You are on page 1of 15

European Journal of Social Theory

http://est.sagepub.com/

Why Remain `Classical'?


Franois Dubet European Journal of Social Theory 2007 10: 247 DOI: 10.1177/1368431007078891 The online version of this article can be found at: http://est.sagepub.com/content/10/2/247

Published by:
http://www.sagepublications.com

Additional services and information for European Journal of Social Theory can be found at: Email Alerts: http://est.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Subscriptions: http://est.sagepub.com/subscriptions Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Permissions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Citations: http://est.sagepub.com/content/10/2/247.refs.html

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2): 247260


Copyright 2007 Sage Publications: Los Angeles, London, New Delhi and Singapore

SYMPOSIUM
Theme 4: But Do We Still Not Need Some Sort of Theoretical Unication?

Why Remain Classical?


Franois Dubet
U N I V E R S I T D E B O R D E AU X - I I , B O R D E AU X , A N D E H E S S - C A D I S

As sociologists, we should ask ourselves the same sociological questions we so readily put when scrutinizing the intellectual and scientic productions of other disciplines. That is, whether the extremely particular type of knowledge of social phenomena called sociology can survive the passing of the specic contexts i.e. the dawning of industrial society and the forming of democratic nation-states and lines of questioning in and around which it came into being. Aristotle, Ibn Khaldun, Machiavelli, Hobbes, Spinoza and many other thinkers were certainly exceptional social thinkers, and we can accept the idea that they said most of what there was to say, but they cannot be considered sociologists. Despite, or indeed thanks to the existing hodge-podge of sociology textbooks and study programmes, there is a pantheon of sociologists and a version of sociology that can be considered classical, if only because contemporary sociologists are constantly returning to them, including as a means to generate new ideas.1 Given how useful expert social knowledge and specialized branches of the discipline are considered in our societies, given how fully sociological-style argumentation and demonstration partake of decision-making today and the legitimacy of the decisions made, and given how close the tie is between sociological reexivity and modernity, as Giddens put it, we need not worry about the academic and professional survival of sociology. But a discipline can survive academically even after losing its unity and epistemological raison dtre. This is what happened to geography and psychology, which have yielded to the battering ram of stronger disciplines: geography by earth sciences, economics, and sociology; psychology by psychoanalysis, ethnology, the neuro- and cognitive sciences. Can sociology hold its own against more formalized disciplines, such as economics, or better established ones, such as history and political philosophy, when the sociological ground in which it took root and developed is transformed or disintegrates?

www.sagepublications.com

DOI: 10.1177/1368431007078891
Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

248

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


The Programme of Classical Sociology The unity of classical sociology derives not so much from the answers proposed by the founding fathers of the discipline as their questions or programme: to dene and study society; that is, invent it as a singular object of science. If we do not wish to extend the boundaries of sociology to include all manners of understanding and explaining social life, e.g., those of La Botie, Rousseau, and Adam Smith, we have to think of the sociological tradition as it came to us and impressed itself upon us: as a particular social philosophy that constructed a set of accounts of modernity using a few principles that since then have been innitely repeated and rearranged: rationalization, individualism, the division of labour, and some others (Nisbet, 1967; Martuccelli, 1999). All these accounts are interwoven in the works of the major authors and function as so many variations on the binary opposition traditionmodernity; all are dominated by a sociological sensibility that combines a sense of something like fate providence was de Tocquevilles word with an insuppressible worry about the risks entailed by modernity. In this sense, a kind of tragic consciousness attaches to the foundations of sociology, a consciousness which goes some way to explaining the eternal return to the classics and the eternal freshness of rereading them. All the founding fathers perceived modernity as the product of necessary developments that no one could resist, but they never fully yielded to its charms. Anomie, alienation, the masses each founding father contributed his small hell, his fear of seeing modernity modulate into dehumanized barbarity. The most brilliant explanation of the development and nature of the sacred, Durkheims Les Formes lmentaires de la vie religieuse, cannot be dissociated from a conception of modernity as disenchanted, and the underlying fear of same. And behind Webers forefronting of the religious sources of capitalism is the haunting fear that these passions [will] directly imprint this pursuit with the character of a sporting contest (Weber, 2002: 124). While sociologists did not perhaps invent the idea of society as a more or less functional whole strongly identied with the national state understood at the time to be taking the place of traditional communities they did make us feel the force of that idea. Society is the theoretical, general construction of the nationstate. Sociologys canonical conceptions are often just ways of implementing narratives of modernity: they transform those narratives into stable systems into society. Socialization, social control, the individual, institutions, social classes, legitimacy, social action all appear as simultaneously synchronic and diachronic, subjective and objective processes that bring together actor and system. The terms do not so much designate objects of study as offer solutions to the question of the nature and mechanisms of the social order: Why and how is it that modern societies hold together when it seems that everything is ultimately swept away by the ux of change? The unity of this thinking seems fairly strong to me, and sociologists re-readings of it often give rise to debates and tensions between holism and individualism, for example that seem reconstituted, trite, excessive, unimaginative: assertions that Durkheim was more of an individualist than he let on in his more scientic statements, and that the Weber who studied the

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

249

great religious systems was less of an individualist than the Weber who theorized rational action. Many such contemporary readings cloud the issue, turning Durkheim or Marx into individualists or structuralists who didnt know thats what they were. But we know that tradition is often nothing more than a projection of the present onto the past. The focus of classical sociology was not social phenomena or social facts, but society conceived as the way modern social life is organized. We may be surprised to see how the spontaneous functionalism of most pre-1960s sociologists, their conception of society as an integrated system, a sort of all-encompassing mechanism in which division of labour, institutions, social control, and conict itself all worked to shape an order that they unanimously thought of as no longer subject to natural ties or shared belief in the same gods we may be surprised to see how this idea has fallen into oblivion. The apprentice sociologists of the 1960s, Parsonians and Marxists alike, learned to think of this representation as an obvious fact. Its power was, and is, due to its capacity both to preserve and be critical without those actions affecting its fundamental nature. The feeling it gave us was of being confronted with alternative versions of the same narrative or myth. While sociology may be thought of as the social philosophy that carried forward the idea of society, it is also a particular philosophy in that it sought to be a positive science. The fact that sociology involves writing and style does not make it an art, and most classic sociologists sought in various ways historical methods, statistics, comparative study, experimentation to lay foundations for objective knowledge. This social philosophy endowed itself with methods, and accepted empirical criticism of its results. Though ours is no Popperian world, clearly not just anything goes in sociology. Moreover, it is fair to think that sociology has its own stock of methods, which, while not making it a genuine science, do make it something more than a philosophy founded on conceptual coherence. It is of course even less a literary exercise, though sociological writing does exist. I would be fairly willing to defend sociological methods and their demands and requirements as effective means of parrying the twin dangers of going off the subjective deep end (more readily imputable to journalists than sociologists) and reaching epistemological heights sometimes so lofty that anyone calling for nomological sociology would then hardly dare attempt to put it into practice. At the very least, sociology can be recognized as a discipline because it requires discipline: rules of demonstration, the establishing of bundles of facts. Traditions Revisited We can begin by observing that the sociological tradition is in ne shape. One need only run an eye down university programmes and the tables of contents of sociology textbooks to see that they are themselves a kind of sacred history where all paradigms are engendered rationally. More seriously, most theoretical works considered essential present themselves as combinations and syntheses of classical sociology: Simmel and Durkheim for Parks; Durkheim and Weber

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

250

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


for Parsons; Durkheim, Weber, and Marx for Bourdieu; Weber and Marx for Touraine; de Tocqueville, Simmel and Weber for Boudon; Marx, Mead, Parsons and Weber for Habermas, etc. Before asking whether contemporary sociological theory is continuous with this tradition, it should be observed that the sociological tradition functions as a source of inspiration and above all an inexhaustible resource in the quest for legitimacy. Appeals to authority have not disappeared, and the classics are continually cited to establish the legitimacy of highly contemporary theories or theoretical analyses. Sometimes a classic is rediscovered; at other times an old text is made into a classic the case of Simmel in France in recent years; some classics, such as Marx and Parsons, are quickly forgotten; and traditions, such as that of the Chicago School, are invented. Sociology does not really wish to break with its history, because over and beyond its methods and theoretical choices, that history still seems like the best guarantee of belonging to the sociology family. Conversely, some works that present themselves as radically new are in fact recycling the most classic notions, adding a few linguistic inventions that are chic rather than truly innovative. Attachment to tradition does not necessarily lead to devotional trotting out of the same old ideas. New combinations emerge, just as new music can be written without changing scales or harmonies. And, frankly, attachment to the sociological tradition is a good thing because it keeps alive sociologys concern to link actor and system, explain one by the other in both directions. Sociology seeks to answer the two questions why? and to what end? by means of the idea of society. This is its real value. And from this perspective, it seems to me we can still accept Lockwoods distinction between systemic and social integration if, that is, we agree that the project of classical sociology has always been to link the two together by showing how one engenders the other in a sort of loop in itself problematic (Lockwood, 1964; Archer, 2003). Sociological tradition thus allows us to resist the danger of a break between the system and nothing but, where society and culture function as purely objective mechanisms, and the actor and nothing but, in which actor intentionality seems almost as if it were pure freedom. The sociologists calling, as I see it, is to get a grip on this problem; to think, as C. Wright Mills put it, of private troubles as public issues and public issues as aggregations of private troubles (Wright Mills, 1959). After all, the canonical texts of sociological tradition became so for a reason: Suicide works to show that the most personal experiences are caught up in larger mechanisms; in the opposite direction, The Protestant Ethic shows that the most private of beliefs engender radical economic mutations. It matters little what path is chosen here; the point is to link action and the system in one analysis where the explanation gives rise to understanding and the reverse is just as necessary. It makes sense that Bourdieus sociology is the most widely read, taught, and quoted in France today and throughout a large part of the world. Bourdieus thought can be considered both a synthesis of classical sociology and a critique of it, both the apogee of that tradition and the thinking that came to slay it. Apogee in that it is unlikely that the integration of actor and system has ever been presented so compellingly, seamlessly, in a language that effaces all rifts and

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

251

doubts thanks to its subjectless projects, its necessary freedoms, its disinterested interests, its clear-eyed blindness, its necessary exceptions. Critique because the social order involves a kind of domination that refuses to acknowledge itself, change is an illusion, immobility a ruse. Bourdieu used Durkheim, Marx, Weber the three pillars of Le sens pratique to obliterate the opposition between LviStrauss and Sartre that dominated France in the 1960s (Bourdieu, 1980). Undeniably, this theoretical and rhetorical power is the beacon that has attracted, or repelled, the members of an entire generation of French sociologists, just as an entire generation of American sociologists existed only in relation to Parsons. As for the method, Bachelards epistemology of the epistemological break made it possible for Bourdieusian sociology to be a science that does not really submit to validation criteria able to demonstrate that a theory is false. This reclarication of the bases of sociological tradition also marked the decline of that tradition, annihilating its open, anxious questions with the internal coherence of its answers. How to resist this theoretical power? Many have given in to it, especially sociology teachers. Researchers, on the other hand, have tended to nd more questions in it than answers. As for the popularity of Bourdieus work, and the appearance of his name in street demonstrations, Im tempted to explain by the fact that his theory has been the strongest defence of the idea of society, precisely the idea that galvanizes defenders of the nation-state and its institutions.2 Between Rationality, Culture, and the Subject The move in France to put classical sociology behind us may be understood with the help of the following idea: there is no continuity or reversibility between actor and system, subjectivity and objectivity.3 Action is no longer perceived as the subjective component of the system but has become instead a problem in itself. And after the structuralist-functionalist-Marxist wave of the 1960s and 1970s, the crushing majority of theoretical texts in the past 30 years have focused on action subjective action. This leaves us two ways of partaking in the return of the actor (Touraine, 1984) and getting out of the circle Bourdieu closed. The rst is methodological individualism in its utilitarian mould, in any case; that of Coleman and Gary Becker. The individual actor is rational and pursues his/her interests as a function of the situations in which he/she nds himself/ herself and the information he/she possesses. The idea is to apply micro-economic reasoning to conduct that seems non-economic, such as voting, marriage, school choice, delinquency, collective mobilization, organizations, social mobility, etc. Let me say that I have no moral repugnance for this type of reasoning since my own empirical studies have convinced me that much of social behaviour can easily be explained this way. In fact, it can be disturbing to see individuals who behave in this way plunge into abysses of self-justication, seeking to transform their honourable interests into disinterested virtue. Each of us is a bit Paretian. My reservations with regard to methodological individualism are of a different order. On the one hand, if we understand the social system as the tting

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

252

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


together of a culture and a social structure, its hard to think of it as a mere effect of the aggregation of individual behaviours. We would do better in that case to speak of overall socio-economic context, or situation, than of society. In fact, studies guided by this approach generally take cultures and social structures for existing realities that could not possibly be explained in terms other than constraints and action frameworks. It is legitimate to think of education as a market (for example), but can the same go for school programmes/curricula and teaching patterns? An overly narrow conception of rationality drastically limits the models reach, and threatens to turn sociology into a eld of micro-economics. On the other hand, the good reasons game, in its attempt to resist this danger, extends the notion of rationality to the point where the model covers all families of motivation and action. Rationality then becomes so distended that it serves as the basis for a kind of cognitive sociology wherein it encompasses beliefs, traditions, and moral and aesthetic judgements (Boudon, 2003). Moreover, the celebrated example of Olsons collective action paradox is paradoxical rst and foremost because it shows that collective mobilization cannot be the product of interest aggregation alone (Olson, 1965). In order to mobilize rationally, a whole series of irrational elements such as beliefs, feelings of belonging, shame, etc. have to combine becoming non-rational components of the enlarged version of rationality. The model swallows up all, and comprehensive sociology does not so much study the subjective good reasons that actors themselves proffer as it deduces those reasons from actors choices and discourses. This kind of sociology requires another kind upstream of it, a sociology that can explain action frameworks and ensure that the system, or society, is not a pure effect of aggregation; its own natural inclination is to explain behaviours by examining increasingly ne-grained empirical material. In response to this theoretical family, other families have developed which, while not being necessarily holistic, do afrm that sociologys object today is what could be called ethical or moral individualism. Here the key terms are social tie (an expression I dont understand very well), gift, individual, identity, subject. In much less radical fashion than classical sociology, the insistence here is on the tension between the system, perceived as a set of objective uxes and forces, and the individual, perceived as a subject concerned to realize himself, herself. Whereas methodological individualism surely hearkens back to eighteenth-century political economy, moral individualism is of Hegelian and phenomenological liation. Touraines thinking is a clear illustration of this option, afrming as it does with increasing clarity the non-social character of the subject, who is dened not so much by society as against it meaning in turn that all in sociology is not social. Though I feel fairly close to this last family, I would be tempted to say that some of the same criticisms apply to it as to its competitor. It constructs social life in opposition to utilitarianism and the market, thus tending to reduce the system to blind, purely objective mechanics and ultimately reintroducing a set of actorvs.-society dualisms: solidarity vs. the market, the community vs. rationality, subject vs. individual, etc. dualisms of the very sort that classic sociological thinking sought to overcome.

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

253

At this time, the theoretical space of contemporary sociology as it may be observed in France seems structured by three major poles. In the rst call it pole A action is reduced to the system; in the second, B, the system is a product of rational action; in the third, C, the two terms stand in opposition. Clearly whats happening is that the very idea of society as the improbable, problematic integration of social integration and systemic integration is weakening, and it is reasonable to think that despite bows and curtsies to the classics, this is indeed a break from the classic age of sociology understood as the social philosophy that invented the idea of society. Habermas, as we know, proposed a complete separation between the problems of system and action. A sociologist like Touraine is perfectly in line with this when he afrms that sociology has to rid itself of the idea of society, whereas Boudon dissolves most of the classical concepts of society in an elementary syntax of rational action that becomes a cognitive grammar. Both approaches, however opposed they may be, must be granted the virtue of following their respective lines of reasoning out to the end. But most sociologists, who use theories rather than doing theory, do not go that far and in fact work far below the ambitious level of classical sociology. Dispersion in Interactions Looking over the space of a generation, we can only observe that the programme of classical sociology has gradually been broken down into a series of specialized sociology elds whose theoretical foundations are often quite local and result from an accumulation of strong individual works. This dispersion is due to the professionalization and massication of the sociology eld.4 A whole set of specialized sociologies have developed, each of which constitutes a relatively autonomous world, with its own reviews, its own games of reference and reverence as if there were a tight correspondence between its theories and its objects of research. We have to acknowledge the fact that young researchers often orient themselves this way in the disciplinary space: when they choose this or that empirical object indeed, because they choose it they take the theoretical package associated with it. In this way, multiple regional theoretical traditions have been created, as attested to by thesis bibliographies and what are considered de rigueur citations. It is hard to see these regional traditions as anything other than sedimentations and fashions that produce synthetic overviews the multiple Sociologies of . . . manuals: Sociology of the family, of education, Occupational sociology that in turn handle traditions as if they were so many bits of patchwork precisely because their purpose is to present a synthetic overview. In general, the outline of these works follows the conventional order, going from macro to micro, objective to subjective, culturalism to rationalism, this balanced with a critique of functionalism, itself reduced to straw man, necessary village idiot, and at the end ne-tuned down to symbolic interactionism and constructivism. Every sociology specialty arranges its own tradition for itself, its own tranquil dramaturgy, thereby fragmenting sociology in a way that

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

254

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


responds fairly well to social and academic demand. I attach great importance to these manuals, given that they were written for students, and to these articles and theses because objectively they represent the crushing majority of sociological production. Sociology seems to have become a science of social problems, as is already the case in some bookstores where sociology books are shelved in the school, social work, immigration, organizations, health, and gender sections, among others. This type of fragmentation explains the very real practical triumph of interactionism, and it confers a degree of theoretical legitimacy on descriptions and analyses that simply dont go very far, that dont do much more than string along a few heartfelt truisms: situations and data are constructed; individuals act within contexts; they want to get someone else to do the dirty work; norms are debatable; deviance is learned; identity is produced by how others see one but people use a mixture of cunning and cynicism to resist against this; youve got to cool the mark out, etc. All these micro-mechanisms which are of great importance, of course thus acquire a kind of high theoretical dignity; the neness of the observations is touted. This passion for the micro is surely understandable after the functionalist orgies of the 1970s, but the danger is that it will turn sociology into an exercise either commanded by genius or doomed to insignicance. Goffman and a few others were and are geniuses putting their novelistic talents to work within the pragmatist tradition of James and Pierce (Joseph, 2004). What I mean by insignicance is that this kind of sociology could never tell us anything more than what its telling us now, which amounts to nothing more than what the actors themselves say fairly spontaneously; namely that they manage, they get by. Any number of novelists, beginning with Proust or Goffmanian lmmakers such as Robert Altman may be preferable to this. I would tend to take the interactionist cluster very seriously, precisely since it is part of the move away from classical sociology. What troubles me is that the idea of society is becoming useless without this being perceived as a problem; without our looking any more at how we get from individual interactions to collective facts. While it is useful to study classroom interactions, we hop uneasily from such interactions to statistical regularities for pupil cohorts very often we make as if the connections were clear. We have a good understanding of how a person becomes a marijuana smoker but we dont go further to explain why a given society smokes more or less than another. My main reason for being concerned about the practical success of interactionism is that as a teacher I see the charm it has for sociology students for what seems a very simple reason: society is no longer Society; it has been reduced to what individuals see and say of it. Students seem to think that once youve described what actors do and presented what they say, the work is done. For the rest, anything is possible and nothing seems connected to social life. The assumption seems to be that on the one hand you have objective, reied mechanisms that no one knows anything about any more, except that they are the market; on the other, actors real-life experience, which sociologists are supposedly experts on in particular, the socialproblem family. In fact, never has there seemed to be such a radical dissociation

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

255

between objectivity and subjectivity once again, exactly the dissociation that classical sociology refused to accept. A few of the ner feelings, democratic and respectful of identities, provide this sociological style with honourable, vaguely critical normative underpinnings. In Chapter 1 of these students theses, you set the scene, using general knowledge accumulated about a situation and a group; in Chapter 2, you present minute description of the behaviour of a few individuals; in Chapter 3, you take care of the epistemological by saying that the analysis and action categories are themselves constructed. In fact, because in interactionism, interactions are thought of as social reality itself rather than one level of social life that can only be explained by other such levels as the notion of role allowed, regardless of its weaknesses interactionism is perfectly malleable, readily adaptable to all possible conceptions of the system, including the most critical. The return to honest, straightforward Marxism in British new education sociology offers a clear illustration of these twists and turns. Obviously in my case against interactionism, I am not claiming that the approach fails to teach us anything and I am certainly not claiming that the works of Becker, Goffman, and Lemert are insignicant. What I do think is that this approach sweeps too many problems under the rug as Goffman said with irony, recalling that while social systems were undoubtedly very important, he wouldnt be talking about them. Actually, the problem is nothing less than the theoretical status of this theoretical family. Intermediate Considerations The intellectual space of current French sociology seems to me to be laid out thus: 1 2 3 4 The critical theory of reproduction is both the crystallization and a disenchanted reversal of classical sociology. Methodological individualism has tried to reconstruct classical sociology under the aegis of utilitarianism and broadened rationality. A return of the actor has been constructed on the basis of a kind of ethical, reexive, self-made individualism. Most sociological theories being used today are specialized and often use a kind of soft interactionism to escape the grip of classical sociology without choosing a stance and without looking like they are/arent choosing one.

The theories implicit in (1), (2), and (3) may be thought of as great theories because the intention is that they be genuinely general constructions; they are visions of the world that, whatever else may be said of them, have taken their building materials from the pantheon of the founding fathers (whose unity I readily admit to be a pure construction; however, that unity is operative in sociologists minds). (1) bets all on the system and reduces action to programming or an effect of the systems own contradictions. (2) understands action as the manifestation of individuals reasons. Finally, (3) continuously underscores

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

256

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


system-actor tensions while radically separating the two. Everything that sociological tradition worked to hold together is coming apart. To historians of sociology, this state of affairs does not seem new: there have always been several ways of apprehending the social (Berthelot, 1990). But how can we resist the contrary pleasures of ever new and nothing new? We could also reasonably think that sociology has something to do with society, and that the fragmenting of paradigms we see in the discipline may be explained by very real changes in what we are nonetheless still obliged to think of as Society, especially since most of these changes were anticipated by classical sociology, already thought of as a combination of various accounts of modernity.5 How could the ideas of system and social structure, the idea of society itself, ever have held their own against transformations of the nation-state dened as an integrated culture, economy, and instance of political sovereignty? How could we possibly believe that the promotion of the individuals sovereignty wouldnt affect the mechanisms that engender actors and those that engender social regulation? How could we imagine that accentuations of the division of labour would not deal a serious blow to the idea of a stable, integrated system? Sociology has become so patently plural because the social world has itself become plural, and no central principle now seems up to the task of explaining it. There are surely good reasons why the classic sociologist most likely to be called to the rescue is Weber, for he was surely the founding father who best resisted the pathos of the unity of social life idea. Weber is a pure theorist who never proposed a unied theory, and this explains his many liations with Nietzscheism, phenomenology, and methodological individualism, among others. Who else could have had the honour of inspiring the Frankfurt School, Schutz, and Boudon? Is it because the world has changed, or did the classical sociology programme exhaust itself? The answer doesnt really matter here. If my analysis is credible, the most reasonable position becomes that which I share with a few others: sociological theory should work from the twofold principle of heterogeneous action and heterogeneous system. This is a means of being loyal to the classical sociology programme while defending middle-range theories by which I do not mean regional ones.6 It favours the idea that sociological theory should bring to light mechanisms borrowed from (1), (2), and (3), rather than sociological laws. If we accept that social life and society no longer have a centre while continuing to insist that social life requires relative order and local unity, then clearly the space of sociological theory can only be dialogic and should be able to coherently combine different conceptions of actions. All sciences are not physics; most of them discover and demonstrate mechanisms rather than laws, and that is already a great deal. Mid-range Theories for Holding it Together Given that culture, society, and the economy are tending to separate out into increasingly autonomous subsystems, it is understandable that a whole set of

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

257

theories have taken on the essential task of constructing ways of tting together the various composite areas. J.-D. Reynauds regulation theory and, in a completely different direction, the theory of conventions, are exemplary in this connection. Mid-range theories are not local ones adapted to a particular type of problemobject such as delinquency or school inequality. They are theories that seek to explain certain mechanisms while only being able to manage this by turning to theories other than themselves. They require both extremely ne grains and coarser ones. They are combinations, assemblages, that do not claim to produce a general vision of society yet cannot do without a representation of society and the concepts it implies: institution, role, classes, power, domination, change, etc. In France, the work of Latour, for example, and Boltanski and Thvenot belong to this family of theories. They offer a point of view on social action without claiming to gather all the threads together, since most of these constructions take off from the postulate that action develops in a plural world, that there are several levels or registers of action, several grammars or modes of justication (Boltanski and Thvenot, 1987; Latour, 1987). Some radicalize this point of view and are moving towards a kind of pragmatics of action sociology, more or less directly inspired by the ethnomethodology critique, itself perhaps the most radical and interesting break from classical sociology.7 Others continue to be more attached to classical sociology and resolutely engage in a kind of combination rhetoric. My own work belongs to this latter approach, and therefore runs the risk of not making the break and being less visible. I would qualify the attitude Ive chosen as neo-classic because it is characterized by a mode of theoretical elaboration less engaged in theoretical discussions than an attempt to resolve empirical and quite practical problems: Why is pupils motivation to work in school so low? Why is work becoming increasingly stressful when, objectively, it is less heavy than before? Why do young people in working-class neighbourhoods manifest irrational violence? This type of theoretical practice, impure because embedded in empirical research that is not primarily concerned to demonstrate or produce a theory but rather to resolve enigmas, is guided by certain principles. But the cameralist style is not necessarily an easy one to do. The following are some of the principles that led me to propose a theory of social experience (Dubet, 1994): 1 As we move away from the central gure of society developed by classical sociology, social action is motivated by several types of logic, one dened by integration mechanisms, another by strategic rationality, and a third by the relation to self or subjectivation. Each of these types of logic refers to a process in which social subsystems the subsystem of norms and identities, that of markets, that of culture are separated from one another. Society is structured around no central principle (Bell, 1978; Dubet and Martuccelli, 1998). Each type may be explained objectively in terms of its link to the subsystem it refers to, according to processes whose nature was established by classical sociology theories: socialization, limited rationality, and subjectivation.

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

258

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


4 Sociology studies the mechanisms that shape the conditions of activity and the nature of that activity activity which creates unity in all places where society is being effaced. This means that social experience is necessarily a cognitive, normative process, as shown by practical conceptions of justice. This sociological approach is ultimately concerned less to describe society than show how it is produced.

This type of theoretical development owes much to theories other than itself. For example, it readily accepts that statistical regularities can reveal mechanisms of holistic formation that determine behaviours and opinions and the socialstructure hypothesis is considered necessary. It also understands that within these structural frameworks, behaviour can be explained in terms of games and choice matrices. Finally, it accepts the idea that actors cannot be reduced to either of these two types of logic and that because they have no choice but to deal with them, they are capable of criticizing and transforming them, thereby producing unity when society no longer provides any. We could call all of these programmes A, B, and C, on condition that those three matrices are understood to determine the space of sociology at a time when the classic idea of society is slipping out from under us. But the slipping away of society, this end of the functionalist illusion, should not invalidate certain of classical sociologys questions. Nor does not exempt us from answering the questions it raised about the nature of the social order, domination, legitimacy, conicts . . . Conclusion Why maintain such a circumscribed, lack-lustre position when we may well think that the point of sociological theory is to construct a general theory which engenders deductive propositions? First, there are several ways of doing theory, several intellectual temperaments, one of which consists in starting with a set of empirical problems starting, therefore, with the aporia and impasses left by earlier theories. Theory is not made exclusively on blackboards; it is also made on the lab table. Sociological theory develops by responding to new questions or providing new answers to old questions without it being necessary to redene all foundations of the edice every time. Second, as I see it, the right reason not to break with classical sociology is that it allows us to hold together what has tended to come undone with the decline of the idea of society. Obviously we dont want to eternally repeat the classics in a series of reverential gestures. The point is rather to hold onto their vocation, i.e., to construct a reasoned representation of social life, and of what we will continue to call society, having no better term for it, even when society can no longer be identied with the nation-state. Sociology appeared at a time when modernity was destroying traditional social worlds; it appeared just as it was once again becoming possible to recompose an integrated image of social life. Now that this rst version of modernity seems to have come apart, if we dont want representation of the social world to be boiled down to

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

Dubet

Why Remain Classical?

259

an opposition between market rationality and the ineffable subjectivities of individuals or irreducibility of cultures, it is more than ever necessary to afrm the relevance of the sociological vocation. Constructing sociology today implies resolutely rejecting both the end of history and the clash of civilizations. Acknowledgements
This article was translated by Amy Jacobs.

Notes
1 I am of course talking about sociology as it exists in France which is not exclusively French sociology. Other traditions exist elsewhere. 2 Bourdieu reviens! [Come back to us, Bourdieu!] was among the slogans heard in demonstrations by French civil servants in spring 2003 a clear indication that they identied their cause with the defence of society as a whole, society itself. 3 I am referring here solely to French sociology, or more exactly the sociology read by most French sociologists (I am aware of what I dont know, and of the strong articiality of any world sociology, even in this era of globalization). 4 Since the 1960s, the number of professional sociologists in France has gone from a few dozen to nearly a thousand more, if we count unemployed sociology PhDs. 5 This is why the notion of post-modernity does not seem very useful to me. We are simply still more modern. 6 It is worth noting that Mertons mid-range theories seem to have better stood the test of time than Parsons supreme theory. 7 This perception can be refuted if we remember that Garnkel sought to re-appropriate the major issues of Parsonian sociology.

References
Archer, M. (2003) Structure, Agency and the Internal Conversation. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Bell, D. (1978) The Cultural Contradictions of Capitalism. New York: Basic Books. Berthelot, J.-M. (1990) Lintelligence du social. Paris: PUF. Boltanski, L. and Thvenot, L. (1987) Les Economies de la grandeur. Paris: PUF. Boudon, R. (2003) Raison, bonnes raisons. Paris: PUF. Bourdieu, P. (1980) Le sens pratique. Paris: Editions de Minuit. Dubet, F. (1994) Sociologie de lexprience. Paris: Seuil. Dubet, F. and Martuccelli, D. (1998) Dans quelle socit vivons-nous? Paris: Seuil. Joseph, I. (2004) Lathlte moral et lenquteur modeste, in B. Karsenti and L. Qur (eds) La croyance et lenqute: Raisons pratiques. Paris: Editions de lEHESS. Latour, B. (1987) La science en action. Paris: Folio. Lockwood, D. (1964) Social Integration and System Integration, in G.K. Zollschan and G.K. Kirsch (eds) Explorations in Social Change. Boston: Houghton-Mifin. Martuccelli, D. (1999) Sociologies de la modernit. Paris: Gallimard.

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

260

European Journal of Social Theory 10(2)


Nisbet, R. (1967) The Sociological Tradition. New York: Basic Books. Olson, M. (1965) The Logic of Collective Action. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Touraine, A. (1984) Le retour de lacteur. Paris: Fayard. Weber, M. (2002) The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. S. Kalberg. Oxford: Blackwell. Wright Mills, C. (1959) The Sociological Imagination. New York: Oxford University Press.
Franois Dubet is Professor of Sociology at the Universit de Bordeaux-2 and a member of the CADIS (EHESS). His recent books include: Lcole des chances: Quest-ce quune cole juste? (Seuil, 2004), and Injustices: Lexprience des ingalits au travail (Seuil, 2006). [email: francois.dubet@sociologie.u-bordeaux2.fr]

Downloaded from est.sagepub.com by Filip Iliev on September 23, 2010

You might also like