.[7] Finally, there is no distinction between domain-general and domain-specific metacognitive skills. This means that metacognitive skills are domain-general in nature and there are no specific skills for certain subject areas. The metacognitive skills that are used to review an essay are the same as those that are used to verify an answer to a math question. Metacognitive experience is responsible for creating an identity that matters to an individual. The creation of the identity with meta-cognitive experience is linked to the identity-based motivation (IBM) model. The identity-based motivation model implies that "identities matter because they provide a basis for meaning making and for action."[8] A person decides also if the identity matters in two ways with meta-cognitive experience. First, a current or possible identity is either "part of the self and so worth pursuing"[9] or the individual thinks that the identity is part of their self, yet it is conflicting with more important identities and the individual will decide if the identity is or is not worth pursuing. Second, it also helps an individual decide if an identity should be pursued or abandoned. Usually, abandoning identity has been linked to meta-cognitive difficulty. Based on the identity-based motivation model there are naive theories describing difficulty as a way to continue to pursue an identity. The incremental theory of ability states that if "effort matters then difficulty is likely to be interpreted as meaning that more effort is needed."[10] Here is an example, a woman who loves to play clarinet has come upon a hard piece. She knows that how much effort she puts into learning this piece is beneficial. The piece had difficulty so she knew the effort was needed. The identity the woman wants to pursue is to be a good clarinet player, having a metacognitive experience difficulty pushed her to learn the difficult piece to continue to identify with her identity. The entity theory of ability represents the opposite. This theory states that if "effort does not matter then difficulty is likely to be interpreted as meaning that ability is lacking so effort should be suspended." Based on the example of the woman playing the clarinet, if she did not want to identify herself as a good clarinet player, she would not have put in any effort to learn the difficult piece which is an example of using metacognitive experience difficulty to abandon an identity.[11]

Relation to sapience
Metacognologists believe that the ability to consciously think about thinking is unique to sapient species and indeed is one of the definitions of sapience.[citation needed] There is evidence that rhesus monkeys and apes can make accurate judgments about the strengths of their memories of fact and monitor their own uncertainty, while attempts to demonstrate metacognition in birds have been inconclusive.[12] A 2007 study has provided some evidence for metacognition in rats,[13] but further analysis suggested that they may have been following simple operant conditioning principles, or a behavioral economic model.

Metacognition

Metacognitive strategies
Metacognitive-like processes are especially ubiquitous when it comes to the discussion of self-regulated learning. Being engaged in metacognition is a salient feature of good self-regulated learners[citation needed]. Groups reinforcing collective discussion of metacognition is a salient feature of self-critical and self-regulating social groups[citation needed] . The activities of strategy selection and application include those concerned with an ongoing attempt to plan, check, monitor, select, revise, evaluate, etc. Metacognition is 'stable' in that learners' initial decisions derive from the pertinent fact about their cognition through years of learning experience. Simultaneously, it is also 'situated' in the sense that it depends on learners' familiarity with the task, motivation, emotion, and so forth. Individuals need to regulate their thoughts about the strategy they are using and adjust it based on the situation to which the strategy is being applied. At a professional level, this has led to emphasis on the development of reflective practice, particularly in the education and health-care professions. Recently, the notion has been applied to the study of second language learners in the field of TESOL and applied linguistics in general (e.g., Wenden, 1987; Zhang, 2001, 2010). This new development has been much related to Flavell (1979), where the notion of metacognition is elaborated within a tripartite theoretical framework. Learner metacognition is defined and investigated by examining their person knowledge, task knowledge and strategy knowledge. Wenden (1991) has proposed and used this framework and Zhang (2001) has adopted this approach and investigated second language learners' metacognition or metacognitive knowledge. In addition to exploring the relationships between learner metacognition and performance, researchers are also interested in the effects of metacognitively-oriented strategic instruction on reading comprehension (e.g., Garner, 1994, in first language contexts, and Chamot, 2005; Zhang, 2010). The efforts are aimed at developing learner autonomy, interdependence and self-regulation. Metacognition helps people to perform many cognitive tasks more effectively. Strategies for promoting metacognition include self-questioning (e.g. "What do I already know about this topic? How have I solved problems like this before?"), thinking aloud while performing a task, and making graphic representations (e.g. concept maps, flow charts, semantic webs) of one's thoughts and knowledge. Carr, 2002, argues that the physical act of writing plays a large part in the development of metacognitive skills. Strategy Evaluation matrices (SEM) can help to improve the knowledge of cognition component of metacogntion. The SEM works by identifying the declarative (Column 1), procedural (Column 2) and conditional (Column 3 and 4) knowledge about specific strategies. The SEM can help individuals identify the strength and weaknesses about certain strategies as well as introduce them to new strategies that they can add to their repertoire. A regulation checklist (RC) is a useful strategy for improving the regulation of cognition aspect of ones metacognition. RCs help individuals to implement a sequence of thoughts that allow them to go over their own metacogntion. King (1991) found that fifth-grade students who used a regulation checklist outperformed control students when looking at a variety of questions including written problem solving, asking strategic questions, and elaborating information. Metacognitive strategies training can consist of coaching the students in thinking skills that will allow them to monitor their own learning. Examples of strategies that can be taught to students are word analysis skills, active reading strategies, listening skills, organizational skills and creating mnemonic devices.

Metacognition

Meta-Strategic Knowledge
Meta-Strategic Knowledge (MSK) is a sub-component of metacognition that is defined as general knowledge about higher order thinking strategies. MSK had been defined as general knowledge about the cognitive procedures that are being manipulated. The knowledge involved in MSK consists of making generalizations and drawing rules regarding a thinking strategy and of naming the thinking strategy.[14] The important conscious act of a meta-strategic strategy is the conscious awareness that one is performing a form of higher order thinking. MSK is an awareness of the type of thinking strategies being used in specific instances and it consists of the following abilities: making generalizations and drawing rules regarding a thinking strategy, naming the thinking strategy, explaining when, why and how such a thinking strategy should be used, when it should not be used, what are the disadvantages of not using appropriate strategies, and what task characteristics call for the use of the strategy.[15] MSK deals with the broader picture of the conceptual problem. It creates rules to describe and understand the physical world around the people who utilize these processes called Higher-order thinking. This is the capability of the individual to take apart complex problems in order to understand the components in problem. These are the building blocks to understanding the big picture (of the main problem) through reflection and problem solving.[16] Characteristics of Theory of Mind: Understanding the mind and the "mental world": 1. 2. 3. 4. False beliefs: understanding that a belief is only one of many and can be false. Appearancereality distinctions: something may look one way but may be something else. Visual perspective taking: the views of physical objects differ based on perspective. Introspection: children's awareness and understanding of their own thoughts.

Mental Illness and Metacognition


Sparks of Interest
In the context of mental health, metacognition can be loosely defined as the process that "reinforces one's subjective sense of being a self and allows for becoming aware that some of one's thoughts and feelings are symptoms of an illness.[17]" The interest in metacognition emerged out of a concern for an individuals ability to understand their own mental status compared to others as well as the ability to cope with the source of their distress.[18] These insights into an individual's mental health status can have a profound affect on the over-all prognosis and recovery. Metacognition brings many unique insights into the normal daily functioning of a human being. It also demonstrates that a lack of these insights compromises normal functioning. This leads to less healthy functioning. In the Autism spectrum, there is a profound inability to feel empathy towards the minds of other human beings.[19] In people who identify as alcoholics, there is a belief that the need to control cognitions is an independent predictor of alcohol use over anxiety. Alcohol may be used as a coping strategy for controlling unwanted thoughts and emotions formed by negative perceptions.[20] This is sometimes referred to as self medication.

Implications
Wells and Matthews theory proposes that when faced with an undesired choice, an individual can operate in two distinct modes: object and Metacognitive. Object mode interprets perceived stimuli as truth, where Metacognitive mode understands thoughts as cues that have to be weighted and evaluated. They are not as easily trusted. There are targeted interventions unique of each patient, that gives rise to the belief that assistance in increasing metacognition in people diagnosed with schizophrenia is possible through tailored psychotherapy. With a customized therapy in place clients then have the potential to develop greater ability to engage in complex self-reflection.[21] This can ultimately be pivotal in the patient's recovery process. In the Obsessive Compulsive Disorder spectrum, cognitive formulations have greater attention to intrusive thoughts related to the disorder. "Cognitive Self-Consciousness" are

Metacognition the tendencies to focus attention on thought. Patients with OCD exemplify varying degrees of these intrusive thoughts. Patients also suffering from Generalized Anxiety Disorder also show negative thought process in their cognition.[22] With any metacognition strategy, the general consensus is to believe that they are good. But in all actuality some may be very harmful. Cognitive-Attentional Syndrome (CAS) characterizes a Metacognitive model of emotion disorder. CAS is consistent with the constant with the attention strategy of excessively focusing on the source of a threat. This ultimately develops through the clients own beliefs. Metacognitive therapy attempts to correct this change in the CAS. One of the techniques in this model is called Attention Training (ATT). It was designed to diminish the worry and anxiety by a sense of control and cognitive awareness. Also ATT trains clients to detect threats, test how controllable reality appears to be.[23]

Works of art as metacognitive artifacts


The concept of metacognition has also been applied to reader-response criticism. Narrative works of art, including novels, movies and musical compositions, can be characterized as metacognitive artifacts which are designed by the artist to anticipate and regulate the beliefs and cognitive processes of the recipient, for instance, how and in which order events and their causes and identities are revealed to the reader of a detective story. As Menakhem Perry has pointed out, mere order has profound effects on the aesthetical meaning of a text. Narrative works of art contain a representation of their own ideal reception process. They are something of a tool with which the creators of the work wish to attain certain aesthetical and even moral effects.[24]

References
[1] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] Metcalfe, J., & Shimamura, A. P. (1994). Metacognition: knowing about knowing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Dunlosky, J. & Bjork, R. A. (Eds), Handbook of Metamemory and Memory. Psychology Press: New York. Wright, Frederick. APERA Conference 2008. 14 Apr. 2009. http:/ / www. apera08. nie. edu. sg/ proceedings/ 4. 24. pdf. . > Oxford Psychology Dictionary;metacognition Nisbet, Shucksmith (1984). The Seventh Sense (p6) SCRE Publications Demetriou, A., Efklides, A., & Platsidou, M. (1993). The architecture and dynamics of developing mind: Experiential structuralism as a frame for unifying cognitive developmental theories. Monographs of the Society for Research in Child Development, 58, Serial Number 234. [7] Hartman, 2001. [8] Oyserman & Destin 1011, 2010. [9] Oyserman & Destin 1013, 2010. [10] Oyserman & Destin 1014, 2010. [11] Oyserman, D., & Destin, M. (2010) Identity-Based Motivation: Implications for Intervention. The Counseling Psychologist, 38 (7), 10011043. [12] Metacognition: Known unknowns (http:/ / www. newscientist. com/ channel/ being-human/ mg19225821. 600-metacognition-known-unknowns. html). Issue 2582 of New Scientist magazine, subscribers only. [13] Rats Capable Of Reflecting On Mental Processes (http:/ / www. sciencedaily. com/ releases/ 2007/ 03/ 070308121856. htm) [14] Zohar, A., & Ben David, A. (2009). Paving a clear path in a thick forest: A conceptual analysis of a metacognitive component. Metacognition And Learning, 4(3), 177-195. doi:10.1007/s11409-009-9044-6 [15] Veenman, M. V. J. (2006). Metacognition: Definitions, constituents, and their intricate relation with cognition. Symposium organized by Marcel V. J. Veenman, Anat Zohar, and Anastasia Efklides for the 2nd conference of the EARLI SIG on Metacognition (SIG 16), Cambridge, UK, July 1921. [16] Beer, N., & Moneta, G. B. (2012). Coping and perceived stress as a function of positive metacognitions and positive meta-emotions. Individual Differences Research, 10(2), 105116. [17] Lysaker, P. H., Dimaggio, G., Buck, K. D., Callaway, S. S., Salvatore, G., Carcione, A., & ... Stanghellini, G. (2011). Poor insight in schizophrenia: Links between different forms of metacognition with awareness of symptoms, treatment needed, and consequences of illness. Comprehensive Psychiatry, 52(3), 253-260. [18] Semerari, A., Carcione, A., Dimaggio, G., Falcone, M., Nicol ` o, G., Procacci, M., & Alleva, G. (2003). How to evaluate Metacognitive function in psychotherapy? The Metacognition Assessment Scale and it's applications. Clinical Psychology & Psychotherapy, 10, 238261. [19] Lysaker, P. H., Gumley, A., & Dimaggio, G. (2011). Metacognitive disturbances in people with severe mental illness: Theory, correlates with psychopathology and models of psychotherapy. Psychology And Psychotherapy: Theory, Research And Practice, 84(1), 1-8. doi:10.1111/j.2044-8341.2010.02007.x

Metacognition
[20] Spada, M. M., Zandvoort, M., & Wells, A. (2007). Metacognitions in problem drinkers. Cognitive Therapy And Research, 31(5), 709-716. doi:10.1007/s10608-006-9066-1 [21] Lysaker, P. H., Buck, K. D., Carcione, A., Procacci, M., Salvatore, G., Nicol, G., & Dimaggio, G. (2011). Addressing metacognitive capacity for self-reflection in the psychotherapy for schizophrenia: A conceptual model of the key tasks and processes. Psychology And Psychotherapy: Theory, Research And Practice, 84(1), 58-69. [22] Jacobi, D. M., Calamari, J. E., & Woodard, J. L. (2006). Obsessive-Compulsive Disorder Beliefs, Metacognitive Beliefs and Obsessional Symptoms: Relations between Parent Beliefs and Child Symptoms. Clinical Psychology & Psychotherapy, 13(3), 153-162. doi:10.1002/cpp.485 [23] Wells, A., Fisher, P., Myers, S., Wheatley, J., Patel, T., & Brewin, C. R. (2009). Metacognitive therapy in recurrent and persistent depression: A multiple-baseline study of a new treatment. Cognitive Therapy And Research, 33(3), 291-300. doi:10.1007/s10608-007-9178-2 [24] Lng 1998, p. 88.

Further reading
Annual Editions: Educational Psychology. Guilford: Dushkin Pub., 2002. Print.

Barell, J. (1992), Like an incredibly hard algebra problem: Teaching for metacognition In A. L. Costa, J. A. Bellanca, & R. Fogarty (eds.) If minds matter: A foreword to the future, Volume I (pp.257266). Palatine, IL: IRI/Skylight Publishing, Inc. Beck, G. M. (1998) The Impact of a Prescriptive Curriculum on the Development of Higher Order Thinking Skills in Children, Unpublished MA dissertation, University of Leicester. Brown, A. (1987). Metacognition, executive control, self-control, and other mysterious mechanisms. In F. Weinert and R. Kluwe (Eds.), Metacognition, Motivation, and Understanding (pp.65116). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum. Burke, K. (1999), The Mindful School: How to Assess Authentic Learning (3rd ed.), SkyLight Training and Publishing, USA. ISBN 1-57517-151-1 Carr, S.C. (2002). "Assessing learning processes: Useful information for teachers and students". Intervention in School and Clinic 37: 156162. Chamot, A. (2005). The Cognitive Academic Language Learning Approach (CALLA): An update. In P. Richard-Amato and M. Snow (eds), Academic Success for English Language Learners (pp.87101). White Plains, NY: Longman. Dunlosky, John & Metcalfe, Janet (2009). Metacognition. Los Angeles: SAGE. ISBN 978-1-4129-3972-0 Fisher, Peter & Wells, Adrian (2009). Metacognitive Therapy: Distinctive Features. London: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-43499-7 Flavell, J. H. (1976). Metacognitive aspects of problem solving. In L. B. Resnick (Ed.), The nature of intelligence (pp.231236). Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum Flavell, J. H. (1979). Metacognition and cognitive monitoring: A new area of cognitive-developmental inquiry. American Psychologist, v34 n10 p906-11 Oct 1979. Hartman, H. J. (2001). Metacognition in Learning and Instruction: Theory, Research and Practice. Dordrecht: Kluwer Academic Publishers Niemi, H. (2002). Active learninga cultural change needed in teacher education and schools. Teaching and Teacher Education, 18, 763-780. Rasekh, Z., & Ranjbary, R. (2003). Metacognitive strategy training for vocabulary learning, TESL-EJ, 7(2), 1-18. Shimamura, A. P. (2000). "Toward a cognitive neuroscience of metacognition". Consciousness and Cognition 9: 313323. H. S. Terrace & J. Metcalfe (Eds.), The Missing Link in Cognition: Origins of Self-Reflective Consciousness. New York: Oxford University Press. Metcalfe, J., & Shimamura, A. P. (1994). Metacognition: knowing about knowing. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Papaleontiou-Louca, Eleonora (2008). Metacognition and Theory of Mind. Newcastle: Cambridge Scholars Publishing. ISBN 978-1-84718-578-5 Smith, J. D., Beran, M. J., Couchman, J. J., Coutinho, M. V. C., & Boomer, J. B. (2009). Animal metacognition: Problems and prospects, WWW

(http://psyc.queensu.ca/ccbr/Vol4/SmithABS.html), Comparative Cognition and Behavior Reviews, 4, 4053.

Wenden, A. L. (1987). "Metacognition: An expanded view on the cognitive abilities of L2 learners". Language Learning 37 (4): 573594. Wenden, A. (1991). Learner Strategies for Learner Autonomy. London: Prentice Hall. Zhang, L. J. (2001). Awareness in reading: EFL students' metacognitive knowledge of reading strategies in an input-poor environment. Language Awareness, WWW

(http://www.multilingual-matters.net), 11 (4), 268-288.

Zhang, L. J. (2010). A dynamic metacognitive systems account of Chinese university students knowledge about EFL reading. TESOL Quarterly, WWW

(http://www.ingentaconnect.com/content/tesol/tq/2010/00000044/00000002/art00006), 44

Metacognition
(2), 320-353.

External links

(http://www.personal.kent.edu/~jdunlosk/metacog/) Metacognition (http:/ / www. instructionaldesign. org/ concepts/ metacognition. html) in Learning Concepts (http:/ / www.instructionaldesign.org/concepts/index.html) Metacognition: An Overview (http://www.gse.buffalo.edu/fas/shuell/cep564/Metacog.htm) by Jennifer A. Livingston
The International Association for Metacognition (1997) at Buffalo.edu

Unskilled and Unaware of It: How Difficulties in Recognizing One's Own Incompetence Lead to Inflated Self-Assessments

(http://www.

apa.org/journals/features/psp7761121.pdf) by Justin Kruger, David Dunning, Cornell University, Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology, vol 77, no 6, p 1121-1134, American Psychological Association (1999)

(http://wik.ed.uiuc.edu/index.php/Metacognitive_knowledge) Metacognition in Computation overview (http:/ / www. cs. umd. edu/ ~anderson/ MIC/ ) links Developing Metacognition (http:/ / www. ericdigests. org/ pre-9218/ developing. htm) ERIC Digest Workshops on Metacognition and Self-Regulated Learning in Educational Technology (http:/ / www. andrew. cmu. edu/ user/ iroll/ workshops/index.html)
Metacognitive knowledge

Deductive reasoning
Deductive reasoning, also deductive logic or logical deduction or, informally, "top-down" logic,[1] is the process of reasoning from one or more general statements (premises) to reach a logically certain conclusion. Deductive reasoning links premises with conclusions. If all premises are true, the terms are clear, and the rules of deductive logic are followed, then the conclusion reached is necessarily true. Deductive reasoning (top-down logic) contrasts with inductive reasoning (bottom-up logic) in the following way: In deductive reasoning, a conclusion is reached reductively by applying general rules that hold over the entirety of a closed domain of discourse, narrowing the range under consideration until only the conclusion is left. In inductive reasoning, the conclusion is reached by generalizing or extrapolating from initial information (and so induction can be used even in an open domain, one where there is epistemic uncertainty. (Note, however, that the inductive reasoning mentioned here is not the same as induction used in mathematical proofs - mathematical induction is actually a form of deductive reasoning.)

Simple example
An example of a deductive argument: 1. All men are mortal. 2. Aristotle is a man. 3. Therefore, Aristotle is mortal. The first premise states that all objects classified as "men" have the attribute "mortal". The second premise states that "Aristotle" is classified as a "man" a member of the set "men". The conclusion then states that "Aristotle" must be "mortal" because he inherits this attribute from his classification as a "man".

Deductive reasoning

Law of detachment
The law of detachment (also known as affirming the antecedent and Modus ponens) is the first form of deductive reasoning. A single conditional statement is made, and a hypothesis (P) is stated. The conclusion (Q) is then deduced from the statement and the hypothesis. The most basic form is listed below: 1. PQ (conditional statement) 2. P (hypothesis stated) 3. Q (conclusion deduced) In deductive reasoning, we can conclude Q from P by using the law of detachment.[2] However, if the conclusion (Q) is given instead of the hypothesis (P) then there is no definitive conclusion. The following is an example of an argument using the law of detachment in the form of an if-then statement: 1. If an angle satisfies 90<A<180, then A is an obtuse angle. 2. A=120 3. A is an obtuse angle. Since the measurement of angle A is greater than 90 and less than 180, we can deduce that A is an obtuse angle.

Law of syllogism
The law of syllogism takes two conditional statements and forms a conclusion by combining the hypothesis of one statement with the conclusion of another. Here is the general form: 1. PQ 2. QR 3. Therefore, PR. The following is an example: 1. If Larry is sick, then he will be absent. 2. If Larry is absent, then he will miss his classwork. 3. If Larry is sick, then he will miss his classwork. We deduced the final statement by combining the hypothesis of the first statement with the conclusion of the second statement. We also allow that this could be a false statement. This is an example of the Transitive Property in mathematics. The Transitive Property is many times phrased in this form: 1. A=B 2. B=C 3. Therefore A=C

Law of contrapositive
The law of contrapositive states that, in a conditional, if the conclusion is false, then the hypothesis must be false also. The general form is the following: 1. PQ 2. ~Q 3. Therefore we can conclude ~P. The following are examples: 1. If it is raining, then there are clouds in the sky. 2. There are no clouds in the sky. 3. Thus, it is not raining.

Deductive reasoning

10

Validity and soundness


Deductive arguments are evaluated in terms of their validity and soundness. An argument is valid if it is impossible for its premises to be true while its conclusion is false. In other words, the conclusion must be true if the premises are true. An argument can be valid even though the premises are false. An argument is sound if it is valid and the premises are true. It is possible to have a deductive argument that is logically valid but is not sound. Fallacious arguments often take that form. The following is an example of an argument that is valid, but not sound: 1. Everyone who eats carrots is a quarterback. 2. John eats carrots. 3. Therefore, John is a quarterback. The example's first premise is false there are people who eat carrots and are not quarterbacks but the conclusion must be true, so long as the premises are true (i.e. it is impossible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false). Therefore the argument is valid, but not sound. Generalizations are often used to make invalid arguments, such as "everyone who eats carrots is a quarterback." Not everyone who eats carrots is a quarterback, thus proving the flaw of such arguments. In this example, the first statement uses categorical reasoning, saying that all carrot-eaters are definitely quarterbacks. This theory of deductive reasoning also known as term logic was developed by Aristotle, but was superseded by propositional (sentential) logic and predicate logic. Deductive reasoning can be contrasted with inductive reasoning, in regards to validity and soundness. In cases of inductive reasoning, even though the premises are true and the argument is "valid", it is possible for the conclusion to be false (determined to be false with a counterexample or other means).

Education
Deductive reasoning is generally thought of as a skill that develops without any formal teaching or training. As a result of this belief, deductive reasoning skills are not taught in secondary schools, where students are expected to use reasoning more often and at a higher level. It is in high school, for example, that students have an abrupt introduction to mathematical proofs which rely heavily on deductive reasoning.

References
[1] Deduction & Induction, Research Methods Knowledge Base (http:/ / www. socialresearchmethods. net/ kb/ dedind. php) [2] Guide to Logic (http:/ / www. jgsee. kmutt. ac. th/ exell/ Logic/ Logic12. htm#25)

Further reading
Vincent F. Hendricks, Thought 2 Talk: A Crash Course in Reflection and Expression, New York: Automatic Press / VIP, 2005, ISBN 87-991013-7-8 Philip Johnson-Laird, Ruth M. J. Byrne, Deduction, Psychology Press 1991, ISBN 978-0-86377-149-1jiii Zarefsky, David, Argumentation: The Study of Effective Reasoning Parts I and II, The Teaching Company 2002

External links
Deductive reasoning (http://philpapers.org/browse/deductive-reasoning) at PhilPapers Deductive reasoning (https://inpho.cogs.indiana.edu/idea/636) at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Deductive reasoning (http://www.iep.utm.edu/ded-ind) entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Inductive reasoning

11

Inductive reasoning
Inductive reasoning (as opposed to deductive reasoning) is reasoning in which the premises seek to supply strong evidence for (not absolute proof of) the truth of the conclusion. While the conclusion of a deductive argument is supposed to be certain, the truth of an inductive argument is supposed to be probable, based upon the evidence given.[1]

Definition
The philosophical definition of inductive reasoning is much more nuanced than simple progression from particular/individual instances to broader generalizations. Rather, the premises of an inductive logical argument indicate some degree of support (inductive probability) for the conclusion but do not entail it; that is, they suggest truth but do not ensure it. In this manner, there is the possibility of moving from general statements to individual instances (for example, statistical syllogisms, discussed below). Though many dictionaries define inductive reasoning as reasoning that derives general principles from specific observations, this usage is outdated.

Description
Inductive reasoning is inherently uncertain. It only deals in degrees to which, given the premises, the conclusion is credible according to some theory of evidence, for example a many-valued logic, DempsterShafer theory, or probability theory with rules for inference such as Bayes' rule. Unlike deductive reasoning, it does not rely on universals holding over a closed domain of discourse to draw conclusions, so it can be applicable even in cases of epistemic uncertainty (technical issues with this may arise however; for example, the second axiom of probability is a closed-world assumption).[2] A statistical syllogism is an example of inductive reasoning: 1. Almost all people are taller than 26inches 2. Gareth is a person 3. Therefore, Gareth is almost certainly taller than 26inches As a stronger example: 100% of biological life forms that we know of depend on liquid water to exist. Therefore, if we discover a new biological life form it will probably depend on liquid water to exist. This argument could have been made every time a new biological life form was found, and would have been correct every time; this does not mean it is impossible that in the future a biological life form that does not require water could be discovered. As a result, the argument may be stated less formally as: All biological life forms that we know of depend on liquid water to exist. All biological life probably depends on liquid water to exist.

Inductive reasoning

12

Inductive vs. deductive reasoning


Unlike deductive arguments, inductive reasoning allows for the possibility that the conclusion is false, even if all of the premises are true.[3] Instead of being valid or invalid, inductive arguments are either strong or weak, which describes how probable it is that the conclusion is true. A classical example of an incorrect inductive argument was presented by John Vickers: All of the swans we have seen are white. Therefore, all swans are white. Note that this definition of inductive reasoning excludes mathematical induction, which is a form of deductive reasoning.

Criticism
Inductive reasoning has been criticized by thinkers as diverse as Sextus Empiricus[4] and Karl Popper.[5] The classic philosophical treatment of the problem of induction was given by the Scottish philosopher David Hume. Hume highlighted the fact that our everyday habits of mind depend on drawing uncertain conclusions from our relatively limited experiences rather than on deductively valid arguments. For example, we believe that bread will nourish us because it has done so in the past, despite no guarantee that it will do so. Hume argued that it is impossible to justify inductive reasoning: specifically, that it cannot be justified deductively, so our only option is to justify it inductively. Since this is circular he concluded that it is impossible to justify induction.[6] However, Hume then stated that even if induction were proved unreliable, we would still have to rely on it. So instead of a position of severe skepticism, Hume advocated a practical skepticism based on common sense, where the inevitability of induction is accepted.[7]

Biases
Inductive reasoning is also known as hypothesis construction because any conclusions made are based on current knowledge and predictions.[citation needed] As with deductive arguments, biases can distort the proper application of inductive argument, thereby preventing the reasoner from forming the most logical conclusion based on the clues. Examples of these biases include the availability heuristic, confirmation bias, and the predictable-world bias. The availability heuristic causes the reasoner to depend primarily upon information that is readily available to him/her. People have a tendency to rely on information that is easily accessible in the world around them. For example, in surveys, when people are asked to estimate the percentage of people who died from various causes, most respondents would choose the causes that have been most prevalent in the media such as terrorism, and murders, and airplane accidents rather than causes such as disease and traffic accidents, which have been technically "less accessible" to the individual since they are not emphasized as heavily in the world around him/her. The confirmation bias is based on the natural tendency to confirm rather than to deny a current hypothesis. Research has demonstrated that people are inclined to seek solutions to problems that are more consistent with known hypotheses rather than attempt to refute those hypotheses. Often, in experiments, subjects will ask questions that seek answers that fit established hypotheses, thus confirming these hypotheses. For example, if it is hypothesized that Sally is a sociable individual, subjects will naturally seek to confirm the premise by asking questions that would produce answers confirming that Sally is in fact a sociable individual. The predictable-world bias revolves around the inclination to perceive order where it has not been proved to exist, either at all or at a particular level of abstraction. Gambling, for example, is one of the most popular examples of predictable-world bias. Gamblers often begin to think that they see simple and obvious patterns in the outcomes and, therefore, believe that they are able to predict outcomes based upon what they have witnessed. In reality, however, the outcomes of these games are difficult to predict and highly complex in nature. However, in general, people tend

Inductive reasoning to seek some type of simplistic order to explain or justify their beliefs and experiences, and it is often difficult for them to realise that their perceptions of order may be entirely different from the truth.[8]

13

Types
Generalization
A generalization (more accurately, an inductive generalization) proceeds from a premise about a sample to a conclusion about the population. The proportion Q of the sample has attribute A. Therefore: The proportion Q of the population has attribute A. Example There are 20 ballseither black or whitein an urn. To estimate their respective numbers, you draw a sample of four balls and find that three are black and one is white. A good inductive generalization would be that there are 15 black, and five white, balls in the urn. How much the premises support the conclusion depends upon (a) the number in the sample group, (b) the number in the population, and (c) the degree to which the sample represents the population (which may be achieved by taking a random sample). The hasty generalization and the biased sample are generalization fallacies.

Statistical syllogism
A statistical syllogism proceeds from a generalization to a conclusion about an individual. A proportion Q of population P has attribute A. An individual X is a member of P. Therefore: There is a probability which corresponds to Q that X has A. The proportion in the first premise would be something like "3/5ths of", "all", "few", etc. Two dicto simpliciter fallacies can occur in statistical syllogisms: "accident" and "converse accident".

Simple induction
Simple induction proceeds from a premise about a sample group to a conclusion about another individual. Proportion Q of the known instances of population P has attribute A. Individual I is another member of P. Therefore: There is a probability corresponding to Q that I has A. This is a combination of a generalization and a statistical syllogism, where the conclusion of the generalization is also the first premise of the statistical syllogism.

Inductive reasoning Argument from analogy The process of analogical inference involves noting the shared properties of two or more things, and from this basis inferring that they also share some further property: P and Q are similar in respect to properties a, b, and c. Object P has been observed to have further property x. Therefore, Q probably has property x also. Analogical reasoning is very frequent in common sense, science, philosophy and the humanities, but sometimes it is accepted only as an auxiliary method. A refined approach is case-based reasoning. For more information on inferences by analogy, see Juthe, 2005 [9].

14

Causal inference
A causal inference draws a conclusion about a causal connection based on the conditions of the occurrence of an effect. Premises about the correlation of two things can indicate a causal relationship between them, but additional factors must be confirmed to establish the exact form of the causal relationship.

Prediction
A prediction draws a conclusion about a future individual from a past sample. Proportion Q of observed members of group G have had attribute A. Therefore: There is a probability corresponding to Q that other members of group G will have attribute A when next observed.

Bayesian inference
As a logic of induction rather than a theory of belief, Bayesian inference does not determine which beliefs are a priori rational, but rather determines how we should rationally change the beliefs we have when presented with evidence. We begin by committing to a prior probability for a hypothesis based on logic or previous experience, and when faced with evidence, we adjust the strength of our belief in that hypothesis in a precise manner using Bayesian logic.

Inductive inference
Around 1960, Ray Solomonoff founded the theory of universal inductive inference, the theory of prediction based on observations; for example, predicting the next symbol based upon a given series of symbols. This is a formal inductive framework that combines algorithmic information theory with the Bayesian framework. Universal inductive inference is based on solid philosophical foundations[10] and can be considered as a mathematically formalized Occam's razor. Fundamental ingredients of the theory are the concepts of algorithmic probability and Kolmogorov complexity.

Inductive reasoning

15

References
[1] [2] [3] [4] [5] [6] Copi, I. M., Cohen, C., & Flage, D. E. (2007). Essentials of logic (2nd ed.). Upper Saddle River, NJ: Pearson Education, Inc. Bart Kosko, Fuzziness vs. Probability, International Journal of General Systems, vol. 17, no. 1, pp. 211-240, 1990. John Vickers. The Problem of Induction (http:/ / plato. stanford. edu/ entries/ induction-problem/ ). The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Sextus Empiricus, Outlines Of Pyrrhonism. Trans. R.G. Bury, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, Massachusetts, 1933, p. 283. Karl R. Popper, David W. Miller. "A proof of the impossibility of inductive probability." Nature 302 (1983), 687688. Vickers, John. "The Problem of Induction" (http:/ / plato. stanford. edu/ entries/ induction-problem/ #2HumIndJus) (Section 2). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 21 June 2010 [7] Vickers, John. "The Problem of Induction" (http:/ / plato. stanford. edu/ entries/ induction-problem/ #IndJus) (Section 2.1). Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy. 21 June 2010. [8] Gray, Peter. Psychology. New York: Worth, 2011. Print. [9] http:/ / www. cs. hut. fi/ Opinnot/ T-93. 850/ 2005/ Papers/ juthe2005-analogy. pdf [10] Samuel Rathmanner and Marcus Hutter. A philosophical treatise of universal induction. Entropy, 13(6):10761136, 2011

Further reading
Herms, D. "Logical Basis of Hypothesis Testing in Scientific Research" (http://www.dartmouth.edu/~bio125/ logic.Giere.pdf) (PDF). Kemerling, G. (27 October 2001). "Causal Reasoning" (http://www.philosophypages.com/lg/e14.htm). Holland, J. H.; Holyoak, K. J.; Nisbett, R. E.; Thagard, P. R. (1989). Induction: Processes of Inference, Learning, and Discovery. Cambridge, MA, USA: MIT Press. ISBN0-262-58096-9. Holyoak, K.; Morrison, R. (2005). The Cambridge Handbook of Thinking and Reasoning. New York: Cambridge University Press. ISBN978-0-521-82417-0.

External links
Confirmation and Induction (http://www.iep.utm.edu/conf-ind) entry in the Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy Inductive Logic (http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/logic-inductive) entry in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy Inductive reasoning (http://philpapers.org/browse/induction) at PhilPapers Inductive reasoning (https://inpho.cogs.indiana.edu/taxonomy/2256) at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project Four Varieties of Inductive Argument (http://www.uncg.edu/phi/phi115/induc4.htm) from the Department of Philosophy, University of North Carolina at Greensboro. Properties of Inductive Reasoning (http://faculty.ucmerced.edu/sites/default/files/eheit/files/heit2000. pdf)PDF(166KiB), a psychological review by Evan Heit of the University of California, Merced. The Mind, Limber (http://dudespaper.com/the-mind-limber.html) An article which employs the film The Big Lebowski to explain the value of inductive reasoning.

Problem solving

16

Problem solving
Problem-solving consists of using generic or ad hoc methods, in an orderly manner, for finding solutions to problems. Some of the problem-solving techniques developed and used in artificial intelligence, computer science, engineering, mathematics, medicine, etc. are related to mental problem-solving techniques studied in psychology.

Definition
The term problem-solving is used in many disciplines, sometimes with different perspectives, and often with different terminologies. For instance, it is a mental process in psychology and a computerized process in computer science. Problems can also be classified into two different types (ill-defined and well-defined) from which appropriate solutions are to be made. Ill-defined problems are those that do not have clear goals, solution paths, or expected solution. Well-defined problems have specific goals, clearly defined solution paths, and clear expected solutions. These problems also allow for more initial planning than ill-defined problems.[1] Being able to solve problems sometimes involves dealing with pragmatics (logic) and semantics (interpretation of the problem). The ability to understand what the goal of the problem is and what rules there are key to solving the problem. Sometimes the problem requires some abstract thinking and coming up with a creative solution.

Psychology
In psychology, problem solving refers to a state of desire for reaching a definite 'goal' from a present condition that either is not directly moving toward the goal, is far from it, or needs more complex logic for finding a missing description of conditions or steps toward the goal.[2] In psychology, problem solving is the concluding part of a larger process that also includes problem finding and problem shaping. Considered the most complex of all intellectual functions, problem solving has been defined as a higher-order cognitive process that requires the modulation and control of more routine or fundamental skills. Problem solving has two major domains: mathematical problem solving and personal problem solving where, in the second, some difficulty or barrier is encountered.[3] Further problem solving occurs when moving from a given state to a desired goal state is needed for either living organisms or an artificial intelligence system. While problem solving accompanies the very beginning of human evolution and especially the history of mathematics, the nature of human problem solving processes and methods has been studied by psychologists over the past hundred years. Methods of studying problem solving include introspection, behaviorism, simulation, computer modeling, and experiment. Social psychologists have recently distinguished between independent and interdependent problem-solving (see more [4]).[5]

Clinical Psychology
Simple laboratory-based tasks can be useful in explicating the steps of logic and reasoning that underlie problem solving; however, they usually omit the complexity and emotional valence of "real-world" problems. In clinical psychology, researchers have focused on the role of emotions in problem solving (D'Zurilla & Goldfried, 1971; D'Zurilla & Nezu, 1982), demonstrating that poor emotional control can disrupt focus on the target task and impede problem resolution (Rath, Langenbahn, Simon, Sherr, & Diller, 2004). In this conceptualization, human problem solving consists of two related processes: problem orientation, the motivational/attitudinal/affective approach to problematic situations and problem-solving skills. Working with individuals with frontal lobe injuries, neuropsychologists have discovered that deficits in emotional control and reasoning can be remedied, improving the capacity of injured persons to resolve everyday problems successfully (Rath, Simon, Langenbahn, Sherr, & Diller, 2003).

Problem solving

17

Cognitive Sciences
The early experimental work of the Gestaltists in Germany placed the beginning of problem solving study (e.g., Karl Duncker in 1935 with his book The psychology of productive thinking ). Later this experimental work continued through the 1960s and early 1970s with research conducted on relatively simple (but novel for participants) laboratory tasks of problem solving.[6] Choosing simple novel tasks was based on the clearly defined optimal solutions and their short time for solving, which made possible for the researchers to trace participants' steps in problem-solving process. Researchers' underlying assumption was that simple tasks such as the Tower of Hanoi correspond to the main properties of "real world" problems and thus the characteristic cognitive processes within participants' attempts to solve simple problems are the same for "real world" problems too; simple problems were used for reasons of convenience and with the expectation that thought generalizations to more complex problems would become possible. Perhaps the best-known and most impressive example of this line of research is the work by Allen Newell and Herbert A. Simon. Other experts have shown that the principle of decomposition improves the ability of the problem solver to make good judgment.

Computer Science and Algorithmics


In computer science and in the part of artificial intelligence that deals with algorithms ("algorithmics"), problem solving encompasses a number of techniques known as algorithms, heuristics, root cause analysis, etc. In these disciplines, problem solving is part of a larger process that encompasses problem determination, de-duplication, analysis, diagnosis, repair, etc.

Engineering
Problem solving is used in engineering when products or processes fail, so corrective action can be taken to prevent further failures. It can also be applied to a product or process prior to an actual fail event, i.e., when a potential problem can be predicted and analyzed, and mitigation applied so the problem never actually occurs. Techniques such as Failure Mode Effects Analysis can be used to proactively reduce the likelihood of problems occurring. Forensic engineering is an important technique of failure analysis that involves tracing product defects and flaws. Corrective action can then be taken to prevent further failures. Reverse engineering attempts to discover the original problem-solving logic used in developing a product by taking it apart.

Cognitive Sciences: Two Schools


In cognitive sciences, researchers' realization that problem-solving processes differ across knowledge domains and across levels of expertise (e.g. Sternberg, 1995) and that, consequently, findings obtained in the laboratory cannot necessarily generalize to problem-solving situations outside the laboratory, has led to an emphasis on real-world problem solving since the 1990s. This emphasis has been expressed quite differently in North America and Europe, however. Whereas North American research has typically concentrated on studying problem solving in separate, natural knowledge domains, much of the European research has focused on novel, complex problems, and has been performed with computerized scenarios (see Funke, 1991, for an overview).

Europe
In Europe, two main approaches have surfaced, one initiated by Donald Broadbent (1977; see Berry & Broadbent, 1995) in the United Kingdom and the other one by Dietrich Drner (1975, 1985; see Drner & Wearing, 1995) in Germany. The two approaches share an emphasis on relatively complex, semantically rich, computerized laboratory tasks, constructed to resemble real-life problems. The approaches differ somewhat in their theoretical goals and methodology, however. The tradition initiated by Broadbent emphasizes the distinction between cognitive

Problem solving problem-solving processes that operate under awareness versus outside of awareness, and typically employs mathematically well-defined computerized systems. The tradition initiated by Drner, on the other hand, has an interest in the interplay of the cognitive, motivational, and social components of problem solving, and utilizes very complex computerized scenarios that contain up to 2,000 highly interconnected variables (e.g., Drner, Kreuzig, Reither & Studel's 1983 LOHHAUSEN project; Ringelband, Misiak & Kluwe, 1990). Buchner (1995) describes the two traditions in detail.

18

North America
In North America, initiated by the work of Herbert A. Simon on "learning by doing" in semantically rich domains (e.g. Anzai & Simon, 1979; Bhaskar & Simon, 1977), researchers began to investigate problem solving separately in different natural knowledge domains such as physics, writing, or chess playing thus relinquishing their attempts to extract a global theory of problem solving (e.g. Sternberg & Frensch, 1991). Instead, these researchers have frequently focused on the development of problem solving within a certain domain, that is on the development of expertise (e.g. Anderson, Boyle & Reiser, 1985; Chase & Simon, 1973; Chi, Feltovich & Glaser, 1981). Areas that have attracted rather intensive attention in North America include: Reading (Stanovich & Cunningham, 1991) Writing (Bryson, Bereiter, Scardamalia & Joram, 1991) Calculation (Sokol & McCloskey, 1991) Political decision making (Voss, Wolfe, Lawrence & Engle, 1991) Problem Solving for Business (Cornell, 2010) Managerial problem solving (Wagner, 1991) Lawyers' reasoning (Amsel, Langer & Loutzenhiser, 1991) Mechanical problem solving (Hegarty, 1991) Problem solving in electronics (Lesgold & Lajoie, 1991) Computer skills (Kay, 1991) Game playing (Frensch & Sternberg, 1991) Personal problem solving (Heppner & Krauskopf, 1987) Mathematical problem solving (Plya, 1945; Schoenfeld, 1985) Social problem solving (D'Zurilla & Goldfreid, 1971; D'Zurilla & Nezu, 1982) Problem solving for innovations and inventions: TRIZ (Altshuller, 1973,1990,1995]

Characteristics of Difficult Problems


As elucidated by Dietrich Drner and later expanded upon by Joachim Funke, difficult problems have some typical characteristics that can be summarized as follows: Intransparency (lack of clarity of the situation) commencement opacity continuation opacity Polytely (multiple goals) inexpressiveness opposition transience Complexity (large numbers of items, interrelations and decisions) enumerability connectivity (hierarchy relation, communication relation, allocation relation) heterogeneity

Problem solving Dynamics (time considerations) temporal constraints temporal sensitivity phase effects dynamic unpredictability

19

The resolution of difficult problems requires a direct attack on each of these characteristics that are encountered.[7]

Problem-Solving Strategies
Problem-solving strategies are the steps that one would use to find the problem(s) that are in the way to getting to ones own goal. Some would refer to this as the problem-solving cycle. (Bransford & Stein, 1993) In this cycle one will recognize the problem, define the problem, develop a strategy to fix the problem, organize the knowledge of the problem, figure-out the resources at the user's disposal, monitor one's progress, and evaluate the solution for accuracy. Although called a cycle, one does not have to do each step in order to fix the problem, in fact those who dont are usually better at problem solving.[citation needed] The reason it is called a cycle is that once one is completed with a problem another usually will pop up. Blanchard-Fields (2007) looks at problem solving from one of two facets. The first looking at those problems that only have one solution (like math problems, or fact based questions) which are grounded in psychometric intelligence. The other that is socioemotional in nature and are unpredictable with answers that are constantly changing (like whats your favorite color or what you should get someone for Christmas). The following techniques are usually called problem-solving strategies:[citation needed] Abstraction: solving the problem in a model of the system before applying it to the real system Analogy: using a solution that solves an analogous problem Brainstorming: (especially among groups of people) suggesting a large number of solutions or ideas and combining and developing them until an optimum solution is found Divide and conquer: breaking down a large, complex problem into smaller, solvable problems Hypothesis testing: assuming a possible explanation to the problem and trying to prove (or, in some contexts, disprove) the assumption Lateral thinking: approaching solutions indirectly and creatively Means-ends analysis: choosing an action at each step to move closer to the goal Method of focal objects: synthesizing seemingly non-matching characteristics of different objects into something new Morphological analysis: assessing the output and interactions of an entire system Proof: try to prove that the problem cannot be solved. The point where the proof fails will be the starting point for solving it Reduction: transforming the problem into another problem for which solutions exist Research: employing existing ideas or adapting existing solutions to similar problems Root cause analysis: identifying the cause of a problem Trial-and-error: testing possible solutions until the right one is found

Problem solving

20

Problem-Solving Methodologies
Eight Disciplines Problem Solving GROW model How to Solve It KEPNERandFOURIE Incident and Problem Investigation Kepner-Tregoe Problem Solving and Decision Making PDCA (plandocheckact) Productive Thinking Model RPR Problem Diagnosis (rapid problem resolution) Thinking Dimensions - Problem Solving TRIZ (in Russian: Teoriya Resheniya Izobretatelskikh Zadatch, "theory of solving inventor's problems")

Notes
[1] Schacter, D.L. et al. (2009). Psychology, Second Edition. New York: Worth Publishers. pp. 376 [2] "In each case "where you want to be" is an imagined(or written) state in which you would like to be. We might use the term 'Problem Identification' or analysis in order to figure out exactly what the problem is. After we have found a problem we need to define what the problem is. In other words, a distinguished feature of a problem is that there is a goal to be reached and how you get there is not immediately obvious.", What is a problem? in S. Ian Robertson, Problem solving, Psychology Press, 2001, p.2 [3] Bernd Zimmermann, On mathematical problem solving processes and history of mathematics (http:/ / www. icme-organisers. dk/ tsg18/ S12BerndZimmermann. pdf), University of Jena [4] https:/ / sites. google. com/ site/ markrubinsocialpsychresearch/ -independent-interdependent-problem-solving-scale [5] Rubin, M., Watt, S. E., & Ramelli, M. (2012). Immigrants social integration as a function of approach-avoidance orientation and problem-solving style. International Journal of Intercultural Relations, 36, 498-505. [6] For example Duncker's "X-ray" problem; Ewert & Lambert's "disk" problem in 1932, later known as Tower of Hanoi. [7] resolver.scholarsportal.info.myaccess.library.utoronto.ca/resolve/02692821/v34i0003/221_pstics

References
Altshuller, Genrich (1973). Innovation Algorithm. Worcester, MA: Technical Innovation Center. ISBN0-9640740-2-8. Altshuller, Genrich (1984). Creativity as an Exact Science. New York, NY: Gordon & Breach. ISBN0-677-21230-5. Altshuller, Genrich (1994). And Suddenly the Inventor Appeared. translated by Lev Shulyak. Worcester, MA: Technical Innovation Center. ISBN0-9640740-1-X. Amsel, E., Langer, R., & Loutzenhiser, L. (1991). Do lawyers reason differently from psychologists? A comparative design for studying expertise. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 223-250). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. ISBN 978-0-8058-1783-6 Anderson, J. R., Boyle, C. B., & Reiser, B. J. (1985). "Intelligent tutoring systems". Science 228 (4698): 456462. doi: 10.1126/science.228.4698.456 (http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.228.4698.456). PMID 17746875 (http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/17746875). Anzai, K., & Simon, H. A. (1979) (1979). "The theory of learning by doing". Psychological Review 86 (2): 124140. doi: 10.1037/0033-295X.86.2.124 (http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/0033-295X.86.2.124). PMID 493441 (http://www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/493441). Beckmann, J. F., & Guthke, J. (1995). Complex problem solving, intelligence, and learning ability. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 177-200). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Berry, D. C., & Broadbent, D. E. (1995). Implicit learning in the control of complex systems: A reconsideration of some of the earlier claims. In P.A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European

Problem solving Perspective (pp. 131-150). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Bhaskar, R., & Simon, H. A. (1977). Problem solving in semantically rich domains: An example from engineering thermodynamics. Cognitive Science, 1, 193-215. Brehmer, B. (1995). Feedback delays in dynamic decision making. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 103-130). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Brehmer, B., & Drner, D. (1993). Experiments with computer-simulated microworlds: Escaping both the narrow straits of the laboratory and the deep blue sea of the field study. Computers in Human Behavior, 9, 171-184. Broadbent, D. E. (1977). Levels, hierarchies, and the locus of control. Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 29, 181-201. Bryson, M., Bereiter, C., Scardamalia, M., & Joram, E. (1991). Going beyond the problem as given: Problem solving in expert and novice writers. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 61-84). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Buchner, A. (1995). Theories of complex problem solving. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 27-63). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Buchner, A., Funke, J., & Berry, D. C. (1995). Negative correlations between control performance and verbalizable knowledge: Indicators for implicit learning in process control tasks? Quarterly Journal of Experimental Psychology, 48A, 166-187.

21

Chase, W. G., & Simon, H. A. (1973). Perception in chess. Cognitive Psychology, 4, 55-81. Chi, M. T. H., Feltovich, P. J., & Glaser, R. (1981). "Categorization and representation of physics problems by experts and novices" (http://www.usabilityviews.com/uv007206.html). Cognitive Science 5 (2): 121152. doi: 10.1207/s15516709cog0502_2 (http://dx.doi.org/10.1207/s15516709cog0502_2). Cornell, Kate (2010). WebKaizen, Better Faster Cheaper Problem Solving for Business. Omaha NE: Prevail Digital Publishing. ISBN978-0-9831102-1-7. Drner, D. (1975). Wie Menschen eine Welt verbessern wollten [How people wanted to improve the world]. Bild der Wissenschaft, 12, 48-53. Drner, D. (1985). Verhalten, Denken und Emotionen [Behavior, thinking, and emotions]. In L. H. Eckensberger & E. D. Lantermann (Eds.), Emotion und Reflexivitt (pp. 157-181). Mnchen, Germany: Urban & Schwarzenberg. Drner, D. (1992). ber die Philosophie der Verwendung von Mikrowelten oder "Computerszenarios" in der psychologischen Forschung [On the proper use of microworlds or "computer scenarios" in psychological research]. In H. Gundlach (Ed.), Psychologische Forschung und Methode: Das Versprechen des Experiments. Festschrift fr Werner Traxel (pp. 53-87). Passau, Germany: Passavia-Universitts-Verlag. Drner, D., Kreuzig, H. W., Reither, F., & Studel, T. (Eds.). (1983). Lohhausen. Vom Umgang mit Unbestimmtheit und Komplexitt [Lohhausen. On dealing with uncertainty and complexity]. Bern, Switzerland: Hans Huber. Drner, D., & Wearing, A. (1995). Complex problem solving: Toward a (computer-simulated) theory. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 65-99). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Duncker, K. (1935). Zur Psychologie des produktiven Denkens [The psychology of productive thinking]. Berlin: Julius Springer. Ewert, P. H., & Lambert, J. F. (1932). Part II: The effect of verbal instructions upon the formation of a concept. Journal of General Psychology, 6, 400-411.* DZurilla, T. J., & Goldfried, M. R. (1971). Problem solving and behavior modification. Journal of Abnormal Psychology, 78, 107-126. D'Zurilla, T. J., & Nezu, A. M. (1982). Social problem solving in adults. In P. C. Kendall (Ed.), Advances in cognitive-behavioral research and therapy (Vol. 1, pp.201274). New York: Academic Press. Eyferth, K., Schmann, M., & Widowski, D. (1986). Der Umgang von Psychologen mit Komplexitt [On how psychologists deal with complexity]. Sprache & Kognition, 5, 11-26.

Problem solving Frensch, P. A., & Funke, J. (Eds.). (1995). Complex problem solving: The European Perspective. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Frensch, P. A., & Sternberg, R. J. (1991). Skill-related differences in game playing. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 343-381). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Funke, J. (1991). Solving complex problems: Human identification and control of complex systems. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 185-222). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Funke, J. (1993). Microworlds based on linear equation systems: A new approach to complex problem solving and experimental results. In G. Strube & K.-F. Wender (Eds.), The cognitive psychology of knowledge (pp. 313-330). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers. Funke, J. (1995). Experimental research on complex problem solving. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 243-268). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Funke, U. (1995). Complex problem solving in personnel selection and training. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 219-240). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Goldstein F. C., & Levin H. S. (1987). Disorders of reasoning and problem-solving ability. In M. Meier, A. Benton, & L. Diller (Eds.), Neuropsychological rehabilitation. London: Taylor & Francis Group. Groner, M., Groner, R., & Bischof, W. F. (1983). Approaches to heuristics: A historical review. In R. Groner, M. Groner, & W. F. Bischof (Eds.), Methods of heuristics (pp. 1-18). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Halpern, Diane F. (2002).Thought & Knowledge. Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Worldcat Library Catalog (http://worldcat.org/oclc/50065032&tab=holdings) Hayes, J. (1980). The complete problem solver. Philadelphia: The Franklin Institute Press. Hegarty, M. (1991). Knowledge and processes in mechanical problem solving. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 253-285). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Heppner, P. P., & Krauskopf, C. J. (1987). An information-processing approach to personal problem solving. The Counseling Psychologist, 15, 371-447. Huber, O. (1995). Complex problem solving as multi stage decision making. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 151-173). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Hbner, R. (1989). Methoden zur Analyse und Konstruktion von Aufgaben zur kognitiven Steuerung dynamischer Systeme [Methods for the analysis and construction of dynamic system control tasks]. Zeitschrift fr Experimentelle und Angewandte Psychologie, 36, 221-238. Hunt, E. (1991). Some comments on the study of complexity. In R. J. Sternberg, & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 383-395). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Hussy, W. (1985). Komplexes Problemlsen - Eine Sackgasse? [Complex problem solving - a dead end?]. Zeitschrift fr Experimentelle und Angewandte Psychologie, 32, 55-77. Kay, D. S. (1991). Computer interaction: Debugging the problems. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 317-340). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Kluwe, R. H. (1993). Knowledge and performance in complex problem solving. In G. Strube & K.-F. Wender (Eds.), The cognitive psychology of knowledge (pp. 401-423). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers. Kluwe, R. H. (1995). Single case studies and models of complex problem solving. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 269-291). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

22

Problem solving Kolb, S., Petzing, F., & Stumpf, S. (1992). Komplexes Problemlsen: Bestimmung der Problemlsegte von Probanden mittels Verfahren des Operations Research ? ein interdisziplinrer Ansatz [Complex problem solving: determining the quality of human problem solving by operations research tools - an interdisciplinary approach]. Sprache & Kognition, 11, 115-128. Krems, J. F. (1995). Cognitive flexibility and complex problem solving. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 201-218). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Lesgold, A., & Lajoie, S. (1991). Complex problem solving in electronics. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 287-316). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Mayer, R. E. (1992). Thinking, problem solving, cognition. Second edition. New York: W. H. Freeman and Company. Mller, H. (1993). Komplexes Problemlsen: Reliabilitt und Wissen [Complex problem solving: Reliability and knowledge]. Bonn, Germany: Holos. Newell, A., & Simon, H. A. (1972). Human problem solving. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall. Offord, Paul (2011). RPR: A Problem Diagnosis Method for IT Professionals. Essex, England: Advance Seven Limited. ISBN978-1-4478-4443-3. Paradies, M.W., & Unger, L. W. (2000). TapRooT - The System for Root Cause Analysis, Problem Investigation, and Proactive Improvement. Knoxville, TN: System Improvements. Putz-Osterloh, W. (1993). Strategies for knowledge acquisition and transfer of knowledge in dynamic tasks. In G. Strube & K.-F. Wender (Eds.), The cognitive psychology of knowledge (pp. 331-350). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers. Rath J. F.; Langenbahn D. M.; Simon D.; Sherr R. L.; Fletcher J.; Diller L. (2004). The construct of problem solving in higher level neuropsychological assessment and rehabilitation. Archives of Clinical Neuropsychology, 19, 613-635. doi: 10.1016/j.acn.2003.08.006 (http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/j.acn.2003.08.006) Rath, J. F.; Simon, D.; Langenbahn, D. M.; Sherr, R. L.; Diller, L. (2003). Group treatment of problem-solving deficits in outpatients with traumatic brain injury: A randomised outcome study. Neuropsychological Rehabilitation, 13, 461-488. Riefer, D.M., & Batchelder, W.H. (1988). Multinomial modeling and the measurement of cognitive processes. Psychological Review, 95, 318-339. Ringelband, O. J., Misiak, C., & Kluwe, R. H. (1990). Mental models and strategies in the control of a complex system. In D. Ackermann, & M. J. Tauber (Eds.), Mental models and human-computer interaction (Vol. 1, pp. 151-164). Amsterdam: Elsevier Science Publishers. Schaub, H. (1993). Modellierung der Handlungsorganisation. Bern, Switzerland: Hans Huber. Schoenfeld, A. H. (1985). Mathematical Problem Solving. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Sokol, S. M., & McCloskey, M. (1991). Cognitive mechanisms in calculation. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 85-116). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Stanovich, K. E., & Cunningham, A. E. (1991). Reading as constrained reasoning. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 3-60). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Sternberg, R. J. (1995). Conceptions of expertise in complex problem solving: A comparison of alternative conceptions. In P. A. Frensch & J. Funke (Eds.), Complex problem solving: The European Perspective (pp. 295-321). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Sternberg, R. J., & Frensch, P. A. (Eds.). (1991). Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms. Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates.

23

Problem solving Strau, B. (1993). Konfundierungen beim Komplexen Problemlsen. Zum Einflu des Anteils der richtigen Lsungen (ArL) auf das Problemlseverhalten in komplexen Situationen [Confoundations in complex problem solving. On the influence of the degree of correct solutions on problem solving in complex situations]. Bonn, Germany: Holos. Strohschneider, S. (1991). Kein System von Systemen! Kommentar zu dem Aufsatz "Systemmerkmale als Determinanten des Umgangs mit dynamischen Systemen" von Joachim Funke [No system of systems! Reply to the paper "System features as determinants of behavior in dynamic task environments" by Joachim Funke]. Sprache & Kognition, 10, 109-113. Van Lehn, K. (1989). Problem solving and cognitive skill acquisition. In M. I. Posner (Ed.), Foundations of cognitive science (pp. 527-579). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press. Voss, J. F., Wolfe, C. R., Lawrence, J. A., & Engle, R. A. (1991). From representation to decision: An analysis of problem solving in international relations. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 119-158). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Wagner, R. K. (1991). Managerial problem solving. In R. J. Sternberg & P. A. Frensch (Eds.), Complex problem solving: Principles and mechanisms (pp. 159-183). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum Associates. Wisconsin Educational Media Association. (1993). "Information literacy: A position paper on information problem-solving." Madison, WI: WEMA Publications. (ED 376 817). (Portions adapted from Michigan State Board of Education's Position Paper on Information Processing Skills, 1992). Blanchard-Fields, F. (2007). "Everyday problem solving and emotion: An adult developmental perspective. Current Directions in Psychological Science". Current Directions in Psychological Science 16 (1): 2631. doi: 10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00469.x (http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1467-8721.2007.00469.x). Bransford, J. D., & Stein, B. S (1993). The ideal problem solver: A guide for improving thinking, learning, and creativity (2nd ed.). Ghasempour,Z., Md Nor Bakar and Jahanshahloo G. R. (2013). Innovation in Teaching and Learning through Problem Posing Tasks and Metacognitive Strategies (http://naturalspublishing.com/files/published/ vw6qz9526444la.pdf). Condell; Wade,Galway,McBride,Gormley,Brennan,Somasundram (2010). Springer Science+Business Media 2010: 223233 http://journals1.scholarsportal.info.myaccess.library.utoronto.ca/tmp/ 7323702971461253957.pdf (http://journals1.scholarsportal.info.myaccess.library.utoronto.ca/tmp/ 7323702971461253957.pdf) |url= missing title (help). </ref>

24

External links
Computer skills for information problem-solving: Learning and teaching technology in context (http://www. ericdigests.org/1996-4/skills.htm) Problem solving - Elementary level (http://wik.ed.uiuc.edu/articles/p/r/o/ Problem_solving-Elementary_level_320d.html)

Decision-making

25

Decision-making
Decision making can be regarded as the cognitive process resulting in the selection of a course of action among several alternative scenarios. Every decision making process produces a final choice. The output can be an action or an opinion of choice.

Overview
Human performance in decision terms has been the subject of active research from several perspectives. From a psychological perspective, it is necessary to examine individual decisions in the context of a set of needs, preferences an Sample flowchart representing the decision individual has and values they seek. process to add a new article to Wikipedia. From a cognitive perspective, the decision making process must be regarded as a continuous process integrated in the interaction with the environment. From a normative perspective, the analysis of individual decisions is concerned with the logic of decision making and rationality and the invariant choice it leads to. Yet, at another level, it might be regarded as a problem solving activity which is terminated when a satisfactory solution is reached. Therefore, decision making is a reasoning or emotional process which can be rational or irrational, can be based on explicit assumptions or tacit assumptions. Decisions are likely to be involuntary and following the decision, we spend time analyzing the cost and benefits of that decision. This is known as "Rational Choice Theory," which encompasses the notion that we maximize benefits and minimize the costs. Some have argued that most decisions are made unconsciously. Jim Nightingale, Author of Think Smart-Act Smart, states that "we simply decide without thinking much about the decision process." In a controlled environment, such as a classroom, instructors might try to encourage students to weigh pros and cons before making a decision. This strategy is known as Franklin's Rule. Because such a rule requires time, cognitive resources and full access to relevant information about the decision, Franklin's Rule may not best describe how people naturally make their decisions. [citation needed] Logical decision making is an important part of all science-based professions, where specialists apply their knowledge in a given area to make informed decisions. For example, medical decision making often involves making a diagnosis and selecting an appropriate treatment. SomeWikipedia:Avoid weasel words research using naturalistic methods shows, however, that in situations with higher time pressure, higher stakes, or increased ambiguities, experts use intuitive decision making rather than structured approaches, following a recognition primed decision approach to fit a set of indicators into the expert's experience and immediately arrive at a satisfactory course of action without weighing alternatives. Recent robust decision efforts have formally integrated uncertainty into the decision making process. However, decision analysis, recognized and included uncertainties with a structured and rationally justifiable method of decision making since its conception in 1964. A major part of decision making involves the analysis of a finite set of alternatives described in terms of evaluative criteria. Information Overload is when there is a substantial gap between the capacity of information and the ways we adapt. The overload of information can be related to problems processing and tasking, which impacts decision making.[1] These criteria may be benefit or cost in nature. Then the problem might be to rank these alternatives in terms of how attractive they are to the decision maker(s) when all the criteria are considered simultaneously. Another goal might be to just find the best alternative or to determine the relative total priority of each alternative (for instance, if alternatives represent projects competing for funds) when all the criteria are considered simultaneously. Solving such problems is the focus of multi-criteria decision analysis (MCDA) also known as multi-criteria decision

Decision-making making (MCDM). This area of decision making, although it is very old and has attracted the interest of many researchers and practitioners, is still highly debated as there are many MCDA / MCDM methods which may yield very different results when they are applied on exactly the same data. This leads to the formulation of a decision making paradox.

26

Rational and irrational decision making


In economics, it is thought that if humans are rational and free to make their own decisions, then they would behave according to the rational choice theory. This theory states that people make decisions by determining the likelihood of a potential outcome, the value of the outcome and then multiplying the two. For example, with a 50% chance of winning $20 or a 100% chance of winning $10, people more likely to choose the first option. However, in reality, there are some factors that affect decision making abilities and cause people to make irrational decisions, one of them being availability bias. Availability bias is the tendency for some items that are more readily available in memory to be judged as more frequently occurring. For example, someone who watches a lot of movies about terrorist attacks may think the frequency of terrorism to be higher than it actually is.

Information overload
Information overload is "a gap between the volume of information and the tools we need to assimilate it." It is proven in some studies Wikipedia:Avoid weasel words that the more information overload, the worse the quality of decisions made. There are 5 factors concerning information overload: Personal Information Factors: personal qualifications, experiences, attitudes etc. Information Characteristics: information quality, quantity and frequency Tasks and Process: standardized procedures or methods Organizational Design: organizations' cooperation, processing capacity and organization relationship Information Technology: IT management, and general technology

Hall, Ariss & Todorov with an assistant Rashar phinyor (2007) described an illusion of knowledge, meaning that as individuals encounter too much knowledge it actually interferes with their ability to make rational decisions.[2]

Problem analysis vs decision making


It is important to differentiate between problem analysis and decision making. The concepts are completely separate from one another. Traditionally it is argued that problem analysis must be done first, so that the information gathered in that process may be used towards decision making. Problem analysis Analyze performance, what should the results be against what they actually are Problems are merely deviations from performance standards Problem must be precisely identified and described Problems are caused by a change from a distinctive feature Something can always be used to distinguish between what has and hasn't been affected by a cause Causes to problems can be deducted from relevant changes found in analyzing the problem Most likely cause to a problem is the one that exactly explains all the facts

Decision making Objectives must first be established Objectives must be classified and placed in order of importance Alternative actions must be developed The alternative must be evaluated against all the objectives

Decision-making The alternative that is able to achieve all the objectives is the tentative decision The tentative decision is evaluated for more possible consequences The decisive actions are taken, and additional actions are taken to prevent any adverse consequences from becoming problems and starting both systems (problem analysis and decision making) all over again There are steps that are generally followed that result in a decision model that can be used to determine an optimal production plan. In a situation featuring conflict, role-playing is helpful for predicting decisions to be made by involved parties. Decision planning Making a decision without planning is fairly common, but does not often end well. Planning allows for decisions to be made comfortably and in a smart way. Planning makes decision making a lot more simple than it is. Decision will get four benefits out of planning: 1. Planning give chance to the establishment of independent goals. It is a conscious and directed series of choices. 2. Planning provides a standard of measurement. It is a measurement of whether you are going towards or further away from your goal. 3. Planning converts values to action. You think twice about the plan and decide what will help advance your plan best. 4. Planning allows for limited resources to be committed in an orderly way. Always govern the use of what is limited to you. (e.g. money, time, etc.) Analysis paralysis Analysis paralysis is the state of over-analyzing (or over-thinking) a situation, or citing sources, so that a decision or action is never taken, in effect paralyzing the outcome.

27

Everyday techniques
Decision making techniques can be separated into two broad categories: Group decision making techniques and individual decision making techniques: Group decision making techniques Consensus decision-making tries to avoid "winners" and "losers". Consensus requires that a majority approve a given course of action, but that the minority agree to go along with the course of action. In other words, if the minority opposes the course of action, consensus requires that the course of action be modified to remove objectionable features. Voting-based methods Range voting lets each member score one or more of the available options. The option with the highest average is chosen. This method has experimentally been shown to produce the lowest Bayesian regret among common voting methods, even when voters are strategic.[citation needed] Majority requires support from more than 50% of the members of the group. Thus, the bar for action is lower than with unanimity and a group of "losers" is implicit to this rule.[citation needed] Plurality, where the largest block in a group decides, even if it falls short of a majority. Delphi method is structured communication technique for groups, originally developed for collaborative forecasting but has also been used for policy making Dotmocracy is a facilitation method that relies on the use of special forms called Dotmocracy Sheets to allow large groups to collectively brainstorm and recognize agreement on an unlimited number of ideas they have authored. Individual decision making techniques Pros and cons: listing the advantages and disadvantages of each option, popularized by Plato and Benjamin Franklin.[3] Contrast the costs and benefits of all alternatives. Also called Rational decision making. Simple prioritization: choosing the alternative with the highest probability-weighted utility for each alternative (see Decision analysis) Satisficing: examining alternatives only until an acceptable one is found.

Decision-making Elimination by Aspects: choosing between alternatives using Mathematical psychology Technique was introduced by Amos Tversky in 1972. It is a covert elimination process that involves comparing all available alternatives by aspects. The decision-maker chooses an aspect; any alternatives without that aspect are eliminated. The decision-maker repeats this process with as many aspects as needed until there remains only one alternative Preference Trees: In 1979 Amos Tversky and Shmuel Sattach updated the elimination by aspects technique by presenting a more ordered and structured way of comparing the available alternatives. This technique compared the alternatives by presenting the aspects in a decided and sequential order. It became a more hierarchical system in which the aspects are ordered from general to specific Acquiesce to a person in authority or an "expert", just following orders Flipism: flipping a coin, cutting a deck of playing cards, and other random or coincidence methods[4] Prayer, tarot cards, astrology, augurs, revelation, or other forms of divination Taking the most opposite action compared to the advice of mistrusted authorities (parents, police officers, partners ...) Opportunity cost: calculating the opportunity cost of each options and decide the decision Bureaucratic: set up criteria for automated decisions Political: negotiate choices among interest groups Participative decision-making (PDM): a methodology in which a single decision maker opens up the decision making process to a group for a collaborative effort in order to take advantage of additional input. Use of a structured decision making method Individual decision making techniques can often be applied by a group as part of a group decision making technique. A need to use software for the decision making process is emerging for individuals and businesses. This is due to increasing decision complexity, and increased requirements to consider additional stakeholders, categories, elements, or factors that impact important decisions.

28

Decision making stages


Developed by B. Aubrey Fisher, there are four stages that should be involved in all group decision making. These stages, or sometimes called phases, are important for the decision making process to begin Orientation stage This phase is where members meet for the first time and start to get to know each other. Conflict stage Once group members become familiar with each other, disputes, little fights and arguments occur. Group members eventually work it out. Emergence stage The group begins to clear up vague opinions by talking about them. Reinforcement stage Members finally make a decision, while justifying themselves that it was the right decision. It is said that critical norms in a group improves the quality of decisions, while the majority of opinions (called consensus norms) do not. This is due to collaboration between one another, and when group members get used to, and familiar with, each other, they will tend to argue and create more of a dispute to agree upon one decision. This does not mean that all group members fully agree they may not want argue further just to be liked by other group members or to "fit in".

Decision-making

29

Decision making steps


Each step in the decision making process may include social, cognitive and cultural obstacles to successfully negotiating dilemmas. It has been suggested that becoming more aware of these obstacles allows one to better anticipate and overcome them.[5] The Arkansas Program presents eight stages of moral decision making based on the work of James Rest: 1. Establishing community: creating and nurturing the relationships, norms, and procedures that will influence how problems are understood and communicated. This stage takes place prior to and during a moral dilemma 2. Perception: recognizing that a problem exists 3. Interpretation: identifying competing explanations for the problem, and evaluating the drivers behind those interpretations 4. Judgment: sifting through various possible actions or responses and determining which is more justifiable 5. Motivation: examining the competing commitments which may distract from a more moral course of action and then prioritizing and committing to moral values over other personal, institutional or social values 6. Action: following through with action that supports the more justified decision. Integrity is supported by the ability to overcome distractions and obstacles, developing implementing skills, and ego strength 7. Reflection in action 8. Reflection on action Other decision making processes have also been proposed. One such process, proposed by Dr. Pam Brown of Singleton Hospital in Swansea, Wales, breaks decision making down into seven steps: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. 6. 7. Outline your goal and outcome. Gather data. Develop alternatives (i.e., brainstorming) List pros and cons of each alternative. Make the decision. Immediately take action to implement it. Learn from and reflect on the decision.

Cognitive and personal biases


Biases can creep into our decision making processes. Many different people have made a decision about the same question (e.g. "Should I have a doctor look at this troubling breast cancer symptom I've discovered?" "Why did I ignore the evidence that the project was going over budget?") and then craft potential cognitive interventions aimed at improving decision making outcomes. Here is a list of commonly debated biases in judgment and decision making. Selective search for evidence (a.k.a. Confirmation bias in psychology) (Scott Plous, 1993) People tend to be willing to gather facts that support certain conclusions but disregard other facts that support different conclusions. Individuals who are highly defensive in this manner show significantly greater left prefrontal cortex activity as measured by EEG than do less defensive individuals. Premature termination of search for evidence People tend to accept the first alternative that looks like it might work. Cognitive inertia Unwillingness to change existing thought patterns in the face of new circumstances. Selective perception We actively screen-out information that we do not think is important. (See prejudice.) In one demonstration of this effect, discounting of arguments with which one disagrees (by judging them as untrue or irrelevant) was decreased by selective activation of right prefrontal cortex. Wishful thinking a tendency to want to see things in a positive light, which can distort perception and thinking.

Decision-making Choice-supportive bias occurs when people distort their memories of chosen and rejected options to make the chosen options seem more attractive. Recency People tend to place more attention on more recent information and either ignore or forget more distant information (see semantic priming). The opposite effect in the first set of data or other information is termed primacy effect.[6] Repetition bias A willingness to believe what one has been told most often and by the greatest number of different sources. Anchoring and adjustment Decisions are unduly influenced by initial information that shapes our view of subsequent information. Group think peer pressure to conform to the opinions held by the group. Source credibility bias A tendency to reject a person's statement on the basis of a bias against the person, organization, or group to which the person belongs. People preferentially accept statement by others that they like (see prejudice). Incremental decision making and escalating commitment We look at a decision as a small step in a process and this tends to perpetuate a series of similar decisions. This can be contrasted with zero-based decision making (see slippery slope). Attribution asymmetry People tend to attribute their own success to internal factors, including abilities and talents, but explain their failures in terms of external factors such as bad luck. The reverse bias is shown when people explain others' success or failure. Role fulfillment A tendency to conform to others' decision-making expectations. Underestimating uncertainty and the illusion of control People tend to underestimate future uncertainty because of a tendency to believe they have more control over events than they really do. Framing bias is best avoided by using numeracy with absolute measures of efficacy. Sunk-cost fallacy is a specific type of framing effect that affects decision making. It involves an individual making a decision about a current situation based on what they have previously invested in the situation.[7] A possible example to this would be an individual that is refraining from dropping a class that that they are most likely to fail, due to the fact that they feel as though they have done so much work in the course thus far. Prospect theoryinvolves the idea that when faced with a decision making event, an individual is more likely to take on a risk when evaluating potential losses, and are more likely to avoid risks when evaluating potential gains. This can influence one's decision making depending if the situation entails a threat, or opportunity.[8] Reference class forecasting was developed to eliminate or reduce cognitive biases in decision making.

30

Post-decision analysis
Evaluation and analysis of past decisions is complementary to decision making; see also mental accounting and Postmortem documentation.

Cognitive styles
Influence of Myers-Briggs type
According to behavioralist Isabel Briggs Myers, a person's decision making process depends to a significant degree on their cognitive style.[9] Myers developed a set of four bi-polar dimensions, called the Myers-Briggs Type Indicator (MBTI). The terminal points on these dimensions are: thinking and feeling; extroversion and introversion; judgment and perception; and sensing and intuition. She claimed that a person's decision making style correlates well with how they score on these four dimensions. For example, someone who scored near the thinking, extroversion, sensing, and judgment ends of the dimensions would tend to have a logical, analytical, objective, critical, and empirical decision making style. However, someWikipedia:Avoid weasel words psychologists say that the MBTI

Decision-making lacks reliability and validity and is poorly constructed. Other studies suggest that these national or cross-cultural differences exist across entire societies. For example, Maris Martinsons has found that American, Japanese and Chinese business leaders each exhibit a distinctive national style of decision making.[10]

31

Optimizing vs. satisficing


Herbert A. Simon coined the phrase "bounded rationality" to express the idea that human decision making is limited by available information, available time, and the information-processing ability of the mind. Simon also defined two cognitive styles: maximizers try to make an optimal decision, whereas satisficers simply try to find a solution that is "good enough". Maximizers tend to take longer making decisions due to the need to maximize performance across all variables and make tradeoffs carefully; they also tend to more often regret their decisions (perhaps because they are more able than satisficers to recognise that a decision turned out to be sub-optimal).

Combinatorial vs. positional


Styles and methods of decision making were elaborated by the founder of Predispositioning Theory, Aron Katsenelinboigen. In his analysis on styles and methods Katsenelinboigen referred to the game of chess, saying that chess does disclose various methods of operation, notably the creation of predispositionmethods which may be applicable to other, more complex systems.[11] In his book Katsenelinboigen states that apart from the methods (reactive and selective) and sub-methods (randomization, predispositioning, programming), there are two major styles positional and combinational. Both styles are utilized in the game of chess. According to Katsenelinboigen, the two styles reflect two basic approaches to the uncertainty: deterministic (combinational style) and indeterministic (positional style). Katsenelinboigens definition of the two styles are the following. The combinational style is characterized by a very narrow, clearly defined, primarily material goal, and a program that links the initial position with the final outcome. In defining the combinational style in chess, Katsenelinboigen writes: The combinational style features a clearly formulated limited objective, namely the capture of material (the main constituent element of a chess position). The objective is implemented via a well-defined, and in some cases, unique sequence of moves aimed at reaching the set goal. As a rule, this sequence leaves no options for the opponent. Finding a combinational objective allows the player to focus all his energies on efficient execution, that is, the players analysis may be limited to the pieces directly partaking in the combination. This approach is the crux of the combination and the combinational style of play. The positional style is distinguished by a positional goal and a formation of semi-complete linkages between the initial step and final outcome. Unlike the combinational player, the positional player is occupied, first and foremost, with the elaboration of the position that will allow him to develop in the unknown future. In playing the positional style, the player must evaluate relational and material parameters as independent variables. ... The positional style gives the player the opportunity to develop a position until it becomes pregnant with a combination. However, the combination is not the final goal of the positional playerit helps him to achieve the desirable, keeping in mind a predisposition for the future development. The Pyrrhic victory is the best example of ones inability to think positionally."[12] The positional style serves to create a predisposition to the future development of the position; induce the environment in a certain way;

Decision-making absorb an unexpected outcome in ones favor; avoid the negative aspects of unexpected outcomes. Katsenelinboigen writes: "As the game progressed and defense became more sophisticated the combinational style of play declined. ... The positional style of chess does not eliminate the combinational one with its attempt to see the entire program of action in advance. The positional style merely prepares the transformation to a combination when the latter becomes feasible.[13]

32

Neuroscience perspective
The anterior cingulate cortex (ACC), orbitofrontal cortex (and the overlapping ventromedial prefrontal cortex) are brain regions involved in decision making processes. A recent neuroimaging study[14] found distinctive patterns of neural activation in these regions depending on whether decisions were made on the basis of personal volition or following directions from someone else. Patients with damage to the ventromedial prefrontal cortex have difficulty making advantageous decisions. A recent study[15] of a Two-alternative forced choice task involving Rhesus monkeys found that neurons in the parietal cortex not only represent the formation of a decision but also signal the degree of certainty (or "confidence") associated with the decision. Another recent study[16] found that lesions to the ACC in the macaque resulted in impaired decision making in the long run of reinforcement guided tasks suggesting that the ACC may be involved in evaluating past reinforcement information and guiding future action. Emotion appears to aid the decision making process: Decision making often occurs in the face of uncertainty about whether one's choices will lead to benefit or harm (see also Risk). The somatic-marker hypothesis is a neurobiological theory of how decisions are made in the face of uncertain outcome. This theory holds that such decisions are aided by emotions, in the form of bodily states, that are elicited during the deliberation of future consequences and that mark different options for behavior as being advantageous or disadvantageous. This process involves an interplay between neural systems that elicit emotional/bodily states and neural systems that map these emotional/bodily states.[17] Although it is unclear whether the studies generalize to all processing, subconscious processes have been implicated in the initiation of conscious volitional movements. See the Neuroscience of free will.

References
[1] Kutty, Ambalika D., and Himanshu Kumar Shee. "Too much info!" Monash Business Review 3.3 (2007): 8+. Academic OneFile. Web. 3 Mar. 2013. [2] Hall, C.C., Ariss, L. & Todorov, A. 2007. The illusion of knowledge: When more information reduces accuracy and increases confidence. Organizational Behavior and Human Decision Processes, 103: 277-290 [3] Benjamin Franklin's 1772 letter to Joseph Priestley - ProCon.org (http:/ / www. procon. org/ view. background-resource. php?resourceID=1474) [4] Random Decision Making App for Windows 8 devices (http:/ / decisionmakingwheel. com) [5] The Role of Learning Theory in Building Effective College Ethics Curricula (http:/ / journals. naspa. org/ cgi/ viewcontent. cgi?article=1088& context=jcc). Pijanowski. 2009, p.6. Retrieved 2012-01-12. [6] Plous, 1993 [7] Schacter, Gilbert, Wegner (2011)Psychology (2nd Edition), page 372, Worth Publishers [8] Schacter, Gilbert, Wegner (2011)Psychology (2nd Edition), page 373, Worth Publishers [9] Myers, I. (1962) Introduction to Type: A description of the theory and applications of the Myers-Briggs type indicator, Consulting Psychologists Press, Palo Alto Ca., 1962. [10] Martinsons, Maris G., Comparing the Decision Styles of American, Chinese and Japanese Business Leaders. Best Paper Proceedings of Academy of Management Meetings, Washington, DC, August 2001 (http:/ / papers. ssrn. com/ sol3/ papers. cfm?abstract_id=952292) [11] Katsenelinboigen, Aron. The Concept of Indeterminism and Its Applications: Economics, Social Systems, Ethics, Artificial Intelligence, and Aesthetics Praeger: Westport, Connecticut, 1997, p.6

Decision-making
[12] V. Ulea, The Concept of Dramatic Genre and The Comedy of A New Type. Chess, Literature, and Film. Southern Illinois University Press, 2002, pp. 1718 [13] Selected Topics in Indeterministic Systems Intersystems Publications: California, 1989, p. 21 [14] Interactions between decision making and performance monitoring within prefrontal cortex (http:/ / www. nature. com/ cgi-taf/ DynaPage. taf?file=/ neuro/ journal/ v7/ n11/ abs/ nn1339. html) [15] Roozbeh Kiani and Michael N. Shadlen, Representation of Confidence Associated with a Decision by Neurons in the Parietal Cortex (http:/ / www. sciencemag. org/ cgi/ content/ abstract/ 324/ 5928/ 759) [16] Kennerly, et al. (2006) (http:/ / www. nature. com/ neuro/ journal/ v9/ n7/ abs/ nn1724. html) [17] Nasir Naqvi, et al. " The Role of Emotion in Decision Making: A Cognitive Neuroscience Perspective (http:/ / www. blackwell-synergy. com/ doi/ abs/ 10. 1111/ j. 1467-8721. 2006. 00448. x?cookieSet=1& journalCode=cdir)", Current Directions in Psychological Science,

33

Library resources about Decision making

Resources in your library (http://tools.wmflabs.org/ftl/cgi-bin/ftl?st=wp&su=Decision-making)

Logical reasoning
Informally, two kinds of logical reasoning can be distinguished in addition to formal deduction: induction and abduction. Given a precondition or premise, a conclusion or logical consequence and a rule or material conditional that implies the conclusion given the precondition, one can explain that: Deductive reasoning determines whether the truth of a conclusion can be determined for that rule, based solely on the truth of the premises. Example: "When it rains, things outside get wet. The grass is outside, therefore: when it rains, the grass gets wet." Mathematical logic and philosophical logic are commonly associated with this style of reasoning.

Inductive and deductive reasoning

Inductive reasoning attempts to support a determination of the rule. It hypothesizes a rule after numerous examples are taken to be a conclusion that follows from a precondition in terms of such a rule. Example: "The grass got wet numerous times when it rained, therefore: the grass always gets wet when it rains." While they may be persuasive, these arguments are not deductively valid, see the problem of induction. Science is associated with this type of reasoning. Abductive reasoning selects a cogent set of preconditions. Given a true conclusion and a rule, it attempts to select some possible premises that, if true also, can support the conclusion, though not uniquely. Example: "When it rains, the grass gets wet. The grass is outside and nothing outside is dry, therefore: maybe it rained." Diagnosticians and detectives are commonly associated with this type of reasoning.

References
T. Menzies. Applications of Abduction: Knowledge-Level Modeling. November 1996

Article Sources and Contributors

34

Article Sources and Contributors


Metacognition Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=581351425 Contributors: Aboluay, Adrian 1001, Ageekgal, Al001, Alan Pascoe, Alansohn, Allen3, Anchoress, AndreasPDemetriou, AndySimpson, Anthony Appleyard, Apeeze, Aps0626, Artbeck, AstroHurricane001, Baylaurel, Bearian, Beno1000, Blinky, the Magician, Bluepaladin, Caesura, Ciphergoth, CuriousOne, DBSBHAT, Darekun, DirectorG, Doorsrocklikerocks, Doulos Christos, Dreadstar, Dream of Nyx, Dysmorodrepanis, Ebear422, ElliottHoffman, Enigma55, Esn, EyebrowOnVacation, Fasten, Flyer22, Fraggle81, FrankTobia, Fuzzform, Gaberdine2, Gabriel Kielland, Gilderien, GwydionM, Hairy Dude, Haymouse, Hnbaofeng, Homonihilis, Ingroc, IvanLanin, JaGa, Jheald, Jlcass, Jm34harvey, John Abbe, Jprg1966, Julia93, Jusdafax, Karenjc, Kavedian, Khazar2, Kiefer.Wolfowitz, Kim Dent-Brown, Krellis, LarryQ, Larryjun, Letranova, Leuko, Ljz0010, Lova Falk, Lycurgus, MasonNation, Master shepherd, Maxim, Mingming, MistyMorn, Mlang.Finn, Moondyne, MrStrathmore, Myanw, Nabeth, Nagelfar, Nesbit, Nn123645, NymphadoraTonks, Ombudsman, Ott, PDH, Paulscho, Pearle, Pegasi195, Pfhorrest, Pgr94, Phdarts, Pinethicket, Profdhw, Proofreader77, Pseudomonas, Pundit, Rama, Ranveig, Rculatta, RedAlgorithm, Reinhardheydt, RichardF, Riley Huntley, Rjwilmsi, SMC, Seth Nimbosa, Sivar, Spangadoola, Specs112, Spiel496, Steve2011, Sydbarrett74, T@Di, THEN WHO WAS PHONE?, Tan wei ren, TennysonXII, Thenext20feet, Tim1357, Tobias Bergemann, Tomchiukc, Tomisti, Trickstar, Trusilver, Tzepish, Ulric1313, Vanischenu, Vanished User 1004, Vashti, Vaughn42sv, Viriditas, Wareh, Widr, Wikiloop, Wikipelli, Woohookitty, Xyzzyplugh, Yintan, ZachCrichfield, ZacharyTaylorJohnson, Zahra241, Zeimusu, 314 anonymous edits Deductive reasoning Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=585013678 Contributors: 2D, 8ty3hree, AaronY, Abdullais4u, AceMyth, Aequo, Agentnj, Aim Here, Allens, Alphachimp, Amr.rs, Andrewaskew, Archenzo, Arno Matthias, Azcolvin429, BD2412, Badelmann, Beclp, BenKovitz, BenMcLean, Bfeylia, Blainster, Borgx, Bovlb, Byelf2007, CanadianLinuxUser, Capricorn42, Cathalwoods, Charles Matthews, Chillllls, ChrisGualtieri, ChristineD, Cnilep, Comicist, CompuChip, ConMan, Courtneysfoster, CyberSkull, Cybercobra, DTRY, DVD R W, Dbtfz, DennisDaniels, DesertSteve, DesolateReality, Dhruv-NJITWILL, Dictabeard, Difu Wu, DirkvdM, Djradon, Doezxcty, Donner60, Dprust, Drdoug5, Dtgm, EEMIV, EdH, Ember of Light, Erachima, EricBright, Escape Orbit, Ewger, Excirial, Extremophile, Flammifer, Flewis, Foreverlove642, Fresheneesz, F, Garrisonroo, George Rodney Maruri Game, Gerhardvalentin, Ggfevans, Giftlite, Gilliam, Ginsuloft, Glane23, GlasGhost, Gmelli, GoShow, GoldenGoose100, Graymornings, Gregbard, Guanaco, Hallows AG, Hartkiller, HemRaj Singh, Hewinsj, Heyitspeter, Holycharly, Humble Rat, Ieopo, Illspirit, Infinity0, Iridescent, IrishPete, J.delanoy, JSquish, Jason Quinn, Javalenok, Jaxha, Jimmynudes2, Jj1236, Jon Awbrey, Jon Harald Sby, Jonwilliamsl, JoseREMY, Julian Mendez, Jweiss11, K, Karol Langner, Kborer, Kenji000, Kenyon, Kevinb, Kimberleyporter, Kirrages, Koavf, Kusyadi, Kwork2, LactoseTI, Lallallal, Leoremy, Lethe, Lord Bane, Lugia2453, Luke13579, Lumos3, MARVINWAGNER, MCTales, MaTT, Mankar Camoran, Marek69, Mauriziogeri2013, Meldor, Mhss, Michael Hardy, MindShifts, Mindmatrix, Mjhy0926, Mo ainm, Mohehab, MostlyListening, Mr.Z-man, Mrwojo, Msviolone, Mygerardromance, N4nojohn, Nasukaren, Neelix, NeuroBells123, Neverquick, Nichole773, Nightscream, Ninjagoat, Nishkid64, Noaa, O.Koslowski, OAC, Octahedron80, Oligocene, Oliver Simon, Oncenawhile, Ordning, OwenX, Oxford Dictionary, Paradoctor, Pasixxxx, PaulKincaidSmith, Pbroks13, Penagate, PhilHibbs, Philogo, Philosophy.dude, Piotrus, Pomte, Prbclj25, PresMan, Probios, Psiphiorg, Q1w2e3, Qwertytastic, R3m0t, Richard84041, Rick Norwood, Rohit nit, Romanm, RossF18, RowanEvans, Ruby.red.roses, Rucha58, Rupes, Rushbugled13, Ruud Koot, Ryanmcdaniel, S h i v a (Visnu), SEASONnmr, Saeed.Veradi, Sardanaphalus, ScienceApe, Sfmammamia, Sgilmore10, Shadro, ShangTsung87, Shawn in Montreal, SidP, Skc0001, Skomorokh, Snowded, Sopidex, SpikeToronto, Stbalbach, Stephen, Stephensuleeman, Stepp-Wulf, Stjeanp, Strikingstar, Svick, TakuyaMurata, Tangotango, Tariqabjotu, Technopat, TedPavlic, Teemu Leisti, Tesseract2, The Cunctator, The Ungovernable Force, The great kawa, TheGeomaster, TheNightFly, Thingg, Thunderboltz, Tide rolls, Tideflat, Tobias Bergemann, Toby Bartels, Tparameter, TriGen, Troy 07, Tziemer991, Van helsing, Vanished User 1004, Velho, Vinsfan368, ViolinGirl, VogelsangLorenzo, Wayne Slam, Widr, WikHead, Wiki13, WookieInHeat, Woz2, Xephras, YAZASHI, Youandme, Zarex, Zenwhat, ZephyrAnycon, , 496 anonymous edits Inductive reasoning Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=583767040 Contributors: 24ip, 90b56587, A157247, A8UDI, Aaronbrick, Abdullais4u, Albertttt, Alfakim, Anarchangel, Ancheta Wis, Andeggs, Andrea.gf, Andres, Andy Marchbanks, Anthonzi, Antonielly, Archer3, Arno Matthias, Aubreybardo, AxelBoldt, Bagatelle, Banno, Bemoeial, Bender235, Bo Jacoby, BoNoMoJo (old), Bob Burkhardt, Bobklahn, Bobo192, Bongwarrior, Bovlb, Bryan H Bell, Byelf2007, CWY2190, CanonLawJunkie, Cathalwoods, Cauzality, Chris Pressey, ChrisGualtieri, ChrisKalt, Chrisdone, Cleon7177, Coffee2theorems, Ctasa221, Curb Chain, DAGwyn, Danny Reese, Davewho2, David Crawshaw, David Kernow, Dbmikus, Defeatedfear, Delbertpeach, Deleet, DennisDaniels, DesertSteve, Dionysiaca, Discospinster, Dmar198, DoctorStrangelove, Doingmorestuffonline, Domokato, Dresdnhope, Duke Ganote, ELApro, Earth, EdH, Edivorce, Ek65, El C, El aprendelenguas, Elspru, Equinexus, Erianna, Eric Schoettle, EricWesBrown, Evercat, Excirial, F-22 Raptored, Fangli997376557, Farquaadhnchmn, Farras Octara, Fastily, FieldOperative, Filemon, Flammifer, FleetCommand, Flyer22, Fotomatt, Fram, Freestylefrappe, Fresheneesz, Gacggt, Gaius Cornelius, Gamewizard71, Gareth Griffith-Jones, George Richard Leeming, Gerhardvalentin, Gfoley4, Giftlite, Gilliam, Go For It, Gogo Dodo, Grafen, Gregbard, Grjoni88, Grumpyyoungman01, Guppyfinsoup, HMSSolent, Hagrid da fifth, Hanberke, Harmonicemundi, Hasek is the best, Hazzzzzz12, Heyitspeter, Holycharly, Hotfeba, Hq3473, Hyperbytev2, IRWolfie-, Ike9898, Indigenius, Infinity0, Iridescent, Istvan, Ivan Bajlo, Jackol, Jammycaketin, Jander80, Jason Quinn, Jazzwick, Jer ome, Jfitzg, Jimmaths, Jmnbatista, Jochen Burghardt, Jon Awbrey, Jonkerz, Jonrgrover, Jor344, Jtradke, Jusdafax, Jweiss11, K, KUSSOMAK, Kalexander, Katoa, Kazvorpal, Kbh3rd, Kenyon, Khromatikos, Kiefer.Wolfowitz, Kikilamb, Kinema, King of Hearts, Klokie, Kzollman, LaggedOnUser, Latka, Leminh91, Letranova, Levineps, Lhu720, Linkboyz, Liz, Logical Cowboy, Logicman2, Lord Bane, Lucidish, Lukemcgrath, Luna Santin, Lx 121, M strat17, Machine Elf 1735, Magioladitis, Mahewa, Mark Klamberg, Markhurd, Matt Deres, Matthew Yeager, Mavit, McGeddon, MelbourneStar, Melcombe, MetsFan76, MiNombreDeGuerra, Michael Hardy, Miguel de Servet, Mikeo, Mikiher, Millermk, Mindmatrix, Minhtung91, Miracle Pen, Mo ainm, Mommyzbrat, Moonstroller-2, Moopiefoof, Mr.Z-man, NerdyScienceDude, Neshatian, NeuroBells123, Neurocitizen, Newbyguesses, Niceguyedc, Nightstallion, Normalityrelief, NotJackhorkheimer, Nufy8, Nurg, Ohnoitsjamie, Oilstone, Ojigiri, Oligocene, Omnipaedista, Oneforlogic, OttoMkel, Owl, Oxymoron83, Paine Ellsworth, Parthian Scribe, Pasixxxx, Peregrine981, Peruvianllama, Peterdjones, Philogo, PhysPhD, Pianoman55, Pinethicket, Pkearney, Pomte, QTxVi4bEMRbrNqOorWBV, Radiojon, Rbakels, Recury, RedHouse18, Reid12345, Reinis, RenamedUser01302013, RexNL, RichMorin, Richard001, RichardMills65, Rjwilmsi, Romanm, Roy Brumback, Rtc, Ruud Koot, Ryguasu, SAE1962, SBA1870, Saeed.Veradi, Salgueiro, Samohyl Jan, Sardanaphalus, Schicagos, ScienceApe, Sethery, Shadro, Shinju, Skarebo, Slazenger, Snowded, Spencer, Spencerk, Strake, Straw Cat, Sunrise, TMN, Tayste, Teply, The Cunctator, Thewolf37, Tide rolls, Tiktuk, Timwi, Tomisti, Touisiau, Trailspark, Trontonian, Tsunamicharlie, Ucanlookitup, Vanakaris, Vandalometer, Vanished user oij8h435jweih3, Velho, Voidvector, WLU, Wagino 20100516, Wandwiki, Watchpup32, Widr, Wikipediarules2221, Will.Oliver, Wolfgang Kufner, Yuckfoo, Zach425, Zigger, 505 anonymous edits Problem solving Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=585476053 Contributors: 2D, 2spyra, AbsolutDan, Acdx, Action potential, Adapt, AdjustShift, Afewum, Agbormbai, Ahoerstemeier, Aleksd, Alex Kosorukoff, Alex Rio Brazil, Ancheta Wis, Andrew Gray, AndriuZ, Angr, Anna512, Antaeus Feldspar, Ap, Arjun G. Menon, Astral, Ayda D, BDD, Bachcell, Beanary, Belovedfreak, Bgwhite, Billfmsd, Bobblewik, Bonadea, Boxplot, Brad7777, Brianmacian, BrotherGeorge, Bufar, Byelf2007, Cdelk, Celestianpower, Cfarrish, ChemGardener, Cielomobile, Cjfsyntropy, Clhtnk, Cmcurrie, Coachuk, Contyk, Cornellk, Corza, Credible58, Custoo, D. Tchurovsky, DBragagnolo, Daniel Cordoba-Bahle, Darren Strash, Dave6, Dawn Bard, Dbfirs, Ddr, Dekart, Derekristow, Destynova, Djcremer, Djdrew76, DoctorW, Download, Dpmuk, Eric-Wester, Eve Teschlemacher, Everyking, Excirial, Extremecircuitz, Eyesnore, Facilitation Author, Favonian, Ferris37, Forenti, Frazzydee, Fvw, F, Galzigler, Genegorp, George100, Giftlite, Gioto, GlassCobra, Good Vibrations, Graham87, Guggenheim, Gunnar Hendrich, HGB, Hahatheirony, Harald.schaub, Hari, Heron, Hommwock Smashr :)), Houghton, Hu12, Hydrogen Iodide, IceCreamAntisocial, IdreamofJeanie, Iggynelix, Ingi.b, Inter, IvR, IvanLanin, JForget, JP.Martin-Flatin, JaGa, Jack Greenmaven, Jacopo, Jan Tik, Jaranda, Jd2718, Jeames, Jhudson1512, JimmyShelter, Jm34harvey, JoachimFunke, JoeC 4321, Johnkarp, Joie67, Jon Awbrey, Jose Icaza, Jrmindlesscom, Jschnur, Jtneill, Juanscott, Jusdafax, Kazooou, Keilana, KillerChihuahua, Kizor, Kku, Klemen Kocjancic, Kosebamse, Ksyrie, LaurensvanLieshout, Laxerf, LcawteHuggle, Leestubbs, Letranova, Leuko, Levineps, Liao, LilHelpa, Lord Bane, Lova Falk, Lubin Wang, Lupin, MCrawford, MMSequeira, Majorclanger, Marc Venot, Marek69, Markstrom, Marsbound2024, Marx01, Materialscientist, MattiasAndersson, Mattisse, Matty Austwick, Mbonline, McGeddon, Merlion444, Mgret07, Michael Hardy, Michaeldeutch, Mild Bill Hiccup, Moe Epsilon, Moeron, Moonriddengirl, Mr.Z-man, MrOllie, Myasuda, Nagika, Nakon, Nesbit, New Thought, Nicearma, Nikolas Stephan, Novum, Oda Mari, Oleg Alexandrov, Ott, Paranomia, ParisianBlade, Pavel Vozenilek, Pedant17, PenDavid, Peter gk, Peterlewis, Petiatil, Philip Trueman, Pickledh, Pilgrim27, Pioneer-12, Plasmon1248, Possum, Prunesqualer, RDBury, Ralphruyters, Rapdetty, RaseaC, Ravi.all.over, Reinyday, Richard001, RichardF, Rick Sidwell, Rjwilmsi, Ronz, Roop25, Rsrikanth05, Ruud Koot, SLcomp, SQUARCLE, Saga City, Samhere, Saxifrage, SchreiberBike, Scoutersig, Seaphoto, Sengkang, Sepguilherme, Sg gower, Shanes, SheldonN, Shoessss, Sidaki, Sigma0 1, Skizzik, Smalljim, Spalding, Srikeit, Starasinicb, Stifle, Stone, Sueshang, Suidafrikaan, Sun Creator, Tagishsimon, Tarquin, Tassedethe, Teles, TexasAndroid, The Evil IP address, TheEgyptian, Theresa knott, This lousy T-shirt, Thiseye, ThreePD, Trusilver, Vaughan, VodkaJazz, VoteFair, Wannabemodel, Wasbeer, Weedwhacker128, Whatfg, Widr, Wiki-uoft, Wikilibrarian, Wimbojambo, WisdomEngine, Woohookitty, Yammy Yamathorn, YellowMonkey, Yhkhoo, Zahra241, ZimZalaBim, Ziphon, , 381 anonymous edits Decision-making Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=584754701 Contributors: 15lsoucy, 16@r, 4RugbyRd, 7&6=thirteen, A314268, AarthigaS, Ace of Spades, Adam M. Gadomski, AdjustShift, Ajraddatz, Akolahi01, Alan Au, Alansz, AlexWaelde, Allens, Altenmann, Amc-australia, Andy Fugard, Andyman1125, Annettec, Antandrus, Appicharlask, Art LaPella, Arthur Rubin, Atif.t2, Atlant, BBiiis08, BD2412, Backslash Forwardslash, Badgettrg, Bairam, Banno, Barrie99, Baseballwarehouse, Batman766, Beland, Bender235, Bettyuponiz, Blathnaid, Bobet, Boccobrock, Boud, BrianKnez, Brigade59, Byelf2007, Calliopejen1, Can't sleep, clown will eat me, CapitalR, Carollaruba, Cask05, Cccantarelli, Changer9451, Chaos guy, Cheapskate08, Chendy, Cherries 80, Chris the speller, Chrismcgrathdc, Citicat, Clicketyclack, Cmh, Coasterlover1994, Cognitionwiki, Cogpsych, Corn cheese, Corpx, Credible58, Cretog8, Crohnie, Cst17, Csutric, Curious1i, D. Tchurovsky, DCDuring, DJ Clayworth, Davidullman, Dcamp314, Ddr, Dekisugi, Dementia13, Dennisthe2, Deon, DerHexer, Dezignr, Diangane, Diego Azeta, Discospinster, Djdrew76, Djk3, Dkrapohl, Don krapohl, Dr. Peter Lankton, DrAllison, Druffschikka, Ds13, Dthede, Dzforman, ELApro, Ed Poor, Edgar181, Edithtung, Elsweyn, Epbr123, Erensezener, Eric Sodomka, Estu124, Excirial, Facilitation Author, Fanispa, Finereach, Fintor, FisherQueen, Fluffernutter, Freddy Fork, Fredrik, Fremsley, FreplySpang, Frood, Frozenevolution, Func, Futureobservatory, Gaberdine, Gaborgulya, Gaius Cornelius, Garion96, Gautehuus, George100, Gerardo.ok, Ggruen, Giltintur, Gimmetrow, Glen, GoingBatty, Goobles, Gosolowe, Gregbard, Gregory S. Waddell, Guillermomora, Guppyfinsoup, Gurch, Hadal, Hayimi, Hropod, Hsn mhd, Hugosbento, Hypercritic, I dream of horses, Iamthebob, Igoldste, Imersion, Immunize, Interactor, Iridescent, IvanLanin, J.delanoy, J04n, JDP90, JHMM13, JWSchmidt, JamesBWatson, Jane McCann, JanvdOever, Jarble, Jcp12, Jdpobrien, Jensgb, Jesanj, Jfdwolff, Jiang, Jim1138, Jimdmurphy, Jimmy Yard, Jmoini, JodyB, John Talbut, Johndbeatty, Johnkarp, Jojalozzo, Joseph Solis in Australia, Jprg1966, Jrvz, Jtmorgan, Kaiba, Karnawalski, Karthijy, Katach, Kazooou, Kea2, Keilana, KenKendall, Ketiltrout, KillerChihuahua, Kimberleyporter, Kku, Koavf, Korny O'Near, Kpmiyapuram, Krzysiulek, Kuru, Larry Hall, Leila 33, Letranova, Levineps, Libcub, LilHelpa, LittleOldMe, Llostrus, Logicaldecisions, Lou Sander, Lova Falk, Luigi30, Lwiner, MBisanz, MER-C, MSGJ, Marc Venot, Maresa.zingo, Mark Renier, MartinPoulter, Materialscientist, Mattisse, Mauls, Maurice Carbonaro, Maveerik, MaxPidkova, Mdd, Mean as custard, Melissabutts, Michael Hardy, Miss Madeline, Mks004, Mmzzhh, Mochalatte1993, Moonray, Morgan Wick,

Article Sources and Contributors


MrOllie, Mrh30, Mrskeptic, Mvuijlst, Mweogerman, Mydogategodshat, Nagatanuj, NatalieAvigail, Nathan Johnson, NawlinWiki, Ncjones86, Nephron, Newbyguesses, Newillusion, Nilgesz, Nkayesmith, Nmayo, Nymf, Ocaasi, Ohnoitsjamie, Oliver202, Omnipaedista, Onlymyopinion, Ooper, Overix, Panyd, Paul foord, PaulWicks, Paulsuckow, Paulwizard, Pgreenfinch, Ph.eyes, Philip Trueman, Piano non troppo, Pickledh, Pietrow, Pilgaard, Pinethicket, Piotrus, Pkrecker, Pm master, Pmjones, Polly Wicks, Ponydepression, Poseidon^3, Pphgibson, Prazan, Prof. Squirrel, Proplib, PuppyLover16, RJBurkhart3, Radagast83, Radon210, Rd232, Reaper Eternal, Red Slash, RexNL, Rhallanger, Richiez, Richmcl, Rikipedia8, Rinconsoleao, Rixrox, Rjwilmsi, Ronz, Rtibbles, STGM, Sam Hocevar, Samohyl Jan, Sampi, Samwaltersdc, Savh, SchreiberBike, SchreyP, Schzmo, ScottyBerg, Seller7, Semperf, Seth ze, Sfmammamia, Shoefly, Sierrbear, Sigma0 1, SiobhanHansa, Sir Nicholas de Mimsy-Porpington, Sivana246, Smashy !, Sni56996, SnowFire, SocialNeuro, Solana00, Solvek2, Somatamonkey, Someguy1221, SonOfNothing, Squeegly, SteinbDJ, Stephen, SteveNash11, Steveetee, Stevietheman, Stronbull, Styrofoam1994, Suidafrikaan, Sunray, Surveyofipsych, Syferion, Tagus, Tanious1, Techman224, Tentinator, Tesseract2, The Anome, The Famous Movie Director, The Thing That Should Not Be, TheEgyptian, TheSuave, Thingg, Thomasmeeks, Timberframe, Titodutta, Tomisti, Tommy2010, Tonyfaull, Tonytypoon, Torbler, Traxs7, Trbdavies, Tribaal, Tslocum, Tveblen, Tyler, UncleDouggie, Valenciano, Vangelis12, VanishedUserABC, Varinder722, Vaughan, Verbalcontract, Verne Equinox, VernoWhitney, Volueras, WATP, Wallmari, Wannabemodel, Wastetheday, Wayiran, Wayne.smith, WayneToms, Welsh, WhatamIdoing, Wiki13, WikiSlasher, Wikid, Wikinacious, Wikipelli, WilyMatzo, Winnard, Wmahan, X96lee15, XLerate, Xcriteria, Xproudfoot, Xyzzyplugh, Yamamoto Ichiro, Yijisoo, Yourmomblah, Yvolution, Zaharous, Zhenqinli, Zymurgy, , , , 620 anonymous edits Logical reasoning Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?oldid=581584523 Contributors: Achowat, ArglebargleIV, Arno Matthias, Arthena, E235, Eliazar, Etincelles, Flammifer, Forderud, Fryed-peach, Gamewizard71, Gregbard, Jaberwocky6669, Jack Greenmaven, Jusdafax, Leminh91, Linas, Lotje, Machine Elf 1735, Minhtung91, Mohamed-Ahmed-FG, Ryanmcdaniel, Salamurai, The Thing That Should Not Be, Velella, Waninge, Wannabemodel, Wjbeaty, Zuidervled, 33 anonymous edits

35

Image Sources, Licenses and Contributors

36

Image Sources, Licenses and Contributors


Image:Wikipedia article-creation-2.svg Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=File:Wikipedia_article-creation-2.svg License: Public Domain Contributors: derivative work: Pbroks13 (talk) Wikipedia_article-creation.svg: Linuxerist File:Reasoning.jpg Source: https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=File:Reasoning.jpg License: Creative Commons Attribution-Sharealike 2.5 Contributors: wikibooks:en:User:Maltewoest Original uploader was Maltewoest at en.wikibooks

License

37

License
Creative Commons Attribution-Share Alike 3.0 //creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/3.0/

You might also like