You are on page 1of 25

Dreams of Pure Sociology*

Donald Black University of Virginia

Unlike older sciences such as physics and biology, sociology has never had a revolution. Modern sociology is still classicallargely psychological, teleological, and individualisticand even less scientific than classical sociology. But pure sociology is different: It predicts and explains the behavior of social life with its location and direction in social spaceits geometry. Here I illustrate pure sociology with formulations about the behavior of ideas, including a theory of scienticity that predicts and explains the degree to which an idea is likely to be scientific (testable, general, simple, valid, and original). For example: Scienticity is a curvilinear function of social distance from the subject. This formulation explains numerous facts about the history and practice of science, such as why some sciences evolved earlier and faster than others and why so much sociology is so unscientific. Because scientific theory is the most scientific science, the theory of scienticity also implies a theory of theory and a methodology for the development of theory.

The history of science is partly a history of revolutions ~see, e.g., Kuhn 1962; Hacking 1981; Cohen 1985!.1 Historian Thomas Kuhn suggests that a scientific revolution overthrows and replaces the prevailing paradigm in a field of scienceits strategy of explanation ~1962: 1011; see also generally Chapters 2, 10!. A new paradigm implies a new conception of reality and a new logic by which reality is understood ~idem: 110; see also Black 1995: 864867 !. Examples are the Copernican revolution that overthrew the earthcentered universe, the Darwinian revolution that overthrew the immutability of plants and animals, and the Einsteinian revolution that overthrew the absolute nature of space and time.2 The period before a scientific revolution is sometimes known as the classical era of a science. Classical physics, for example, refers to physics before relativity theory
*Prepared for a session entitled Where Do Theories Come From? at the annual meeting of the American Sociological Association, San Francisco, California, August 24, 1998. The session was part of a Theory Section Miniconference on Methods of Theoretical Work. I presented other versions to the Department of Sociology, Texas A & M University, College Station, Texas, March 26, 1998; the Justice Studies Program, University of New Hampshire, Durham, New Hampshire, May 7, 1998; the Department of Sociology, Rutgers University, New Brunswick, New Jersey, October 14, 1998; the International Sociological Association Research Committee on the Sociology of Law, World Congress of the Sociology of Law, Warsaw University, Warsaw, Poland, July 16, 1999, and Jagiellonian University, Krakow, Poland, July 17, 1999. For comments on earlier drafts I thank M. P. Baumgartner, Albert Bergesen, Thomas J. Bernard, Mark Cooney, Murray S. Davis, Ellis Godard, Marcus Mahmood, Calvin Morrill, Roberta Senechal de la Roche, Christopher Stevens, Frank J. Sulloway, James Tucker, and Jonathan Turner. Please address correspondence to the author at the Department of Sociology, Cabell Hall, University of Virginia, Charlottesville, VA 22903. Black@Virginia.edu 1 Philosopher Karl Popper comments that new theories ideally overthrow past theories of the same subject: In this sense, progress in scienceor at least striking progressis always revolutionary ~1975: 9394!. 2 Kuhn proposes that a scientific revolution becomes a possibility when an old paradigmnormal science encounters facts it cannot explain. Such anomalies pose a crisis that may ultimately be resolved by a revolutionary paradigm ~1962; see also McAllister 1996: Chapter 8!. But Kuhns model is wrong: Revolutionary theories such as those of Copernicus, Darwin, and Einstein did not explain facts their fellow scientists were trying to explain. No crisis existed ~see Lightman and Gingerich 1992; Kelly 1994: 455 457 !. Revolutionary scientists typically answer questions virtually no one else is asking and initiate revolutions virtually no one else wants. Scientific revolutions thereby differ considerably from political revolutions ~see Feuer 1982: 252268; see also 269311; Kubler 1962: 109!. Sociological Theory 18:3 November 2000 American Sociological Association. 1307 New York Avenue NW, Washington, DC 20005-4701

344

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

~developed by Albert Einstein! and quantum theory ~developed by Max Planck, Niels Bohr, Werner Heisenberg, and others! early in the twentieth century. A revolution fundamentally changes science, and classical science becomes obsolete.3

CLASSICAL SOCIOLOGY Sociology has never had a revolution. Classical sociology merely refers to early sociology, and it has never been overthrown or abandoned. On the contrary: Modern sociologists widely agree that the fundamentals of sociology outlined by the classical sociologists Max Weber, Emile Durkheim, Georg Simmel, and the rest 4 still prevail. Classical sociology is the model of sociology itself. Moreover, the classical conception of social reality is largely psychological ~a matter of subjectivity!, the classical logic of explanation is largely teleological ~a matter of means and ends!, and the classical subject is largely the person ~including a number or group of persons!. Social action is individual action. Max Weberpossibly the most celebrated classical sociologistis explicitly and militantly psychological, teleological, and individualistic. He asserts, for example, that sociology is the interpretive understanding of social action and that subjective understanding is the specific characteristic of sociological knowledge ~@1922# 1978, Volume 1: 4, 15; see also 8; Ringer 1997: 1, 92!. Human behavior is action only if it has subjective meaning for the actor, and action is social only if its subjective meaning takes account of the behavior of others ~idem: 4; see also 26; Volume 2: 13751376!. Furthermore, only individual human beings engage in social action ~ Volume 1: 13, italics in original!; collectivities do not.5 His most respected ideas of a substantive nature, such as his conception of the legitimacy of authority ~idem: 212216; see also Volume 2: 901910! and his theory of the rise of capitalism ~@190405# 1958!, are explicitly psychological, teleological, and individualistic as well. The classical sociologist most famous for insisting that sociology is different from psychologyEmile Durkheim ~@1895# 1964! also continually addresses the subjectivity of the goal-seeking individual. He psychologizes virtually every subject, even society: Because society can exist only in and by means of individual minds, it must enter into us and become organized within us. . . . Society is a synthesis of human consciousnesses ~@1912# 1995: 211, 432; see also 445!. He claims that everything in social life rests on opinion and that sociology is primarily the study of opinion: We can make opinion an object of study and create a science of it; that is what sociology principally consists in ~439!. Everywhere he discusses the contents of the human mind, whether a feeling of solidarity with others ~@1893# 1964!, a predisposition to suicide ~@1897# 1951!, or a reverence for society ~@1912# 1995!. If Durkheimian sociology is not psychological, then Durkheim is not Durkheimian. But Weber and Durkheim are not uniquely psychological, teleological, and individualistic. They exemplify classical sociology.6 And they exemplify modern sociology as well.
3 Classical science may survive in a limited capacity, however. Although Einsteins general theory of relativity is more powerful than Newtons law of gravity, for example, Newtons law is still used to predict gravitation on or near the surface of earth ~see Weinberg 1998; Greene 1999: 380381!. 4 I particularly refer to the generation of sociologists whose work spanned the turn of the twentieth century. See any textbook on the history of sociological theory for a more complete list. 5 Weber acknowledges that a concern with subjectivity limits the scope of sociology, such as its capacity to understand human behavior in tribal societies: Our ability to share the feelings of primitive men is not very much greater than our ability to share the subjective state of an animalwhich is at best very unsatisfactory ~@1922# 1978, Volume 1: 16!. 6 So does Georg Simmel: Everywhere he addresses the subjectivity of individuals, such as the psychological dynamics of friendship, coquetry, sex, and love ~@1908# 1950: 5051, 324329; see also Poggi 1993!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

345

Modern sociology remains classical.7 It is modern only in a chronological sense ~ but see, e.g., Luhmann @1984# 1995: xlvxlvii; quotation in Sciulli 1994: 66!. Modern sociologists commonly regard classical sociology as the most important sociology ever written ~see, e.g., Collins 1986: xi, 5; Poggi 1996: 39, 46!. They invoke it as the supreme authority ~see, e.g., Alexander 1987: 28!. They read it for inspiration, and teach it to their students. Many spend their entire careers reading and writing about classical sociology. They assume that every modern sociologist stands on the shoulders of classical sociologists and that every sociological theory is a version of classical sociologyWeberian, Durkheimian, Simmelian, and so on. And they are right: Modern sociology still has the psychological conception of social reality found in the classical texts. It still has a teleological strategy of explanation. It still places the person at the center of social life. Understandably, therefore, no one challenges classical sociology ~see, e.g., Alexander 1987: 28!. It has never become obsolete. If the classical works were to appear todaysuch as Webers Economy and Society ~@1922# 1978! and The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism ~@190405# 1958! or Durkheims The Division of Labor in Society ~@1893# 1964! and The Elementary Forms of Religious Life ~@1912# 1995! they would still be acclaimed as major contributions. The stature of classical sociology could hardly be greater ~see, e.g., Parsons 1968: xiii; Alexander 1987: 3132 and title of essay; Turner 1996: 15!. It has never been questioned, much less overthrown. Pure sociology, however, is not classical sociology. It has a new conception of social reality and a new strategy of explanation. It answers questions unasked by classical sociologists and their modern counterparts. It solves a crisis unknown to either. The crisis is that sociology is not really sociological. NORMAL SOCIOLOGY In our student days we hear that sociology is the science of social life. Its subject is social, and its theory is social. Our teachers and textbooks tell us sociology is different from psychologybecause it is not psychological. They tell us sociology is different from ideology and humanismbecause it is scientific. They tell us we should read classical sociologists ~such as Weber and Durkheim! to see how sociology is done. But sociology is actually not so different from psychology, and it is not so scientific either. Virtually all sociology explicitly or implicitly addresses human subjectivity. Often it explains human behavior with the psychological impact of the social environment. Motivations and meanings are central. This applies, for example, to the sociology of deviant behavior, collective behavior, political behavior, religious behavior, legal behavior, medical behavior, and behavior in business organizations, schools, professions, families, and other groups. It also applies to fields such as social stratification, race and ethnic relations, and culture ~including the sociology of science, knowledge, and art!. All include subjective matters such as prestige, prejudice, perceptions, and beliefs. Even when the questions asked by sociologists are not explicitly psychologicalwhen they seek only to explain particular patterns of human behaviortheir answers are psychological, including answers based on psychological assumptions about human preferences and proclivities. Where then is the science of social life that is truly different from psychology? And where is the science of social life that is truly scientific? Much is ideologicala critique of modern society. Much is humanisticinterpretations and arguments rather than predictions and explanations. Much is scholarship about scholarship, books about
7 Although sociological theorythe explanation of human behavioris still largely classical, sociology has otherwise advanced considerably in its methods of research ~including statistical methods! and its accumulation of empirical findings ~mainly on modern societies such as the United States!.

346

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

books, words about words. If explanatory at all, most is teleological: It explains human behavior as a means to an end. It assumes or imputes endsgoals, needs, values, interests and then explains human behavior as a means to those ends. Teleology has a bad reputation in sociologybut only when it attributes a mission or destiny to society as a whole. A well-known example is Karl Marxs theory that all societies inevitably progress toward communism ~see, e.g., Marx and Engels in Feuer 1959; see also Popper @1961# 1964!. We hear that teleology is unscientific because the goal or purpose of a society is unobservable and unknowable. We hear it is metaphysical. Yet other versions of teleology still dominate sociological theory. Virtually all sociology explains human behavior as a means to an enda goal or purpose. Teleology is the superparadigm of sociology ~ Black 1995: 861863!. But it is bad science: Like the goal or purpose of society as a whole, the goal or purpose of human behavior of any kind is unobservable and unknowable ~see idem: 861864!. Sociology is unscientific in other respects as well. Research is often independent of theory, and theory is often independent of research. Because so much theory is untestable unfalsifiableit is mostly irrelevant to researchers, and research is mostly irrelevant to theorists. Moreover, most sociologists study only a single subject in their own society: Americans study American society, Germans study German society, Japanese study Japanese society, and so on. Many study only their own part of society: Many women study only women, many African-Americans study only African-Americans, many HispanicAmericans study only Hispanic-Americans, and so on. Their research is largely practical and ideological, designed to assess the well-being of their society or part of society. Some search for inequality, injustice, or other conditions they wish to evaluate or expose. Others conduct surveys about modern life in the manner of political pollsters and consumer researchers. Who thinks what? How do they feel? And theory? Much so-called theory is merely a discussion of other theorists, a clarification or elaboration of past ideas. Much is merely conceptual, a way to classify and describe human behavior. Even explanatory theory is mostly untestableneither right nor wrong. What then is it? Many sociologists believe sociology can never meet the highest standards of science testability, generality, and so on. They lack a requirement of good science: the faith that they can do what seems impossible to others. They accept their inferiority in the world of science.8 Others totally or partially reject the standards of science. They regard the nature of sociology as a matter of personal opinion and claim the right to do whatever they like, scientific or not. Their sociology is not even classical. Classical sociology is more scientific. In sum, from the beginning I was disappointed by the psychological, teleological, and ideological nature of sociology. Sociology had not met its obligation to be sociological, and sociologists lacked faith in sociology. I became a sociological fundamentalist and vowed to say only what is truly sociological or to say nothing at all. I dreamed of a genuine science of social life. But what is truly sociological? What is social life? These simple questions led to a new sociology with a new theoretical logic: pure sociology.
8 Historic figures in science, philosophy, and modern art virtually always believe their work is extremely important. A number of eminent scientists called their own work revolutionary, for example, including Charles Darwin and Albert Einstein ~see Cohen 1985: 46!. Philosopher Ludwig Wittgenstein evaluated his first book in its preface: The truth of the thoughts that are here communicated seems to me unassailable and definitive. I therefore believe myself to have found, on all essential points, the final solution to the problems ~1921: 5; italics omitted !. Philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche called his work Thus Spake Zarathustra the most exalted and the profoundest book in existence ~@1888# 1992: 5, italics omitted; see also 39, 42 45, 87 !. And Spanish painter Salvador Dal entitled his journal Diary of a Genius ~@1964# 1986!. But how many sociologists regard their own work as historically important? How many claim it is revolutionary, or even that anyone elses is revolutionary? I have never seen or heard such a claim.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY THE ELIMINATION OF PEOPLE

347

The subject of pure sociology is not human behavior in the usual sense. It is not the behavior of a person or a group of persons. It is a new subject in the history of science: the behavior of social life. Pure sociology thus violates common sense by removing humans from human behavior and eliminating what has always been central to the visualization of the subject, scientifically and otherwise: people. It reverses the direction of human action by reconceptualizing the action of a person or group as the action of a social entity such as law or science or art. Social action becomes truly social ~compare, e.g., Weber @1922# 1978, Volume 1: 4, 8, 1315; Parsons @1937# 1968; Luhmann @1984# 1995: 137, 165177; 1990: 5354; see also Black 1995: 859860!. Pure sociology completely contradicts the viewpoint known as methodological individualismwhat Popper calls the quite unassailable doctrine that we must try to understand all collective phenomena as due to the actions, interactions, aims, hopes, and thoughts of individual men, and as due to traditions created and preserved by individual men ~@1961# 1964: 155156; see also Homans 1967: 61 64!. Because social life such as law or science or art has no psychology of its ownno mind, no thoughts, no subjectivitypsychology totally disappears from sociology. The conceptual leap from the behavior of people to the behavior of social life changes the identity of everything once viewed anthropocentricallyfrom the point of view of a person. The subject of legal sociology, for example, now becomes the behavior of law itself. A call to the police is an increase of law, a movement of law into a conflict. An arrest is also an increase of law, and so is a prosecution, conviction, or punishment. A severe punishment is a greater increase of law than a mild punishment. A civil lawsuit is an increase of law as well, and so is a victory for the plaintiff or an order to pay damages. Every action of every person in legal life becomes an action of law, and everything is simpler: With a single concept the behavior of law includes everything previously regarded as the behavior of diverse individuals such as citizens, police officers, lawyers, and judges. It also led to a new discovery: Law behaves according to the same principles everywhereacross all legal cases, all stages of the legal process, all societies, all times. Law obeys sociological laws. Numerous formulations predict and explain variation in the quantity and style of law without qualifications of any kind ~see Black 1976!. These formulations specify how law varies with its location and direction in social spaceits geometrysuch as its social elevation, whether it has an upward or downward direction, and the social distance it spans.9 They predict, for instance, more law at higher elevations, more in a downward than an upward direction, and more across greater distances in relational and cultural spacepatterns actually found in diverse times and places ~see, e.g., idem, 1989, 1995: 842844!. More formulations pertain to other kinds of conflict ~e.g., Baumgartner 1988; Black 1995: 834837, 855, notes 129 130; 1998; Senechal de la Roche 1996! 10 and to other phenomena such as the behavior of art, medicine, and supernatural beings ~see, e.g., Black 1979b, 1995: 855857 !. Sociology is a matter of degree, and pure sociology is the most sociological sociology: It is entirely scientific and entirely uncontaminated by psychology or other sciences ~compare Ward 1903; Simmel @1908# 1950: 21!. It contains no assumptions, assertions, or implications about the human mind or its contents. It completely ignores human subjectivity, the con9 Social space includes vertical, horizontal, cultural, corporate, and normative dimensions. Pure sociology predicts and explains social life with the shape of social spacesocial structurewhere it occurs ~see Black 1976; 1979b; 1995: 851852!. Neither macroscopic nor microscopic, the geometry of social space transcends the usual units of sociological analysis such as societies, communities, and persons. 10 For other applications, tests, and extensions, see, e.g., ~in alphabetical order! Baumgartner ~1978, 1985, 1992, 1999: Chapter 1!, Black and Baumgartner ~1983!, Borg ~1992!, Cooney ~1994, 1997, 1998!, Griffiths ~1984!, Horwitz ~1982, 1990!, Kruttschnitt ~1982!, Morrill ~1992, 1995!, Morrill, Snyderman and Dawson ~1997 !, Mullis ~1995!, Senechal de la Roche ~1997a, 1997b!, Silberman ~1985!, Tucker ~1989, 1999a, 1999b!; see also the citations in Black ~1989: 108, note 52; 1995: 844845, note 88!.

348

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

scious and unconscious meanings and feelings people experience, including their perceptions, cognitions, and attitudes. And it has no teleologyno conceptions or explanations of human behavior as a means to an end, conscious or unconscious, individual or collective. It does not assume, assert, or imply that people have particular purposes or preferences, intentions or motives, interests or values, or that groups have particular needs or functions or goals. It does not attribute reasons or rationales to people for anything they do or fail to do. And because it removes people, it eliminates something universally regarded as indispensable to the understanding of human behavior.11 All that remains is social life. In several respects, then, pure sociology is a radical departure from classical and modern sociology. I now illustrate pure sociology with several formulations about the behavior of ideas, including the behavior of science and sociologya pure sociology of knowledge. Ultimately I outline a theory of theory with practical implications for the creation of theory itself. THE THEORY OF THE SUBJECT An idea is a statement about the nature of reality ~see Black 1979b: 157160!. Every idea has a social structurea multidimensional location in social spaceknown by the characteristics of its source, audience, and subject. The source of an idea is its agent, the audience anyone to whom it is directed, and the subject anything it describes or explains.12 The source and audience may be more or less intimate with the subject ~relational distance!, for example, culturally different ~cultural distance!, or engage in different activities ~functional distance!.13 The source is relationally close to the subject when someone talks about a spouse, friend, himself, or herself, for instance, while a mere acquaintance or stranger is more distant. The relational closeness of the audience to the subject is similarly variable.14 Note, too, that the subject might be anything at all, human or nonhuman.15 It might be dead, alive, or inorganican animal, plant, or part of the physical world.16 It might be a human creationmusic, money, or a machine. It might be a theory, sociology, or God.17
11 The removal of people from sociology is similar to the removal of a recognizable subject ~such as a person or landscape! from painting early in the twentieth centuryalso viewed as the removal of something indispensable ~see Greenberg @1958# 1961: 208209!. Art without a subject is pure artthe most artistic artentirely aesthetic and uncontaminated by practical utility. Anything pure is the most of itself, autonomous and free of everything else ~see Bourdieu @1992# 1996: 223, 241, 248249, 299; compare Latour @1991# 1993: 1011!. A purification is an essentialization: Something becomes the essence of itself. Russian painter Wassily Kandinsky thus spoke of pure painting and a higher level of pure art concerned with painterly-spiritual essences ~@1911# 1982: 103; @1913# 1982: 353!, and Dutch painter Piet Mondrian called for a purification of art that preserves only the essence of art ~respectively, @1938# 1986: 302303; @1936# 1986: 299!. 12 My concept of the subject is short for subject matteras in the subject index of a book ~compare, e.g., Bourdieu @1992# 1996: 206208; Luhmann 1995: xxxviiixliii!. 13 Relational distance refers to the degree of participation in the existence of someone or something, such as the frequency, duration, breadth, and depth of contact, including the amount of information communicated about each ~see Black 1976: 40 41!. Cultural distance refers to a difference in the content of culture, such as differences between religions or modes of dress ~idem: 7475!. Functional distance refers to a difference in activity, such as differences between occupations or daily responsibilities ~a type of social distance separating men and women throughout human history that is now decreasing !. 14 Art that depicts reality, such as a painting or work of literature, likewise has a social structure that includes its subject. A painter is very close to the subject of a self-portrait, for example, but more distant from a less familiar or less similar human subject or a nonhuman subject such as a bowl of apples. The closeness of the audience to the artistic subject is variable as well. 15 Partly because humans have contact with nonhuman as well as human reality, the jurisdiction of sociology extends beyond humanity ~see generally Knorr Cetina 1997 !. It also extends to the social life of nonhumans ~see Black 2000: 114116!. 16 Although humans may become highly intimate with a physical object such as an automobile, house, or computer, they ordinarily are functionally as well as relationally closer to living thingsespecially fellow humans and other animals but also plants such as trees and flowers. In many ways humans are functionally closer to fellow humans than to nonhumans, though all animals are somewhat close merely because they move, consume, and reproduce in a manner that resembles the behavior of humans. 17 Physicist Richard P. Feynman speaks of falling deeply in love with a particular theory when he was a young man and maintaining the relationship until the theory became an old lady who had given birth to some very good children ~quoted in Traweek 1988: 102103!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY The Two-Directional Nature of Social Distance

349

Social distance is two-directional: measurable from both A to B and B to A. And it may be asymmetricalunequal in each direction, the distance from A to B closer or farther than the distance from B to A. Such differences are obvious in relationships between humans and nonhumans: Humans may be intimate with virtually anything, living or not, while the reverse does not apply. Human relationships are often asymmetrical as well. A husband may be closer to his wife than is she to him, for instanceif he participates more in her life than she participates in his. The same often applies to friends and acquaintances. Asymmetrical relationships commonly involve an unequal flow of information between the parties, illustrated to an extreme degree by the one-sided closeness of those exposed electronically on television sets or computers, possibly celebrities known to millions, while their audience is entirely unknown to them.18 Historical records allow a one-sided closeness with those long dead. The two-directional and possibly asymmetrical nature of social distance is radically unlike physical distance, which is always equal in both directions. Pure sociology thus introduces a new geometry of reality unlike the geometry of earlier sciences such as physics and astronomy. The following pages feature the two-directional nature of social distance in the geometry of ideas. What Is Important? The social structure of an idea predicts and explains its success. The success of an idea is the degree to which it is defined as true and importantits magnitude. One idea is recognized as useful or even brilliant while another receives only mild approval or total indifference. How does the former differ sociologically from the latter? Hold constant an ideas content, and its success partly depends on the social location of its source and audience.19 Who presents the idea to whom? One relevant variable is the closeness of the audience to the source: The magnitude of an idea is an inverse function of social distance from the audience ~see idem: 159!. An intimates idea is more likely to succeed than a strangers. Social elevation is relevant as well: Downward ideas are greater than upward ideas ~idem: 158159!. A social superiors idea is more likely to succeed than a social inferiors.20 The success of an idea also depends on the social location of the subject. One factor is the subjects closeness: The magnitude of an idea is a curvilinear function of social distance from the subject. The success of an idea increases with the social distance of the source and audience from the subject until a point when it decreases.21 A statement about
18 Other distances in social space are two-directional and possibly asymmetrical as well. A might speak Bs native language, for example, while B cannot speak Asan asymmetrical distance in cultural space. Or A might receive information about Bs great wealth while B has little or no information about As wealthan asymmetrical distance in vertical space. Formulations pertaining to the behavior of social life in social space should recognize the two-directional nature of social distance. For instance, law may have relational direction from a closer toward a farther party, or vice versa, and the amount of law depends more on the distance from the complainant to the defendant than from the defendant to the complainant ~compare Black 1976: 40 48!. 19 The content of an idea, such as the degree to which it is scientific or new, also predicts and explains its fate. But here I leave aside the content of ideas and focus entirely on their social structurethe shape of social space where they occur. 20 By social superior I mean someone with a higher social elevationmore social status. Social status includes vertical status ~wealth, such as money or livestock!, radial status ~integration, such as employment or marriage!, relational status ~a degree of prominence, resulting from social ties to others!, functional status ~a level of performance, such as the points scored by a basketball player!, cultural status ~conventionality, such as the relative preponderance of a religion!, and normative status ~respectability, a condition that declines with the application of social control! ~see Black 1976: Chapters 2 6!. 21 Theoretical sociologists do not always recognize curvilinearity in social life. For example, Durkheim presents three major propositions about egoistic, altruistic, and anomic suicide and a fourth ~in a footnote! about fatalistic suicide ~@1897# 1951: Chapters 25; 276, note 25!, but these can be reduced to two curvilinear formulations: 1! Suicide is a U-curvilinear function of social integration ~egoistic and altruistic suicide at the extremes!, and 2! suicide is a U-curvilinear function of social regulation ~anomic and fatalistic suicide at the extremes!.

350

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

a stranger is more likely to succeed than a statement about someone closer such as a colleague, spouse, or oneself. Courtroom testimony by a stranger to a subject is more likely to succeed than identical testimony by a subjects wife or mother. Even less likely to succeed is the subjects own testimony. The same principle implies that an idea in a physical or biological science ~such as chemistry or biology! is more likely to succeed than an idea in sociologybecause the human subjects of sociology are closer to humans than the nonhuman subjects of the natural sciences.22 For the same reason a sociological idea about a foreign or past society is more likely to succeed than an idea about the sociologists own society. Because classical sociology was more comparative and historical than modern sociology, it was regarded as more important in its own time than is modern sociology today ~see Elias @1987# 1994: 94!. The same still applies to comparative and historical sociology: It attracts more recognition and respect than the sociology of modern life. The success of an idea likewise depends on the social status of its subject: The magnitude of an idea is an inverse function of the social elevation of the subject. An idea about a lower subject ~such as the sources or audiences employee! is more likely to succeed than the same idea about a higher subject ~such as the sources or audiences employer!. Legal testimony about a social inferior is more likely to succeed than identical testimony about a social superior. Testimony about a homeless man, for instance, is more likely to succeed than identical testimony about a prominent politician ~see Cooney 1994: 848 851!. The sociology of lower subjects ~such as poor people or criminals! is more likely to succeed than the sociology of higher subjects ~such as monarchs and states!. What Is Interesting? The social structure of the subject also predicts and explains what is interestingwhat attracts ideas and attention ~compare Davis 1971!. The social distance from the source and audience is again relevant: The attractiveness of a subject is an inverse function of social distance. Relationally, culturally, and functionally closer subjects attract both more ideas and more attention. We can predict what people talk about, what they write and read about, and what movies, television programs, and other information they consume. Human subjectsespecially living humansare more attractive than nonhuman subjects, for example, and nonhuman subjects functionally close to humans ~such as fellow mammals! are more attractive than other subjects ~such as atomic particles!. As one physicist remarks: We dont study elementary particles because they are intrinsically interesting, like people. They are notif youve seen one electron youve seen them all ~ Weinberg 1998: 50!. And one biologist complains that his subjectantsnever receives as much attention as monkeys and other vertebrates more familiar to humans ~ Wilson 1994: 135!. The more a subject is studied, however, the closer and more interesting it becomes. Among human subjects, ones own society, activities, intimates, and self are especially interesting: They attract more ideas and attention than subjects farther away in social space. More sociology therefore pertains to the sociologists home society than to foreign or earlier societies. Whether a subject is interesting also depends on its social status: The attractiveness of a subject is a direct function of its social elevation. Higher subjects such as the rich and powerful attract more ideas and attention than lower subjects such as the poor and weak. The rich and powerful are more interesting to themselves as well. But recall that ideas with closer and higher subjects are less likely to be defined as true and important. An implication is that ideas with more interesting subjects ~also closer and
22 Economist Milton Friedman observes that the closeness of economics to everyday life impedes the success of economic ideas: Familiarity with the subject matter of economics breeds contempt for special knowledge about it ~1953: 40!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

351

higher! are less likely to succeed. For example, ideas about human behavior occur at a very high rate and attract a great deal of attention: Everyone is an amateur psychologist and sociologist. Closer and higher humans are the most interesting of all. Yet ideas with closer and higher subjects are less successful. Although domestic sociology ~on the sociologists own society! is more common and attracts more attention than foreign sociology ~on other societies!, then, domestic sociology is doomed to be forever unimportantforever disappointing. The same applies to the sociology of higher subjects, such as the sociology of law and religion. Sciences with nonhuman subjects are different: Natural scientists such as physicists and astronomers regard their ideas as more important than those of sociologists, and virtually everyone agreeseven sociologists. The formulations above, however, logically imply nothing about the ultimate truth or value of any ideas ~see Black 1979b: 159160!. The sociology of knowledge, including the sociology of science, implies nothing about whether any idea deserves special credibility or prestige ~compare, e.g., Pickering 1984: 413 414; see also Mannheim 1936: 7587, 286306!. Nor does it imply epistemological relativismthe view that no form of knowledge is better than another. Like moral or aesthetic relativism, epistemological relativism is itself an evaluationan evaluation of evaluation ~compare, e.g., Woolgar 1983; Fuchs 1992: 2034!. Ludwig Wittgenstein remarks that neither a moral nor an aesthetic evaluation derives from facts alone, and that the two are logically indistinguishable: Ethics and aesthetics are one and the same ~@1921# 1961: 147; see also Monk 1990: 277 !. But he does not go far enough: Ethics, aesthetics, and epistemology are one and the same. THE THEORY OF SCIENTICITY stiinticitate Science is a matter of degreescienticity. The scienticity of an idea increases with its testability, generality, simplicity, validity, and originality.23 Testability is the capacity of an idea to predict facts,24 generality the diversity of facts it addresses, simplicity its economy of expression,25 validity its conformity with the facts,26 and originality its newness ~see generally Black 1995: 831847; see also, e.g., Friedman 1953; Jasso 1988!. Super23 Another aspect of scienticity is facticitythe degree to which an idea pertains to an observable aspect of reality. Note that the scienticity of an idea pertains to its content alone and is logically independent of its origins, including the psychology and sociology of its occurrence ~see Dahrendorf @1961# 1968: 811; compare Mannheim 1936: 286306!. Some regard objectivity as central to scienticity ~e.g., Popper @1961# 1964: 152156; Polanyi @1962# 1964: Chapter 1; Fuchs 1997 !. But if objectivity is a revelation of the one and only reality, it is scientifically unknowable. If it is mental, it is sociologically irrelevant. If it is an observable characteristic of an idea, it is an element of validity and is already included in my concept of scienticity. 24 A prediction is a logical implication about quantitative variation. If an idea cannot be tested by counting something, its validity is unknowable ~see Black 1995: 831833!. Even so, testability is a matter of degree. An idea is more testable than another if its implications are clearer and more readily observable. Ideas are merely suggestive if they do not imply predictions of a quantitative nature but nevertheless inspire research. The work of Karl Marx ~e.g., Marx and Engels in Feuer 1959! is suggestive rather than testable, for example, and the same applies to sociological theorists such as Erving Goffman ~e.g., 1959, 1967 ! and Pierre Bourdieu ~e.g., @1979# 1984, @1992# 1996!. Others, such as Talcott Parsons ~e.g., 1951, 1954! and Niklas Luhmann ~e.g., @1984# 1995, 1990!, are hardly even suggestive: Their work inspires little research. 25 The simplicity of an idea is measurable with its length, such as the number of words or mathematical notations it includes ~Gell-Mann 1994: 3034; McAllister 1996: 118120; see also Black 1995: 838841!. Friedman comments that a scientific theory is simpler if it requires less initial knowledge . . . to make a prediction ~1953: 10!. 26 The validity of a scientific theory is measurable with its precision: the degree to which the frequency and magnitude of its explanatory variable match the frequency and magnitude of the variable it seeks to explain. The highest validity is total precision. For instance, a theory that variable A explains variable B is highly precise if all As are also Bs and all Bs are also As, but less precise if only a few As are also Bs or only a few Bs are also As. An example of a theory with low precision is that later-borns ~children with at least one older sibling ! are more likely to be highly creative than firstbornswhich is said to explain major innovations in such fields as science, art, religion, and politics ~Sulloway 1996!. Its precision is low because most people are later-bornsall the more so in earlier societies with larger familieswhile very few are highly creative.

352

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

natural and metaphysical ideas have little or no scienticity, for instance, whereas theories in physics and astronomy often have a great deal. These differences are predictable. The social location of the subject is fateful: Scienticity is a curvilinear function of social distance from the subject. Both very close and very distant subjects attract less scienticity. Scienticity increases with social distance until the subject disappears or becomes completely alien.27 This principle explains numerous differences across sciences, scientists, and nonscientists as well as aspects of the evolution of science, including sociology. First consider why some sciences are more scientific. The Behavior of Science The history of science is a history of relationshipscommonly a history of contact with subjects once entirely unknown. The greatest scienticity occurs not where scientists are very familiar with their subjects, but where they are newly acquainted and largely distant. Science developed earliest and fastest where its subjects were extremely remote. First came astronomy, a science with a subject only barely observable: The earth-centered astronomy of Claudius Ptolemy was the most scientific body of ideas for nearly 1,500 years, until overturned by Nicholas Copernicus in the sixteenth century. Physics, a science now mostly dependent on experiments for contact with its subject, advanced dramatically in the seventeenth century with Isaac Newtons revolutionary ideasespecially his merging of astronomical and earthly science in the theory of gravitation. Chemistry had its revolution when Antoine Lavoisier introduced modern chemical classification in the eighteenth century ~see generally Mason 1962!. Biology, closer to its subject than astronomy, physics, or chemistry, had no revolution until Charles Darwin challenged the Biblical doctrine of divine creation in the nineteenth century. Sociology and psychology, the sciences with the closest subjects of all, came lastwith the twentieth century. Astronomy and physics are still the most scientific sciences, while sociology and psychology are still the least. Why did the sciences with nonhuman subjects arise earlier and become more scientific over timemore testable, general, and so on? And why did the sciences with human subjects arise and advance at all? An implication of my principle of scienticity is that science advances most when the subject is neither too far nor too close. Sciences with nonhuman and remote subjects must therefore overcome their distance, while those with human and familiar subjects must overcome their closeness. Both actually occurred: The physical sciences arose and became more scientific as their subjects became increasingly observable, while the social sciences did so as they reached beyond subjects previously too close and increasingly made contact with a more distant world. The nonhuman sciences advanced faster because they overcame their distance faster than the human sciences overcame their closeness. Distant sciences such as astronomy and physics employed new means of observation such as telescopes, microscopes, and electronic instruments to become acquainted with subjects once completely invisible. Physicist Stephen Hawking notes that cosmologists could once observe hardly any of their subjectthe universe as a whole: Until the 1920s about the only important cosmological observation was that the sky at night is dark. . . . However, in recent years the range and quality of cosmological observations has improved enormously with developments in technology ~quoted in Hawking and Penrose 1996: 75!. Cosmology is literally light-years from most of its subject, yet close enough for a considerable degree of scienticity. The tiny subject of particle physicsbehavior in
27 Scienticity declines when information about a subjecta form of relational closenessdiminishes to a point when the behavior of the subject is invisible. It also declines when the subject is so distant functionally or culturally that its characteristics are completely foreign and incomparable to anything else.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

353

atomswas entirely unobservable until the twentieth century, but the invention of particle accelerators ~the largest scientific instruments in history! made this subject sufficiently visible for a high degree of scienticity ~see, e.g., Segr @1976# 1980; Pickering 1984; Traweek 1988!.28 Closer sciences such as biology and sociology advance by making contact with previously distant subjects as well. Darwins revolutionary theory might never have occurred to him had he known only the flora and fauna of his native England and never taken his famous voyage on the Beagle to South America and its nearby islands. Especially valuable was the strangeness of the species in the Galpagos Islands ~ Desmond and Moore @1991# 1992: 170; see also Darwin @1859# 1967: 1; Sulloway 1996: Chapter 1!. A close subject is a scientific handicap.

The Behavior of Sociology Sociology took a great leap forward in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries its classical periodwhen sociologists reached beyond their home societies. Classical sociologists devoured information about past and present societies around the world provided by historians, explorers, missionaries, and other observers. But later sociologists mostly studied only their own societies, and comparative and historical sociology came to be regarded as a specialty. Scienticity declined. Some research methodssuch as participant observation and in-depth interviewingbrought modern sociology even closer to its subject and subverted its scienticity still more. Modern sociology became less scientific than classical sociology. The scienticity of each field and topic in sociology varies with its closeness to the subject as well. Close sociology is less scientific. Domestic subjects ~ located in the sociologists own society and time! attract less scienticity than foreign subjects. Domestic sociologists are more practical and ideological, and also more concerned with unobservables such as human meanings, motives, interests, and goals.29 Outsiders are more scientific: Social distance contributed to such respected works as French aristocrat Alexis de Tocquevilles study of American society ~@1835 40# 1969!, Swedish economist Gunnar Myrdals study of American race relations ~1944!, and northern psychologist John Dollards study of race relations in the American South ~1937 !. Yet modern sociologists have gravitated increasingly to subjects ever closer to their own lives. Many study only their own race, ethnicity, gender, or locality.30 Once preoccupied with distant subjects below their own social elevation ~slum dwellers and poor criminals!, they increasingly shifted to closer and higher subjects ~ professionals and others like themselves! and undermined their scienticity even more. The sociology of white-collar crime, for instance, is more critical and otherwise unscientific than the sociology of blue-collar crime ~ Black 1995: 856, note 137 !. The sociology of knowledgean especially close subjectis one of sociologys
28 The particle accelerators detector drastically reduces the social distance from physicists to particles: The relationship between the scientist and nature is at its most intimate and physical in the detectors. . . . The consummation of the marriage between scientist and nature in the detector sometimes leads to progeny for the proud scientist: a discovery ~ Traweek 1988: 158159!. 29 Some physicists are more scientific about human behavior than many sociologists: They dismiss anything unconscious as unknowable and assert their ignorance of human motives and everything subjective ~ Traweek 1988: 91!. 30 The most scientific science is internationalstatelesswith a subject matter independent of the nationality of its practitioners: Particle physicists from anywhere in the world are fond of remarking that they have more in common with each other than with their next-door neighbors ~ Traweek 1988: 126!. But sociologys largely domestic subject matter segregates most of it in particular nations. International interaction between sociologists will remain infrequent and shallow until the subject matter escapes its national boundaries.

354

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

least scientific fields. Science itself was one of the last subjects to be studied scientifically. The sociology of sociology hardly exists.31 Closeness to the subject is also an occupational hazard of anthropologists and historians who study only a single society and period. Initially separated from their subject by a considerable distance in social space, their research brings them closer and reduces their scienticity. Traditional anthropologists literally live with their subject, a condition so intimate that many explicitly reject scientific standards such as generality and simplicity in social science ~e.g., Geertz 1973; see also Cooney 1988: 22; Fuchs and Marshall 1998: 21!. Scienticity is everywhere lower where the subject is closer. Consider law: For centuries legal scholarship was pursued exclusively by those extremely close to lawlawyers, judges, and law professorsand hardly any scientific ideas about the subject existed. Many legal professionals continue to impute their own scientific incapacitation to everyone and insist that law is immune to science ~see Black 1997 !. Yet when legal strangers such as sociologists and anthropologists began to study law, especially foreign law in foreign places, a significant degree of scienticity occurred ~see Cooney 1988: 2027 !. Art resists science for the same reason: Most art scholars are too close to be scientific. Nearly all participate in artwhether as artists, collectors, critics, or historiansand nearly all insist that art is immune to science. But closeness to art, not art itself, is the enemy of science ~see Bourdieu @1992# 1996: Preface, 229231, 296!.32 The social status of the subject is also important. Ideas about lower subjects are more scientific: Scienticity is an inverse function of the social elevation of the subject. Downward science ~directed at subjects below the scientist! is more scientific than lateral or upward science. In sociology the poor attract more scienticity than the rich, the marginal more than the integrated, minorities more than majorities, criminal behavior more than legal behavior, the behavior of factory workers more than the behavior of corporate executives, and so on. American sociology was once primarily concerned with poor, disadvantaged, and unrespectable people, and some of its most scientific work pertains to their behavior. The Chicago School of sociology of the 1920s and 30s, for instance, mainly studied those at lower elevations, such as slum dwellers, struggling immigrants, and petty criminals ~e.g., Anderson 1923; Zorbaugh 1929!. The closeness of the subject ~in Chicago itself ! nevertheless retarded its scienticity to some degree, especially its theoreticity. Anthropology also has the scientific advantage of an inferior subject ~usually tribal people and peasants!, though closeness to the subject likewise subverts its scienticity to some degree. Still lower are the nonhuman subjects of fields such as physics, chemistry, and biology. Particles, molecules, bacteria, and genessubjects highly attractive to sciencehave no social standing at all. Some science stratifies reality by ranking the explanatory power of its variables, while other science treats its variables more equally. Eminent physicist Ernst Mach, for example, rejected every methodological axiom in science that smacked of privilege and status for any given body or event in nature ~ Feuer 1982: 31; see also 3234; Keller 1983b: 154 157; 1985b: 170171; Pickering 1984: 74; 1995: 250; Hawking and Penrose 1996: 76!. Pure sociology similarly rejects the theoretical domination of any sociological variable,
31 The scienticity of the sociology of science increases with the social distance from the science studied: The sociology of the physical and biological sciences is more scientific than the sociology of the social sciences, for instance, and the sociology of foreign and earlier science is more scientific than the sociology of domestic and contemporary science ~for examples of relatively scientific sociology of science, see Merton @1938# 1970, 1973; Crane 1972; Latour and Woolgar 1979; Pickering 1984!. 32 Bourdieu comments: If the science of works of art is still today in its infancy, it is probably because those in charge of it, and in particular art historians and theoreticians of the aesthetic, are engaged . . . in the struggles which yield the meaning and value of the work of art: In other words, they are caught up in the object they would take as their object ~@1992# 1996: 296; see also 229231!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

355

such as the domination of economic ownership in the theory of Karl Marx ~e.g., Marx and Engels in Feuer 1959!, social solidarity in the theory of Emile Durkheim ~e.g., @1893# 1964!, or culture in the theory of Pierre Bourdieu ~e.g., @1979# 1984!. We cannot rank the explanatory power of the various dimensions of social space ~see, e.g., Black 1976, 1995: 851852!. The reason is logical rather than factual. A principle of incomparability undermines any hierarchical theory that gives a privileged place to any variable or that otherwise ranks scientific variables lacking a common denominatora common unit of measurement. To rank the explanatory power of variables we must compare equal amounts of each, measured by the same standard. Because the various distances and directions in social space ~such as relational distance or vertical direction! have no such common denominator, we cannot compare their explanatory power. Although we can rank these or other variables for the practical purposes of a single study where the comparisons reflect their measurement in one contextwe cannot rank them in a theory that applies more widely, such as across societies and history. How can we compare, say, the impact of intimacy to the impact of economic superiority in legal or other matters? How much intimacy equals how much economic superiority? They have no common denominator. We therefore cannot compare the impact of equal amounts of each, and cannot rank their explanatory power.33 The only exception would be a variable with no explanatory power at all. The same principle of incomparability applies throughout science wherever variables lack a common denominator. Why, then, does theory so often rank one variable over another? The ranking of variables in science reflects ranking in the social environment: Hierarchical explanation is a direct function of hierarchical space ~see Durkheim and Mauss @190102# 1963; Schwartz 1981; Keller 1983b: 154155!. Theoretical domination by a single variable expresses social domination by a single authority. An implication is that one-dimensional theory in sciencemonotheorismoccurs in the same environment as monotheism in religion: monolithic authority ~see Durkheim @1912# 1995; Swanson 1960: Chapter 3!. Marxian theory, for example, is a dictatorial theory: One variable ~capital ownership! is said to explain and thereby dominate everything else. Such a theory thrives best in dictatorial settings such as twentieth-century Russia, China, and various societies in Latin America. But the egalitarian theory of pure sociologywhere no variable dominates anotherthrives best in more egalitarian settings such as modern America and western Europe. Different theories inhabit different locations in social space, and theoretical change reflects social change ~compare Kuhn 1962; but see Durkheim @1912# 1995: 818, 440 448!. Scientific revolutions commonly establish that something once regarded as constant is actually variable, whether the position of the earth ~Copernicus!, the characteristics of plants and animals ~ Darwin!, the nature of space and time ~ Einstein!, the size of the universe ~ Hubble!, or the placement of the continents ~ Wegener!. Pure sociology similarly shows that social phenomena previously regarded as constant are actually variable. The theory of law outlined earlier, for instance, implies that the law does not exist. Law varies from case to case. It is relative rather than universal ~see Black 1976, 1989!. The same applies to morality, ideas, and God ~see idem 1995: 855857 !. The discovery of new variation follows changes in the social location of subjects once too close or distant for a
33 Sociological studies that statistically rank the explanatory power of variables may have little or no theoretical relevance. On the one hand, for instance, because different amounts of wealth have a common denominator ~a unit of value such as dollars!, we can readily rank their impact on legal or other behavior. It is thus possible to theorize that law against economic inferiors is greater than law against economic superiors ~ Black 1976: 2124!. On the other hand, because different amounts of, say, wealth, intimacy, and cultural closeness have no such common denominator, we cannot rank their impact on law or anything else.

356

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

higher level of scienticity. Scientific revolutions thus reflect transformations in the social structure of the subject ~compare, e.g., Kuhn 1962!. The Behavior of Common Sense The familiarity of a subject repels scienticity and attracts common sensethe popular understanding of reality in everyday life ~see Geertz @1975# 1983; Black 1979a!. Rarely are we scientific about our families, lovers, friends, or colleagues.34 Instead we endow them with free will and utter an unending stream of untestable ideas about the unobservable content of their minds.35 And who is scientific about the behavior of God? Surely not those close to God who pray as inferiors for favors or forgiveness ~see Black 1995: 856 857, 860!. Never are we less scientific, however, than about ourselves. A similar lack of scienticity applies to subjects totally alien to us. Consider the explanation of human behavior. Common sense ignores science and says that our closest subjects, such as our nearest associates and ourselves, have free will and do as they please. They are not mere products of their environment. Nor are those in distant societies and the distant past. The reason is that the explanation of human behavior with free willvoluntarismoccurs under conditions opposite those of scienticity: Voluntarism is a U-curvilinear function of social distance from the subject ~compare Black 1995: 856, note 137; Fuchs and Marshall 1998: 1822!. The same applies to teleology, the explanation of anything as a means to an end. When all subjects were either very close or very distant, teleology dominated all science. Copernicus, for example, even had a teleological theory of gravity: Gravity is nothing else than a natural appetency, given to the parts by the Divine Providence of the Maker of the universe, in order that they may establish their unity and wholeness by combining in the form of a sphere. It is probable that this affection also belongs to the sun, moon, and the planets, in order that they may . . . remain in their roundness ~quoted in Mason 1962: 130!. But teleology in the natural sciences steadily declined during the past several centuries ~see Burtt 1954: 1819; Feuer 1982: 352; Black 1995: 861863!. It survives mainly in the human sciences such as sociology and psychology. The explanation of human behavior with factors beyond the control of the person determinismoccurs under the same conditions as scienticity: Determinism is a curvilinear function of social distance from the subject ~compare idem: 856, note 137 !. Deterministic explanation implies that people cannot behave otherwise than they do. They lack the free will of our intimates and ourselves. Even close nonhumans are endowed with free will. People close to nonhuman animals ~such as their research subjects or domestic pets! often speak of them as if they were humans and explain their behavior as a free choice ~see, e.g., de Waal 1989, 1996; see also
34 Simmel notes an incompatibility between intimacy and generality, most extreme in the case of lovers: In the stage of first passion, erotic relations strongly reject any thought of generalization: The lovers think that there has never been a love like theirs, that nothing can be compared either to the person loved or to the feelings for that person ~@1908# 1950: 406, punctuation edited !. The same applies to every element of scienticity in every close relationship: Scientists are unscientific about their colleagues, for instance, and sociologists are unsociological about fellow sociologists. 35 The theory of the subject includes the subjects subjectivitypsychological experience. Although we cannot directly observe subjectivity, we can observe its attribution by others ~including self-attributions!. These attributions are predictable and explainable with their location and direction in social space. The goal or purpose attributed to a persons action depends, for example, on the social closeness and elevation of the action. We can thereby predict and explain attributions of subjectivity in social science as well as everyday life. The same applies to the goals and purposes attributed to groups.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

357

Fuchs and Marshall 1998: 2122!. Tribal people and others close to nature likewise attribute feelings and choices to the animals they hunt, fish, and farm, and to close insects, crops, and trees ~see, e.g., Frazer @1890# 1981, Volume 1: 60108; Volume 2: 90147 !. The Ojibwa of southern Canada say that trees feel pain and wail when cut, for instance, and some Indonesian tribes and European peasants beg the pardon of the trees they fell ~idem, Volume 1: 58 61!. Modern people, including scientists, may adopt the same style toward close nonhumans: My Boston fern looks unhappy. It must want some water ~see also Keller 1983a: 198200!. One physicist even speaks of electrons and other atomic particles that want to do this or that ~Christopher Stevens, personal communication!. Social status is also relevant to the explanation of human behavior: Voluntarism is a direct function of the social elevation of the subject ~ Black 1995: 856, note 137 !. And contrariwise: Determinism is an inverse function of the social elevation of the subject ~idem!. Common sense says that social elites such as kings and generals freely choose to act as they do. So does God. But sociology says that the poor and lowly lack free will: Forces beyond their control determine their behavior ~e.g., Cohen 1955; Miller 1958!. The rich who exploit or otherwise victimize the poor have free will, then, but not the poor who victimize the rich.36 THE THEORY OF THEORY Common sense says that theories derive from facts. But philosopher Karl Popper long ago observed that a theory can never be logically deduced from the facts it explains: The so-called logical induction of a theory is impossible ~@1934# 1968: 2732; see also Wittgenstein @1921# 1961: 143!. He added more generally that there is no such thing as a logical method of having new ideas ~idem: 32!. Creativity is always necessary ~idem!. Albert Einstein makes a similar point about scientific laws: There is no logical path leading to these laws; only intuition, resting on sympathetic understanding of experience, can reach them ~@1923# 1934: 22; see also Friedman 1953: 42 43!.37 Biologist Peter Medawar notes that because a theory contains more information than the facts it explains, it cannot be deduced from facts alone ~1963: 377 !. Philosopher Paul Feyerabend goes further and argues that no rules or methods of any kind can assure the advancement of science, theoretical or otherwise ~1975; compare, e.g., Glaser and Strauss 1967; Stinchcombe 1968!. Yet scientific theory is human behavior, and nothing excludes the possibility of explaining scientific theory scientificallyas a natural phenomenon. A theory of theory specifies
36 A sociological version of voluntarism is phenomenologythe explanation of human behavior from within the subjective experience of a person. Sociology is more phenomenological when the subject is closer and higher in social space: Phenomenology is a joint function of the social closeness and superiority of the subject ~see Black 1995: 856, note 137 !. A sociological version of determinism is motivational theorythe explanation of human behavior with the psychological impact of social forces. Sociology is more motivational when the subject is farther away and lower in social space: Motivational theory is a joint function of the social remoteness and inferiority of the subject. These formulations predict, for example, a more phenomenological explanation of closer and higher crimes such as those of professionals and business people ~white-collar crime!, but a more motivational explanation of farther and lower crimes such as those of poor minorities ~blue-collar crime! ~idem!. We can also explain the explanatory variables in sociological theories. For example, some motivational theories explain human behavior with variables close to the behavior in space and time, such as theories that explain human behavior with peer pressurethe direct and immediate influence of ones associates. Other motivational theories explain human behavior with more distant variables, such as theories that explain human behavior with the cultural values of a society. More distant subjects attract more distant explanations: The spatial and temporal distance of an explanatory variable is a direct function of social distance from the subject. We thus explain the behavior of our intimates with variables close to them in space and time ~such as their own intentions!, but we explain the behavior of strangers with more distant variables ~such as the values of their society!. Because Freudian psychotherapists are somewhat close to their patients, they explain the patients behavior with close influences ~in the family!, but because they are also somewhat distant, their explanations pertain to family experiences in the distant past ~in early childhood !. 37 A scientific law is an idea with an extremely high degree of scienticitytestability, generality, simplicity, validity, and originality.

358

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

the conditions that lead to the creation of scientific theory, including itself ~see Black 1995: 856, note 137 !. The theory of scienticity sketched above implies such a theory. Scientific theory is the most scientific science. Only theory can attain all the elements of the highest degree of scienticitytestability, generality, simplicity, validity, and originalityat once. The best conditions for scienticity are therefore the best conditions for scientific theory.38 The theory of scienticity explains why some sciences and scientists are more theoretical than others, and has practical value as well: It is a theory that implies how to develop theory. The theory of scienticity implies that theory is a curvilinear function of social distance from the subject. We can thereby explain why the physical sciences have the most theory with a high degree of scienticity while the social sciences have the least. The physical sciences have more theory because their subjects are more distant ~while still close enough to be observable!. Subjects in the social sciences are often too close or too far away. Within each science as well, some scientists are more theoretical because their subjects have a better theoretical location in social space. The same theory explains the lack of theory beyond formal science, such as the lack of theory in tribal and other simple societies. Tribal societies do not lack descriptive science ~such as botany or zoology! but only theoretical scienceexplanations of their observations ~ Lingis 1994: 12!. The reason is that tribal reality is polarized: Virtually everything is either entirely local or entirely foreign, too close or too far away for the development of scientific theory. Most scientists never invent theory either, especially theory with a high degree of scienticity. The reason is that most do research.39 Researchers theoretically incapacitate themselves by becoming too intimate with their subjects. Many have an exclusive relationship with a single subject and disregard almost everything else. One eminent biologist ~ known for her observations of genetic mobility! speaks almost maternally of the corn plants she studied for decades: I start with the seedling, and I dont want to leave it. I dont feel I really know the story if I dont watch the plant all the way along. So I know every plant in the field. I know them intimately, and I find it a great pleasure to know them ~ Barbara McClintock, quoted in Keller 1983a: 198; see also Keller 1985b: 164165!. Another biologist ~who later stopped doing research and became more theoretical! notes that years of experiments made his enzymes as familiar as old friends ~ Kauffman 1995: 81, 99!. Still another speaks romantically of cells: Here is a cell. It has been going around all the time, and nobody has taken any notice of it. Suddenly you fall in love with it. Why? You, the scientist, dont know youre falling in love, but suddenly you become attracted to that cell ~Anna Brito, pseudonym, quoted in Goodfield @1981# 1982: 226!. Although celebrated theorists may do research in their early years, their theories usually appear only after they become full-time theorists. Many have no research experience at all. The most celebrated theories in physics, for instance, were largely developed by full-time theorists such as Albert Einstein, Niels Bohr, and Werner Heisenberg.40 The same applies to cosmology, the most theoretical field of astronomy. Biologists James Watson and Francis Crick likewise developed a theoretical model of the DNA molecule ~central to the understanding of genetic inheritance! without doing any of their own research on the subject ~Crick 1988: 65!. The revolutionary theory of continental drift in geology was not even formulated by a geologist, but by astronomer and meteo38 Theory hereafter refers to ideas with a comparatively high degree of scienticity. Exceptions are apparent in the text. 39 By research I mean primary researchthe gathering of data and production of findings. 40 About one-half of all particle physicists are full-time theorists; the rest are experimentalists ~ Traweek 1988: 3!. The only experiments some theorists conduct are so-called thought experimentsby which they imagine empirical reality under hypothetical conditions never actually observed. Einstein, for example, is famous for his experimental fantasies ~see, e.g., Miller 1996: 312320!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

359

rologist Alfred Wegener ~Cohen 1985: 446 450!. Major theorists also typically follow a nomadic way of scientific life, moving from subject to subject, never too close to any.41 Youth is an advantage for the same reason: It limits intimacy with the subject ~suggested by Roberta Senechal de la Roche!. Darwin was 29 years old when he formulated the theory of natural selection, for example; Einstein was 26 when he published the special theory of relativity; and Heisenberg was 23 when he initiated the theory of quantum mechanics and 25 when he propounded his famous uncertainty principle that ended classical causality in particle physics ~ Pais 1991: 275276, 304306; see also Simonton 1984: Chapter 6!. Watson and Crick were newcomers to molecular biology when they formulated the structure of DNA: Watson was a postdoctoral fellow only 24 years old, while Crick was a graduate student of 36 who had migrated to the field from physics ~ Watson @1968# 1969; Crick 1988: 6, 65!. In theoretical science, too much experience may be harmful. Social isolation is another condition conducive to the highest achievements in scienceto originality, for example ~also called creativity, imagination, innovation, and inventiveness!. Philosopher Arthur Schopenhauer long ago observed that The genius lives essentially alone. He is too rare to be easily capable of coming across his like, and too different from the rest to be their companion ~@1859# 1969, Volume 2: 390!. Philosopher Michel Serres similarly remarks that originality always takes place in solitude, independence, and freedomrelational isolation ~@1990# 1995: 37; see also 8182; Storr 1988!. Also important are cultural isolation ~such as the marginality of migrants or minorities! and functional isolation ~exclusive involvement in a single activity!: Creativity is a direct function of social isolation. In this respect, moreover, the social structure of theory differs considerably from the social structure of research. Scientific research typically occurs in social networks of colleagues known in the sociology of science as invisible colleges ~see generally Crane 1972!. Often research is a team project that includes a number of individuals working closely together in the same organization ~see, e.g., Collins 1975: Chapter 9; Whitley 1984; Fuchs 1992: Chapter 7 !. But such research is relatively routinewhat Thomas Kuhn calls normal science ~1962: Chapters 2 4!. Rarely does it lead to creativity of the highest degree, such as the development of revolutionary theories. Far from it. As one fictional scientist remarks, Highly organized research is guaranteed to produce nothing new ~ Herbert @1965# 1990: 496!. Instead, the most acclaimed theories occur under opposite conditionsin isolated locations in social space. Consider the most illustrious thinkersthe Newtons, Einsteins, Nietzsches, and Wittgensteinsat the height of their creativity. All were loners devoted to their own projects.42 In their early years their new ideas isolated them all the more. The theory of scienticityand the theory of theory it impliespertains not only to the creation of scientific ideas but to their acceptance and application by others. The social location of the most receptive audiences, including those most receptive to radically new ideas, is the same as the social location of the sources: those comparatively distant from the subject. For this reason, young people and other newcomers to a field ~including students! more readily accept and apply its newest and most scientific ideas ~suggested by Roberta Senechal de la Roche!. Scientific revolutions primarily attract the support of younger scientists while their senior colleagues cling to older ideas about their older sub41 Weber notes that dilettantes without close knowledge of a subject often outperform specialists in the development of theory: Many of our very best hypotheses and insights are due precisely to dilettantes ~@1919# 1958: 135136!. 42 Although social isolation is conducive to creativity, it is not conducive to the success of creative work: Because social isolation has a low elevation and distant location in social space, isolated ideas are less likely to succeed than ideas in social networks ~see section above entitled What Is Important?!. But sponsorship by a more integrated person or network may win recognition for an isolated idea that might otherwise be ignored ~see also Latour 1987; compare Collins 1998!.

360

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

jects ~see, e.g., Feuer 1982!. When the audience is too close to the subject, the greatest advances in science meet indifference if not resistance and hostility ~see, e.g., Barber 1961; see also Black 1976: 82!. All the above applies equally to social scientists: Least theoretical are researchers long intimate with a single subject in a particular time and place, such as anthropologists who study a single tribe or area, historians who study a single period of a single society or region, and sociologists who study a single topic in their own society and time. Especially damaging to the creation and reception of theory is participant observation or other close contact with the subject ~see Cooney 1988: 22; Fuchs and Marshall 1998: 18!. Closeness to a human subject breeds an involvement with the subjects mind and undermines the creation of ideas with a high degree of testability, generality, and other attributes of scienticity ~see Black 1995: 856, note 137; see also Fuchs and Marshall 1998: 1821!. If you are close enough to imagine the subjectivity of a subject, you are probably too close to be theoretical. Yet most sociologists know their subject only in their own society and time and have little information about anything else. Those who study inequality or religion or violence in modern America, for example, rarely know anything about these subjects in tribal, ancient, medieval, or other societies unlike their own. As noted earlier, classical sociologists were more cosmopolitan: They exploited information from numerous societies across history. They were nomadic as well, moving from one topic, place, and time to another ~compare Brekhus 1998: 47 48!. Most modern sociologists are too close to their subject to develop theory comparable to classical theory. Researchers often criticize theorists for not doing research, and theorists often criticize researchers for not doing theory. But such criticisms are unsociological. Researchers and theorists have opposite locations in social space: Research is close to its subject and sedentary while theory is more distant and nomadic. It is difficult to do both at once. But not all modern sociologists are too close to their subject to develop scientific theory. Some are too far away. The prolific theorist Talcott Parsons did virtually no research and moved nomadically from subject to subject ~see, e.g., 1951, 1954!. Even so, he did not exploit or explain the findings of other sociologists, anthropologists, or historians. Distant enough from his subject to be theoretical, he was nonetheless too distant to achieve a high degree of scienticity: He produced only general concepts and classifications rather than testable formulations, and his writings have little value to researchers. Another prolific theorist, Niklas Luhmann, was similarly uninvolved in factual reality and produced similarly unscientific theory. Researchers were useless to him, and his writings are equally useless to them ~see, e.g., @1984# 1995, 1990!. Theorists such as Parsons and Luhmann promiscuously publish thousands of theoretical pages, a mode of scholarship possible only when the actual behavior of the subject is irrelevant. Each published a small library, but neither owns a single formulation that meets all the standards of scienticity.43 Still less scientific are those who write only about the writings of earlier sociol43 Scientific productivity is often measured with publications. But scienticity varies inversely with the number of pages published by an author. Albert Einsteins special theory of relativity appears in a paper only 30 pages long; Charles Darwins first statement of the theory of natural selection ~with independent co-discoverer Alfred Russel Wallace! is only 17 pages long; James Watson and Francis Cricks structural model of DNA is only one page long ~with double columns!; and Max Borns major contribution to quantum theorythe probability concept in quantum mechanicsappears in a footnote ~ Pais 1991: 285286!. A better measure of scientific productivity is the number of testable, general, simple, valid, and original formulations in an authors workits scienticity. By this measure Max Weber, for instance, would do poorly. When not merely historical, his work is mainly conceptual rather than explanatory. Emile Durkheim does better, though his total number of testable and general formulations is probably fewer than ten. The Division of Labor ~@1893# 1964! has twoboth wrong ~see Black 1987: 568!. Suicide ~@1897# 1951! has four ~counting one in a footnote!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

361

ogists ~e.g., Poggi 1972; Lukes 1973; Bierstedt 1981; Alexander 198283!. The history of sociology is not even sociology. Every epistemology reflects the social structure of its subject. Many sociologists endorse the pessimistic epistemology of sociology that flowered in Germany over a century ago: Sociology was classified as one of the cultural sciences ~ Kulturwissenschaften or Geisteswissenschaften ! whose human subjects were claimed to differ fundamentally from the subjects of astronomy, physics, and other natural sciences ~ Naturwissenschaften !. Human subjects allegedly lie beyond the reach of genuine science and forever condemn the cultural sciences to scientific failure ~see, e.g., Ringer 1997: Chapters 12!. One modern sociologist declares, for example, that the pursuit of sociology in the manner of natural science is misguided and utopian ~Alexander 1987: 2223!. Sociology cannot even establish a fact, much less a theory about human behavior: From the most specific factual statements up to the most abstract generalizations, social science is essentially contestable. Every conclusion is open to argument ~idem: 25!. Social science is ideological as well inherently evaluative: The ideological implications of social science redound to the very descriptions of the objects of investigation themselves ~idem: 21!. Another modern sociologist remarks that a centurys experience now suggests a truly scientific theoretical sociology is beyond anyones grasp ~ Turner 1996: 15!. These philosophers of failure assume that all sociology has a close subject, including human thoughts and feelings. They believe it must address either mental states or conditions in which mental states are embedded, and any generalization about the structure or causes of a social phenomenon . . . depends on some conception of the motives involved ~Alexander 1987: 21, 29; see also Winch 1958; Homans 1964, 1967: Chapters 23!. Yet they themselves commonly contemplate human behavior from afar, without facts about anything. Their scientific pessimism reflects the unscientific location of their subject: too close or too far away.

Now consider the methodological implications: Do you wish to develop sociological theory with a high degree of scienticity? If so, my theory of scienticity can help you succeed. It specifies social locations especially attractive to scientific theory: subjects neither too close nor too far. It implies several rules of theoretical methodsociological rules that enhance your chances of being successful.44 They tell you where to go and what to do. Obey these commandments: 1. 2. 3. 4. 5. Leave home: Find subjects in other times and places. Be a nomad: Move from subject to subject. Be a parasite: Subsist on the findings of others. Avoid intimacy: Do not get too close to your subject. Avoid people: Study social life.

44 Because they specify a means to an end, Durkheim would classify these methodological rules as rules of technique ~@1906# 1953: 42!. Their violation reduces the likelihood of sociological theory with a high degree of scienticity. Feyerabend argues against all methodological rules in science: Scientific progress requires creativity, and creativity does not obey rules ~1975: especially 10, 23, 2728!. But he does not consider the possibility of a scientific theory that implies how to develop scientific theory or encourage creativity ~compare Serres @1990# 1995: 86!.

362 THE THEORY OF ITSELF

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

I dreamed of pure sociology, and my dreams came true. Pure sociology explains why.45 It came into being where science and theory flourish: neither too close nor too far from the subject. First I stopped doing research. I left my society, and I left the present. I began reading anthropology and history, wandering across social space from one place and time to another. Soon I discovered a strange and mysterious subject: the behavior of law. It was an unfamiliar form of life that everywhere obeyed its own principles. It attracted a high degree of scienticity as well as a new sociologywithout psychology, teleology, or people. Pure sociology. I lost contact with the classical tradition and became a stranger to my fellow sociologists. I studied the behavior of science and the behavior of sociology itself. Then came a scientific theory of why most sociology is so unscientific and a theory of why it has so little theory: Most has an unscientific and untheoretical locationeither too close or too far from its subject. Most sociologists study only their own society in their own time. Others sit in armchairs and do not study reality at all. Whether too close or too far, few believe that sociology is really a science or that sociological laws are possible. They blame the complexity of human behavior, they blame subjectivity, and they blame free will. But the problem is the social structure of their own sociology: They study only themselves, or nothing. The subject is hopeless. THE GHOST OF THE PERSON What does it all mean? We are agents of countless forms of social life fluctuating across the social universe. We obey principles we do not know and cannot change. Our actions are social, chosen no more than we chose to be born. Our ideas are social as well, attracted by the social structure of our lives. We conform to the shape of social space. Geometry is destiny. Who, then, is speaking? I am the voice of pure sociology. I speak a new language. I travel social space, habitat of social beings, a form of life both human and unhuman. I explore unknown locations, calculate distances in uncharted directions, measure quantities never counted. My subject is everything, I go everywhere, and I live in the past, present, and future at once.46 I am sociology becoming itself. I study the behavior of social life, the laws of law, the laws of art, the laws of God. I am the science of science, the theory of theory. I myself am social, and I predict myself. I am post-personal. Post-human.47 And I am notorious. I killed the person. I am the end of the classical tradition. The end of Western thought.48
45 Luhmann regards a theory as universal only if it claims to be able to describe every phenomenon in its field, including itself ~quoted in Sciulli 1994: 54!. It must be self-referential ~@1984# 1995: xlvii!. Yet he speaks only of what a theory can describenot what it can explain. His own theory can classify many things, including itself, but it cannot explain itself or anything else. 46 Norman Mailer on Picassos Cubist paintings: One had to find a way to paint works that would embody past, present, and future all in one ~1995: 311; see also 310; Ball @1927# 1996: 43; Mondrian @1938 44# 1986: 362; Snyder 1974a: 88; 1974b: 114!. Scientific theory with the highest degree of generality is timeless and placeless as well. 47 The concept of post-human derives from Douglas Coupland ~1996: 85!. 48 Suggested by Roberta Senechal de la Roche. The Western tradition of humanism places the person at the center of the universe. Pure sociology makes the person irrelevant.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

363

But you said you dreamed of pure sociology. What is a dream? What science is this? What theory? It sounds like a person. It is just common sense. Remember the theory of the subject: I am talking about myself. The subject is very close, and science is forbidden. The structure is commonsensical. The structure even dreams.

REFERENCES
Alexander, Jeffrey C. 198283. Theoretical Logic in Sociology. Berkeley: University of California Press. Four volumes. . 1987. The Centrality of the Classics. Pp. 1157 in Social Theory Today, edited by Anthony Giddens and Jonathan H. Turner. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press. Anderson, Nels. 1923. The Hobo: The Sociology of the Homeless Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ball, Hugo. @1927# 1996. Flight Out of Time: A Dada Diary. Berkeley: University of California Press. Barber, Bernard. 1961. Resistance by Scientists to Scientific Discovery. Science 134:596 602. Baumgartner, M. P. 1978. Law and Social Status in Colonial New Haven, 16391665. Pp. 15378 in Research in Law and Sociology: An Annual Compilation of Research, Volume 1, edited by Rita J. Simon. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. . 1985. Law and the Middle Class: Evidence from a Suburban Town. Law and Human Behavior 9:324. . 1988. The Moral Order of a Suburb. New York: Oxford University Press. . 1992. War and Peace in Early Childhood. Pp. 138 in Virginia Review of Sociology, Volume 1: Law and Conflict Management, edited by James Tucker. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. ~ed.!. 1999. The Social Organization of Law. San Diego: Academic Press ~second edition; first edition, 1973!. Bierstedt, Robert. 1981. American Sociological Theory: A Critical History. New York: Academic Press. Black, Donald. 1976. The Behavior of Law. New York: Academic Press. . 1979a. Common Sense in the Sociology of Law. American Sociological Review 44:1827. . 1979b. A Strategy of Pure Sociology. Pp. 149 68 in Theoretical Perspectives in Sociology, edited by Scott G. McNall. New York: St. Martins Press ~reprinted in Black 1998!. . 1987. Compensation and the Social Structure of Misfortune. Law & Society Review 21:56384 ~reprinted in Black 1998!. . 1989. Sociological Justice. New York: Oxford University Press. . 1995. The Epistemology of Pure Sociology. Law & Social Inquiry 20:82970. . 1997. The Lawyerization of Legal Sociology. Amici ~ Newsletter of the Sociology of Law Section, American Sociological Association! 5:47. . 1998. The Social Structure of Right and Wrong. San Diego: Academic Press ~revised edition; first edition, 1993!. . 2000. On the Origin of Morality. Journal of Consciousness Studies 7:10709. Black, Donald and M. P. Baumgartner. 1983. Toward a Theory of the Third Party. Pp. 84114 in Empirical Theories about Courts, edited by Keith O. Boyum and Lynn Mather. New York: Longman. Borg, Marian J. 1992. Conflict Management in the Modern World-System. Sociological Forum 7:26282. Bourdieu, Pierre. @1979# 1984. Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. . @1992# 1996. The Rules of Art: Genesis and Structure of the Literary Field. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Brekhus, Wayne. 1998. A Sociology of the Unmarked: Redirecting Our Focus. Sociological Theory 16:3451. Burtt, Edwin Arthur. 1954. The Metaphysical Foundations of Modern Science. Garden City, NY: Doubleday ~revised edition; first edition, 1952!. Cohen, Albert K. 1955. Delinquent Boys: The Culture of the Gang. New York: Free Press. Cohen, I. Bernard. 1985. Revolution in Science. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Collins, Randall. 1975. Conflict Sociology: Toward an Explanatory Science. New York: Academic Press. . 1986. Weberian Sociological Theory. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. . 1998. The Sociology of Philosophies. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Cooney, Mark. 1988. Two Traditions of Legal Sociology: An Existential Analysis. Paper presented at the annual meeting of the Law and Society Association, Vail, Colorado, June 18, 1988. . 1994. Evidence as Partisanship. Law & Society Review 28:83358.

364

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

. 1997. The Decline of Elite Homicide. Criminology 35:381 407. . 1998. Warriors and Peacemakers: How Third Parties Shape Violence. New York: New York University Press. Coupland, Douglas. 1996. Polaroids from the Dead. Toronto: HarperCollins. Crane, Diana. 1972. Invisible Colleges: Diffusion of Knowledge in Scientific Communities. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Crick, Francis. 1988. What Mad Pursuit: A Personal View of Scientific Discovery. New York: Basic Books. Dahrendorf, Ralf. 1959. Class and Class Conflict in Industrial Society. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press ~revised edition; first edition, 1957 !. . @1961# 1968. Values and Social Science: The Value Dispute in Perspective. Pp. 118 in Essays in the Theory of Society, by Ralf Dahrendorf. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. Dal, Salvador. @1964# 1986. Diary of a Genius. New York: Prentice Hall Press. Darwin, Charles. @1859# 1967. On the Origin of Species. New York: Atheneum ~facsimile of the first edition!. Davis, Murray S. 1971. Thats Interesting! Towards a Phenomenology of Sociology and a Sociology of Phenomenology. Philosophy of the Social Sciences 1:309 44. Desmond, Adrian and James Moore. @1991# 1992. Darwin. New York: Warner Books. de Tocqueville, Alexis. @1835 40# 1969. Democracy in America. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. Two volumes. de Waal, Frans. 1989. Peacemaking among Primates. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. . 1996. Good Natured: The Origins of Right and Wrong in Humans and Other Animals. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Dollard, John. 1937. Caste and Class in a Southern Town. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Durkheim, Emile. @1893# 1964. The Division of Labor in Society. New York: Free Press. . @1895# 1964. The Rules of Sociological Method. New York: Free Press. . @1897# 1951. Suicide: A Study in Sociology. New York: Free Press. . @1906# 1953. The Determination of Moral Facts. Pp. 3579 in Sociology and Philosophy. Glencoe, IL: Free Press ~first published 1924!. . @1912# 1995. The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. New York: Free Press. Durkheim, Emile and Marcel Mauss. @190102# 1963. Primitive Classification. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Einstein, Albert. @1923# 1934. Principles of Research. Address on the occasion of Max Plancks sixtieth birthday. Pp. 1924 in The World as I See It. New York: Covici Friede Publishers ~first published 1933!. Elias, Norbert. @1987# 1994. Reflections on a Life. Cambridge, U.K.: Polity Press. Feuer, Lewis S. ~ed.!. 1959. Marx and Engels: Basic Writings on Politics and Philosophy. Garden City, NY: Anchor Books. . 1982. Einstein and the Generations of Science. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction Publishers ~second edition; first edition, 1974!. Feyerabend, Paul. 1975. Against Method: Outline of an Anarchistic Theory of Knowledge. London: Verso. . 1995. Killing Time: The Autobiography of Paul Feyerabend. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Frazer, James G. @1890# 1981. The Golden Bough: The Roots of Religion and Folklore. New York: Avenel Books ~original title: The Golden Bough: A Study in Comparative Religion !. Two volumes. Friedman, Milton. 1953. The Methodology of Positive Economics. Pp. 3 43 in Essays in Positive Economics, by Milton Friedman. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Fuchs, Stephan. 1992. The Professional Quest for Truth: A Social Theory of Science and Knowledge. Albany: State University of New York Press. . 1997. A Sociological Theory of Objectivity. Science Studies 11:426. Fuchs, Stephan and Douglas A. Marshall. 1998. Across the Great ~and Small! Divides. Soziale Systeme 4: 631. Geertz, Clifford. 1973. Thick Description: Toward an Interpretive Theory of Culture. Pp. 330 in The Interpretation of Cultures, by Clifford Geertz. New York: Basic Books. . @1975# 1983. Common Sense as a Cultural System. Pp. 7393 in Local Knowledge: Further Essays in Interpretive Anthropology, by Clifford Geertz. New York: Basic Books. Gell-Mann, Murray. 1994. The Quark and the Jaguar: Adventures in the Simple and the Complex. New York: W. H. Freeman. Glaser, Barney G. and Anselm L. Strauss. 1967. The Discovery of Grounded Theory: Strategies for Qualitative Research. New York: Aldine de Gruyter. Goffman, Erving. 1959. The Presentation of Self in Everyday Life. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. . 1967. Interaction Ritual: Essays on Face-to-Face Behavior. Garden City, NY: Doubleday. Goodfield, June. @1981# 1982. An Imagined World: A Story of Scientific Discovery. New York: Penguin Books. Greenberg, Clement. @1958# 1961. American-Type Painting. Pp. 20829 in Art and Culture: Critical Essays. Boston: Beacon Press ~revised version; first published, 1955!.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

365

Greene, Brian. 1999. The Elegant Universe: Superstrings, Hidden Dimensions, and the Quest for the Ultimate Theory. New York: W. W. Norton. Griffiths, John. 1984. The Division of Labor in Social Control. Pp. 3770 in Toward a General Theory of Social Control, Volume 1: Fundamentals, edited by Donald Black. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Hacking, Ian ~ed.!. 1981. Scientific Revolutions. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hawking, Stephen and Roger Penrose. 1996. The Nature of Space and Time. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Herbert, Frank. @1965# 1990. Dune. New York: Ace Books. Holtzman, Harry and Martin S. James ~eds.!. 1986. The New ArtThe New Life: The Collected Writings of Piet Mondrian. Boston: G. K. Hall & Company. Homans, George C. 1964. Bringing Men Back In. American Sociological Review 29:80918. . 1967. The Nature of Social Science. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Horwitz, Allan V. 1982. The Social Control of Mental Illness. New York: Academic Press. . 1990. The Logic of Social Control. New York: Plenum Press. Jasso, Guillermina. 1988. Principles of Theoretical Analysis. Sociological Theory 6:120. Kandinsky, Wassily. @1911# 1982. Whither the New Art? Pp. 96104 in Lindsay and Vergo 1982. . @1913# 1982. Painting as Pure Art. Pp. 34854 in Lindsay and Vergo 1982. Kauffman, Stuart. 1995. At Home in the Universe: The Search for Laws of Self-Organization and Complexity. New York: Oxford University Press. Keller, Evelyn Fox. 1983a. A Feeling for the Organism: The Life and Work of Barbara McClintock. New York: W. H. Freeman and Company. . 1983b. The Force of the Pacemaker Concept in Theories of Aggregation in Cellular Slime Mold. Pp. 15057 in Keller 1985a. . 1985a. Reflections on Gender and Science. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. . 1985b. A World of Difference. Pp. 15876 in Keller 1985a. Kelly, Kevin. 1994. Out of Control: The Rise of Neo-Biological Civilization. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley. Knorr Cetina, Karin. 1997. Sociality with Objects: Social Relations in Postsocial Knowledge Societies. Theory, Culture & Society: Explorations in Critical Social Science 14:130. Kruttschnitt, Candace. 1982. Women, Crime and Dependency: An Application of the Theory of Law. Criminology 19:495513. Kubler, George. 1962. The Shape of Time: Remarks on the History of Things. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Kuhn, Thomas S. 1962. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Latour, Bruno. 1987. Science in Action: How to Follow Scientists and Engineers through Society. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. . @1991# 1993. We Have Never Been Modern. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Latour, Bruno and Steve Woolgar. 1979. Laboratory Life: The Social Construction of Scientific Facts. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications. Lindsay, Kenneth C. and Peter Vergo ~eds.!. 1982. Kandinsky: Complete Writings on Art. Volume 1: 19011921. Boston: G. K. Hall & Company. Lightman, Alan and Owen Gingerich. 1992. When Do Anomalies Begin? Science 255:69095. Lingis, Alphonso. 1994. The Community of Those Who Have Nothing in Common. Bloomington: Indiana University Press. Luhmann, Niklas. @1984# 1995. Social Systems. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. . 1990. Essays on Self-Reference. New York: Columbia University Press. . 1995. Instead of a Preface to the English Edition: On the Concepts of Subject and Action. Pp. xxxvii xliv in Luhmann @1984# 1995. Lukes, Steven. 1973. Emile Durkheim: His Life and Work, a Historical and Critical Study. London: Allen Lane. Mailer, Norman. 1995. Portrait of Picasso as a Young Man. New York: Warner Books. Mannheim, Karl. 1936. Ideology and Utopia: An Introduction to the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World ~expanded version; first published, 1929!. Mason, Stephen F. 1962. A History of the Sciences. New York: Collier Books ~revised edition; first edition, 1956!. McAllister, James W. 1996. Beauty and Revolution in Science. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press. Medawar, P. B. 1963. Is the Scientific Paper a Fraud? The Listener ~September 12!:37778. Merton, Robert K. @1938# 1970. Science, Technology and Society in Seventeenth-Century England. New York: Harper & Row. . 1973. The Sociology of Science: Theoretical and Empirical Investigations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Miller, Arthur I. 1996. Insights of Genius: Imagery and Creativity in Science and Art. New York: Springer-Verlag.

366

SOCIOLOGICAL THEORY

Miller, Walter B. 1958. Lower Class Culture as a Generating Milieu of Gang Delinquency. Journal of Social Issues 14:513. Mondrian, Piet. @1936# 1986. Plastic Art and Pure Plastic Art. Pp. 288300 in Holtzman and James 1986. . @1938# 1986. Art Without Subject Matter. Pp. 30204 in Holtzman and James 1986. Monk, Ray. 1990. Ludwig Wittgenstein: The Duty of Genius. New York: Free Press. Morrill, Calvin. 1992. Vengeance among Executives. Pp. 5176 in Virginia Review of Sociology, Volume 1: Law and Conflict Management, edited by James Tucker. Greenwich, CT: JAI Press. . 1995. The Executive Way: Conflict Management in Corporations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Morrill, Calvin, Ellen Snyderman, and Edwin J. Dawson. 1997. Its Not What You Do, But Who You Are: Informal Social Control, Social Status, and Normative Seriousness in Organizations. Sociological Forum 12: 519 43. Mullis, Jeffery. 1995. Medical Malpractice, Social Structure, and Social Control. Sociological Forum 10: 135 63. Myrdal, Gunnar ~with the assistance of Richard Sterner and Arnold Rose!. 1944. An American Dilemma: The Negro Problem and Modern Democracy. New York: Harper and Brothers. Nietzsche, Friedrich. @1888# 1992. Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One Is. London: Penguin Books. Pais, Abraham. 1991. Niels Bohrs Times: In Physics, Philosophy, and Polity. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Parsons, Talcott. @1937# 1968. The Structure of Social Action: A Study in Social Theory with Special Reference to a Group of Recent European Writers. New York: Free Press. Two volumes. . 1951. The Social System. Glencoe, IL: Free Press. . 1954. Essays in Sociological Theory. New York: Free Press ~revised edition; first edition, 1949!. . 1968. Introduction to the Paperback Edition. Pp. vxiv in Parsons @1937# 1968. Pickering, Andrew. 1984. Constructing Quarks: A Sociological History of Particle Physics. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. . 1995. The Mangle of Practice: Time, Agency, and Science. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Poggi, Gianfranco. 1972. Images of Society: Essays on the Sociological Theories of Tocqueville, Marx, and Durkheim. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press. . 1993. Money and the Modern Mind: Georg Simmels Philosophy of Money. Berkeley: University of California Press. . 1996. Lego Quia Inutile: An Alternative Justification for the Classics. Pp. 39 47 in Social Theory and Sociology: The Classics and Beyond, edited by Stephen P. Turner. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. Polanyi, Michael. @1962# 1964. Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy. New York: Harper & Row ~revised edition; first edition, 1958!. Popper, Karl. @1934# 1968. The Logic of Scientific Discovery. New York: Harper & Row ~third edition; first English edition, 1959!. . @1961# 1964. The Poverty of Historicism. New York: Harper & Row ~third edition; first edition, 1957 !. . 1975. The Rationality of Scientific Revolutions. Pp. 80106 in Hacking 1981. Ringer, Fritz. 1997. Max Webers Methodology: The Unification of the Cultural and Social Sciences. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Schopenhauer, Arthur. @1859# 1969. The World as Will and Representation. New York: Dover Publications ~third edition; first edition, 1818; second edition with Volume 2, 1844!. Two volumes. Schwartz, Barry. 1981. Vertical Classification: A Study in Structuralism and the Sociology of Knowledge. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Sciulli, David. 1994. An Interview with Niklas Luhmann. Theory, Culture & Society 11:37 68. Segr, Emilio. @1976# 1980. From X-Rays to Quarks: Modern Physicists and Their Discoveries. New York: W. H. Freeman and Company. Senechal de la Roche, Roberta. 1996. Collective Violence as Social Control. Sociological Forum 11:97128. . 1997a. The Sociogenesis of Lynching. Pp. 4876 in Under Sentence of Death: Lynching in the South, edited by W. Fitzhugh Brundage. Chapel Hill: University of North Carolina Press. . 1997b. Why Is Collective Violence Collective? Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American Society of Criminology, San Diego, California, November 22, 1997. Serres, Michel ~with Bruno Latour!. @1990# 1995. Conversations on Science, Culture, and Time. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Silberman, Matthew. 1985. The Civil Justice Process: A Detroit Area Study. Orlando, FL: Academic Press. Simmel, Georg. @1908# 1950. The Sociology of Georg Simmel. New York: Free Press. Simonton, Dean Keith. 1984. Genius, Creativity, and Leadership: Historiometric Inquiries. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Snyder, Gary. 1974a. As for Poets. Pp. 8788 in Snyder 1974c. . 1974b. On As for Poets. Pp. 11314 in Snyder 1974c. . 1974c. Turtle Island. New York: New Directions.

DREAMS OF PURE SOCIOLOGY

367

Stinchcombe, Arthur L. 1968. Constructing Social Theories. New York: Harcourt, Brace & World. Storr, Anthony. 1988. Solitude: A Return to the Self. New York: Ballantine Books. Sulloway, Frank J. 1996. Born to Rebel: Birth Order, Family Dynamics, and Creative Lives. New York: Pantheon Books. Swanson, Guy E. 1960. The Birth of the Gods: The Origin of Primitive Beliefs. Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press. Traweek, Sharon. 1988. Beamtimes and Lifetimes: The World of High Energy Physics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Tucker, James. 1989. Employee Theft as Social Control. Deviant Behavior 10:31934. . 1999a. The Therapeutic Corporation. New York: Oxford University Press. . 1999b. Therapy, Organization, and the State: A Blackian Perspective. Pp. 7887 in Counseling and the Therapeutic State, edited by James J. Chriss. New York: Aldine de Gruyter. Turner, Stephen P. 1996. Introduction: Social Theory and Sociology. Pp. 116 in Social Theory and Sociology: The Classics and Beyond, edited by Stephen P. Turner. Cambridge, MA: Blackwell Publishers. Ward, Lester Frank. 1903. Pure Sociology: A Treatise on the Origin and Spontaneous Development of Society. New York: Macmillan. Watson, James D. @1968# 1969. The Double Helix: A Personal Account of the Discovery of the Structure of DNA. New York: New American Library. Weber, Max. @190405# 1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. New York: Charles Scribners Sons. . @1919# 1958. Science as a Vocation. Pp. 12956 in From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology, edited by H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York: Oxford University Press. . @1922# 1978. Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, edited by Guenther Roth and Claus Wittich. Berkeley: University of California Press ~reissued edition; first edition, 1968!. Two volumes. Weinberg, Steven. 1998. The Revolution That Didnt Happen. New York Review of Books 45 ~ Number 15, October 8!:4852. Whitley, Richard. 1984. The Intellectual and Social Organization of the Sciences. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Wilson, Edward O. 1994. Naturalist. Washington: Island Press. Winch, Peter. 1958. The Idea of a Social Science and Its Relation to Philosophy. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Wittgenstein, Ludwig. @1921# 1961. Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Woolgar, Steve. 1983. Irony in the Social Study of Science. Pp. 239 66 in Science Observed: Perspectives on the Social Study of Science, edited by Karin D. Knorr Cetina and Michael Mulkay. Beverly Hills, CA: Sage Publications. Zorbaugh, Harvey Warren. 1929. The Gold Coast and the Slum: A Sociological Study of Chicagos Near North Side. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

You might also like