You are on page 1of 215

7.6.

07

HOME

FEDERAL
theory

MAX FRENKEL

Centre for Research on Federal Financial Relations

Max Frenkel (Zuchwil/Switzerland) 1986/2007

CONTENTS

Top Index End

CHAPTER A. B. C. C.1 C.11 C.12 C.121 C.13 Introduction Antagonism or Harmony Democracy Forms of Democracy Democracy as a regime Democracy and Democratization Opinion Polls Democracy as autocracy in Disguise

C.2 C.21 C.211 C.212 C.22 C.221 C.222 C.2221 C.2222 C.23 C.231 D. D.1. D.2 D.21 D.22 D.3 D.31 D.32 D.321 D.3211 D.3212 D.33 D.34 D.341 D.342 D.3421 D.3422 D.3423 D.4

Functional Aspects of Democracy Democracy and Learning in political systems Maintenance of Learning Capacity Problem Solving Capacity Democracy and Stability of Political Systems Conflict Resolution Legitimation Legitimation and the Majority Principle Legitimation and Political Culture Democracy's Assigned Functions Equality Federalism The Concept of Pluralism The Concept of Federalism Federalism and its Complements Federalism and Subsidiarity Federalism in Government Confederation Federation The Sovereignty Problem Sovereignty Sovereignty and Federation Federation and Confederation A Bevy of Federalisms The Alphabet of Federalism New, Co-operative, and Creative Federalisms New Federalism Co-operative Federalism Creative Federalism A Brief Survey of Federal History

E.

Functions of Federalism

E.1 E.11 E,111 E.112 E.113 E.12 E.121 E.1211 E.1212 E.1213 E.1214 E.122 E.1221 E.1222 E.123 E.13 E.2 E.21 E.22 E221 E.222 E.2221 E.23 E.231 E.232 E.3 E.31 E.32 E.4 F. F.1 F.2

Federalism and the Political System's Learning Capacity Maintenance of the Political System's Learning Capacity Relief of Decision Centres Competition and Division of Powers Innovation Solving Problems in Pluricentral Organizations Costs of Federalist Solutions Costs of Information Costs of Mobility Costs of Scale Spillovers Quality of Federalist Solutions Quality as Technical Adequacy Quality as Public Satisfaction Large and Small-scale Democracy Intellectual sthetics Federalism and the Political System's Stability Stabilization and System Reliability Conflict Resolution Integration of Individuals Integration of Groups Limits of Federalist Integration Legitimation Compact and Compromise Political Culture Assigned Functions of Federalism Citizen Participation Civic Liberty Function of Middle Levels Genesis and Durability of Federations Genesis of Federations Durability of Federations

Constitutions Bibliography Index

A. INTRODUCTION

Contents Index End

001 In their discourses on government, Plato and Aristotle discussed all those problems which were important to an Attic citizen if he were to understand and order his polity. This encyclopdic approach was also used in theories of government that were developed in the Middle Ages (Rehm L650/261). Only very slowly public law became a science proper (L650/261). But the theory of government remained an overarching theoretical concept in continental Europe right to the end of the nineteenth century (e.g. Bluntschli L75/1, Jellinek L382/4). 002 To-day, at least in Europe, such a unity is at best a historical recollection. The sciences concerned with the state have been differentiated and specialized. Public law, economics, political science, political sociology, geography, planning, and other academic disciplines have developed their own systems of reference for theory and analysis. To some degree the scientific dialects have become rites of passage, restricting access to the mysteries of special knowledge to the initiated few. Interdisciplinary discussion has become difficult and is neglected, assertions to the contrary notwithstanding. 003 Public law as a scientific discipline has been part and parcel of this development. On the one hand it has benefited from compartmentalization. Thus the impressive system of the Viennese doctrine of so-called pure law came into being. And thus it became possible continuously to hone and refine legal techniques.

004 On the other hand, compartmentalization has also brought disadvantages to public law doctrine. In continental Europe, lawyers traditionally do not deal with the state as an abstraction only. They also look at it as a reality. Yet most public law specialists are not interested in empirical studies. They prefer an intuitive approach. Whilst this may be possible where the scholar is thoroughly acquainted with the object of his studies and where he is aware of his ideological biases, both these prerequisites do not always obtain. But worse still is the habit of deducing normative findings from general principles such as democracy or federalism without having first analysed the extra-legal content of such concepts. And yet the instruments for such theoretical and empirical analysis are there. They can be adapted from the methodology of political science and, to some extent, of political economy. Even some of the necessary information can be found there. 005 All scientific disciplines that analyse government have one thing in common. They all claim that their findings are relevant to policy making. They all want to furnish basic information for political and administrative decision making. But as these findings are only relevant to parts of the problem and as they may very often be interpreted contradictorily, what really happens is that researchers do not furnish basic data for decision making but produce arguments for preconceived ideas. Obviously, this selective dealing with scientific data by political office-holders can never be and should never be quite eliminated. But the complementarity of the different sciences and their overlapping has become so evident that something along the lines of the old integrated theory of government is desirable.
006 The Swiss economist Frey (L268/117) for instance criticizes lawyers for not having devised ways of organizing special districts (i.e. voluntary or compulsory associations of local governments) without reducing democracy. Already the words used - special district and democracy - exemplify the different connotations they have for economists, lawyers and political scientists. Without mastering the different vocabularies nobody can solve the organizational problem.

007 The best starting point for such an attempt at integration is systems theory or systems thinking, because in a technical sense there are several competing systems theories. 008 Systems theory is a change of scientific paradigm in the sense proposed by Kuhn (L444). The former and still now predominant approach in the humanities emphasized relations of cause and effect. Systems theories -preceded by Gestalt psychology, Pepper's contextualism and Henderson's theory of balance- are different. They look for interrelations within a whole, the system, whose parts must not be treated in isolation. Systems theories do not build hierarchies. They analyse patterns. The first influential theoretician was von Bertalanffy in the thirties. At about the same time Parsons introduced systems thinking into social science. In connection with Wiener's cybernetics (systematic study of communications and control in organizations of all kinds: Deutsch L166/76) and computer technology systems theory experienced a boom after the Second World War. Thence its technical flavour which sometimes appears as exaggeratedly modernistic (for a critical presentation of systems theories' development see Lilienfeld L482/7ss,196ss).

009 Systems theory tends to be a theory of integration (Schmieg L300/444). It is able to show and analyse systemic relationships between findings of different scientific disciplines. This is achieved by tying them together in an abstract network. The latter's parameters are different as between different schools of thought. Systems theory dispenses to a large degree with causal relationships, whereas the usual attempts at integration try to relate in a consistent way different scientific findings to a few grand basic hypotheses.
010 The degree of abstraction of the frame of reference used is of necessity high. A system for instance is defined (Hall/Fagen in L300/444) as a set of objects together with the relationships between these objects and their attributions. But because in everyday language nearly everything is a system - e.g. the political system, the education system, the public transit system, the economic system etc. - two distinct dangers arise. One is that every time something can be understood, if only in a banal way, to be part of a system, it is presented as systems theory and glorified or mystified with cybernetic terms (for examples see Lilienfeld L482/232ss). The other danger is the mixing of different scales of abstraction. Thus there is talk about the political system, understood in accordance with Easton (L188/21) as those structures and interactions of society by which authoritative decisions on values are arrived at. Against this some critics then hold (e.g. L482/216) that such a political system does not exist in reality or, in other words, that it does not conform with the parliamentary or some other political system of quite another scale of abstraction. This is a pitfall which is very difficult to avoid in discussion.

011 Systems thinking analyses relationships. It shows the functions that parts of systems have in connection with other parts and with the system as a whole. But such an integration is not intended to achieve consistency or to solve social conflicts. Systems thinking is for instance wholly alien to efforts to achieve harmony between federalism rightly understood and democracy rightly understood (e.g. Lang L451/322, Messmer L542/230s, Usteri L825/347). Systems thinking will regard both federalism and democracy as forms of governance, different but in several respects closely related. Starting from there it will then analyse the role of both organizational patterns in the political system as a whole, showing amongst other things the prerequisites for harmony and for conflict. The ways to do this will differ with various schools of thought. But the scientific as well as the political value of such an approach is integration, integration in this case standing for the processing of findings of different scientific disciplines so that their homogeneity with respect to specific systemic elements becomes apparent and allows comparisons. 012 Considered this way the advantage of systems thinking is its aptness as an interdisciplinary metascience. In data processing parlance, systems thinking is the program used to achieve compatibility of different computers. It is therefore obvious that systems thinking is no substitute for the sciences of law, economics, political science etc. But all social sciences can profit from the attempt to make the knowledge of other disciplines bear fruit for their own work through the techniques of systems thinking. 013 I was introduced to systems thinking by two key books: Karl W. Deutsch's The Nerves of Government (L166) and Norbert Wiener's The human use of human beings (L860). My professional insights into the realities of Swiss federalism, my

study of economics, political science, legal and other theories of federalism, visits abroad, and contacts with foreign scholars made me look for a vantage point for a global view of the phenomena I was confronted with. I started to play with systemic approaches, designing for my own use the first elements of a systems theory. It was only later that I realized certain parallels with Parsons's theory, as for instance with his functions of pattern maintenance, integration and adaptation (L604/4s). But parallelism is all there is, not identity. Parsons's aims are directly connected with his interests in sociological research. Mine have little to do with the explanation of empirical data. I was looking for a reference model for interdisciplinary integration. 014 During the seventies many people worked with hierarchies of goals within global conceptions. I, too, attempted to take material goals of government as starting points for my attempts at integration. But because such goals are of necessity value oriented the approach bore, to my mind, little fruit. 015 It is a very old philosopher's thesis that human society has a value-oriented goal. This goal is justice. Thus Plato (L125/68s), thus some thinkers in the Middle Ages (Cassirer L125/51), thus in more modern times Elyot( L211/1) and Madison (L334/51), thus also in our own century Burckhardt (L109/228). Related to justice, or just another version of the same idea is the goal of general welfare or happiness (Kelsen: Justice is social happiness L413/6). For further examples, see Aristotle (L34/7/13), Bentham (L49/184), Madison (L334/43), Sismondi (L755/93).
016 Another goal of government which is often postulated is the full development of the personality either of individuals (e.g. Imboden L386/56, Marcic L509/314, Mill L547/206) or of society as a whole (e.g. Bluntschli L74/362s). Sometimes the safeguarding of private property is mentioned (Locke L489/124). For Hegel the State is an end in itself (L348/258), the reality of the moral idea (L348/257, compare Cassirer L125/274s).

017 It is comparatively easy to agree that justice is the ultimate end of society and of government. It is more difficult to define the contents of justice. The material definitions usually introduce elements which are themselves in need of explanation. Thus the famous first phrase of Justinian's Institutions, which may be traced back to Aristotle Iustitia est constans et perpetua voluntas ius suum cuique tribuens, is unambiguous only for those for whom ius (law, right) is an evident reality in itself (e.g. Marcic L509/176). Wiener, mentioned above as the father of cybernetics, made this comment (L860/105): Empirically, the concepts of justice which men have maintained throughout history are as varied as the religions of the world, or the cultures recognized by anthropologists. I doubt if it is possible to justify them by any higher sanction than our moral code itself, which is indeed only another name for our conception of justice. But if justice is a formula the contents of which are defined by social value judgments, definitions might be as positivistic or legalistic as, for instance, the one by Hobbes (L363/15): And the definition of Iniustice, is no other than the not Performance of Covenant. And whatsoever is not Unjust, is Just. Thus the stress is no longer put on the aims of the procedure but on the procedure itself. Hobbes's law is just in itself; whatever happens legally realizes justice.

018 It may nevertheless be questioned whether such a counter-intuitive and ultimately paradoxical use of words has any cognitive value. 019 The former Prussian Prime Minister and political theoretician Brecht once undertook the task of listing all the tenets of belief taken as yardsticks for justice over the centuries. He found twelve of them: 1) egalitarianism, 2) liberalism, 3) belief in revelation, 4) conservatism, 5) authoritarianism, 6) majoritarianism, 7) hedonism, 8) group allegiance, 9) harmonism, 10) transpersonalism, 11) dedication to duty, and 12) maintenance of peace and order (L86/181ss). He then went on to isolate those elements which had always been part of the idea of justice, namely (L86/477s): 1) truth, 2) generality of the value system, 3) equal treatment of all who are equal according to accepted values, 4) no limitations on freedom other than those accepted by the value code, and 5) respect for the basic necessities of life in the strict sense of the term.

020 As to justice I accept positivism insofar as I have my own idea of justice as well as recognizing several others. But there is none which I would proclaim to be evident for everyone, even if there might be such a thing as true justice. My personal idea of justice has to do with the values of equal opportunity (materially and procedurally), human dignity and tolerance. This is my view of the aim of government. But it is certainly not the aim of government (compare Kelsen L414/24). For me there is no such thing as a unique goal or system of goals of government capable of being stated with more than a formal content. But this also means that it becomes impossible to start my attempt at integration from a value-oriented viewpoint if I want to claim evidence beyond the restricted circle of those who might share my values.
021 Bertrand de Jouvenel once stated his ideas about goals of government in a very lucid way (L375/14): It is a very important matter to make up our minds whether the civil society we live in is to be thought of as dedicated to a purpose. If so, our institutions do not correspond. Personally, my feeling is that civil society should not be regarded as dedicated.... On the other hand we may reasonably think of the administration as a dedicated body from which we 'get' good public service just as we 'get' science from the republic of scientists. This perhaps is not a morally pleasing picture (though I would say in favor of such a state of affairs that it allows us to join dedicated societies of our own choice, which would not be the case if civil society were a dedicated body) but it seems to me to fit the facts. Certainly there is not the least implication in our institutions and mores that a man must make himself into a partner of a general purpose.

022 All that may validly be said about goals of government is encapsulated in the concluding sentence of Woodrow Wilson's The State (L863/1536): This, then, is the sum of the whole matter: the end of government is the facilitation of the objects of society. These objects are manifold and conflict-ridden. It is not possible consistently to harmonize the demands of both crusading teetotallers and wine-makers. It is only possible to optimize such demands, that is, to balance them into a state of but partial satisfaction. 023 Under such a formal definition of the ends of government the state is a subsystem of society. Systems theory does not normally concern itself with the state but rather concentrates on the political system. This helps to avoid the dangerous confusion of abstract notion and concrete representation of a particular regime (compare no.010). The political system is the totality of those structures and procedures as well as their connexions by which value judgments are authoritatively arrived at, i.e. with an accepted and, if necessary, also enforceable claim to validity

within the social system (see also Easton L188/21,153). In its legal essence the political system is the social subsystem of governance. 024 If we try to go a little further and to formulate an encompassing abstract end for the political system, we arrive at the axiomatic systemic statement of selfpreservation. To avoid a possible misunderstanding: If we talk about self-preservation we do not mean the preservation of a particular social state of affairs obtaining somewhere in real life. This state of affairs, this regime may be changed. Perhaps it even has to be changed to maintain the function of governance necessary for the survival of the social system. Politics as such have to be preserved, not particular policies. For this axiomatic self-preservation of the political system the latter's structures and procedures all have their role to play. They thus have systemic functions within the political system. 025 I make a distinction between two different sets of such systemic functions. I differentiate between functions which have to do with the system's learning capacity and those which are concerned with its stability. I am fully aware that this difference is neither rigid nor compelling. Learning may be seen as a means to maintain stability and vice versa. But I think that this difference nevertheless corresponds to certain centres of gravity of individual functions. As a third set of functions I then introduce willed functions. These are functions which society assigns through the political process to certain structures and procedures. Such functions are systemic only in an indirect way. As examples, we may take the functions of guaranteeing individual liberties, participation in decision making, etc. The reason for treating these functions separately, and not translating them into systemic ones first, are purely practical, making the presentation easier. 026 According to Deutsch (L166/129) every system designed to steer and maintain itself autonomously is in need of a constant flux of information about its environment, its past, its own functioning and its parts. If this flux is stopped for any length of time - as the result of, say, information suppression, secrecy or bureaucracy - a loss of adaptability may ensue leading to gradual or to sudden collapse. A system's learning capacity is its capability to process information adequately and to make the necessary adjustments (see also Schmidt L300/213). Learning in this sense combines several closely related functions which will form the basis of this book's analysis: the maintenance of learning through structures and procedures, the perception of social as well as other demands, and, finally, the efficient processing of such demands. These considerations will be elaborated upon below. 027 As to the stability of a system, there are three groups of functions: systemic maintenance of stability (e.g. crisis management through organizational duplication involving so-called redundancies), resolution of material as well as demographic conflicts (the latter through integration) and, finally, legitimation of the system.
028 Maintaining stability through redundancies is the answer to the question whether it is conceivable to group elements which are unreliable individually into a reliable whole. This may be achieved if there is a sufficient and adequately organized overlap or duplication through redundancies.

The system has to be designed in such a way as to prevent the failure of some of its parts to cause the breakdown of the whole. Wherever such failures could become dangerous for the system the parts will be duplicated and arranged along parallel lines so that several mutually independent information channels are provided for (compare Landau L449/187s). 029 In the context of conflict resolution, demographic integration will be important. This requires the focusing of individual or group loyalties to a given political system, thereby defusing or diminishing potential demographic conflicts (for political integration see also Deutsch L166/150,241). But we shall also look at the reduction of material conflicts as a prerequisite to stable government (see Eckstein L190/256). 030 In the long run, the state as a system can survive only if its citizens or subjects accept the given government. This is one of the older tenets of the science of government (see for instance Hooker L367/1/10/8, Jellinek L382/426). Governance will be accepted if this is an evident social duty. Government, then, is legitimized or, in cybernetic terms (Deutsch L166/152): In this sense, a 'legitimacy myth'... is an effective set of interrelated memories that identify more or less clearly those classes of commands, and sources of commands, that are to be given preferential attention, compliance, and support, and that are to be so treated on grounds connecting them with some of the general value patterns prevailing in the culture of its members (see also Duverger L186/32ss). In the context of cultural legitimation, then, a society is self-sufficient to the extent that its institutions are legitimized by values that its members hold with relative consensus and that are in turn legitimized by their congruence with other components of the cultural system, especially its constitutive symbolism (Parsons L604/10).

031 Finally, we shall look at the so called assigned functions of a political system: goals are ascribed to the system which are not strictly necessary for the latter's maintenance but which give expression to a society's values and ambitions. It is this kind of function which is usually at the centre of political debate. Critical discussion of federalism or of democracy, for example, is very often influenced by such values, as for instance with equality in the one case or minority rights in the other. (Readers with a penchant for economics might understand the word assigned better if they translate it as meritorized, L566/65.)
032 A considerable part of the commonly proffered catalogues of the ends of government is of this assigned kind. For an economist, for instance (Frey L268/25s), the tasks of the state result from the imperfections of a pure market economy: 1. the provision of public services (mainly of infrastructure in its broadest sense); 2. economic stabilization; 3. distribution policy to adjust disparities in income and wealth resulting from the play of market forces; and, 4. order and security (creation and maintenance of the market-place's legal framework). (For other catalogues see Weidenbaum L462/7s and Wilson L863/1475ss.)

033 It is obvious that a political system faced with such an array of tasks cannot possibly pursue one unique goal. It will constantly have to balance diverse demands it is confronted with. Any government, therefore, will be unable to achieve more than some medium degree of citizens' satisfaction. It will usually strive to contain dissatisfaction within tolerable limits. The best definition of the best Government is, that it hath no inconveniences but such as are supportable - inconveniences there must be (Halifax L330/203). The state is, as has already been pointed out, an optimizing system. As such it not only realizes values and goals. Through the continuing interplay of social groups it also defines the values and goals which are to be realized (for the relevant theories of Bentley, Lamprecht, Dewey and Lippmann see L579/20ss). Some of these goals will have long-range validity, others will only be

pursued for a short time. But one thing is clear: given an optimizing decision-making system willed goals will never in their totality be consistent. There will always be contradictions. 034 This, then, is in a few short words the frame of reference used for the analysis here presented. But I would not dare to declare it exempt from ideology. By choosing systems thinking rather than a value-oriented theory for my approach I have taken a stand. And there is ideology very often in reflections on details. The author's ideological standpoint might be characterized as liberal in the traditional European sense, conservative and populist. But the greatest danger inherent in functionalism is probably another one. It is a certain inclination to abstain so completely from passing judgment and to explain everything systemically, so that the status quo might finally become an end in itself and will thereby be legitimized. Nevertheless, as long as one is aware of this problem, systems thinking still presents, to my mind, the best basis for identifying and integrating findings of different scientific disciplines. 035 The monograph you are reading is essentially a translation from the German original of the first volume Fderalismus of a treatise Fderalismus und Bundesstaat (L264a). The second volume Bundesstaat (L264b) contains mainly an exposition of comparative constitutional law and policy, based on the conceptual foundations laid with the present book. Part of the monograph was written in 1978 during my stay as a Visiting Fellow of the Centre for Research on Federal Financial Relations at the Australian National University in Canberra. I not only profited there from the intellectual stimulation of what was then probably the finest, most productive and most international centre for research on federalism. I also had the benefit of the far-reaching knowledge of the late Professor Russell Mathews, then the Centre's director. I should also like to mention those scholars of federalism which over the years have become friends and who have influenced me greatly, if not always in the same direction (I am an optimizer, too, insisting on the right to make my own mistakes). I refer specifically to the late Professor Daniel J. Elazar from Jerusalem and Philadelphia, John Hayes from Chichester and Professors Ellinor and Vincent Ostrom from Bloomington, Indiana. Looking back in 2007 on what I published in 1986 I think it wasn't too bad. But by then I already had an advantage over many of the socalled experts on federalism: I had studied federalism on a worldwide scale and I knew what I was writing about.

B. ANTAGONISM OR HARMONY

Contents Index End

036 Federations are federalism's typical manifestation in the world of politics (no.255). For the moment we may leave the question as to what degree the federal principle has in fact been realized in these federations and how far it has remained an empty formula. The fact is that this model is either so attractive or that it corresponds so well to given facts that more than 52 per cent of the world's surface with 40 per cent of the world's population is organized under federal regimes (no.389, Duchacek L180/195ss). But applications of the federal principle may also be found in most unitary states, because it is a natural consequence of sociologically different political units (Elazar L205b/20ss, also Frey L268/40, Friedrich L275/1, Jerusalem L385/6, Imboden L387/21, Schollenberger L727/272, Schwartz L736/1s). Even communist China has made provision for autonomous regions (V4,95ss, Domes L177/122ss) with a say in central decision making (V59/1).
037 Today's federations are: Argentina, Australia, Austria, Brazil, Canada, the Comores, Czechoslovakia, the Federal Republic of Germany, India, Malaysia, Mexico, Nigeria, Pakistan, Switzerland, the Soviet Union, Tanzania, the United Arab Emirates, the United States of America, Venezuela and Yugoslavia. If classic federations are mentioned below this is meant to denote those that are committed to European/Anglo-American constitutionalism, e.g. Australia, Austria, Canada, Germany, Switzerland and the United States of America. (The Federated States of Micronesia with internal self-government as a U.S. administered trust territory are not treated in this text.)

038 But this does not mean that federalism has no critics. Far from it. Criticism of federalism, like federalism itself, enjoys a long tradition. Only the emphasis has been shifting somewhat since the advent of the welfare state. In earlier centuries it was primarily the weakness of federations that was negatively commented upon (see for instance James Harrington in the seventeenth century, L340/261, and Tocqueville in 1835, L806/553). To-day federations are blamed for being insufficiently efficient. And, above all, they are reproached with their obvious problems in fully accommodating another great principle of government, democracy. 039 There are obvious relationships between democracy and federalism. Those following Proudhon's ideology might even say that democracy is achievable only in federations. Thus constituted only Federation is able to solve, in theory and in practice, the problem of harmony between Liberty and Authority by giving to each of these principles its just measure, its true attributions and all its initiative. Only Federation, therefore, guarantees, by absolutely respecting both the citizen and the state, order, justice, stability, peace (L634/546). And from an empirical point of view Elazar is able to say: Not only do all modern federal systems claim to be democratic

and seek democratic legitimacy, but there is likely to be general agreement among true democrats that the great majority of those polities held up as models of democracy (France is the great and important exception), are either federal in form or extensively utilize federal principles (L205b/47, see also Duchacek L181/6, Hahn L328/272). 040 But it is still more obvious that there is also considerable strain in the relationship between federalism and democracy. Riker states this in an extreme way (L660/142): To one who believes in the majoritarian notion of freedom, as he obviously does himself, it is impossible to interpret federalism as other than a device for minority tyranny. It is not necessary to go as far as Riker does. It is sufficient to point out that federalism by its very nature will always isolate areas where minorities (or localized majorities) will outweigh national majorities. When is that minority tyranny, and when is it a just political order? 041 It is possible to answer the question with rhetoric. This up to now has more or less always been the case in European analyses of the tensions between democracy and federalism. The first step is then to define both concepts so that they are of necessity mutually exclusive: If democracy is understood in terms of the absolute and unrestrained rule of the majority of a given political community, then a stark and unresolved conflict between federalism and democracy must be acknowledged (L277/54). Whether you want it or not, modern democracy, your democracy, is centralizing. Federalism and this democracy are fundamentally incompatible. It is the incompatibility of two opposing philosophies of man and of life (de Reynold L654/89). The next step is consistent. The extreme is exposed. The solution is the correct understanding of both terms. But if democracy is looked at correctly, that is to say in the light of liberty, and if one, therefore, subordinates the principles of popular sovereignty and of equality to the idea of liberty, then there cannot be but positive relationships between federal organization and democracy (Usteri L825/347, also L826/11). And Lang states in a similar train of thought (L451/322): To postulate an antinomy between Democracy and Federalism is accurate only with a view to their degenerate forms. 042 This is but stating the obvious. Antinomy, the clearly incompatible, is not the problem. The problem is a tension or a grey area between two principles which intuitively on the one hand are designed to achieve similar ends but on the other hand very often clash in their actual application. This tension is not relievable. It would be a doomed endeavour to understand democracy on the base of a theory of federalism and vice versa (for such an attempt see Lang L451). Both federalism and democracy are means to certain ends. Both are principles for the organization of governance. They are organizational principles and not ends in themselves. Both principles may assume different forms, and these different forms are unequally apt to realize individual social aspirations. It is the difference in these aspirations that may make for tensions between specific forms of federalism and democracy. Using the systems framework presented in the Introduction I shall now try to elucidate the functions which democracy and federalism assume in the political process. This will indicate that, like their causes, there are parallels as well as strains and conflicts. Some of the prerequisites for the

functionality of the one or the other of these principles will, I hope, become clearer. But as the political system is an optimizing system which cannot fall back on a hierarchy of ends of government (no.022), it will not be possible to make valid generalizations about the right relationship between federalism and democracy. Such assertions could only be made in a concrete context, and even then an ideological bias is often inevitable. The aim of the present monograph is to make this evident. At the same time it also attempts to make accessible empirical and theoretical information which is to a large extent widely dispersed.
043 Federalism and democracy are not considered to be legal concepts. Both terms may have legal implications. They may also in a given situation be treated as constitutionally relevant value choices. But they are only legal terms in such cases where positive law confers this status upon them (no.215), thereby referring back to general theories for their eventual interpretation.

C. DEMOCRACY

Contents Index End

044 Democracy is a concept that virtually defies definition (Lijphart L481/4).

045 If there existed such a thing as an accepted definition of democracy it would be much easier to trace its relation with federalism. But there is no such definition. Democracy shows an increasing tendency to become synonymous with everything in society that is good, beautiful and true. Each of the other models of order or conflict has its followers in certain political parties and scientific doctrines as well as its adversaries in others. Only democracy is claimed by everybody.... All systems - social situation and level of development notwithstanding - are, according to a Unesco survey..., advocates of democracy (Beyme L65/12, also L579/26, L702/8). 046 All that may be said about the concept in general terms is that it has an organizational and/or a value-oriented component. In organizational terms democracy is a system of governance that is essentially based on the autonomy (Kelsen

L413/205,284) or on the participation of all members of the system. Certain forms of participation are foremost: universal suffrage and majority decision. From a valueoriented perspective, a system is democratic if it pursues specific aims of equality (chances, influence etc.) and of liberation from dependence. 047 Democracy is associated with several thousand years of occidental history. But democratic institutions are not only to be found in western history. There are also Japanese (L35/55, L819/51) and African examples. Yet there is no denying that it is the occidental Greco/Judeo/Christian tradition which moulded the traits of modern worldwide democracy. 048 For ancient forms of democracy immediacy was essential, that is the universal competence of the assembly of politically equal citizens (L382/719s). The fact that it was only the free who enjoyed political rights and not also the slaves (L494/479) did not worry the Greeks (with the exception of the human rights doctrine of the Stoa, L125/100). But what was important to them was rotation in office (L34/1)12). Whenever possible vacancies were filled through the casting of lots or through sequential service. Elections were, because of their aristocratic element, not favoured (L382/719).
049 Democracy was not favoured by Aristotle, who was probably the most influential of the political philo-sophers of antiquity. He considered democracy to be a degenerate form of government favouring only the have-nots. What we call democracy nowadays was to him polity: the minding of public business by the majority in the general interest (L34/3/7). But Aristotle, like other Greek thinkers (e.g. Heraklit L354/33,47) was no unconditional advocate of polity. He feared demagogy and therefore held polity to be best suited for an agrarian population (L34/6/4): Because of all populations the agrarian one is the best.... As on the one hand people do not own much they have little spare time, and thus assemblies do not often congegrate. And as, on the other hand, they still own all they need... they do their work and do not desire other people's property. They prefer to pursue their toil to dealing with public business or holding office...

050 Such direct democracy was and is only possible in small communities (Bryce L99/489, Madison L334/10, Montesquieu L551/8/20, Rousseau L677/577). As the city states grew and as they were unable to create representative democracy, classical antiquity brought forth autocratic territorial government. This was legally achieved by combining different offices in one man as in Rome (L544/340). It is true that the early Christian thinkers, influenced as they were by the teachings of Aristotle and the Stoa, reintroduced the idea of democracy. But as their democracy was oriented to the hereafter and not to this life (Cassirer L125/106s, Marcic L510/193) they could not prevent monarchy, aristocracy and autocratic regimes in general from becoming the norm.
051 It was probably the spreading of the reformation doctrine of religious resistance to the state (Loewenstein L494/278), and with it the idea of the social compact backtracing political governance to a contractual basis, which opened the way for the transfer of sovereignty from the autocrat to the people (no.281ss) and for the democratic theories of the Enlightenment, the English, American and French revolutions. Regimes are legitimate because they rest on the will of the citizens. That all power is vested in and consequently derived from the people (Virginia bill of rights sect.2, L250/6).

The oil of anointing seems unawares to have dripped from the head of the one to the heads of the many, and given sacredness to them also and to their decrees (Spencer L762/151).

052 The classical philosophers' theory of the social compact solves the problem of how to justify the political duty to obey by creating a fiction (Cassirer L125/173, Sismondi L755/87) of an original contract amongst absolutely free individuals to subordinate themselves to a sovereign in order to secure life and possessions. For Hobbes this sovereign or depository of supreme power in the commonwealth was normally a monarch (L363/18, Oakeshot L584/40ss). For Rousseau the community as such was sovereign (L677/569, L678/1/6): It is not possible to constitute government in any other legitimate way (L678/3/17).
053 Rousseau gives the following text for his social compact (L678/1/6, similar L77/569): Each of us gives his person and all his powers in common under the supreme direction of the general will; and we shall receive as one body every member as an indivisible part of the whole. (For Hobbes see L363/17, L401/25.) Further information on the religious foundations of the social compact and the latter's significance for the legitimization of federal government is to be found in no.598ss.

054 Rousseau was without doubt the most influential theoretician of modern democracy. Apart from the social compact his distinction between the general will (volont gnrale) and the will of all (volont de tous) is important. It is still nowadays at the bottom of many controversies about democracy. The will of all is arrived at by adding the determinations of everybody. It is a procedure. This procedure should produce the general will. This general will is a quality because it always corresponds to the general welfare: will to attain common survival and general welfare ... public welfare is always evident and it needs but common sense to perceive it (L678/4/1). Thus there is always a general will, and Rousseau transcends Aristotle. But the problem is obviously the conformity of the will of the many with the general will. There is often quite a difference between the will of the many and the general will. The latter's aim is always the common interest. The former is only related to particular interests. It is but the sum of such interests. But if from these you take away the extreme ones which mutually destroy each other the sum of the differences will be the general will (L678/2/3). With this statistical method which, incidentally, is analogous to the one used by classical economists, Rousseau tries to demonstrate the agreement of both kinds of public will. But he does see limits: If the people sufficiently informed do not communicate with each other (the conditions are evidently contradictory) there shall always result the general will from the great number of small differences... But if there are machinations, if there are partial associations to the prejudice of the community, if the will of each of these becomes general in relation to its members and particular in relation to the state: then one may say that there are no longer as many voters as there are people but only as many as there are associations. The differences become less numerous and give a less general result (L678/2/3). We are therefore confronted with the situation that there is always a general will. But the will of the many will not always perceive it (in legal theory the analogy would be the difference between true, or natural, and positive law: L414/298). Thus the democrat Rousseau paves the way for those who claim to be able to detect the general will which is always superior to the will of the many,

even when it is different from the latter. History's first illustration of this was the terror of the French Revolution. For Kgi it is one of the most farreaching facts in the history of Democracy and of the Rule of Law that modern democracy's most influential theoretician is not part of the rule of law tradition but part of the absolutist school of occidental political thinking (L405/110). 055 With the English Revolution of 1688 and the French Revolution of 1789 democracy triumphed over absolutism. The American Revolution of 1776 was a landmark for the autonomy of individuals and of peoples, another aspect of democracy. The nineteenth century's role was the enlargement, the development and the consolidation of democratic practices. Some of the important stages were Jackson's presidency in the United States (populism instead of elitism), the reform laws of 1832 in Great Britain and the French Revolution of 1848 (extension of the franchise) and America's civil war 1861-65 (priority of national over local democracy). 056 The twentieth century brought about the general emergence of the democratic principle already mentioned (no.045) in all the countries of the world, at least by way of lip service. It is doubtful whether Rousseau was aware of such a possibility (L678/3/4): If there were a people of gods it would govern itself democratically. Government as perfect as this does not correspond to man.

C.1 FORMS OF DEMOCRACY

Contents Index End

057 The democratic idea is too grand to be trivialized by restricting itself to only one form of authority (Dahl L156/67).

058 All the states of the world claim to have a democratic regime. It is not surprising, therefore, that democracy, depending on different theories, may have many faces, too. To facilitate the later exposition of functions it may be advisable to discuss briefly the main forms of democracy. 059 I make a distinction between democracy as a type of regime, democracy as a mechanism of democratization and democracy as autocracy in disguise. This is not meant to be a typology (such as is proposed by most theoreticians of democracy, e.g. Dahl L156/76s, Lehmbruch L465/97, Lijphart L481/105s). My distinction has but a

practical purpose, namely the illustration of different centres of gravity: classical structures, modern postulates for democratization, hidden autocracy.

C.11 Democracy as a Regime

Contents Index End

060 In the German-speaking world at least there exists a language convention distinguishing between the form of the state (Staatsform) and the form of government (Regierungsform). The form of the state stands for the organization of the supreme political authority or formal organization of the body politic. The form of government characterizes actual governance arrangements. Democracy is used in both sets of terms which makes it somewhat confusing. Since the time of Aristotle (L34/3/7), monarchy, aristocracy and democracy have represented state forms. But democracy is also, and foremost, a form of government (oligarchy and autocracy are other such forms). It is in this sense that I shall henceforth use the term, referring to a republic when designating the analogous state form. 061 A typology for the democracy group of forms of government has often been proposed. But these proposals are usually not very convincing and none of them has been able to prevail in scientific parlance. Democracy, like the other forms of government, is... a matter of degree, and the possible variations of degree are almost infinite (Field L240/92s).
062 Loewenstein (L493/69s) gives a survey of the main types and subtypes of constitutional democracy corresponding more or less with legal terminology: 1. If the people organized as electorate is the primary depositary of power we talk about 'direct democracy'. 2. 'Assembly government' is the name of that type where parliament representing the population at large is the paramount power. 3. 'Parliamentary government' designates a state of balance between an autonomous parliament and an autonomous executive in such a way as to integrate the latter in the former: the members of the executive... are at the same time also members of the assembly.... 4. If parliament and the executive remain independently autonomous under a constitutional mandate to cooperate this may be achieved by coordination rather than by integration. Because of the usual predominance of the leadership function in the executive this type of government is called 'presidentialism'... 5. Finally, constitutionalists are wont to talk about the Swiss system of government as a type in its own right under the name of 'directorate government' because of the collegiate structure of the executive.

063 Current usage can only be claimed for the terminological pair of direct and indirect or representative (Dahl L156a/27: polyarchy) democracy. Under direct democracy the electorate directly exercises so-called state sovereignty. Under indirect

democracy this is done through representatives. The distinction is a clear one. But the clarity is only apparent. 064 As Rousseau pointed out (L678/3/4): Taken in the accepted sense of the word true democracy has never existed and will never exist. It is against nature that a multitude governs and that the few are governed. It is inconceivable that the people stay continuously assembled to mind the public affairs. It is easy to see that for this purpose they have no choice but to institute committees without changing thereby the form of administration. Direct democracy in its absolute form does not even exist in local communities or in the five Swiss cantons always mentioned because they still practise the Landsgemeinde. But depending on the political system we do find more or less markedly direct democratic institutions. If we talk about direct democracy in the common usage of the term we say that the main political decisions are taken by the population at large, either in an assembly or through the ballot-box (L493/73). Which are the main political decisions? These are largely a matter of convention. But they must involve considerably more than elections and the adoption of a constitution. Usually laws will also have to be submitted to this procedure.
065 Duverger's new distinction between direct and mediated democracy, where direct democracy stands for the popular election of the head of government, may be understandable in the context of French constitutional policy. But it is of little relevance.

066 Who is part of the demos that makes decisions in direct democracies? That is the age-old question. Never has it been the whole population. Franchise qualifications such as sex (mainly in former times), age, citizenship, domicile, wealth, and literacy have meant that even in the most direct of democracies only a part of the population constitutes the electorate. Schindler therefore asks (L713/28): is it, then, really possible to talk about identity when, in truth, only the so-called active citizens commit the whole population? He gives his own answer: As a matter of fact there is no identity of persons. But this is without significance. There is identity of interests, aims and views: these are the same that hold in the electorate as well as in the population at large. The disenfranchised population as a whole has no political will different from that of the electorate. Considering that this was written in Switzerland and at a time when women's vote was still unknown there, Schindler's assertion appears to be a rather bold one. At the most it might be said that the factors influencing decision making, e.g. the mass media, are the same for the whole population. Still, this would hardly hold in the case of youth and of immigrant foreigners. Who should be part of the electorate is, in the final analysis, connected with the question about what will be accepted as legitimate governance in a given political system. For reasons which democratic procedure itself determines, the electorate will never comprise the whole population even in the most direct of democracies.
067 Direct democracy can be practised in a meaningful way only in restricted space. As in a free republic every free man should be governed by himself it would be necessary that the people as a whole should exercise the powers of legislation. But this is impossible in big states, and it is subject to many inconveniences in small ones. It is necessary that the people have representatives do all they cannot do themselves (Montesquieu L551/1/11). - Democracy in the classical sense at the base of European parliamentary systems since the French Revolution is a system of delegating the powers of

the people in such a way that the delegates are continuously accountable before those their delegation stems from (Lenk L475/32). - Democracy, as we understand it, means that the people must be free, the free choose the rulers, and the rulers govern according to the wishes of the people (Jennings L383/204).

068 Direct democracy is replaced by indirect or representative democracy. But is this still democracy? It is evident that, looked at from the outside, elections are all there are (as for instance in Schumpeter's definition L475/35). This from the viewpoint of Imboden creates tension which in the final analysis is fatal: All power emanates from the people.... This dogma sounds so very evident and it is usually accepted without examination. But it is strangely contradictory. It says that the people rule and yet don't rule;... The people don't govern directly. They only govern indirectly and in theory: in between the ruled and the presumed rulers there are the authorities which as representatives are the real actors (L387/16ss). Is it conceivable that the state always remains subject to this tension? May it always be something else than it purports to be? Isn't there a natural necessity that the face of an institution corresponds to the political ideas behind it? (L387/25). This is a real question. But the doubt expressed will probably only be justified in situations where there is too much of a gulf between democratic rhetoric and oligarchic reality. In all other cases there are at least regular elections to remind the representatives -as well as those they represent- of their ties with the will of the people (Bryce L99/603). The legitimizing function (no.151ss) will remain unimpaired as long as the great majority of the electorate see themselves adequately represented by their representatives, or if this system at least corresponds to their idea about the correct political process.
069 It is possible to augment the control of the representatives and thereby their ties with the demands of those they represent through plebiscitary elements (Neidhart L782/609) as is the case in Switzerland for instance. But the cost to be paid is a sometimes significant retardation of decision making.

070 Every kind of organizational differentiation of government which may be traced back, sometimes over several stages, to popular election is indirect democracy. But it only makes sense to talk about democracy where this connection between office holders and popular election is still evident, albeit indirectly. A distinctive mark of all representative democracies is a popularly elected parliament which amongst other functions of policy making has at least control over the purse.
071 A special form of representative democracy is the delegation system. It is an attempt to keep the distance between the representatives and those they represent as close as possible. For details see no.078ss.

072 The role of elites is one of the basic problems for direct as well as indirect democracy. Every kind of politics, and not in the last instance the most liberal and the most democratic politics, are shaped and supported by elites (Kopp L442/257). Thus Free Government cannot be, and has in reality always been an Oligarchy within a Democracy (Bryce L99/603, see also Thoma L801/67, to the contrary Arendt L32/276). According to the American political economist Ostrom the existence of an elite is unavoidable for any political system, be it democratic or not (L592/108s):

First, individual human beings are assumed to be the basic material or units which form any political system.... Each person, in the final analysis, is assumed to be the judge of his own self-interest and can be expected to act in a way that will enhance his net welfare potential. Second, decision rules are the basis for ordering relationships in any association. Decision rules are propositions assigning decision-making capabilities to those who participate in social relationships... Third, decision rules are neither self-generating nor self-modifying, but depend upon individual persons both for their formulation and alternation. ... Fourth, decision rules are not self-enforcing but depend upon the assignment of extraordinary powers to some persons to enforce decision rules in relation to other members of the community.... Fifth, given the conditions specified in the above assumptions, then we must necessarily conclude that any form of organization capable of establishing and enforcing ordered social relationships among a large community of persons will necessarily depend upon a radical inequality in the assignment of decision-making capabilities to those who exercise the prerogatives for allocating and controlling the decision-making capabilities exercised by others. Conditions of political inequality must necessarily exist in any political association. We might add that the postulate of popular rule in the sense of an equal influence of everybody is also unrealistic inasmuch as this presupposes such an interest of everybody. This is manifestly not the case just as not everybody has an interest in music, in sports or in stamp-collecting. To discuss public affairs, to keep informed, to use the appropriate instruments or to run for office, all these are quite exacting in time and intellect. In a functionally differentiated society the pursuit of political interests cannot escape being a specific function of a specific group.
073 Scharpf (L702/58) perceives two factors which might explain a low level of political participation: on the one hand discrepancy between the number and complexity of political decisions as against the capacity of each citizen to absorb and process information, and on the other hand competition of politics with additional relevant interests of the individual. Even if they might be considered trivial, especially in the face of the pretensions of participatory theories both points have to emphasized. Looked at from the point of view of individual self-determination political participation does not appear as a particularly promising chance for the active shaping of concrete conditions of life. The least that can be said is that participation is usually competing with a multitude of 'private' endeavours which might be much more effective. In an empirical perspective the political commitment of the few is much more in need of an explanation than the relative disinterest of the many (L702/61ss, also L31/222).

074 Democracy's problem with elites is not the existence of an elite as such. The problem is rather guaranteeing open access to elites (Ostrom L593/231) so that the latter have a democratic legitimacy, too, not being based just on the accidents of birth, school or wealth. This, amongst other things, is the aim of many of democracy's institutions: fixed terms in office, the division of powers, party primaries, federal noncentralization. The other problem is the safeguarding of these democratically legitimized elites' access to all important decision-making arenas so that decisions are not arrived at outside democratic structures. Here again, specific institutions support this goal in democracies: the press, omnicompetence of the constitution, parliamentary questions, publicity and transparency of procedures etc. That both postulates remain to a considerable degree postulates is not an indictment of democracy. It is rather the

result of the fact that in any pluralist society the system of government itself is a result of the optimizing (no.022) of conflicting interests.

C.12 Democracy and Democratization

Contents Index End

075 The elitist character of democratic institutions has not escaped criticism. The radically democratic left, for instance, (L702/25) reintroduces a classical idea (no.048) by taking citizen participation as a value in itself and giving it priority over other ends such as efficiency (see also Barry L49/173s.).
076 Eschenburg (L217/150) describes this approach: Is it too bold to conceive the introduction of the parliamentary system on the basis of the general and equal franchise as the completion of the first phase of democratization? Its start was very soon overlapped by a second phase of democratization, i.e. the introduction of social safeguards for working people, the numerically biggest but economically weakest class.... Since the mid-sixties there appears to be a third phase of democratization: democratization of democracy.... Democratization means to bring more democracy about. Its thrust is against oligarchic and monocratic elements. Its demands are: more power to parliaments, public access to committee meetings, the introduction of plebiscites about personnel and other matters, participation in administrative affairs, extension of the transparency of political procedures. Democratization means power-sharing and, at the same time, reduction of domination wherever there is domination. In addition to that the democratization of instruments to attain political decisions is postulated and practised.

077 Leftist criticism of parliamentary democracy comes from two sides (Beyme L65/15): 1) A moderate position asks for the revitalization of forms of direct democracy and for more autonomy for basic groups (with original vote, referenda, rotation in office, publicity and control). 2) The radical position demands the introduction of the delegations (soviet) system on the basis of socialist property and with a binding mandate, recall, rotation, publicity, ban on factions, criticism and selfcriticism as well as control. 078 The delegations or soviet system is the most thorough-going of these models of democratization. Kevenhrster describes it in the following way (L417/96): The voters organize themselves in basic groups in enterprises, living communities or administrative units. Most proponents favour enterprises. The basic groups articulate political positions. They also take the political decisions. All public positions are elective. A global competence for all questions is ascribed to members. It is desirable

that society is totally politicized. All officeholders are accountable to their electors even for matters of detail. Their mandate is tied to specific instructions. They are submitted to continuous scrutiny and they may be recalled at any time. The delegates work as such without pay. Their average income must not be higher than that of the electors to preclude the emergence of an economically autonomous ruling group. All workers are in turn participating in the administration of the state. The possibilities for re-election are drastically reduced. Rotation in office is designed to make corruption and the accumulation of influence impossible. The traditional civil service no longer exists. The powers are not separated but fused because in a society with a politically and socially organized electorate institutional division of powers has no function. The aims of the delegations model are exacting: - permanent and unconditional accountability of the elected, - permanent participation of electors in personnel and other matters, - debureaucratization of decision making procedures, - disappearance of parties and factions, - abolition of the electorate's alienation from the state (L417/95). 079 It would be wrong to dismiss the delegations system as something artificial. It is impressive to see the regularity with which, after revolutions, soviets have been constituted, very often against the wishes of the revolutionary leaders (see Arendt L32/256ss, L33/216s). But this model's typical problem is the near-impossibility of organizing it in larger polities which need several tiers of decision making. There are attempts to accommodate these needs with differentiated delegations and indirect elections, delegations electing their delegations on the next higher level (L32/278, L702/64). But this necessarily restrains basic group influence on central decision making (L417/97, L702/64), thereby weakening one of the main arguments for the system's introduction. Compared with direct elections of representatives to parliaments the delegations model would in fact bring about a considerable weakening of the ruled's democratic influence and control vis--vis the rulers (Scharpf L702/64).
080 The only actual example of the delegations model is Yugoslavia (C132ss, Stefanovic L772/15ss). But the institutions have been modified better to achieve a certain stability and -this is most important- they have been combined with the Marxist model of democratic centralism (no.100ss).

081 The ideology of democratization is based - even more so than classical direct democracy ideology - on the assumption that citizens may be held in a state of continuous political activity. That is against all experience (no.072s). It is therefore necessary for participation theory to interpret the empirical diagnosis of political apathy obtaining with the large majority of the population as... surmountable. It is difficult to see how this premise might be justified (Scharpf L702/57, also Ellwein L208/124). Unreflected participatory romanticism courts the danger to end as mass pseudoparticipation, manipulated by totalitarian groups, if its excessive aspirations fail to be realized. All that has a chance to survive in such circumstances is the reduced form of democratic centralism (Beyme L65/29). Democratic theory which does not totally lose contact with reality because of normative participatory postulates - as such justified - will have to accept that even enlightened citizens remain consumers of

services and passive onlookers in areas where they could and should participate (Beyme L65/29, also L65/15). 082 A further difficulty with the delegations model is its relation to conflict resolution. Grosser (L229/69): It is inevitable that in a society marked by heterogeneity of interests more participation and basic group autonomy will intensify conflict. Yet the weakening of the representation principle through elements of direct democracy -especially the binding mandate and office rotation- will lessen the system's ability to solve cflicts via the balancing of interests. 083 Finally, it should not be forgotten that the modern state is so complex that it cannot do without a relatively complicated and large administrative machinery. To apply the delegations model to the administration might have anti-democratic results. Lwenthal points out (L217/156): that wherever we have to do with functional organs of society whose goals, whose aims, whose ends are prescribed by society as a whole we cannot in a meaningful way democratize them in themselves. A ministry the civil servants of which democratically decide is not a ministry of a democratic government. 084 For all these reasons Beyme formulates four limits to democratization (L65/25ss): 1) Participatory models have to take the specific requirements of individual subsystems into account. It may well be that the basic group or delegations model could be quite adequate... for not too complex multifunctional organizations without being equally well suited to the organization of a large combine.... 2) The potential for democratization of organizations may vary considerably with their dependence on the accountability mechanisms of other organizations... 3) Limits to democratization may result from the plurality of status hierarchies in society. To demand total participation of all citizens on every level is to apply a one-dimensional model of stratification which makes a distinction only between owners of means of production and workers. Modern theories of stratification are multi-dimensional.... 4) Finally, limits to democratization may also result from the plurality of organizational allegiances. 085 It is interesting to note that American ideologies of democratization have a different point of departure from European ones. In the United States we have at the base of the demands the realization that up to now it has not been possible to sensibly improve the situation of underprivileged groups. There is a theory that social welfare programmes have been to a large degree unsuccessful because they are run by the privileged. Thence, it would appear necessary to give the underprivileged the decisive influence for deciding of the use of the money earmarked for them. Only by generating political power, therefore, could the poor alter the structure of community influence and thus open up opportunities currently denied them - for example by breaking the dependence of the social service agencies on the local middle class (Salamon L693/263). Since the sixties there have been provisions in some of the federal social laws that the programmes have to be administered with maximum feasible participation of the local poor. Democratization took the form of

community control. This means that central government programmes were administered through a centrally designed local political ad hoc forum which ignored the traditional local structure in favour of the underprivileged (blacks, Puerto Ricans etc., see Eisinger L197/144, Sundquist L792/85). The reviews of this approach are controversial. But there is agreement that maximum feasible participation has influenced the traditional power structures of the communities concerned in a much bigger way than had been anticipated by the politicians who decided on this provision (as to this time-bomb effect compare Salamon L693/264). 086 Rein describes this kind of democratization with its basic dilemma (L652/222s): American democracy has to reduce this basic imbalance of elites and non-elites by changing the power disparity between them. It tries to achieve that by helping underprivileged groups to better articulate their demands and preferences; by helping them to organize protests where they may express their moral right to justice and equality; by giving the poor in addition to collective action the support of the legal machinery to put them in a position to sue institutions which denied them their rights... The logical conclusion to this approach is an anomaly: there will necessarily be two kinds of democracy - one for the poor and one for the rest. In the final analysis this, too, is an elite theory, only this time it is an elite of the underprivileged. Whether such interventions have in the long run a stabilizing or a destabilizing influence on the democratic system is an open question. 087 But this attempt, too, cannot bypass the problem that the groups it is designed to activate do not develop the expected permanent citizen's interest. This seems to be even more the case with the underprivileged than it is elsewhere. The policy courts very quickly the danger of being exploited for other interests. Rein (L652/22s): It is quite astonishing how bureaucrats try to organize lower income groups to put through their own goals. Redevelopment authorities create block groups, welfare offices in the ghettos organize community work, schools further PTAs (parent/teacher associations). In a similar way town planners try to mobilize streets to take the wind out of the opposition's sails etc. (for further examples see L792/65).
088 This American experience with democratization is mainly influencing local political structure. It is an important factor changing the quality of American federalism. For a further discussion of this kind of structural intervention see the German companion volume to this book (L264b/866ss).

089 Scharpf considers this to be the real possibility of the democratization movements (L702/66s): If it is true that political participation of the great majority of the population is hardly ever greater than the participation in general elections then, from a participatory point of view, it is important to add to the importance of elections for the political process. If, beyond participation in elections, the political systems provides possibilities for active participation in other decision-making procedures it, secondly, is important that these possibilities are equally opened up to all willing and able to actively commit themselves. And if there are social areas where the postulate of universal participation may be approximated such prospects, thirdly, should be made use of to the highest possible degree.

C.121 Opinion Polls

Contents Index End

090 To legally organize public opinion or the 'will of the people' - that is the goal modern democracy's constitutions seek to attain with their great array of instruments (Preuss L632/244).

091 Democracy's methods of measuring public opinion (elections, ballots, popular initiative etc.) record real public opinion but imperfectly. That is evident. The mechanisms are clumsy and not frequently applied. They do not take into account those who do not have the vote or who do not vote (the latter very often constituting a majority). The questions put to the voters are very simple and do not allow differentiated answers. To-day's developments in mass communications and data processing technology render polls possible which are much more sophisticated than the ones devised in the nineteenth century, when political rights were introduced. It cannot come as a surprise, then, that there are many who propose to put these new techniques to the use of democracy, to further democratize democracy. 092 Opinion surveys, where statistically representative samples of the population are polled, are well known in the political realm. They are privately commissioned in most democracies before important elections and ballots (in some countries, for example in France, the final dates for the publication of their results are regulated by the state). They are also used by politicians as a barometer for the public mood (for a critical voice about this new industry of 'Big Opinion' see Boorstin L79/18). In the opinion poll we have an instrument that extends the legitimizing function of vote counting to a larger segment of the political process (Edelman L191/119, compare also L743/55). 093 But the procedure in use to-day is questionable for political purposes: There is no control over the framing of the question. Yet it is a fact that slight modifications of questions, the formulation of set answers as well as the actual polling procedures may be of great importance to the outcome. Apart from statistical imprecision it is probably these elements which account for the deviant results found very often with competing polls. Furthermore, the population's low level of information may yield results which are anything but clear.
094 This has been demonstrated by, among others, Pimlott with his example of the U.S. Metallic Metals Act (L618/256). This nonsensical and non-existent bill elicited opinions from 70 per cent of

those who were asked. Of the respondent,. 21.4 per cent were favourably disposed; 58.6 per cent would have preferred the states to be responsible; 15.7 per cent considered such a measure to be necessary abroad but not for the United States; 4.3 per cent were against it outright. This poll is perhaps significant for the state of public opinion on federalism and the constitutional division of functions. But such an attempt at interpretation just further illustrates the method's limitations.

095 Advocates of opinion polls (demoscopy) for political decision making also misjudge the difference between opinion and demand as analysed by Easton (L188/42s): it is not at all unusual for members of a political system to feel, for example, that they should have more public housing and yet, in the political context of the moment, they may also hold the opinion that they ought not to press for government action. They may recognize the urgent need for housing, express themselves in an opinion survey as being in favor of having something done about it. But because of the state of the economy or the priorities of other urgent matters, they may not be prepared to take a position one way or another as to whether political action should be taken, that is, to state their position as demand. 096 The main argument against constitutive use of opinion polls for political decision making is their misconception of the political process. They are apolitical. Imboden (387/87): If the idea is to measure with the help of modern opinion surveys which opinion prevails in a given collective this procedure may correspond formally... to the majority formula. And yet it is the complete opposite of democratic decision making. In actual democracy the demos... is 'advised'. It considers the advice of public authorities or... political parties. It listens to those persons whose opinion seems to be important. The majority finally counted is the result of an exchange of opinions or of a debate. Democratic decision is not just the arithmetical sum of non-reflected statements. It is an integrationary discussion.... Individual opinion is confronted with the opinions of those representative for society.... The technique of demoscopy, the statistical collection of set and unreflected 'opinions' threatens to choke true democracy. 097 For demoscopy to be a legitimizing instrument for democratic decision making it would probably have to meet four conditions: 1) The procedure would have to be government controlled. 2) The questions would have to be set in a democratically acceptable way. 3) The organization of the survey would have to guarantee a prior public debate. 4) To arrive at democratically legitimized results the polling of all citizens, not just of a sample, might well be a prerequisite. 098 There are three considerations which illustrate the problematic nature of such a procedure. 1) Multiplication of surveys and the concomitant need to digest the relevant information might make citizens politically still more apathetic than they are now. 2) It is not realistic to expect political parties and interest groups to finance any number of information campaigns. Government financed campaigns, on the other hand, would introduce the problems of censure as well as the blowing up of fringe positions. 3) It is difficult to see why such expense should be entered into only to facilitate the participation of those citizens who are so little interested in public affairs

that they stay away from the ballot-box, thereby doing the very thing which corresponds to their level of information. 099 The sum of the matter is that the instruments of direct democracy are only superficially the means of surveying public opinion. Their foremost function is the legitimation of decisions through a democratic procedure, i.e. one that all citizens have access to (compare no.155ss). This is not to deny the possibility that the traditional ways for the expression of political opinion will be changed with the introduction of modern data transmission techniques. Under such circumstances one of the results might be the facilitation and increase of ballots. But private ballots also would certainly greatly increase and compete with the public ones. In all probability this would destabilize the legitimizing function of the latter and to some extent even destabilize democracy.

C.13 Democracy as Autocracy in Disguise

Contents Index End

100 We have seen that every democratic regime contains elitist elements. But these elements are not part of the democratic ideology (with the possible exception of representation). Yet there are ideologies which try to present an organic linkage between democracy and autocracy. The best known example of these guided democracies is democratic centralism. 101 To better understand democratic centralism it is necessary to remember that, according to Marxist doctrine, democracy will have to disappear with the withering away of the state (Lenin L473/5). But until the full introduction of communism, dictatorship of the proletariat is a necessity. Democratic centralism tries to combine dictatorial rule over the class-enemy with democracy amongst class-comrades. Only a government of democratic centralism can fully express the will of all the revolutionary people and most effectively fight the enemies of the revolution.... The state system - joint dictatorship of all revolutionary classes. The political structure democratic centralism (Mao L506/25, see also article 3/1 of the 1982 Constitution of the People's Republic of China, article 3 of the Soviet and article 18/1 of the Czechoslovakian Constitutions). 102 Grosser describes democratic centralism as follows (L229/71): The electorate is limited to the confirmation of candidates selected by the party leadership and to

non-binding discussion of alternatives. The decisions are the prerogative of central office. Minorities have no right to organize themselves in order to achieve a reversal of a decision (prohibition of factions). It is possible to reconcile democratic centralism with the principle of legitimation by popular rule only in so far as one accepts with Rousseau a true 'general will' which the leaders will objectively and scientifically discern and to which every well meaning and sufficiently informed person would agree (for Rousseau's volonte gnrale see no.054). In theory it might be feasible to organize the preparation of decisions democratically and to have the decisions themselves autocratically arrived at. If there always is objective and perceivable truth then the only function of the democratic process would be the furnishing of data for the decision and not the latter itself. Yet the history of communist governments with their leaders denouncing their predecessors' mistakes is too obvious an illustration of the weakness of such a theory. Democratic centralism is centralism first and foremost. Its learning capacity is therefore quite restricted in a cybernetic sense (no.114ss).
103 Authoritarian democracy is not confined to Marxist states. It is or was also to be found in South America (L496/51) in Franco Spain, in Salazar's Portugal etc. But the western ideal of strong leadership also indicates authoritarian elements in conceptions of democracy. As to illustrations we may think of Gaullist France and of the United States under Kennedy, Johnson and Nixon.

104 A similar trend is depoliticization of political decisions by handing them over to experts instead of politicians. But because there is no such thing as an impartial decision as such (no.122) and even less so when we have to deal with value judgements, the conclusions of experts are also political conclusions. Technocracy is an authoritarian style of government. 105 Is democracy suited to developing countries? There, we are faced with a dilemma. On the one hand the prerequisites for democracy of a more than narrowly local nature are severely lacking. On the other hand democratic culture cannot come about without democratic institutions (Field L240/127). Under such circumstances some kind of guided democracy seems to be required for a transition system. This would mean an authoritarian regime practising democracy in limited areas with the idea of expanding these areas according to the developments in political expertise of the population. After all this was the way western democracy gradually grew (the stages there were demographical rather than functional). Such a regime is sometimes called tutelary democracy. It is a fine theory. It also has the advantage of offering one of the few possibilities of limiting inflation of demand in underdeveloped countries (see Easton L188/115). But, alas, there is often a complete lack of the ruling class's will to democratize. Instead, political reality shows that the concepts of 'tutelary democracy', 'guided democracy' (e.g. Sukarno in Indonesia), 'basic democracies' (in Pakistan) etc. have primarily served political leaders to hide their authoritarian practices behind a 'democratic' cloak (Berg-Schlosser L61/154). Only the future will show whether this has been a transitional, perhaps inevitable, stage.

C.2 FUNCTIONAL ASPECTS OF DEMOCRACY

Contents Index End

106 Democracy is a form of government that is never completely achieved (MacIver L499/175).

107 If we take democracy to be a postulate or a principle of political organization we are faced with a question. What are its ends? The formal approach yields little in the way of an answer: In conclusion, it can be said that majority rule is indeed the quintessence of democracy, if it is not taken to mean 'majority of one' (Friedrich L277/49). Yet to point to majority decision is but a very terse description. It is no explanation. Still, it has always been a goal of democratic theory to justify democracy. Many diverse deductions have been tried: truth, justice, rule of law, popular sovereignty, individual personality development. A consensus about the correct set of values has, understandably, not been arrived at. There is, to follow Ellwein (L208/136)), only some sort of minimal consensus in particular areas: The basic characteristic of modern constitutional democracy is the phenomenon of a largely shared anthropological point of departure without any concomitant agreement on final goals. The common basis is founded in the democrats' conviction that man is destined to freely rule himself. There is no complete agreement as to the direction of man's self-rule and as to whence this freedom is bestowed on him. 108 Confronted with this problem modern political science has a tendency to cease making deductions from general principles and to attempt a description taking mechanisms as a reference. But modern democracy research pays a heavy price for such progress: Democracy is but a specific political method; its institutions are formally nothing more than a system of balance; and in the end it is sufficient to adequately perceive the conditions for balance to correctly steer the apparatus. This conception of social engineering takes democracy to be a model that, given the necessary adaptations, may be completely isolated from its social background and transferred to any given situation (Habermas L323/317s). 109 A review of theories of democracy shows that most of them are onedimensional or mini-dimensional, whatever their scientific nature. They set out to explain the nature of democracy with the help of one or just a few parameters. By doing this they expose themselves to the reproach of being insufficiently general or complex. Such blame is significant for the state of modern theoretical discussion (Beyme L65/23). Sometimes, therefore, the state of the art is said to be primitive (Barry L49/193). 110 Fortunately, it is not necessary to adopt one of these theories or to propose a new one to be able to present both harmony and tension between democracy and federalism in federations. According to the systems thinking approach presented in the introduction, we may look at democracy - and likewise at federalism (no.198) - as a

principle to organize governance within a political system. Various justifications for democracy may then be analysed for their systemic functions. To do that we shall use three main functions or bundles of functions: democracy's contribution to the system's learning capacity (no.111ss); its contribution to the system's stabilization (no.134ss); and the connection between democracy and assigned functions (no.183ss). This same approach will be applied later to the functions of federalism (no.404ss). As the main emphasis of this monograph is laid on federalism, the latter part will be more extensive. It will also primarily be there where we consider the interrelationships of democratic and federalist ends.

C.21 Democracy and Learning in Political Systems

Contents Index End

111 It has been shown in the Introduction that the study of systems is of special interest to cybernetics. Cybernetics is the systematic exploration of communication and control in all kinds of organization (Deutsch L166/76, also Wiener L860/15s). The emphasis is on the marshalling and processing of information by a system. Looked at from this point of view the concept of learning capacity is of paramount importance. 112 Learning is taken to be a process of communication. It is dependent on the structure of the flow of information, the information channels' capacity and the effectiveness of the mechanisms for steering and control. It is a decision center's learning capacity that determines its viability and its pathology. Social systems can only survive if they are capable of social learning. With other words: if it is able to effect necessary changes in its structure of preferences in order to guarantee successful operation in the future. ... Learning becomes pathological for instance through the coincidence of will and power; will being the desire not to learn and power the faculty of not having to learn. Thus, important decision makers will quite often learn but in a pathological way, i.e. through painful experience. This we should want to avoid (Schmidt L300/213s, see also Deutsch L166/92). 113 For the purposes of the following description I shall differentiate as components of learning its maintenance and its problem solving capacity. This approach will be further refined later for the analysing of the relevant functions of federalism (no.402ss.).

C.211 Maintenance of Learning Capacity

Contents Index End

114 It is already evident that, from a statistical viewpoint, the participation of the many in decision making introduces great variety into social learning. Institutions providing for citizen access to decision-making force the ruling elite to be confronted with undesirable information even in democracies with authoritarian traits. This will not be the case in perfect autocracies or oligarchies. 115 Democratic procedures create a quasi-continuous flow of new findings, arguments or other data for decision making. Such procedures are ballots, elections, political freedoms (as for instance the right to the free expression of opinions, freedom of the press, petitions, the right to associate freely with one another, freedom of instruction), public hearings, etc. 116 On the other hand, information overload may well clog a system's capacities for processing information. This may happen through excessively long discussion in preparation for decisions (for this reason Steiner, L774/105s, to my mind wrongly, criticizes Switzerland for her direct democratic ballot process). But overload may also result from an inflationary accumulation of demand by the mechanisms of competitive democracy (Scharpf L705/14s). Because of the last phenomenon and also because in small countries the number of personal interests to be taken into account is more restricted (Lijphart L481/68), small states are more suited than larger ones to the extension of institutions of direct democracy. (The problem of information overload will be treated once again in connection with functions of federalism, no.418ss.) 117 The means with which the foregoing democratic procedures further learning may all be discussed under the heading of competition. Competition results in variety of arguments. That is why it was and is so important to enlightened liberalism to structure the composition, the organization and the procedure of representative authorities in such a way that they provided for a maximum of competition of ideas while at the same time bringing about a close nexus between parliamentary deliberation and open discussion by an enlightened public (Scharpf L702/22s). 118 Thus, competition is essential for democracy. The specific difference between other systems of government and democracy is the latter's potential to question governance (Lenk L475/43). The concept, therefore, stands in the first place for the

critical reflection of all rule and of all power to decide other people's possibilities, actions and thoughts (Ellwein L458/56). In most countries the mechanism for such critical reflection is party competition in elections (in small democracies, as for instance in Switzerland, direct competition of arguments in ballots is also possible). Elections which offer the chance of a change in the composition of the ruling majority are one of the answers to the age-old problem (e.g. Constant L147/133 and Mill L547/68) that a ruling majority may be just as tyrannical and unwilling to learn as an autocrat.
119 Elections, therefore, have an important role to play in many definitions of democracy, as for instance in the one of Lipset (in L586/263): Democracy in a complex society may be defined as a political system providing for regular constitutional opportunities for a change of the rulers, and as a social mechanism enabling a maximum part of the population to influence important political decisions via their choice amongst several candidates for political office.

120 To justify democracy by reference to the competition of opinions reminds us of the division of powers doctrine. Certainly the latter is primarily designed to guarantee individual liberty (see Frenkel L253/103, Kgi L401/248, Kopp L441/475). But in a cybernetic sense division of powers can also be an instrument for keeping information channels open and thereby for maintaining the learning capacity of a political system (see also Dahrendorf's definition of democracy, L157/116). This is a function which, if attributed to the separation of parliament and executive, has to-day become somewhat problematic in countries where there is for all practical purposes political identity of the parliamentary majority and the executive (see also no.633).

C.212 Problem Solving Capacity

Contents Index End

121 It is not without reason that the voice of the people is likened to the voice of God (Machiavelli according to L737/703). Whereas the people taken apart, are but so many private interests, but if you take them together, they are the publick interest; the publick interest of a Common-wealth... is nearest that of mankind, and that of mankind is right reason (Harrington L340/141s).

122 The goal of political learning is to make a correct decision. But a correct decision per se does not exist or, if it exists, it is not perceivable as such for everybody. There is only that which is reputed to be correct. The basis for this

reputation may be varied. One such basis is democracy. Democracy legitimizes truth through the democratic procedures used to determine it. 123 In principle, democratic opinion formation offers equal chances for all arguments to be heard. This consideration, enhanced by the expectation of some sort of adding up of truth, leads to Aristotle's justification of democracy (L34/3/11): That it is rather the many who should have supreme power than the best which are only few, this is an assertion which may evidently be defended as possessing a certain probability and perhaps even a certain veracity.... Because with the many each one of them owns a modicum of virtue and of insight. And if they assemble the many will be as one man with a multitude of feet, hands and sense-organs. The same will hold true for attitudes and insights, too. Certainly, experience offers abundant illustrations for the problematic nature of such a theory.
124 When for instance in 1958 Egypt and Syria voted on their merger in a new United Arab Republic there were only 286 out of nearly seven and a half million votes cast against such union (L493/273). But already at the end of 1961 this never fully implemented state disintegrated again into its two component units. It appears that democratic procedure (if it really can be called that) produced but a relative or very provisional truth. And it is obvious that not only truths might be added but errors, too (see Montesquieu L552/86, Tocqueville L806/352).

125 But, as has been pointed out before, it is not really truth we are concerned with. We are examining a decision-making process in an optimizing social system (no.033) which accords the status of importance to those demands which are directly or indirectly carried by a majority. In this perspective it may be said with Downs (see L49/172) that the system of competing political parties offers a practicable method for a society to aggregate their members' preferences for different political measures expected from their government. The rulers are able to maintain their position as long as they also take into account the demands of others. For elites that are actively engaged in the political process support from non-elites is an important, often decisive factor. Therefore, established elites in such an output-oriented model always fear the entrance of competing new elites which represent heretofore neglected group interests. Given this situation, established elites will try to anticipate the interests of potentially mobilizable elites and to base their own recruitment on a broad spectrum of social strata and groups (Scharpf L702/39, see Ostrom L593/231). 126 According to Dahl/Tufte the ideal political system meets two criteria: the criterion of citizen effectiveness (citizens acting responsibly and competently fully control the decisions of the polity); and the criterion of system capacity (the polity has the capacity to respond fully to the collective preferences of its citizens). 127 As to the first criterion of citizen effectiveness, we may assert that, from the viewpoint of what has been said before, democratic systems are able to process the most varied demands. Democracy's problems in this field have to do with the way opinions and demands are generated. Convictions do not come from nowhere. They are arrived at by personal experience, interests and environmental influences. The main problem, therefore, is manipulation of opinions. Considering that the majority

of politically active electors have already opted for a political party leaving only the undecided as a propaganda target propaganda will have to concentrate its efforts on this comparatively apolitic and wavering group. This group, then, will not be subjected to arguments about the relationships between everyday problems and political decisions. It is cheaper and quicker to try to ensnare it with psychologically loaded advertising (Fetscher L239/167). If we consider democracy not just as a political system, but as a set of institutions which do aim to make everything available to everybody, it would not be an overstatement to describe advertising as the characteristic rhetoric of democracy. One of the tendencies of democracy, which Plato and other anti-democrats warned against a long time ago, was the danger that rhetoric would displace or at least overshadow epistemology; that is, the temptation to allow the problem of persuasion to overshadow the problem of knowledge. Democratic societies tend to become more concerned with what people believe than with what is true, to become more concerned with credibility than with truth (Boorstin L79/28s, also L98/109ss). 128 The problem, perhaps, is not so much that opinions are influenced by rhetoric but that they are focused on something which may have little or nothing to do with the matter at hand. This may still be acceptable for elections because they are primarily votes of confidence, despite all propaganda efforts. But with the kinds of ballots which are common in Switzerland and the United States, reduction to votes of confidence or competition among purely symbolic formulas is more questionable. Two sets of preconditions may be responsible for this situation: First, the image of the competent voter informing himself about the details of a bill is pure fiction. It presupposes a degree of civic training and of political interest not obtaining with more than ten per cent of the population and unlikely to be bettered even through the most well-intentioned programmes, given the competition from other interesting pursuits. And then we have to realize that, since the victory of democracy in the second half of the nineteenth century, politics, as exemplified by legislation, has had a tendency to favour empty formulas. These permit the greatest possible number of participants in the process to see their ideas translated into reality, even if the ideas are mutually contradictory (see also Glaser L295/9). This explains the spreading of notions like optimal, considering also, ordinarily etc. Constitutions as well as other laws increasingly adopt journalistic traits. This in turn makes advertising rhetoric appear almost relevant.
129 One of the most interesting monographs on symbolic politics has been written by Edelman. To his eyes essential elements of politics are of a purely symbolic nature (L191/172): The basic thesis is that mass publics respond to currently conspicuous political symbols: not to 'facts', and not to moral codes embedded in the character or soul, but to the gestures and speeches that make up the drama of the state. The mass public does not study and analyze detailed data about secondary boycotts, provisions for stock ownership and control in a proposed space communications corporation, or missile installations in Cuba. It ignores these things until political actions and speeches make them symbolically threatening or reassuring, and it then responds to the cues furnished by the actions and the speeches, not to direct knowledge of the facts. It is therefore political actions that chiefly shape men's political wants and 'knowledge', not the other way around.

130 This proneness of democratic public opinion to manipulation (it is the same with other regimes but of less consequence there) leads to something which might be called excessive learning. This appears as a nervous vacillation of political demand, the desire to see every whim effected at once. The age of instant coffee is the age of instant solutions everywhere (based, of course, on long-range global master plans). 131 Already Tocqueville foresaw this inflation of demand in democracies (L806/332s): In democratic societies there is also some sort of agitation without precise aim. They are struck by a kind of permanent fever bringing forth all sorts of innovations, innovations which are nearly always expensive.... In democracies where the sovereign is always needy his favour can only be acquired by improving his welfare. This can hardly ever be achieved without money. What's more: when the people themselves start thinking about their position a multitude of needs arise which were not perceived before and which can only be satisfied with the recourse to the public coffers.
132 Scharpf's explanation makes sense (L705/16): Public services are mostly financed not with servicerelated fees but with general taxes. For the individual taxpayer the 'price' of a service used is no longer identifiable. Thus on the one hand cost-awareness as a factor limiting demand no longer works: a public service, for the consumer, is a quasi-free good. There is in the public sector as opposed to the private sector a general tendency to excessive demand bringing about political postulates for an expansion of public services offered. On the other hand there is by no means a corresponding willingness to contribute to the costs. One reason for this is the possibility of redistribution where it is not the beneficiaries that have to bear the costs of the additional supply but other groups. Still, if we consider that the net redistributory effects of public budgets are rather small and tendentially even regressive, then the main cause for this state of affairs seems to be the maximum separation of the determination of the sum total of the budget (which fixes the tax ceiling) from the earmarking of the monies for the various categories of services. Each political group will find in the budget so many unnecessary or even undesirable expenses which might quite easily be struck out to make place for its own pet projects that the correlation between the latter and the tax ceiling doesn't at all appear evident (see also Pawlowsky L607/35ss).

133 The result is a conflict between both the criteria mentioned above (no.126), citizen effectiveness and system capacity. It may be said that the standard for meeting citizens' demands will itself be subject to the democratic process and that it will thereby contribute to the problem solving capacity of the system even here. Still, the constraints placed by the scarcity of financial and other means on the solution of problems democratically perceived to be in need of a solution may eventually endanger democracy itself. According to Lipset (L49/72), every regime is supported by the two convictions of its legitimacy and of its efficiency. The history of democracies shows that the absence of the second conviction will either lead to the introduction of oligarchical elements or to the system's abandonment in favour of an authoritarian one. For Scharpf, therefore, one of the foremost tasks of modern democratic theory is (L702/24s) the theoretical reflexion of the welfare and planning state considering both technological and political/democratic rationality.

C.22 Democracy and Stability of Political Systems

Contents Index End

134 In whatever way one organizes and balances power in a democratic society it will always be very difficult to believe in that which the masses reject and to profess what they condemn. This favours marvelously the stability of beliefs (Tocqueville L807/356).

135 This ironical dictum of Tocqueville's refers to a kind of system stabilization which is only marginally related to the systemic functions I shall now be treating (there is perhaps a certain connection with political apathy's stabilizing influence, see no.174s). We will now be concerned with democracy's role in the stabilization of the political system, i.e. to guarantee it a high probability of survival (as to the concepts of political stability or of stable democracy see L49/60ss, L480/71, L481/4). But beware: we are not talking about a specific regime but about the political system as such (compare no.023s). 136 When we discussed the social frame of reference we included under the heading of systems stabilization (no.027) three bundles of functions: systemic maintenance of stability, conflict resolution and system legitimation. In order to avoid unnecessary duplication I shall now only talk about one aspect of conflict resolution and about legitimation. That is because only here do we have to do with basic problems which are not treated or not adequately treated in connection with federalism. On the other hand, everything which has to be said about other stabilization functions may be contrasted with the relevant functions of federalism (no.541ss and 551ss).

C.221 Conflict Resolution

Contents Index End

137 A stable political system is one that successfully reduces and processes tensions which are always in evidence (Eckstein L190/256). Conflicts or tensions may have

primarily material causes or primarily demographical ones. Insofar as democratic procedures reduce material conflicts, this is mainly achieved by their legitimizing attributes (see especially the comments on the majority principle no.156ss). Therefore, the resolution of material conflicts will not be discussed here. 138 Demographic tensions, on the other hand, are based on the pluralist structure of society (as to pluralism see no.201ss). In a segmented society clearly the most pressing problem is to find a form of association which will maintain the unity and peace of the state without threatening the existence of the social and cultural segments (Nicholls L579/62, compare L491/33). Questions which individual groups consider as essential for their very existence cannot be decisively solved by majority decision in the overarching system, because groups which are continuously in a minority position do not accept the system as a legitimate decision mechanism in such matters. The integration of different population groups in a democracy has to be achieved by forms which, whilst being of a democratic nature, still modify democracy to a considerable degree. For this we know several, partially overlapping models, the most important of which I shall now briefly discuss. 139 The assimilation model, which would have the effect of making group differences disappear in a generalized society, has little chance of success in democracies (Lijphart L481/44s). History shows (Vile L835/11) that assimilation has only been successful in a few authoritarian states, as for instance Tudor England, absolutist France and Stalinist Russia. In democracies assimilation may only be brought about in a very slow and gradual way through the success of other models. In the short run it is only possible with very specific groups, as for example in Switzerland with foreigners who want to become citizens and from whom a severe naturalization procedure demands full personal assimilation. 140 The model of cross-cutting cleavages: This idea hails back to Bentley, Truman and Lipset (L189/70s, L481/10). It explains the low level of conflict obtaining in some plural systems as being due to the fact that group allegiances criss-cross. This makes for a continuous shifting of the fronts of conflict, which prevents individual tensions from becoming strong enough to endanger the stability of the whole system. Further consideration will be given to this model when we deal with federalist integration of groups (no.582ss). 141 Based on his analysis of Norwegian democracy, Eckstein developed a community model (L189/194): This involves systems in which cohesion exists mainly despite division, due to overarching sentiments of solidarity, whatever their source may be. Community, it is essential to note, does not make for cohesion in the same way as consensus. The latter obviates the need for searching out agreements, while the former makes for cohesion rather through norms that facilitate the quest for agreements - for example by putting a high value on agreeing as an end in itself, even where men are manifestly divided (as happens in most societies when events, such as war, induce temporarily strong sentiments of solidarity), or by cultivating a certain political considerateness of others: deference to their expertise or experience,

sympathy with their special interests, or reluctance to raise issues that might exacerbate feelings of hostility of any kind. In short, Norway's great political divisions and its great political cohesion are perfectly consistent if both have a single source rather than being results of contradictory pulls in Norwegian life, if both result from unusually compelling demands for solidarity that operate on all levels of social life (L189/176).
142 Segregation models are based on the observation that, contrary to widespread opinion, increased contact amongst culturally and linguistically different groups does not reduce tensions; it may even heighten them. This will especially be the case if there are minorities with a feeling of deprivation (see Duchacek L181/27, Lijphart L481/88s). The segregation models try to have as few points of contact or of friction as possible amongst groups by granting to each of them maximum autonomy and by reducing the need for consensus to a few central affairs.

143 Of this model there are two basic varieties. The better known one is federalism. The greater part of this book is devoted to it. The other variant, which will be explained below, is called consociationalism. There are other segregationary approaches which may be mentioned without further explanation. The first of these is the Ottoman Millet system (no.205), which underlies the Cypriot and Lebanese Constitutions. It differs from consociationalism by its mechanistic integration at the centre of elites that have little will to co-operate. Corporativism also should be mentioned (see no.206s), even if segregation in this case is restricted to relatively few areas. 144 The word consociational may be traced back to Althusius's consociatio. In the 20th century it was first used by Apter (L155/107, L481/1,161s). As an explicit model consociational democracy (or accommodation democracy as it is sometimes also called) is based on Lijphart's analysis of Dutch politics (L480). But it may also be used outside the Netherlands to explain political stability in countries where population groups are to a considerable degree segregated, as for instance in Austria, Belgium, Canada, Colombia, Israel, Switzerland and Uruguay. The main characteristic of consociational democracy is a clear mutual distrust between population groups coupled with an elite policy of co-operation and peaceful settlement of conflicts. The essential elements of the politics of accommodation are the division of society into a number of distinct and self-contained segments or blocs, overarching co-operation at the elite level, strong deference to the bloc leaders, and, as a result, a high degree of political stability (Lijphart L480/197). For us it is less important to know whether the roots of consociational democracy are to be found in elite policy (Lijphart L480/196) or in the historical experience from earlier centuries and thus in a certain form of political culture (Lehmbruch L465/93, see also Daalder L155/121); or whether the model still adequately describes to-day's political situation of the Netherlands (see L480/197ss, L492/205s). The latter it quite obviously does no longer. Our interest is for the model as such. 145 The condition for the consociational model is a deeply divided population without cross-cutting allegiances. This, at least until the sixties, was the case in the Netherlands with her divided existence of Catholics, Calvinists, socialists and liberals

(L480/23): Deep religious and class divisions separate distinct, isolated, and selfcontained population groups. Social communication across class and religious boundary lines is minimal. Each group has its own ideology and its own political organizations: political parties, labor unions, employers' associations, farmers' groups, newspapers, radio and television organizations, and schools - from kindergarten to university (Lijphart L480/1, also L481/56, L670/49). Yet television later on made strict segregation over the long run impossible. This medium, therefore, contributed to the eventual pulling-down of barriers between the various population groups or pillars (Lorwin L491/58s). 146 A key element of this conception is the lack of a comprehensive political consensus, but not the complete absence of consensus. There must be a minimum of agreement on fundamentals. Dutch national consensus is weak and narrow, but it does contain the crucial component of a widely shared attitude that the existing system ought to be maintained and not be allowed to disintegrate. The second key requirement is that the leaders of the selfcontained blocs must be particularly convinced of the desirability of preserving the system. And they must be willing and capable of bridging the gaps between the mutually isolated blocs and of resolving serious disputes in a largely nonconsensual context. The politics of accommodation resembles politics at the international level (Lijphart L480/103s). The first and foremost rule of the Dutch political game is that politics should not be regarded as a game at all. It is... a business.... Probably the second most important rule that governs the Dutch political business is the pragmatic acceptance of the ideological differences as basic realities which cannot and should not be changed (L480/123s). 147 The elites are supported in their function of finding arrangements and compromises by various political rules. Thus coalition-type governments and authorities are quite typical for consociational democracies (L481/25). Where the theory of games usually lets coalitions be just as big as necessary to achieve a simple majority (L84/217s), consociational coalitions are to the largest possible extent grand coalitions thereby giving minorities a veto-position (L481/26s,37). Proportionality is the basic pattern for representation and for the allocation of offices and of financial means (L480/127s, L482/25). To better solve political problems they are depoliticized through economic or legal formulas (L188/262ss, L480/129) or discussed in a climate of utter confidentiality as to the compromise mechanism (l480/131ss). 148 Consociationalism has its political price. Stability is achieved at the expense of a sometimes technically non-rational use of scarce resources (L491/51). There is also a certain immobility (L491/51s). Still, the innovations finally arrived at are then rather stable (L481/51s). Politics are dull because they largely lack the drama of conflict between the government and the opposition, keeping public interest at a low ebb (L260/328, L480/137s). Consociational democracy accepts elite government as a fact. But this can only be considered a shortcoming if it is compared with some ideal but non-existent form of democracy (L481/49s). And, finally, there is a danger in consociational regimes that citizen dissatisfaction is not absorbed by changes in

government but produces a generalized discontent with the regime as such. Although this is indeed a serious weakness, it does not have to be fatal. If voter disaffection is mobilized by new political parties, these may be antisystem or antiregime parties but they are not necessarily antidemocratic. And because the typical electoral system of consociational democracy is proportional representation, it is easy for new parties to gain a voice in the political process. This is what happened when consociational government began to break down in the Netherlands in the late 1960s. The relative ease with which consociationalism can be discarded makes the persistence of a democratic regime more likely. This argument can also serve as a final reply to the various charges of the insufficiently democratic character of consociational democracy: when these weaknesses are felt to be increasingly onerous, and particularly when they are regarded as less and less necessary because a society has become less plural, it is not difficult to move from a consociational to a more competitive democratic regime (Lijphart L481/52).
149 Lijphart's consociational democracy is primarily an analytical concept. It is a description of a certain type of regime to be found in various countries. But Lijphart goes further. He ascribes also normative value to his model: This book's message to the political leaders of plural societies is to encourage them to engage in a form of political engineering: if they wish to establish or strengthen democratic institutions in their countries, they must become consociational engineers (L481/223). Consociational democracy is both an empirical and a normative model.... The argument that consociational democracy can serve as a normative model challenges the pervasively pessimistic mood of our times and is deliberately unconventional (L481/1,3). Such an application Lijphart proposes for instance for South Africa (L481/236). This proposition has greatly influenced South African intellectuals, as I have been able to see myself in the years 1979 and 1981. The new South African Constitution is an attempt to achieve consociational democracy for the white, the Indian and the brown population groups -but not for the blacks- in a mechanist way. But consociationalism arranged for by one of the partners does not conform to the prerequisite of elite compromise. And the question is still open whether the different elites can count on the kind of deference from their followers which the model stipulates as necessary to achieve accommodation (see also Nicholls L579/57s).

150 I consider both consociational democracy and federalism to be models of segregation (no.143). There are obvious similarities amongst them, as Lijphart pointed out himself (L481/42s): As a theory, federalism has a few significant parallels with consociational theory: not only the granting of autonomy to constituent parts of the state, which is its most important feature, but also the overrepresentation of the smaller subdivisions in the 'federal' chamber. Federal theory can therefore be regarded as a limited and special type of consociational theory. Similarly, federalism can be used as a consociational method when the plural society is a 'federal society': a society in which the segmental cleavages coincide with regional cleavages. Because government at the subnational level is in practice always organized along territorial lines, federalism offers an especially attractive way of implementing the idea of segmental autonomy.

C.222 Legitimation

Contents Index End

151 There is no logical necessity for man to obey the state. On the contrary, there is a fundamental contradiction between state domination and human autonomy (Scharpf L701/9). True, fear of punishment is a powerful inducement to obedience. But those who trace the latter back uniquely to the former (as, for example, Raz L644/186) fail to see that fear cannot be sufficient reason for a whole population's obedience. At least in a long-range perspective force is always on the side of the governed (Hume in L170/77). Government must be perceived as correct, right, or legitimate to have a good chance of permanent success.
152 Easton (L188/278): A member may be willing to obey the authorities and conform to the requirements of the regime for many different reasons. But the most stable support will derive from the conviction on the part of the member that it is right and proper for him to accept and obey the authorities and to abide by the requirements of the regime. It reflects the fact that in some vague or explicit way he sees these objects as conforming to his own moral principles, his own sense of what is right and proper in the political sphere. Jouvenel (L398/323): The idea of democracy means that the rulers are legitimized through their harmony with public opinion. This harmony does not have to be perfect; but neither must it sink below a certain level. 153 The ultimate foundation of state and law is irrational (Burckhardt L109/186, also Eckstein L190/266s, Weber L850/70ss). Legitimacy of regimes is no abstract quality. It depends on subjective attitudes. Legitimacy is the quality of a regime to conform to the theory of government accepted as true.... Thus defined, legitimacy is of a subjective nature (Duverger L186/32). Or, in a cybernetic sense, legitimacy is (Deutsch L166/152) an effective set of interrelated memories that identify more or less clearly those classes of commands, and sources of commands, that are to be given preferential attention, compliance, and support, and that are to be so treated on grounds connecting them with some of the general value patterns prevailing in the culture of the society, and with important aspects of the personality structures of its members. (As to the distinction between legitimacy and legality, not treated here, see e.g. Blank L300/215ss, Friedrich L277/113 and Marcic L510/197,322.)

154 Friedrich (L277/114) makes a distinction between four kinds of legitimation: religious, legal (philosophical), traditional and procedural. The meaning of the first three concepts is self-evident. Democracy is the main type of procedural legitimation. To-day this form of legitimacy is for all practical purposes the only one universally accepted. In the modern world there is in the long run no other justification left for governance than the idea of democratic legitimation (Abendroth L1/156). For the social system the democratic myth has thus also the function of justifying governance. From a systemic point of view, democracy thereby guarantees the continuity of the system. It has a stabilizing influence, making it possible to defuse conflict without undue force (see Barry L49/173).

155 If we look at the elements of democracy's legitimizing strength we perceive that citizen participation (compare no.184) plays a vital role. Any kind of government can claim to rest on 'the will of the people,' whether it be oligarchy or dictatorship or monarchy. One kind of government alone rests on the constitutional exercise of the will of the people (MacIver L499/198). It may be that the actual exercise of participation is limited, both by citizen interest and by factual possibilities. We no longer share the belief, originally looked upon as self-evident, that each citizen can participate in all important decisions. The multitude as well as the complexity of such decisions make this impossible. Bureaucracy and expertocracy are also democratic phenomena (Ellwein L208/120, also Scharpf L703/168). However, in the final analysis democratic regimes may trace back their legitimation to ultimate citizen consent. This is the old idea of the social compact (no.051ss,598ss). But consent is not directed towards some legal text. It is a shared conviction that the political rules of the game are right, that they are rules which organize the volont de tous (no.054).

C.2221 Legitimation and the Majority Principle

Contents Index End

156 The gathering of information in the political system is learning (no.114ss). Learning prepares decisions. The latter are no longer learning. On the contrary: the specific quality of decision, will in a cybernetic sense, is not being influenced by additional information. Will resembles the 'deadline' in a newspaper: it could be called the internally-labeled preference for predecision messages over postdecision ones. The 'moment of decision' might then be seen as that threshold where the cumulative outcome of a combination of past information begins to inhibit effectively the transmission of contradictory data (Deutsch L166/105s). But what should be the rules for arriving at political decisions? It is obvious that unanimity of all participants will only rarely be required (as in some African and Asian village democracies, L482/166s). Yet for the non-persuaded to follow the opinions of somebody else there has to be a compelling conviction that no alternative action is possible. Such a conviction may be based on the fear of force. As such, it does not interest us here. But as a rule the conviction will be based on the fact that the decision emanates from some authority which in the context of a given political culture is considered to be legitimate for this sort of decision. 157 In democracies, this authority is the totality of the citizens. It is not, strictly speaking, their majority. The majority is but the procedure to determine the will of the

totality (compare Arendt L32/164). This is easy to demonstrate. If for instance there would always be the same majority imposing its will on the same minority, we could expect sooner or later a legitimacy crisis. But as there is in reality always a succession of winners and losers, this fact somehow recedes into the background and it is the majority decision as such that appears to be the essential quality of democracy.
158 Sometimes the concept of democracy is reduced in a one-dimensional way to this procedure as for instance by Schumpeter (according to L702/36) who holds democracy to be this state of institutions to achieve political decisions where some acquire jurisdiction through a competition for the votes of the people.

159 There is no objective answer to the questions as to how large a majority has to be to assume identity with the totality and as to whose voice is to be counted. This again is subject to the beliefs held in a given political culture. To-day general (no.046) and equal suffrage is the rule.
160 Ruys (L685/136): Democracy is defined as being a system of assigning a bundle of public goods such that each participant has an equal weight in the determination of the social benefit of that bundle. 161 From an academic point of view it is evident that we may question the theory of the equal weighting of votes. In early forms of democracy, theory and practice favoured weighted over counted votes. This is no surprise if we consider the interests of the bourgeoisie that struggled for democratic rights. Thus for instance Mill (L547/281): It is also important, that the assembly which votes the taxes, either general or local, should be elected exclusively by those who pay something towards the taxes imposed. Those who pay no taxes, disposing by their votes of other people's money, have every motive to be lavish and none to economise. As far as money matters are concerned, any power of voting possessed by them is a violation of the fundamental principle of free government; a severance of the power of control from the interest in its beneficial exercise. It amounts to allowing them to put their hands into other people's pockets for any purpose which they think fit to call a public one. Mill also proposed the weighting of votes (L547/284s): It can always be taken into the calculation, and counted at a certain figure, a higher figure being assigned to the suffrages of those whose opinion is entitled to greater weight. ... The only thing which can justify reckoning one person's opinion as equivalent to more than one is individual mental superiority; and what is wanted is some approximate means of ascertaining that. If there existed such a thing as a really national education or a trustworthy system of general examination, education might be tested directly. In the absence of these, the nature of a person's occupation is some test. Notwithstanding such ideas universal and equal suffrage is nowadays the rule everywhere, even in large illiterate states where it becomes something of a farce. Nevertheless, maximum equality is logical for democratic systems.

162 The assumption that majorities are right and may impose their will on minorities is not logically compelling (for the medieval discussion of this point see L98/164). It is the majority of one that especially provokes contradiction: The nation is in doubt, the assembly is uncertain. And now one of the people's representatives crosses from the right to the left without evident motive thereby tipping the scales; he is making the law. And this law, this expression of some fantastic will, this is to be considered the will of the people!... And my holy duty to oppose tyranny yields to the almighty ball of a fool (Proudhon in L328/289)! We might even say that truth is more likely to be with the minority, as again did the utilitarian Mill playing on a very much older theme (L547/107): On any of the great open questions just enumerated, if

either of the two opinions has a better claim to be encouraged and countenanced, it is the one which happens at the particular time and place to be in a minority. That is the opinion which, for the time being, represents the neglected interests, the side of human well-being which is in danger of obtaining less than its share. But here,too, the radical solution, simple majority, has carried the day. Still, this has not been so to the same degree as for general and equal franchise. Constitutional law for instance presents many cases of some qualified majority requirements. 163 Again, it stands to reason that a logically compelling justification for qualified majority requirements is not to be found. But it is possible to give rational arguments for them. Public choice theory nevertheless makes a very interesting attempt: According to Buchanan and Tullock, a representative individual wanting to form an organization to provide a public good would need to take two types of costs into account: 1)external costs which are defined as those costs an individual would expect to bear as a result of decisions which deviate from his preferences and impose deprivations upon him; and 2)decision-making costs which are defined as the expenditure of resources, time, effort and opportunities forgone in decision making.... If a constitutional decision maker were a cost minimizer, and the two types of costs described above were an accurate representation of the costs he perceives, we would expect him to prefer the constitutional choice of a decision rule where the two cost curves intersect. When the two cost curves are roughly symmetrical, some form of simple majority vote would be a rational choice of a voting rule. If expected external costs were far greater than expected decision-making costs, an extraordinary majority would be a rational choice of a voting rule (Ostrom L592/67s). In other words: If in a political system we have to anticipate difficulties resulting from a simple majority decision to be greater than those entailed by the enlarging of the basis for consensus, the introduction of some qualified majority would seem to be appropriate.
164 The opposition against qualified majorities usually refers to public welfare (this is Rousseau's general will, no.054) or to the undemocratic preference of a minority introduced by qualified majorities. Thus Lord Brougham (L92/305): This clumsy device is liable to the manifest objection among others that it must frequently prevent measures being adopted which the public good requires. It also tends to... give a minority undue weight and influence.

165 But the most difficult problem that any attempt to validate democratic decision rules has to face is the forming of the opinions which, in their aggregate, constitute a majority and are therefore called the will of the people. Dahl stipulates the conditions that have to be met if we are to be able to talk about majority will in a strict sense (according to L277/10): 1) every member of the organization expresses his preference for one of the alternatives, for example by voting; 2) these expressions are treated as identical in weight; 3) the alternative with the greatest number of preferences is the winner... 4) members may add an alternative not previously identified; 5) all members possess identical information about the alternatives; 6) the preferred alternatives become operational and are executed by those in authority. Dahl adds that no human organization has ever met or is ever likely to meet these conditions. If we were to complete condition 5 by Edelman's thesis about the symbolic contents of political information (no.129), the democratic process would

appear as pure fiction. But this would be a misconception of its function. Democratic procedures are a sham only if they are measured against their rhetoric. In reality they are but a means to submit fundamental political decisions to the largest possible forum, in order to bestow legitimacy upon them through the acquiescence of the ruled (and also to open up additional channels of information, no.028). 166 If we conceive of the majority principle as a legitimation mechanism, we have nevertheless to realize that it is not unquestioningly accepted as such in all democratic regimes. In plural democracies (see especially the discussion of consociationalism, no.143ss), the case for simple majoritarianism is opposed by the fact that it might place specific groups in a permanent minority. It is more likely that majoritarianism may have to be defused at the outset through special institutions to protect these groups (veto, coalition-type government, etc., see also L481/145).

C.2222 Legitimation and Political Culture

Contents Index End

167 Every society is held together by amyth-system, a complex of dominating thought-forms that determines and sustains all its activities. All social relations, the very texture of human society, are myth-born and myth-sustained (MacIver L499/4).

168 We have arrived at the conclusion that democracy legitimizes governance. But if we say that we presume a specific kind of political culture, what is political culture? Gabriel Almond who, together with Sidney Verba, was one of the pioneers of modern empirical research in this field, once defined political culture as consisting of cognitive, affective, and evaluative orientations to political phenomena, distributed in national populations or in subgroups (in L19/26, compare L61/26ss, L206/5ss, L516/9s, L606/52s and especially L671/4ss). 169 There is a very close relationship between forms of government and political culture. According to Eckstein's congruence theory (L189/186ss, L190/234ss) the stability of a given regime is greater the more its characteristics and especially its authority patterns coincide with those of society at large. To take as an example British political institutions, we immediately see that they are a creation of British political culture and, in turn, have their influence on the latter. They cannot be transplanted to places where the foundations are not the same without having different

results. The unsuccessful attempts to introduce Westminster institutions in Africa and in Asia are obvious demonstrations of this truth.
170 There exist different types of political culture. Almond for instance makes a distinction between a parochial, a subject and a participant type. The different forms of government, according to him, result from the mix of these types (L61/49ss). Eckstein proposes a democratic, an authoritarian and a constitutionalist pattern (L190/235).

171 We are mainly interested in the democratic type of political culture. It demands a certain level of intellectual abilities. Democratic government, although based on such a simple and natural idea, always presupposes a very civilized and very wellinformed society (Tocqueville L806/328). Another condition which seems at first sight necessary or highly desirable for the working of democracy is a minimum standard of education, amounting at least to literacy (Field L240/131s). But intellectual abilities are not enough. If we look to Verba's definition we will also ask for certain kinds of values and behavioural attitudes. It is not easy to say what is part of these attitudes and what is not. 172 Almond and Verba have described this type of culture as civic culture. Barry (L49/56): To put it in a very simple way civic culture is characterized by a balance of deference to public authority and steadfast independence. In this sense the ideal democratic citizen would believe in the legitimacy, general competence and good will of political authorities whilst being convinced at the same time that he has the right (if not the duty) to influence their decisions and to remedy abuses. 173 Empirical studies have shown that this civic culture is regarded very differently by the population at large and by their elites. It has even been found that the great majority of the population has a surprisingly low commitment to democratic values (Bachrach L328/309). Scharpf points to the same problem when he states (L702/34) that even under the favourable conditions of Anglosaxon or Scandinavian democracies participation research has always confirmed the existence of a large majority of politically apathetic citizens; and opinion surveys have not only demonstrated the low level of information and of political interest obtaining with the majority of the population, they have also shown how little perceptions of a broad consensus on basic values and rules in a pluralist democracy correspond to reality. It appears that the population at large, for whom democracy offers more access to political influence than any other form of government, is less interested in it than is the elite (Lipset talks in this context of working class authoritarianism, L702/41). 174 Given these facts official policy tries, at least superficially, to activate citizens through information campaigns and other measures. Contrasting with this a behaviourist school of democratic theory talks about stabilizing apathy. This hypothesis of stabilizing apathy has three very different sources: 1) a psychoanalytic trend suspecting behind every active politician a neurotic being using politics for pathological relief - a thesis as developed e.g. by Erich Fromm... probably too much impressed by dictatorial regimes; 2) a theory of modern mass society as developed in David Riesman's 'The lonely crowd'... where he described the dangers of manipulated

pseudo-activities by externally guided mass man; 3) a theory of stable government as developed by Berelson, Lipset and other researchers with failed democracies in mind (as for instance the German Weimar Republic). For them these collapses were the result of, amongst other influences, over-participation of doctrinaire groups (Beyme L65/16).
175 Such deferential apathy is also described by Lijphart (L480/144) in his study of Dutch democracy: Neither the ideologically stylized pattern of elite-mass communications nor the high degree of elite dominance of the bloc organizations can fully explain the persistent allegiance of the rank and file of the blocs to their leaders. The people must have an inherently strong tendency to be obedient and allegiant - regardless of particular circumstances. This tendency will be referred to as deference. This term is here used in its broadest meaning: an individual's acceptance of his position both in the social hierarchy and on the scale of political authority, accompanied by a low level of participation and interest in politics. For the masses this entails respect for and submission to their superiors. These deferential attitudes are strong among the Dutch. Hans Daalder... speaks of the 'mixture of both deference and indifference which has tended to characterize the attitude of most Dutchmen toward authority'. Eckstein is another of those who have studied this phenomenon's function for the system of democracy (L189/169): Functional deference clearly narrows the range of groups and men among whom agreement must be sought... and helps identify men who can speak and act authoritatively in special areas of policy. This enables the system to act with some ease even in many nonconsensual areas (that is, those not governed clearly by communal norms)... At the same time it is a kind of deference highly consonant with democratic norms, since it does not militate against diffuse egalitarian sentiments, restricts authority to highly limited fields, disperses it among many men and structures, and compartmentalizes it in leagues (this study's focus is Norway).

176 Democratic culture, like any other political culture, is thus characterized by the existence of stratified groups who participate differently in political life. Dahrendorf (L157/108): There is continuous exchange between the different groups. But at any given time we may still discern the following ones: a) the latent public of the nonparticipating, be it that they lack motivation and interest, be it that they are hindered in their decisions by cross-pressures; b) the passive public comprising those who sporadically make an appearance in the political process as members of the public or as voters but whose initiative does not transcend the occasional question in a political meeting or nominal membership of an organization; c) the active public of those who participate regularly with their own ideas in the political process, who belong to organizations, enter upon public office, and who in their public utterances deplore the non-participation of the others. The dimensions of these different publics vary according to conditions that have been largely elucidated by science. But normally the active public is very much smaller than the other two. At no time and under no definition is it probable that it comprises more than one percent of the electors. There is only one thing that makes this stratification democratically acceptable: transition is basically open to everybody (compare Berg-Schlosser L61/52). 177 Such findings - restriction of active participation to a small group, authoritarian attitudes in democratic systems - together with the already mentioned convergence of social and political authority patterns necessary for stable government, may explain why neither ideal democracies nor ideal democratic cultures exist in the real world. The democratic form of government always exhibits oligarchic and even autocratic elements. This lends support to the still older theory of political science that mixed

government is the most stable form of government - and puts it also in a new light (Eckstein L190/267). 178 In this analysis of political culture we have up to now neglected one essential element. Populations must not only be seen as assemblies of individuals. They are also assemblies of groups (see also no.579). Practically all states have a plural structure of population (for pluralism see no.201ss). They are based on political part-cultures showing more or less great differences. An important part of the general political culture, therefore, is formed by the values and rules governing the living together of these groups. In democracies this coincides practically always with the renunciation in some form (federalism, consociationalism etc.) of full reliance on the majority principle. Plural democracy is a concept which shows an inherent tension. It is this tension that we shall examine below in connection with a specific kind of plural democracy: federalism. 179 Lijphart's models of democracy (L481/105s) are attempts to do justice to pluralism. They are based on two dimensions: population structure and elite behaviour. Lijphart distinguishes between four types of democratic systems, depending on whether the political culture is homogeneous or pluralist, and on whether elite behaviour is oriented towards co-operation or conflict. According to Lijphart, homogeneous culture and co-operation-oriented elite behaviour make for a depoliticized model of democracy. The same kind of elite behaviour in a pluralist setting results in consociational or accommodational democracy (no.144ss), where group leaders able to commit their followers will arrange for the peaceful resolution of conflicts. If elite behaviour is conflict-oriented, we have the models of centripetal democracy with homogeneous political culture and of centrifugal democracy with pluralist political culture. The latter is either a transitory state of affairs on the way to disintegration or it is associated with continuous crises of government. In centripetal democracy we may expect one elite or coalition of elites to impose its will on the others. That is why some authors (see L61/139s) even postulate tensions to be a necessary prerequisite for stability and the long-term survival of democratic structures. 180 Finally, of great importance for the continuance of democratic culture are the information channels transmitting and consolidating this culture. Amongst them are the mass media. It is obvious that the mobility of an ideology as well as the receptivity of the ruled is in the first place dependent on the technological intensity of communication techniques. It comes as no wonder, then, that to-day's democratic state has to consider the control or at least the neutralization of the media a guarantee to its survival (Loewenstein L494/253). Pluralism of information media is an element of the pluralism of government, next to the pluralism of political parties. Besides, the political parties' pluralism would remain illusory and formal were it not accompanied by information media pluralism (Duverger L187/220).
181 The mass media's contribution to democracy is somewhat different from official ideology's ideal democracy. A noted opinion surveyor (Dichter) assessed the situation in the United States in devastating terms (L171/207s): If during the day the radio offers serialized soap operas, television

fairy tales and popular tabloids stories with very strong mass appeal this only promotes latent tendencies to mental apathy, stereotyped reactions and standardized response.... There is a near kinship between moral routine reactions as called forth by these media and the blind following of fascist and communist ideologies' dogmas. One could perhaps accept this with a shrug and point to the theory on stabilizing apathy (no.174) if the values transmitted corresponded to the accepted image of democracy. But this is very often not the case. The essential problem of mass communication for to-day's society is the negative influence on the beliefs which are at the basis of this society. This results in the disintegration of values.... The so-called crisis of democracy is largely the outcome of developments in this field (Friedrich L276/67).

182 The twentieth century brought the universal break-through of the principle of democracy (no.056). It is still very much an open question what the form of the twenty-first century's political culture will be.

C.23 Democracy's assigned Functions

Contents Index End

183 Assigned functions are understood to be those that have no systemically necessary connection with the survival of political governance or organization per se (see no.031s). Such functions are assigned by a given social value system to a specific regime, in our case to the democratic regime. 184 The distinction is not always very easy. Citizen participation for instance is a core element of democracy. In one form or another it is essential for the functions of both learning and stabilization. But citizen participation is also deemed to have humanitarian ends. Thus Borter (L81/55): This principle of citizen participation may be justified from an anthropological as well as from a political viewpoint. Participation facilitates in the political realm the preeminence of human development and self-determination, both committed to the ideas of freedom and equality. For Tocqueville citizen participation had a pedagogic function (L806/369): Democratic government makes the idea of political rights descend right to the lowliest citizen... This, to my mind, is one of its greatest merits. These functions are what I call assigned functions. I will not treat these specific functons in detail here. Relevant considerations are examined in the corresponding discussion of assigned functions of federalism (no.614ss). 185 Next to the pedagogical idea of citizen participation, the most typically democratic of the functions assigned to democracy is equality.

C.231 Equality

Contents Index End

186 I think that democratic populations have a natural liking for liberty. Left to themselves they will search for it, they will love it, and they will feel grieved if it is removed from them. Yet for equality they have a passion ardent, unquenchable, eternal, and invincible. They want equality in liberty, and if they cannot have that they still want it in servitude (Tocqueville L807/133s).

187 The idea of equality is part of the core of democratic ideology. But which equality? Aristotle (L34/5/1) made a distinction between two kinds of equality. One is arithmetic and the other one according to one's due. By arithmetic equality I want to say that according to quantity or to size something is the same and equal. By proper equality I hold something to be equal according to its proportions. 188 The kind of equality nineteenth century's liberalism stood for was proportional equality (see Burke L111/56s, Cooper L149/152, Leibholz L470/174, Preuss L632/39s, Schindler L713/56s). Equality according to one's due is to be understood as an attempt at a synthesis of individual autonomy and public governance. It is buffered equality. Only then may we talk about 'true' democracy... when the definition of a democracy also contains material elements which will be of necessity normative, resting on the individual's ethical conviction and humanitarianism, as for instance the guarantee of liberal and social rights, minorities' rights, formal as well as substantive rule of law etc. (Berg-Schlosser L61/155).
189 For emerging liberalism proportional equality was compatible with quite a few inequalities, especially in the field of the franchise (see no.161). This can be explained in the historic context of the interests of the bourgeois class. But democratic ideology also had to come to terms with conservative objections pointing to natural inequalities. Thus for instance Carlyle (L122/315s): I have to complain that, in these days, the relation of master to servant, and of superior to inferior, in all stages of it, is fallen sadly out of joint.... Certainly, by any ballot-box, Jesus Christ goes just as far as Judas Iscariot; and with reason, according to the New Gospels, Talmuds and Dismal Sciences of these days.

190 But it is in the nature of the democratic system that the yardstick for measuring equality cannot come from outside the system. The definitions of equality, of due, and of justice are also subject to the democratic process. The characteristic element of modern democracy is the dismantling of inequalities of every kind. I prefer to describe a democratic society as one which is governed by a spirit of equality and dominated by the desire to equalize, to give everything to everybody (Boorstin

L79/102). The result of this development which, incidentally, the French Revolution confirmed soon afterwards, had been foreseen by Tocqueville (L807/185): But man will never achieve equality he will be satisfied with.
191 The Jacobine Republic introduced this unitary ideal into the laws and habits of France which later a minister of the second Empire so well expressed when he, looking at his watch, flattered himself on the fact that he was able to say just which exercise all the pupils in all the schools of France were doing according to their curriculum (Viatte L834/180s).

192 Hippel (L361/233) attempted to contrast modern democracy, which he described as quantitative democracy, with the qualitative, moral order of classical democracy. But mass society's democracy is also value oriented with its ideal measure (Imboden L387/23s), its idea of justice. In the final analysis both classical and modern Western democracy aim to enhance the individual person. The difference lies with the methods used and especially with the role of the state in this process. As modern democracy seeks to achieve this end through the highest possible degree of social and political equality, where the state has to play a major role it is impatient with formalities and with individual interests which impede the achievement of the objectives of the majority (see Kgi L403/181, L405/137). And as political freedom is nothing but a special kind of protection for certain areas of individual autonomy from majority dictate, it is particularly endangered in egalitarian democracies.
193 Democracy cannot be conceived without equality, but it can be conceived... without liberty (Schindler L713/60). Or Lenin (L474/38): In reality, democracy excludes liberty. - Tocqueville (L807/432ss): Let's imagine which could be the traits of a new kind of despotism in the world: I see an uncounted multitude of men, all similar and equal, in constant agitation to procure themselves little vulgar pleasures with which to fill their souls.... Above them there is an immense tutelary power that unassisted assumes the task to provide for their pleasures and to look to their future. This power is absolute, detailed, orderly, farsighted, and benign.... I have always thought that this kind of servitude... which I have just described could be combined much better than many believe with some of the outward appearances of liberty and that it would not be impossible for it to be established even in the shadow of popular sovereignty.

194 It is part of the logic of equality that it applies to individuals rather than to groups. The image that corresponds most closely to the democracy's vision of society is a social atomism: the atoms themselves being simple and perfectly interchangeable are suitably governed by a few majestic generalities (Koritansky L443/69, see also Tocqueville L807/137). Social atomism is the antithesis of pluralism, where groups are the building blocks. Pluralist democracy stands for the equal treatment of varied groups. This will of necessity result in a certain measure of inequality towards individuals. The concept of equality in the modern, individualist, and all-embracing sense is clearly strained if it has to include the acceptance of the autonomy of plural groups. This tension becomes obvious precisely in the relations of democracy, modern democracy especially, with federalism.

D. FEDERALISM

Contents Index End

195 As was the case with democracy (no.045), the term federalism has no universally accepted meaning. Federalism has now become one of those good echo words that evoke a positive response but that may mean all things to all men, like democracy... or peace. We see the term applied to almost any form of pluralism and cooperation within and among nations (Duchacek L180/190). Federalism is a generic concept for very diverse forms of the organizational combination of more or less autonomous units (Walper L843/11) or for the process leading to either such combinations or to their opposite, disaggregation (Duchacek L180/189). 196 It is understandable that proposals are made from time to time for a standard vocabulary of federalism for research purposes (e.g. Baker L45/1, Landau L449/173). I do not believe in such an enterprise. It would be unlikely to bear more fruit than the scholastic quarrels in former centuries. All that may in fairness be insisted on is that it becomes clear in the context of an author's thesis what he means by using the word federalism and that he applies a certain economy to his use of concepts by not calling the same thing under different names (as would be the case, for example, if pluralism were to be equated with federalism). But the last expectation is possibly already too ambitious. 197 The following considerations are not designed to bring forth the definitive definition of federalism. My only aim is to bring some clarity to conceptual relationships and to show what we are talking about. It goes without saying that I shall try to use consistent terminology. But I make no purist claims. Judged by its results my approach is to steer a middle course between the tendency to expand the concept to all forms of pluralist decision making (L180/51, L550/1111, L654/109s, L843/11) and the opposing tendency to use federalism in such a narrow way that only a very small part of the existing federations may still be called federal (L528/10). 198 For the purpose of explaining federalism, the point of departure is the observation that it is a principle for the organization of decision making in an association of groups. The particularity of this association is that the groups as such

have a special function in central decision making and they possess also a certain autonomy. Such a system is pluralist (no.201ss). It is only when the basis of group diversity is territorial that we call it federalist (no.210ss). If the territorially organized groups are at the same time states under the law of nations we may then talk about a confederacy or a confederation of states (no.247ss). And if both the association and its members are states -the latter, it is true, in a limited sense- then we are confronted with a federation (no.254ss). This classification at least has the merit that each definition is deduced from a more general one by the introduction of a strict minimum of additional limitations. However, a proviso must be made for the concept of federation. This is not only a scientific term. It may also be a de iure term defined by a given constitution. This means that it is logically possible that there is federation without federalism (no.256) because the concepts are defined on different levels. 199 This hierarchy of concepts is simply a useful aid for classification. It conveys nothing, or very little, about the essence, the meaning, and the ends of federalism. It is static. The dynamic aspects of federalism and its relation to democracy will only be seen when we analyse the functional aspects of federalism (no.404ss).
200 There are advantages to be gained from this distinction between concepts and functions. For one thing it makes it possible to clarify the interdependence of terms which up to now has been the case mostly for word-pairs but not for the whole array of terms (see Frenkel L258/1s). Thus it is feasible to answer the question what is federalism? (as to some doubts see Fleiner L782/1028) without falling prey to some empty empiricism (see Hunger L373/10), and without becoming entangled in the confusion caused by the difference between reality and normativity (Dennewitz L161/84). Furthermore, the distinction provides a useful framework for the understanding of the characteristics of other definitions. Such characteristics usually emphasize specific goals implicit in the definitions. Alternatively, federalism could be defined by isolating specific institutions that establish the federal character of a political system. This approach is not very successful. It either leads to a vague concept (e.g. Livingston L485/272) or to a somewhat arbitrary one, as for instance Hughes (L370/13,16) who does not admit of the very concept of federation. (To Hughes federations are but a subspecies of the constitutional type of government, differentiated by some institutional elements of confederacy which alone has true conceptual reality. This approach reminds us of the notion of federation as a decentralized unitary state, no.228s.)

D.1 THE CONCEPT OF PLURALISM

Contents Index End

201 A system for decision making is pluralist if it is an entity composed of groups each of which enjoys a certain independence and which, together, participate in an ordered and permanent way in the formation of the central entity's will.
202 This definition shows a certain relationship to some other definitions, for example those of Kremendahl and by Presthus. Pluralism is the existence of a multitude of varied social interests and their organized representation in political decision making. The struggle for influence takes place within a framework of mutually agreed rules (Kremendahl L229/286). We shall here understand it as a social system of politics where the state, a multitude of private groups, interest organizations, and individuals represented by such associations share power.... To state it briefly: Pluralism stands for a system which distributes political power amongst public law corporations, in addition to which it is split up between the public realm and a plurality of private groups and individuals (Presthus L631/81).

203 The decision-making system defined here does not necessarily have to be in the public realm. It may be any association at all. However, at the centre of theories of pluralism we nearly always find the state and thus political pluralism. The groups may represent any deliberately formed human associations. These may be based on ethnic, professional, religious, geographic, voluntary and other affiliations. That they enjoy a certain independence, that is autonomous regulation, is both a result of their organization as a group and a practical prerequisite for their participation in central decision making. This participation has to be secured and permanent; it must not be left to chance. The guarantee is to be found in the existence of regular mechanisms for participation with their own sanctions. (As to the connection between autonomy and participation see Kelsen L413/284s.) 204 Elements of pluralism may be found in practically all states. Some of the best known empirical studies are Dahl's in the United States city of New Haven, Lijphart's in the Netherlands (L480) and Lorwin's in Belgium and in the Netherlands (L491s). But Austria (Diamant L532/150, Lehmbruch L465/93) and Switzerland (Steiner L773s) also offer interesting opportunities for studies in this context.
205 The actual Lebanese Constitution, which is largely in abeyance because of Lebanon's entanglement in the Middle East conflicts, is a marked example of a pluralist but non-federalist model. Following the Ottoman millet tradition (L205a/5), the Constitution neatly distributes public power among most of the different denominational population groups (L180/106, L183/96s, L465/93, L481/148ss, L582/23). This pluralist approach was also a characteristic of the former Estonian Constitution (Blck L104/12, L275/3) as well as of the Cypriot Constitution from 1960 until the coup d'tat of 1974. The Cyprus Constitution attempted to achieve a settlement between the Greek and the Turkish population groups (compare articles 1 to 5; L180/105, L183/97s, L481/158ss). A similar approach was to be found in Appartheid South Africa. The Constitution in existence before 1982 in no way corresponded with the plural structure of society. Appartheid reform plans were mostly oriented towards a pluralist concept (see L656/409s,455, L870/53ss, Government Gazette 3.4.1979 pp.12 and 30).

206 Another variety of pluralist political organization is the corporativist or corporatist state (both expressions are used). Under corporativism or corporatism representation in at least one house of parliament is organized on the basis of nonethnic groups, especially professional groups (see Manoilesco in L719/44 and already Hegel L348/255). D'Annunzio's Constitution for Fiume after the first World War was

of this kind. But the favour corporativism enjoyed with the fascists in Germany, Italy and on the Iberian peninsula made the concept fall into disrepute, along with fascism itself (L579/54s, L719/8). Nevertheless, we find a modern application in the Yugoslav Constitution, where the Federation Council is composed of representatives from enterprises, local communities and social organizations. 207 Recently corporatism or neo-corporatism has had a renaissance as an analytical tool for political science. It has been used, for example, by Schmitter. For him it is not a subset of pluralism but stands on the same level with the latter (L719/15, like monism and syndicalism L719/16s). To this end Schmitter has constructed a definition of pluralism which is markedly different from the one used here (L719/15). He conceives corporatism as (L719/13, critical: Lehmbruch L467/149s) a system of interest representation in which the constituent units are organized into a limited number of singular, compulsory, noncompetitive, hierarchically ordered and functionally differentiated categories, recognized and licensed (if not created) by the state and granted a deliberate representational monopoly within their respective categories in exchange for observing certain controls on their selection of leaders and articulation of demands and supports. Schmitter readily admits that this definition is a construct (L719/45), the elements of which will not be fully implemented in any real state (L719/14). His examples - Brazil, Chile, Denmark, Portugal, Switzerland, and Yugoslavia (L719/18) - lead to the conclusion that for him corporatist structures may be found in all pluralistically organized political systems. This somewhat diminishes the analytical value of his concept. However, corporativism or corporatism seems to be very much the darling of contemporary political science (for a detailed exposition see Lehmbruch L468/1ss). 208 The theory of pluralism is multi-faceted. The models of pluralism and of democracy are very often closely intertwined. For an overview of different, mainly British and American, schools of pluralism see Nicholls (L579). The functions ascribed to pluralism are very often the same as those assigned to federalism. Therefore, a considerable part of the presentation below (no.404ss) is also applicable to pluralism.
209 In the foreground of theories of pluralism we usually find the problem of how to manage intergroup conflict, i.e. the problem of the integration of groups into the overarching system. In this context there are two mechanisms which have been closely analysed: separation or segmentation with elite-accommodation (see no.142ss) and cross-cutting cleavages (see no.582ss).

D.2 THE CONCEPT OF FEDERALISM

Contents Index End

210 A system for decision making is federalist if it is an entity composed of territorially defined groups each of which enjoys relatively high autonomy and which, together, participate in an ordered and permanent way in the formation of the central entity's will. 211 It is the territorial element that distinguishes federalism from pluralism and defines the former as a subvariety of the latter. The main characteristic of the groups, then, is their relationship to some specific part of the globe's surface. To paraphrase Gabriel Almond, a territorial interest group is a group of people 'linked by a particular bond of territorial concern and advantage and aware of these bonds (Duchacek L181/3).
212 When other authors make a distinction between pluralism and federalism they practically always use territory as a basis for their differentiation (e.g. Aubert L37/402, Duchacek L180/51,192, Ermacora L214/22, Friedrich L277/51, King L419a/19, Livingston L485/2s, L486/23, and Lorwin L491/44). It appears that this territorial element is one of the most vital components of political structures generally. This may be one of the reasons for the comparatively large number of federal organizations relative to other plural ones. This is so because territory provides one of the primary foci of identity, not in the sense of any romanticized 'territorial imperative,' but simply because where one lives is a basic way of establishing a social as well as a physical location (Schwartz L736/107). Politically, territorial organization has an attractive function, as it aims at and often succeeds in aggregating various special and functional interests into a comprehensive and cooperative whole.... In general, people seem to support and identify with a spatially defined community more readily than with a nonterritorial interest or organization (Duchacek L181/24s).

213 The definition proposed here does not specify autonomy but requires relatively high autonomy. This recognizes ordinary usage whereby an entity with a small degree of autonomy would be called decentralized rather than federal (as to this distinction see no.222ss). Relatively at the same time introduces a factor of judgment, which explains why the federal character of a given political system may be assessed differently by different observers. And lastly we must be careful not to interpret autonomy in an absolute sense. It is always relative autonomy, autonomy within the framework of a system (see Altenstetter L21/5). 214 As a word federalism may be traced back to foedus, the Latin term for union. The English term was coined during the Civil War in 1645. Its present meaning originated in 1777 during the American Revolution (Elazar L198/xiiis, also L424/580). The French fdralisme was first used by Montesquieu (Voyenne L837/63, but fdration dates back to the 14th century). In French parlance the concept is mainly connected with the Revolution and the struggle between Jacobins and Girondists (L675/97s, see no.381s). The modern European use of the word usually stresses the autonomy of the units (see Deuerlein L165/153s). The English term federal, on the other hand, rather points to central concerns. This is certainly the case for the United States and Canada. It is increasingly so for Australia

(Alexander L17/vi). When the word federalism is used in the present book it is in a more scientific sense, in relation to the system as a whole. (See the comments on federation and confederation, no.302.) 215 Federalism is not a legal term (Dennewitz L161/21, Harbich L339/46, Loebenstein L487/834, de Reynold L654/110; Messmer is inaccurate L542/110). It is an organizational principle in the political or social realm. Confederation and federation are both legal terms (no.241ss). Federalism might be a legal concept if a given constitution would make it a binding mandate for legislation, administration and the judiciary (for an illustration see L525/20/I/20). In such a case the general meaning of the word would not suffice for its interpretation. The legal construction would have to be arrived at in the context of the specific constitutional arrangements.
216 There exists a certain relation between the definition here proposed and those given by, amongst others, Friedrich (L277/54) and Livingston (L485/9). Friedrich: In short, we can properly speak of federalism only if a set of political groupings coexist and interact as autonomous entities, united in a common order with an autonomy of its own. Livingston: Federal government is a form of political and constitutional organization that unites into a single polity a number of diversified groups or component polities so that the personality and individuality of the component parts is largely preserved while creating in the new totality a separate and distinct political and constitutional unit. 217 Some authors stress additional requirements. Schechter for instance (L710/3s) emphasizes contractual relationships as the historic basis of federalism. Ostrom (L593/205) asks for a minimum of democratic control; and many scholars introduce goals or rule of law prerequisites into their definitions. I prefer not to include such elements but to look at them in the context of the functions of federalism (no.404ss). A more recent tendency considers federalism to be mainly a process (Altenstetter L20/5, Friedrich L275/3) or a model (Vile L835/4,6s). This may be understandable as a reaction to the emptiness (Vile L835/2) of many modern definitions. However, both approaches are not of much help for classification. 218 In the United States the disparity of the various concepts of federalism (compare the alphabet in no.316ss) has resulted in a certain academic preference for the more clearly definable term intergovernmental relations as a substitute for federalism (Beer L57/50, Wright L873/1s). It is obvious that this term covers but a segment of the subject.

219 If we look at federal systems we will find federations like Australia, Germany, and Switzerland. But there are also nongovernmental entities we may call federal, such as the League of Red Cross Societies, trade unions, and political parties (especially in federations). And finally associations of states are federal systems, as for instance the United Nations and the Council of Europe.
220 The economic theory of federalism (see no.223, 472ss, 516ss) shows a tendency to equate federalism with pluralism. Kirsch (L421/13s) is a case in point: There are, then, two ways to transcend the actual state of the theory of federalism. One is to include decision processes that take place within collectives. The other approach extends the field of inquiry to non-state, non-regional associations. For the sake of conceptual clarity it might be better to call this an economic theory of pluralism.

D.21 Federalism and its Complements

Contents Index End

221 Federalism, particularism, centralism, unitarianism, or decentralization are terms very often used together. Let us see how we may differentiate them. (American texts very often make little distinction between intergovernmental relations and federalism. Yet the former are but one aspect of federalism, Frenkel L264b/1477, Gaus L783a/44ss.) 222 The terms just mentioned are not opposites. We may imagine a continuum of links ranging from no connection at all to complete unity. It is on such a continuum that we must localize our terms. Viewed from the one end of the row - unrelated diversity - to the other -unity- the process will appear as one of centralization or consolidation. Centralization is usually more concerned with the concentration of procedures, consolidation with the concentration of structures. But we may also look at the continuum from the other side, from unity to diversity. Then we are faced with decentralization, particularization, disintegration, or separatism. Again these are processes. The concept of federalism occupies a fairly large range somewhere in the centre of the continuum, where particularist and unitary elements overlap. If we transfer these considerations to government we may say that confederation as well as federation are to be found in some place between the complete (theoretical) independence of states and their (equally theoretical) consolidation in a totally undifferentiated unitary state. Confederation is nearer to the one, federation is nearer to the other side (see also L161/92, L174/4, L221/8ss, L251/1, L339/20, L370/5s, L413/310,316, L486/24, L654/21s, L685/111, L700/16, L708/138, L744/177, L862/136).
223 Political economists have shown a special interest in the concept of decentralization. They see it as the common denominator for federalism, democracy, and the market economy. All three types of decentralization are about the distribution of decision-making powers amongst a great number of persons or organizations. In the market economy we will have the consumers and employees on the one and the producers and employers on the other side which are the autonomous actors; in democracy these are the citizens, in federations the regional member-states (Frey L268/17, also L58/22, L267/362, for a more subtle analysis compare Winkler L868a/277ss).

224 Sometimes a distinction is made between decentralization, deconcentration and devolution. The essence of deconcentration is the transfer of powers from central authorities to subordinate, specialized, and usually local ones which are still part of the same hierarchy (L231/5s, L503/23, L538/348, L742/52, L855a/151). Decentralization, then, would stand for the transfer of powers to local communities with a certain autonomy. The same differentiation is meant when authors talk about

administrative and geographic decentralization (L377/86). Transfer to autonomous local units is also known as devolution, especially in British parlance. It could be said that decentralization is the general concept which comprises both administrative deconcentration and political devolution (L503/23). But usage is very loose. 225 There is a theoretic discussion about the difference between 'federalism' proper and 'decentralization'. As a matter of fact there exists no difference of quality but only one of degree: decentralization is reduced federalism, federalism is decentralization very emphasized (Duverger L186/71). If we are only concerned with the logical graduation of legal normativity we may accept this idea of Duverger and others. But it does not do justice to the political phenomenon of federalism. I agree with Diamond (L169/136): Now the very word decentralization implies the existence of a real center from which things are to be decentralized, and not only the existence of that center, but also its priority or supremacy.... As we have seen, the essence of federalism lies in the fact that it rests upon arguments as to why a group of polities ought, despite certain common interests, to remain decisively themselves and ought not to form a nation. Decentralization, on the contrary, presupposes a nation and rests upon arguments merely as to how the nation ought to be organized so as to achieve liberty or other desired qualities. 226 If we look to social reality rather than to abstract terms we observe that federal structures are usually brought forth by some process of centralization and not by decentralization. It is not unity that is the basis but particularism. For federations, to take the typically federal form of government, it is not decentralization that is essential but non-centralization. True federal systems must be non-centralized systems. Even when, in practical situations, there seems to be only the thin line of the spirit between non-centralization and decentralization, it is that thin line which determines the extent and character of the diffusion of power in a particular regime (Elazar L198/xii, compare Elazar L205b/14, Richardson L637/6-4/4).
227 There are some additional terms which complement decentralization, for instance selforganization and self-management. The differences are similar to those between non-centralization and decentralization (Pernthaler L615/19ss). Federalism is based on the assumption that its constituent parts are to a considerable degree self-organized and self-managed.

228 The constitutional law analogy to the general discussion about federalism and decentralization is the distinction between federations and decentralized unitary states (L244/45, no.292). Preuss calls this the eternal question with no possible answer (L632/145).
229 To conceive of federations as decentralized unitary states is in keeping with a purely normlogical approach (such as Kelsen's so-called pure theory of law). From this point of departure it is quite probable that a clear-cut distinction will never be possible (see Usteri's attempt in L825/236). The whole discussion is very much steeped in the whimsicalities of European constitutional law traditions. To call a federation a decentralized unitary state introduces a polemical element into the discussion. From a pure theory of law viewpoint, the unitary state is a tautology. As legal systems states are, according to this theory, always unitary. If logical consistency were the aim -and Kelsen's school aims for it- federations might be called decentralized states. To talk about decentralized unitary states makes sense only if we wish to introduce a pointedly anti-federal note.

230 I quite like the graphic description of the difference between administrative decentralization and political federalism which was given by the French politician Barrot who, when commenting on the decentralization decrees of 1852 and 1861, sarcastically said (L837/294): It's still the same hammer that pounds, they have but shortened the handle.

D.22 Federalism and Subsidiarity

Contents Index End

231 The concepts of federalism and subsidiarity are related to each other. But they do not coincide. Federalism is concerned with the structure of the decision-making process, with the co-existence and co-operation of different autonomies (no.210). Subsidiarity has to do with the allocation of tasks within a given political structure in such a way that the process ascends from bottom to top. The principle of subsidiarity may be optimally implemented within a federal structure. But the latter is not indispensable (see Dennewitz L161/87, Ehringhaus L194/33, Hesse L356/2s). Subsidiarity is suited to every kind of pluralism and also to the relationship between the private and the public sector (compare Jellinek L382/259, Utz L827/84, Wilson L863/1531s). It also has its place in unitary states, e.g. for problems of decentralization, because the element of participation in central decision making, essential for federalism, plays no role for the subsidiarity principle.
232 Like federalism, subsidiarity is not a legal concept. When the Basic Law (Grundgesetz) of the Federal Republic of Germany was being drafted, an attempt was made to make this notion part of the law of the land (L339/117s). But this was not successful. Within the European Union's legal framework subsidiarity is a concept of law. But it is questionable to what degree its application corresponds to the bottom-up approach usually associated with the term.

233 What is the meaning of the principle of subsidiarity? The term has two different if related connotations. Both derive from the Latin word subsidium. One meaning has to do with reserve, i.e. with something that applies only if some primary condition is lacking. The other meaning is connected with the concept of help: subsidy. 234 The first meaning is the one mainly used in European theories of government. It signifies that one should always start with the smallest group or even with individuals when allocating functions. This level is always competent insofar as it can assume a

function effectively and without damage to others. Only those problems that exceed the group's possibilities are to be assumed by the next more encompassing group. As a supreme principle of social philosophy the subsidiarity principle is nothing else than a kind of jurisdiction rule, for the jurisdiction between communities and finally also between the individual and society (Marcic L509/431).
235 Thus defined, subsidiarity corresponds with Hraud's concept of exact adequation (adquation exacte, L668/211). Hraud himself does not admit this because he burdens his definition of subsidiarity with an unnecessary element of delegation (L668/208ss).

236 In its other sense the term is that used by the Freiburg (Switzerland) social philosopher Utz: The principle of subsidiarity is a law concerning assistance: society's to the individual, or the more encompassing group's to the smaller one, as e.g. the state helping the families or free associations (subsidium = assistance)... According to the principle of subsidiarity society should assist the individual where the latter cannot fully achieve his goals with his own means (L827/17s). The general welfare is based on solidary subsidiarity. This is to say that in the interest of the public welfare society as a whole has the duty to come to the aid of the individual according to his needs (L827/61). 237 The philosophic foundation of subsidiarity may in both cases be the same. The view-points are different. In the first case it is bottom to top, in the second one top to bottom. This is the same with political parlance. The subsidiarity principle in its theory of government meaning is invoked when the non-centralization of a function is to be defended. The other meaning is emphasized when there is a need to justify financial subsidies.
238 Quite often the principle of subsidiarity is interpreted as an achievement of Catholic social teaching (e.g. Marcic L509/429, Stadler L764/12ss) by pointing to Pope Pius XIth's encyclical quadragesimo anno. But this is too narrow an understanding. Based on the doctrines of the division of powers and of the social compact there is a Western tradition of subsidiarity which has probably been more influential than the religious one (L764/13). Classical antiquity was familiar with the idea, as is evidenced for instance by Aristotle's consideration of the advantage of independence over unification (L34/2/2).

239 In the context of this text, subsidiarity is not taken as an end of or a justification for federalism (see the doubts of Hangartner L336/31, Lerche L477/74s). Subsidiarity is first and foremost a principle for the allocation of functions in federations. Despite other authors' doubts, it is helpful to use subsidiarity as a principle for assigning the burden of proof in discussions about the division of functions in federations. As a matter of fact, it is more functional than most other approaches (such as national interest or spillover theories). From a federalist perspective, subsidiarity introduces a bias towards non-centralization. Given the overwhelmingly centralizing pull of modern institutions this is not an undesirable counterweight. For a more detailed discussion of the application of the principle of subsidiarity see the German companion volume to this monograph (L264b/957ss).

240 The legal embodiment of subsidiarity in federal constitutions is, to a certain degree, the states' rights clause, for instance the 10th Amendment to the United States Constitution: The powers not delegated to the United States by the Constitution, nor prohibited by it to the States, are reserved to the States respectively, or to the people. In all federations with the exception of India and of Canada the constitution presumes that tasks not assigned to the central government are of the member states' jurisdiction. Because of very special circumstances the situation is practically the same in Canada, although the Constitution says something different (see L264b/996 and L684/1ss). The Yugoslav Constitution (C116/3) even contains a presumption in favour of local government.

D.3 FEDERALISM IN GOVERNMENT

Contents Index End

241 I have repeatedly emphasized that federalism is an organizational principle that is not restricted to the political sphere. Nevertheless, it is here that scientific interest is most acute. Two specific forms are in the foreground of discussions: confederation (no.247ss) and federation (no.254ss). 242 Elements of federalism are also to be found, however, in many non-federations. Very often, for instance, territorial units like provinces or communes enjoy a relatively high degree of autonomy and even participate in central decision making. In federations there is also a relatively high probability that the member states will show traits of federalism in their organization. Even if they are not themselves federations (as some were in the USSR and in Yugoslavia), local governments are very often considered to be the political pillar of federalism; as for instance in Switzerland (see Bumlin L54/143). In unitary states with demographically different units we may also find elements of federalism. Even if, to give an example, we know very little about the actual structure of the People's Republic of China, geography, the existence of 54 national minorities (L176/14) and the Constitution (e.g. art.4,95ss), it is evident that we may expect some federal traits, democratic centralism notwithstanding (see Bryce L99/559, also Donnithorne L177a/3ss). Another illustration of federal structures in a unitary state are the Italian regions, especially those with a special statute (L182/101ss, L852/introduction; in this context see also my reflections on partially deconcentrated states, no.403). The Spanish Constitution reads very much like that of a federation. Federalism in this unitary state appears to be at least as real as in Argentina, to take a real federation. Or consider the special status of Northern Ireland and of Scotland in Great Britain (L180/121, L182/98, L485/269s, L505/331s). Federalism is undoubtedly more universal than federations are!

243 The quasi-state entity of the Roman Catholic Church also shows elements of federalism. Thus there exists a kind of confederation of the fifteen Benedictine congregations which are themselves federally structured.

244 Political federalism, therefore, is not tied to the existence of member states or of other territorial subdivisions of a specific kind. The groups I mentioned in my definition of federalism (no.210) may be varied and of different influence. In this I concur with Ostrom (L593/205) who prefers to characterize a 'highly federalized' political system as one which has a rich structure of overlapping jurisdictions with substantial autonomy among jurisdictions. I see no point in confining discussions... to state governments and the Federal government. The federal principle can be (and is in the American context) used to organize numerous concurrent regimes. 245 Because federalism is a political rather than a legal concept (no.215), the usual imagery representing it as a pyramid and thereby as a hierarchy is erroneous. The hierarchy of legal norms which has been taken over from legal theory is not essential even there (see L264b/877). To illustrate federalism as a structure of more or less overlapping centres of power is much more accurate than to point to the pre-eminence of a higher level in a pyramid (compare Elazar L201/283, Jerusalem L385/5). The adjoining illustration is taken from Elazar (L205b/15).
246 In this context we should introduce Grodzin's famous analogy between federalism and the marble cake (L310/3s, compare no.328): The federal system is not accurately symbolized by a neat layer cake of three distinct and separate planes. A far more realistic symbol is that of the marble cake. Wherever you slice through it you reveal an inseparable mixture of differently colored ingredients. There is no horizontal stratification. Vertical and diagonal lines almost obliterate the horizontal ones, and in some places there are unexpected whirls and an imperceptible merging of colors, so that it is difficult to tell where one ends and the other begins. So it is with federal, state, and local responsibilities in the chaotic marble cake of American government. This is quite different from the Frenchman Scelle's assertion (L700/14): Federalism is, let's repeat it, the contrary of anarchy because it is hierarchy: hierarchy of norms, hierarchy of institutions, of governments, and of administrations.

D.31 Confederation

Contents Index End

247 A system for decision making is a confederation if it is an entity composed of states, i.e. of territorial governments independent under the law of nations which, together, participate in an ordered and permanent way in the formation of the central entity's will.
248 States being comprehensive territorial units, they have by their nature great autonomy. It is therefore not necessary to emphasize this element (no.210) in the above definition.

249 Confederations (we will also encounter the terms leagues or unions) are not complete unions. They are restricted to a few specific common tasks. It is thus possible - and normal - for a state to be a partner in several confederations. An earlier German doctrine considered certain ends to be conceptually essential: The confederation ('Staatenbund') is a permanent treaty based union of independent states with the twin goals of common defense of the union's territory and the keeping of peace amongst the united states. Additional aims may be agreed upon (Jellinek L382/762). It is true that internal and external security were at the basis of most old confederations. But to-day we are also talking about confederations, even if they have nothing to do with security, being for instance concerned with economic problems only, or with very restricted technical ones (e.g. navigation on common water-ways).

Still, not every international treaty institutes a confederation or union. This occurs only when some sort of common decision making is institutionalized. This institutionalization, incidentally, will sometimes go very far and the common functions may be so important that the new entity is treated not unlike a state in international relations (as with the United Nations and the European Communities).
250 From an historical perspective confederations are forerunners of federations. The inventors of modern federations, the founding fathers of the American Constitution (no.379), set out to combine the kind of loose federalism they considered the ancient Greek unions to have had with the unitary or national principle. The result was a new kind of regime, federation. This explains why the partisans of the 1787 Constitution were very often attacked as anti-federalists: They are national men, and their opponents, or at least a great majority of them, are federal, in the only true and strict sense of the word (L80/6, compare Diamond L169/135s). A modern parallel to this discussion is Hughes's theory granting conceptual reality only to confederation (no.200, for his differentiation of loose, narrow and very narrow confederation see L370/11ss).

251 The main terminological problem is the distinction between confederations and federations. It is comparatively recent (no.250). I will come back to this after analysing the concept of federation (no.302ss). Let me just point out that English and French parlance are less rigid than is the German use of the words Staatenbund (confederation) and Bundesstaat (federation).
252 I do not make a distinction between alliances and confed erations. If such a one had to be proffered, it would probably be based on the level of institutionalization and on the fact that alliances are usually temporary, whereas confederations are permanent (compare Flora L247/11, Nelson L576/8). But both unions are soluble and transitions are fluid. Nor do I deal with the other kinds of associations of states such as personal unions, real unions and the formerly important relations of suzerainty (see Jellinek L382/750ss, Rivier L664/94ss).

253 To-day all states of the world which are independent under the law of nations belong to at least one confederation. The few countries which are not yet members of the United Nations, Taiwan for instance, are bound to other nations through a multitude of different treaties.

D.32 Federation

Contents Index End

254 A system for decision making is a federation if it is itself a state, i.e. a territorial government independent under the law of nations, composed of territorial units with a

relatively high degree of autonomy which therefore, or for historical reasons, are also called states and which participate in an ordered and permanent way in the formation of the central government's will. 255 The federation is the typical form of federalist government (compare Dennewitz L161/105, Huber L782/1158, Jellinek L382/785; for a different theory, see Hughes no.200). Federation is a legal term (Frenkel L264b/699, Harbich L339/46, Macmahon L501/v,3). Like most legal terms the concept of federation has two aspects. First it is a subject for constitutional law or theory in general (for a contrary view: Hippel L361/250). However, this is not enough to understand fully the practical applications of the concept. We have to consider also its use in a given constitution. The concept of federation as we find it in the basic law thus has two sources. By using this term (the actual wording is different) the constitution refers to general theory. But this theory is then complemented, and sometimes considerably amended, by the actual form of federation (see Hempel L352/209).
256 It may very well be the case that a given federation is not a federation in the sense of the general theory. Thus the federal character of communist and Latin American federations is denied by many scholars. And it was indeed difficult to consider the two member republics of former Czechoslovakia as enjoying relatively high autonomy. Nevertheless, the fact that separate authorities do exist may create the fertile soil necessary for a certain federalist evolution. As to the Yugoslav Constitution, it was the most dogmatically federalist basic law ever devised (see for instance the member republics' absolute veto power in article 295). We may perhaps question the effectiveness of such federalist elements. In any case it is advisable to check closely the constitutional realities before passing judgement on the federality of federations (compare L26/163s, L339/46, L838/51).

257 My definition of federation may sound unusual. Yet it is not so different from Wheare's, the one usually found in textbooks (L858/10, also L859/19): By the federal principle I mean the method of dividing powers so that the general and regional governments are each, within a sphere co-ordinate and independent. Unlike Wheare I emphasize the applicability of the federal principle to the non-governmental realm, and in the governmental one I do not restrict it to federations as Wheare's definition implicitly does.
258 Wheare's definition may be traced back to Garran (L858/14): A form of government in which sovereignty or political power is divided between the central and the local governments, so that each of them within its own sphere is independent of the other. Birch has slightly restated Wheare's formula (L173/7): a federal system of government is one in which there is a division of powers between one general and several regional authorities, each of which, in its own sphere, is coordinate with the others, and each of which acts directly on the people through its own administrative agencies. In a similar vein Duchacek (L180/194): By a federal system we mean a constitutional division of power between one general government (that is to have authority over the entire national territory) and a series of subnational governments (that individually have their own independent authority over their own territories, whose sum total represent almost the whole national territory. Further refinements have been added by Vile (L63/4): Federalism is a system of government in which central and regional authorities are linked in a mutually interdependent political relationship; in this system a balance is maintained such that neither level of government becomes dominant to the extent that it can dictate the decisions of the other, but each can influence, bargain with, and persuade the other. Usually, but not necessarily, this system will be related to a constitutional structure

establishing an independent legal existence for both central and regional governments, and providing that neither shall be legally subordinate to the other. The functions of government will be distributed between these levels (exclusively, competitively, or co-operatively), initially perhaps by a political process, involving where appropriate the judiciary... These definitions, incidentally, show that Anglo-Saxon writers do not usually make a clear distinction between federalism and federation.

259 In German definitions, as in many French ones, the problem of sovereignty is very often an essential element. The federation is a sovereign state composed of a plurality of states whose power is based on its politically united member states. It is a public law association of states instituting governance over the united states in such a way that the members are always these states which in their totality rule or participate in ruling and which singly are subjects in certain areas (Jellinek L382/769). For Merk (L833/21/115) federations are legal associations of several states creating an aggregate state with an aggregate state population, an aggregate state territory, and an independent and supreme dominion, in such a way that according to its constitution these member states have independent state powers not derived from the central government, that they participate in the decision making of central government in a supreme authority, but that they are subjected to the domination of the central government in the areas of the latter's jurisdiction. The problem of the locus of sovereignty in federations bedevils a great part of German and French legal discussion about the concept of federation. This, together with the related debate about the status of member states, will be treated in more detail below (no.272ss). 260 Let us now consider the individual elements of my definition: First, the association has to be a state, i.e. a state as conceived by the law of nations. This establishes a differentiation from a confederation (for details see no.302ss). It also points to the existence of an encompassing legal structure (compare the detailed description in Frenkel L264b/875ss). 261 The parts are member states, i.e. territorial governments which are designated as states. This parlance is somewhat questionable because it is obvious that such entities differ from the nation states which usually participate in international relations. Many European authors, therefore, refuse to talk of states in this context (see Giacometti L244/43s, hlinger L587/15, Usteri L825/209). This has a close connection to the discussion about sovereignty in federations (no.272ss). On the other hand we must not fail to notice that the constitutions very often talk about states, republics or Lnder. Science thus has no choice but to accept that there exists some state quality to be defined in member states, even if we lack legal yardsticks for the clear-cut differentiation from provincial self-government (in political reality this may be simpler).
262 The characteristic elements of a member state are a) a full and autonomously appointed structure of authorities not only administrative but also political, b) direct constitutional settlement of organization and essential tasks (see article 29 of the West German Basic Law providing for legislative rearrangement of state boundaries), and c) a specific role in central decision making. The level of central control (see the difference between decentralized and non-centralized no.226) is also important. But an evident distinction between member states and provinces is not possible. In addition to this, there is the problem that in some countries (such as Canada by article 5 of the

Constitution) member states are called provinces. In the final analysis the difference between member states and autonomous provinces is largely one of terminology and of little importance so long as it is not used as the basis for normative deductions and it is clear what one talks about. The particularity of a member state as compared with an autonomous province cannot be deduced from the term but only from the fact that it is part of a federation. 263 The term state is used in Australia, Brazil, India, Malaysia, Mexico, Nigeria, the United States of America, and Venezuela. In the composite council of states it also appears in the French and in the Italian texts of the Swiss Constitution. Here the common term is cantons or Stnde. The term republic was used in Czechoslovakia, the USSR, and Yugoslavia. Austria and the Federal Republic of Germany speak of Lnder, Argentina, Canada and Pakistan of provinces. The Comores are made up of isles. The United Arab Emirates contain emirates. Finally, Tanzania just talks about Zanzibar and sometimes, by way of contrast, of Mainland Tanzania.

264 According to the definition the autonomy of member states should be relatively high. If something is relative it is based on a value judgment. This explains why we often find differences of opinion as to some federation's genuineness or its quasi status (e.g. Wagner L838/29, Wheare L858/20, L859/20s). It is obvious that it is quite difficult to place an exact borderline between sufficient and insufficient autonomy. The observer's ideological viewpoint will colour his assessment. (The question is one I deal with further in the context of the criteria for the allocation of functions in federations, L264b/886ss). The field is open-ended at both sides. A given federation is federalist if its member states, in their relations with the federal government, enjoy some full autonomy which may be heightened to such a degree that there is but a theoretical difference to confederation. Where, on the other side, a federation shows unitary traits, the member states' independence is more or less restricted in favour of the federal government. This may reach a point where the difference to a unitary state is, again, but theoretical (Jerusalem L385/5). 265 The definition's last component is participation. This concerns a large variety of forms which are treated in detail in my German companion volume (Frenkel L264b/1302ss). Let us just say at this point that there are different variants of participation. A member state may either participate as a structured political unity through its authorities, or it may appear as an essentially statistical base as is the case with electoral boundaries. It is also necessary to look not only to legal texts but to the political realities of participation, which are sometimes much more important than the texts (e.g. career patterns in political parties etc.). Finally, we must not overlook that there is a relationship between the relatively high degree of autonomy postulated and participation. Both are dependent on and mutually guarantee each other (see Wagner L838/29). To emphasize but the element of autonomy (see Bennett L59/10, Schollenberger L725/170ss) is too narrow. On the other hand, it is difficult to conceive that participation would be of much importance in the long run if it were not based on autonomous political activities in the member states. These, again, presuppose a considerable degree of independence. There is a tendency in modern German theory to give priority to participation to the exclusion of autonomy. This results from an interesting analysis of modern German federalism (Hesse L356/25). However, this analysis is perhaps too narrow (see Hempel L352/200, Tiemann L804/323ss), and the conclusion mentioned is certainly not warranted in a normative sense.

266 Participation has to take place in an ordered and permanent way. This is to say that it must not be at the mercy of the central government. As a rule it will be organized by the constitution (Burckhardt L109/163). It will also happen regularly, i.e. in the ordinary process of decision making, and not as an exception.
267 As tasks are interrelated the central government also participates in the decision making of member states. But this is a by-product. Participation of the centre in member state decision making is not an element of federalism. It may even open the way to the destruction of autonomy. This form of participation is a form of decentralization rather than non-centralization (no.226). Ermacora (L435/87) has postulated the conceptual necessity that member states participate in the governance of the central government and vice versa, but the latter element is very questionable.

268 From the viewpoint of the definition, it is irrelevant whether a federation has been brought into being by an aggregation of formerly separate states or by partial disintegration of a unitary state (compare no.674ss). Fischer (L241/44) prefers to call only the first entity federation. For the second case, he proposes to talk about a federal unitary state (bundesstaatlicher Einheitsstaat). This is neither necessary nor practical. If such a distinction were really to be made it would be more sensible to refer to the level of autonomy and of participation than to the origin of the federation. 269 Usually the member states of a federation have equal rights without regard to their economic or demographic strength (Macmahon L501/9). But there are deviations. We find them in multi-level federations (e.g. USSR and Yugoslavia) and especially in the organization of participation in central decision making (compare L264b/1301ss). The principle of equality is of some political importance but it is not conceptually essential. 270 Whether the member states themselves are federally organized is, again, not conceptually essential. It may even be said that one of the real-type characteristics of member states, which sets them apart from decentralized regions in unitary states, is the ability to change the boundaries and the political structures of local government. According to the classic doctrine as developed in the United States (Dillon's rule L315/123, L371/140; compare L264b/759) local governments are mere tenants at the will of the legislature. Member states may be organized as unitary states. This usually leads to two conclusions. In the first place the central government in theory does not have the power to deal directly with local government (see L632/137s, L782/426,1162s, and especially Frenkel L264b/766ss, 866ss). In the second place, a member state is free in granting autonomy to local government. The first conclusion may be politically sound as a means of bolstering state autonomy and discouraging central circumvention of state governments. But it is wrong to assume that member state autonomy is not compatible with an original, constitutionally acknowledged, right to exist for local government. As to the second conclusion it fails to grasp that this is compatible with federation but hardly compatible with the fact that federations should ideally be an embodiment of the federal principle. This federal principle should be pervasive where its prerequisites are to be found at the local level. Or as the Swiss de Reynold put it (L654/105s): It has been the mistake of our federalists to have always remained at the surface only of federalism, to have confounded federalism

with cantonal sovereignty, to have never been able to apply federalism within the cantons themselves. Where has centralism really started from? Where has tatism begun? In the cantons and even in the communes; contamination and bad examples come from there. Jefferson, too, perhaps the most eminent of early American constitutional thinkers, made local elementary republics, ward democracy the cornerstone of his structure of government (see Arendt L32/249ss).
271 It is not always easy to establish, on the basis of abstract definitions, whether a given state is a federation. Duchacek has therefore proposed ten criteria (he does not weight them) for this purpose. All of them are illustrations of one or other elements of the definition of federation (L180/207): The ten yardsticks of federalism (the first four aim at measuring the reality and 'indestructibility' of the union) that we will now use are: 1: Has the central authority exclusive control over diplomacy and defense as befits a nation-state in its relations with other nations? (Compare the relevant analysis in Frenkel L264b/1553ss.) 2: Is the federal union constitutionally immune against dissolution by secession? 3: Is the exercise of the central authority as it reaches all citizens directly independent of the individual approval and resources of the component units? 4: Who has the ultimate control over amendments to the federal constitution? 5: Are the component units immune to elimination of their identity (antedating or postdating the union) and authority? 6: Is the collective sharing in federal rule making adequately secured by equal representation of unequal units in a bicameral system? What are the constitutional provisions for collective sharing in the executive and judiciary rule implementation? 7: Are there two independent sets of courts, one interpreting and adjudicating the federal laws and the other the state laws? (Again, compare L264b/1066ss.) 8: Is there a judicial authority in the central authority but standing above the central authority and the component units to determine their respective rights? 9: Have the component units retained all the powers that the constitution has not given the central authority? And are these retained powers significant or marginal? 10: Is the territorial division of authority clear and unambiguous?

D.321 The Sovereignty Problem

Contents Index End

272 A federation is a unity composed of several states which continue to exist as sovereign states (Schollenberger L726/4). - It is obvious and uncontradicted by science that now even less than before (under the imperial constitution of 1871) there can be talk about some lnder sovereignty (Anschtz L29/41). - The citizen faces sovereignty in the central government and in the member states together. They are sovereign both together (Bumlin L54/145). - All federalisms, to the extent that they oppose absolute concentration of power at the expense of territorial autonomy (and international organization), are doctrines of anti-sovereignty; but at the same time that they

oppose sovereignty, they ascribe it to themselves, and is precisely the source of the oddity of federal theory (Riley L637/6-3/18).

273 The discussion carried on with much relish and little success (Triepel L812/51) about the locus of sovereignty in federations is one of those debates that are kept alive by the fact that there are divergent views about their starting point and in this case about sovereignty itself. It strictly depends on its definition whether sovereignty is divisible or not and whether it is comprehensive or limited. It is therefore appropriate to arrive at some conceptual clarity about sovereignty and the scientific function of this term (no.274ss) before engaging a discussion about sovereignty and federation. It is my thesis that for the theory of government the concept of sovereignty is no longer functionally necessary and that it is therefore superfluous (no.287). Nevertheless, for the sake of completeness I shall also deal with the federal consequences of various doctrines of sovereignty (no.289ss).

D.3211 Sovereignty

Contents Index End

274 The historical origin of sovereignty is a political idea which was later consolidated as a legal one (Jellinek L382/435).

275 The term sovereignty may be traced back to the medieval Latin superanus or superanitas and the old French souverain: one who takes precedence over others (L626/6). In Pufendorf's works we occasionally find the neologism suverenitas (L638/13*). The history of the concept goes back to antiquity (see L382/436ss). But its modern use is connected with the first real theory of sovereignty put forward in the 16th century by the Frenchman Bodin (L626/8). Hobbes in his Leviathan emphasized its absolutist core even more (L363/43). 276 Throughout the history of sovereignty two elements intertwine: the sovereign as holder of supreme power, and sovereignty as supreme power itself (compare L240/61,76, L626/11s, L644/41s, L825/86s). 277 Sovereignty as supreme power per se is a logical abstraction. It is a concept of legal methodology. Sovereignty in its legal meaning is comprehensive legal power, not delegated and thus supreme. Legal power which is not further deducible corresponds to the idea of the state (compare L109/417, L414/377, L500/272) or of the community of nations (see L413/287, L414/389). Whether it is the state that is

sovereign, or the community of nations, or both, is a problem of legal theory (L413/284ss). In German public law doctrine sovereignty is usually tied in its abstract sense to the state. To be consistent this state must also be taken as an abstraction. (To describe a given state, e.g. Australia, as sovereign would point to its being the holder of supreme power, see below.) 278 This abstract concept of sovereignty was present in the teachings of the early theoreticians. But it took second place to the concept of the holder of supreme power. It had to take second place because the idea of sovereignty evolved as a political weapon, first in the conflict between church and state, and later in the struggle between absolutist monarchy and the estates of the realm. The focus, obviously, was on who was sovereign, who was to hold supreme power.
279 An interesting early abstract definition of sovereignty was given by the seventeenth century English politician Halifax (L329/135): For instance, there can be no government without a Supreme Power; that power is not always in the same hands, it is in different shapes and dresses, but still, wherever it is lodged, it must be unlimited, it hath a jurisdiction over everything else, but it cannot have it above itself. Supreme Power can no more be limited than infinity can be measured, because it ceaseth to be the thing; its very being is dissolved when any bounds can be put to it.

280 For the political conflict, abstract supreme power was of less consequence than its holder. This holder is the sovereign. Thus Hobbes (L363/17): And in him consisteth the Essence of the Common-wealth; which (to define it,) is One Person, of whose Acts a great Multitude, by mutuall Covenants one with another, have made themselves every one the Author, to the end he may use the strength and means of them all, as he shall think expedient, for their Peace and Common Defence. And he that carryeth this Person, is called Soveraigne, and said to have Soveraigne Power; and every one besides, his Subject. Or in the words of Pufendorf (L639/5/4): For one to be sovereign ruler he not only must not have a superior, but all the others must obey him without demur or recourse. This anticipates elements of the concept of sovereignty as put forward by Austin (based on Bentham L644/9), who was probably the legal thinker who had most influence on the development of Anglo-American law. For Austin the sovereign was this person or group of persons who as a rule are obeyed by the majority of the subjects and who as a rule do not have to obey a superior (L579/11, for a further discussion of this concept see Field L240/62ss, Raz L644/6ss). He is sovereign who in a given political community is legitimated to exercise power or who in the final analysis does exercise it (Loewenstein L493/4). 281 I have already intimated (no.278) that the historical bases for the doctrine of sovereignty were the struggles between church and state, absolutism and estates. These conflicts were described in detail by Jellinek (L382/441s). Two aspects proved to be of particular importance: the legitimation of the holder to exercise sovereignty as well as the unity and the unlimitable nature of sovereignty. 282 As to legitimation, medieval theory had the choice of two authorities. It was either possible to attribute imperial or princely dominion to divine will (for the Etrusco-Roman sources see L18/188). Or sovereignty could be based under natural

right on the consent of the ruled (lex regia, Digests 1/4/1, L494/17s), that is on the social compact (no.051ss). It was this second approach which the French and English monarchomachs used in their conflict with absolutist monarchy after the latter's victory over Papal aspirations. Althusius was its prime apologist (compare Denzer L639/195ss, Duverger L186/37, Riley L637/6-3/32). 283 To be useful as a political weapon, sovereignty also had to be conceived as uniform and unlimitable in its exercise. It would not have been expedient for the instrument in this struggle for supremacy to contain restricting elements which might have limited one's own claims. For the same reason that sovereignty is inalienable it is also indivisible (Rousseau L678/2/2). This explains Harrington's (L340/17), Hobbes' (L363/29), Pufendorf's (L638/30*), Rousseau's and other thinkers' aversion to limitation of sovereignty and, especially, to the doctrine of the separation of powers. When the sovereignty of the people triumphed over monarchical sovereignty in the French Revolution, one absolutism was simply replaced by another one (compare Arendt L32/156, Paine L600/69). 284 For further constitutional developments the concept of sovereignty had become dysfunctional. Power was now exercised in the name of the people and no longer in the name of the king. The problem of how to safeguard individual interests against state encroachment remained. This became the new focus for constitutional policy. The absolutist content the concept of sovereignty had assumed during the earlier struggles hindered the breakthrough of liberalism. The dogma of sovereignty's indivisibility was one of the big obstacles to the evolution of the rule of law and constitutional doctrine (Kgi L405/117). The abstract recognition of the sovereignty of the people does in no way augment the sum of individual liberties; and if this sovereignty is given an extent it should not have liberty may be lost despite this principle or even because of this principle (Constant L147/2). The liberal thinkers used two approaches to deal with sovereignty (both having their own traditions). They considered state sovereignty to be limited in its extent. It had to respect an area of individual liberty where even the sovereign majority had no right to intrude. The second course was the theory of the separation of powers. The exercise of sovereignty was to be functionally and personally distributed for the sake of guaranteeing individual liberty. 285 What function has the concept of sovereignty to-day? It is minimal for both constitutional and international law. In both cases it is pointed out that sovereignty in a sociological sense does not exist and has never existed. The omnicompetence of the state or its authorities is considered to be a legal fiction (compare L156a/128s, L373/18, L863/1448). I concur. Nevertheless, this does not dispose of the question whether the concept is in any way necessary for legal purposes. 286 If we look to public international law, we discern the ubiquity of sovereignty. But the term is never used to say something which in other words might not be said with more precision. Wherever it should decide a conflict this concept does not work, because the conflict is usually about matters that are at the same time essential

conceptual elements. The famous controversy about the precedence of state or international law, for instance (see Kelsen L413/384ss, L414/203s,283), cannot be solved by pointing to the sovereignty of the one or other legal order. This would be circular reasoning because the result differs according to the definitions. Nor is it of any scientific value to call states, which are independent under the law of nations, sovereign. If one would deduce from this that non-sovereign states, e.g. member states in federations, have no status in public international law, this would again be circular reasoning using some custom-made definition of sovereignty. To say what it is supposed to say, the term directly under the law of nations is more precise and quite sufficient. And to paraphrase final jurisdiction in a given field, modern international law rightly prefers the concept of competence over sovereignty (L688/6). Sovereignty, because of its history, provokes erroneous associations in a world where final jurisdiction very often lies with international organizations. To sum up, for public international law the concept of sovereignty has become unnecessary if not misleading. 287 For constitutional law our findings are similar. It is true that the concept of sovereignty is less used here. But where it is used -as for instance in the discussion about federations, no.289ss- its usefulness is again limited by the fact that it leads to circular reasoning. Let us take, for instance, the problem of legislative delegation. This is treated differently in the United States on the one side and in the United Kingdom and Australia on the other. In the USA, the legislative power is conceived to be delegated to Congress and thus, under Anglo-American legal theory, there is no way to delegate it further. In the United Kingdom and Australia, it is an original function of parliament which may be delegated. To base these findings on the sovereignty or non-sovereignty of parliament is to ask whether the powers of parliament are to be considered original or derivative. The notion of sovereignty certainly does not add further clarification. When sovereignty was introduced into the system of law it led to conflicts about the very elements which should be universally accepted to make the concept useful. Because the necessary conceptual agreement is not likely to be found, and because such agreement is not necessary since there exist adequate terms to describe whatever sovereignty should stand for, it is advisable to dispense with the latter concept.
288 I fully agree with Portus who says (L626/18): Can we not drop the term altogether from political discussions? The lawyers will not agree to drop it. It is too hallowed by ancient usage. It is embedded in too many documents. Very well. Let us leave it to the lawyers along with 'torts' and 'decrees nisi' and 'mandamus' and 'feme sole'. And let plain people like us stick to the less ambiguous word 'power'. For sovereignty is a concept which has been brought out of its original historical setting, and endued with metaphysical attributes of supremacy to law, irresponsible prerogative, and with almost divine right, to tease and bewilder us moderns with notions of national righteousness, ineffable privilege, and moral omnipotence. Unfortunately, it is unlikely that sovereignty will disappear. Its very ambiguity makes it a near priceless asset for political debate.

D.3212 Sovereignty and Federation

Contents Index End

289 To-day the use of sovereignty as a catchword is restricted mainly to two fields. In international relations it is invoked to ward off foreign interference. This aspect does not concern us here. But sovereignty is also used in dealing with federation and its institutions. 290 With the exception of Canada, the problem of the locus of sover eignty was a topic for political argument in all pre-1900 federations. The states were not readily willing to give up their sovereignty in favour of federation. That is why in the United States the concept of dual sovereignty was invented (L59/195, L96/422). The Swiss federal Constitution explicitly mentioned cantonal sovereignty (article 1). In the North German Union and the German Empire, the literature was unanimous in holding that sovereignty was vested in the totality of the united sovereigns and governments (L106/19ss, for the Weimar discussion see L632/53). In Germany the prestige aspects of the debate were especially evident, because there were monarchs or sovereigns at the head of both the Empire and the Lnder (Schindler L715/9s, L343/61). Another solution than the one arrived at would have been a slight to the prestige of these rulers. (A similar discussion took place in 1849 in Austria, L214/30.) Dual sovereignty was a doctrine near at hand. In 1792 the U.S. Supreme Court declared in Chisholm v. Georgia (L626/12): the United States are sovereign as to all the powers of government actually surrendered. Each State in the Union is sovereign as to all the powers not conferred. And in 1819 the Court restated this theory in McCulloch v. Maryland (L626/12): the powers of sovereignty are divided between the government of the Union and those of the States. They are each sovereign with respect to the objects committed to it, and neither is sovereign with respect to the objects committed to the other. (As to dual sovereignty compare Bluntschli L75/577s, Dubs L179/28, Hamilton L334/32, Tocqueville L806/239s.) 291 Such a doctrine may be justified if sovereignty is taken to mean original powers of governance in a sociological sense . Legal originality is a more delicate question. In particular, the fact that powers may be taken away from a member state even against the latter's will makes legal originality difficult to construe. But the essence of sovereignty is not original power but supreme power. Supreme power is a logical abstraction (no.277). As such it is not divisible. That is why many scholars strongly repudiate the doctrine of dual sovereignty. Thus Kelsen (L415/117): To prove... member states to be sovereign was not easily possible even for a theory fully committed to 'life's realities'. It therefore fell back upon... the grotesque idea to 'divide' sovereignty among central state and member states. This doctrine of dual sovereignty,

too, hardly merits repudiation. Or Giacometti (L244/40): If the Confederation is sovereign, i.e. if it is the supreme government on Swiss territory, it is not logical to ascribe sovereignty to the Cantons, too, because sovereignty as pre-eminence is a concept of relations. 292 If, to pursue this approach, one agrees with the dominant view that sovereignty is an essential element in the definition of the state (although Anschtz L29/39, Jellinek L382/769s, Veiter L829/149 and others differ on this) then Giacometti's opinion necessarily leads to the rejection of the state quality of member states (L244/43). If the Cantons therefore are not states even if they show the essential elements of a territorial government, they can only be intrastate governments, that is to say a certain level of decentralization by self-managing units. In other words they are self-managing units of the Confederation just as the local governments are the self-managing units of the Cantons. The Cantons are the Confederation's local governments.... It is also possible ('because of their qualified functions and autonomies, M.F.') to call them magnified self-managing units (L244/44s). Federation (the Swiss Constitution uses the term confederation), thus, appears as a highly decentralized unitary state (L244/45, also Merkl L435/92). It even seems to appear that a federation in the sense of a state composed of states is conceptually impossible (Giacometti L244/45; as to the rejection of an independent concept of federation see L825/354). 293 This disapprobation of member states' sovereignty and state character corresponds to the so-called monistic theory of federation. A federation is nothing else than a special form of a decentralized unitary state (L435/92, compare L541/299). An illustration is Fleiner's definition of federalism (L782/1028): Federalism is the renunciation of the supreme government to fully enforce its sovereignty as to decision, control, and implementation in favour of the autonomy of territorially circumscribed units. (To-day Fleiner seems to lean towards divided sovereignty, L365/88s.) 294 The dualist doctrine of federation acknowledges the co-existence of the central state and the member states. The theoretical foundations are varied. They may be based on dual sovereignty (no.290), on the recognition of some special legal position as for instance non-sovereign statehood of member states (no.292), or on the attribution of full sovereignty together with functionally divided governance to both central and member states (compare L63/22, L339/23, L435/75, L751/8, L811/72s). 295 The trinomial theory of federation has been expounded most consistently by Kelsen. He starts from indivisible, abstract sovereignty. In federations sovereignty lies with the legal system as a whole (Gesamtrechtsordnung). This consists of two coordinate partial legal systems (Teilrechtsordnungen): central state and member states. If the state is no longer personified but seen to be a legal order, or its personification, then both central state and member states are decentralized legal orders. Thus, based... on a global constitution attributing and delegating functional jurisdictions there are two kinds of partial orders: one partial order with spatial jurisdiction for the whole territory ('partial order' because only competent for specified

fields), and several partial orders with spatial jurisdiction for partial territories. The first partial order is the 'central state', or (in confederations) the union. The others are the member or individual states. If we analyse the relations between these orders we will find that there is no subordination (because there is no delegation) between the central state and the members states. There is rather coordination (L412/135, compare L833/6/57).
296 The trinomial theory of federation had its precursors in Haenel, Max Huber (L557/44) and Austin. Haenel (L435/113): Not the member states, not the central states are states pure and simple, they are but political communities organized and acting in the way of states. The true state is only the federation as the totality of both. Austin (L557/144): the sovereignty of each of the united societies, and also of the larger society arising from the union of all, resides in the united government as forming one aggregate body. 297 The American Calhoun started with a concept of personalized sovereignty. He construed a middle form between the dualist and the trinomial concept of federation by making a distinction between the constituent and the legislative power. Only the former was sovereign to Calhoun, and it was an attribution of the people in the states. The state people, then, delegated it to the states as well as to the federal legislators (L541/279ss).

298 The trinomial theory of federation has been adopted by various scholars (e.g. Harbich L339/85, Loebenstein L487/828, Maunz L525/20/I/5, Monz L554/38), by Mexican constitutional theory (212/94), and for a time also by the German Constitutional Court (L339/38s). Irrespective of the sovereignty question -here one can dispense with this concept- the trinomial theory is best able to construe a consistent legal order in such a way as to recognize satisfactorily the phenomenon of federation with its actual political structure and its states rights' clause (no.240). Critics maintain that the joint state does not exist (Burckhardt L109/162, Grawert L304/68, Huber L782/1159, Koja L435/126, Usteri L825/219). To this we may respond that the central government and the state governments are merely the organs of the joint state. It is true that there is not usually a written joint constitution (the Swiss Constitution of 1815 was such a text, L406/113) but there is a joint legal order which is presupposed by both federal and member state constitutions. (Organized joint state institutions may be found, too, as for instance the Loan Council in Australia and the provisions for changing Lnder frontiers in Austria and for amending the Federal Constitution in Switzerland. But this is not theoretically essential.)
299 Foreign policy also provides a good illustration of trinomial federation. It is neither the central state nor the member states which are direct subjects of international law but the whole or joint state. This joint state is bound by the actions of its organs. These are usually the central state's authorities, but may sometimes be member states' authorities (see L264b/1608ss). The trinomial theory is the approach which can most easily be reconciled with the international law peculiarities of federations. It comes therefore as no surprise that the German Constitutional Court's application of the theory was in the context of the so-called concordate lawsuit when intrastate validity of an international treaty was under litigation. 300 Strictly, trinomial theory is also a monistic doctrine. The legal order is hierarchical (not necessarily with relation to its partial orders, see L264b/883s). Sovereignty as abstract supreme power lies with the joint legal order. (Whether it is only the joint legal order that enjoys state quality may be left unanswered.)

301 The trinomial concept of federation relegates the member states as well as the central state out of supremacy in favour of an encompassing joint state. The dualist (based on non-sovereign units) and the monistic theories, on the other hand, attribute pre-eminence to the central state, and this not only in the sense of legal precedence. It is obvious that an author's preference for one or the other doctrine often runs parallel to his more or less centralizing bias. hlinger (L587/14s) for instance observes with relation to most of to-day's representatives of the so-called pure theory of law that the vehemence with which this thesis (of the decentralized unitary state) is proffered will of necessity antagonize those who... make a qualitative difference between unitary states and federations. On the same level is the constant disqualification of the lnder (member states) as non-states, even if this can only be a nominal definition in the context of pure theory of law. Here indeed a certain... anti-federalist emotion seems to come out (against a similar reproach see Koja L435/66). Again, it is obvious that those who nurture an aversion to centralization will be inclined to construe their concept of federation in such a way as to ascribe to member states sovereignty, autonomy, statehood, or at least no qualitative discrimination (compare Riley L637/6-3/41). Although I am convinced of my own objectivity I am, perhaps, no exception.

D.33 Federation and Confederation

Contents Index End

302 The distinction between federation and confederation has been of scholarly interest mainly in Germany in the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries (Jellinek L382/762). Here and in continental European parlance in general the distinction is still quite well observed, even if a clear-cut scientific differentiation is no longer of much concern for to-day's authors. In Anglo-American theory, the distinction is not considered to be of much importance. The generic term federalism is used where a German or a Frenchman would specifically talk about federation as a form of government. Thus, Duchacek's yardsticks for federalism (no.271) apply to federations only. They would be virtually meaningless in the context of either federalism at large or confederation. However, the difference between confederation or confederacy on the one hand and federation or federal state on the other one is also known (see L863/1375). The corresponding terms in French are confdration and fdration. Until the nineteenth century, both words had been used rather indiscriminately (it is interesting to note that the medieval prefix con once

emphasized unity, thereby reversing modern usage, Voyenne L837/61s). The Swiss federation even to-day is styled Confdration in French and not Fdration (article 1 of the actual Federal Constitution of 1874, Confederazione in Italian; for Canada see L859/23). 303 The essential elements of the differentiation are the legal basis of the union, the relations between central authorities and the citizens, and the status of the member states in international law. 304 A confederation is based on a treaty between independent states. This treaty remains the foundation of the union's activities. Amendments to at least its more important provisions have to be accepted by all the members. The latter have in principle the right to leave the association (the right to secession). A federation's base, on the other hand, is a constitution. This may originally have been arrived at by treaty. But it is something new, a new public will, independent from the treaty makers' will. The constitution may be amended according to its own provisions for revision. The members have in principle no right to secede. The main practical sources of the differentiation are the basic text's amendment procedure and the members' right to secession. 305 However, it is questionable to say that the members of a fed eration have no right to secede and to take this as a major characteristic differentiating a federation from a confederation. Some federations, for example former USSR (article 72 of the Constitution) and Burma under its first Constitution (L180/297) allow the member states - at least in theory - to leave the union. Kelsen (L415/224) considers such a faculty to be fundamentally admissible. Some authors deduce the right to secession from the original treaty base even where it is not mentioned in the Constitution (see, for Austria, Pernthaler L616/134). If, with Bryce (L96/321), we explain the silence of the federal constitution on this matter as being due to the results of a compromise which was not to be burdened with certain delicate questions, then the absence of the right to secession is not a particularly distinctive mark of federation. (As to secession compare Frenkel L264b/732ss.) 306 The amendment procedure is probably a more decisive difference (thus Durand L185/167). But, again, we must not forget that a federation is able to make amendments to its constitution dependent on the agreement of all member states. This was for instance the case in Yugoslavia (article 402 of the Constitution). It makes little sense to describe as a confederation a state which in all other respects is fully integrated, simply because of this one element.
307 Federation differs from confederation in its considerably greater number of central competencies (Kelsen L415/207, also Dubs L179/5). But as it is impossible to state the exact degree of functions necessary to transform confederation into federation, this observation does not yield a criterion for differentiation.

308 The second characteristic mentioned above (no.303) is the central authorities' relations with the citizens. The subjects of a confederation's directions are usually the

member states and not their citizens. To enforce its decisions it has to rely on the member states and not on its own authorities. In federations, central laws and decisions are directly binding on individual citizens. They may be enforced by central authorities. In Tocqueville's words (L806/225): In America, the union has as subjects not states but ordinary citizens. It is true, that this question played a major role in the discussions of the founding fathers of the American Constitution (e.g. Hamilton L334/15s, Morris L232/34). But, again, it is also conceivable that the treaty which establishes a confederation may give its authorities power to deal directly with the citizens (compare Hughes L370/6s). This is increasingly the case in modern, economically oriented confederations. 309 The criterion most used to distinguish between federation and confederation is the international status of the member states. If after union they remain independent states under the law of nations, they form a confederation. A federation exists if there is no such independence or if it is restricted to some specific matters (for details see Frenkel L264b/1574ss). Scholars usually give expression to this distinction by pointing to the sovereignty or non-sovereignty of member states (see L343/44s, L382/767, L542/72). But as has been shown above (no.290ss), it is neither necessary nor expedient to refer to sovereignty in this context. Nevertheless, the international law status of member states is probably the most suitable test for differentiating between the two types of association of states (it is also the basis of the definitions given here, nos.247 and 254), notwithstanding the fact that formally two of the USSR's republics (the Ukraine and Byelorussia, L771a/7s) are treated by the United Nations and some other transnational organizations as full and direct participants in international relations. It has to be acknowledged that this criterion also is not unambiguous. It comes close to circular reasoning because the distinction between a federation and a confederation is of some practical importance in determining international law status.
310 To use the internal or international law character of legal relations between the member states as the basis for the distinction (thus Wildhaber L862/256) is, in the final analysis, also a reference to the law of nations.

311 Whether we are dealing with a confederation or with a federation is usually not very difficult to decide in real life. Despite a common view to the contrary (e.g. L277/52), the concepts are difficult to distinguish only in theory. In reality an association is clearly one regime or the other. The distinction is more clear-cut than the one between a federation and a unitary state (compare Burckhardt L109/154, Hughes L370/6). A difficulty arises only in connection with the consolidation of certain transnational organizations (no.286). And it is precisely in this case that we must question the value of a sharp theoretical distinction based on the accidents of a specific historical evolution.

D.34 A Bevy of Federalisms

Contents Index End

312 Federalism is a widely used term. As long as we are concerned only with structural and general questions, its meaning is more or less clear. But, as is the case with all concepts which contain an element of judgment, it is sometimes difficult to ascribe a meaning to borderline cases. In such instances it is customary to use epithets. With federalism, likewise, this is usual. Unfortunately, however, these hyphenated or qualified federalisms have not led to greater clarity (thus Landau L449/176). On the contrary, they have multiplied borderline cases. Sometimes linguistic usage is further complicated by including in the definition some goal or criticism ascribed to federalism. Such differentiations usually take the form of adjectives or of some other addition. They do not really inform us about the matter at hand - creativity, cooperation, rigidity, competition, etc. may be found everywhere - but indicate an author's basic opinion of his subject. Co-operative federalists for instance have little regard for federalism that is old-style and dual. There is a danger that emotionally attractive adjectives may be used to confer pseudo-objectivity on a political programme. Co-operation under some conditions is equivalent to collusion and may be detrimental to the aggregate welfare of the persons involved. The choice of valueladen words should not be used to prejudge findings and conclusions (Ostrom L594/17). 313 Practically every text on federalism contains hyphenated or qualified federalisms. I have amused myself collecting them, and so far have found some 460 (compare Davis L158/204ss, Frenkel L255/725ss). The following list is by no means complete, notwithstanding its impressive length. It would be easy to extend it at will by self-made terms and catchwords taken from the daily press (rate federalism, censorship federalism, witch federalism, etc.).
314 A comprehensive list has been compiled by Stewart (L637/12-2/5ss). He divides his 326 federalisms into twelve categories. Although the source and the explanation are only given for a few of them (this was not the author's aim) I have included in my own list those of Stewart's terms I was not familiar with.

315 After presenting this catalogue of federalisms, I shall analyse in some detail the co-operative and creative varieties. These concepts nowadays dominate the market of hyphenated federalisms. Unlike most of the others, they are more than mere curiosities.

D.341 The Alphabet of Federalisms

Contents Index End

316 Federalism -la-carte: confederational character, restricted to certain areas (Baudoin L56/13) Abstract f.: purely analytic justification (Duclos L183/173s) Achaean f.: (L637/12-2/23) Active f.: ready for co-operation (Tschni L578/1965/254) Adaptive f.: title of a discussion of criteria for the allocation of functions in federations (L13) Adjectival f.: see hyphenated f. (Stewart L637/12-2/9) Administrative f.: see executive f.; term for f. of execution (L289/171, L423/56); contractually based (Wiltshire L864); role of administrations in German f. (Ellwein L209/232); unilateral change of state boundaries by the central government (Kis L422/127); a special form of federal management of assistance relationships (Newton L873a/218ss) Africanized f.: (L637/12-2/23) F. by aggregation: (L637/12-2/23) Althusian f.: (L637/12-2/23) American f.: republican federation (Diamond L169/134) Amphictyonic f.: close union of social units (Sidjanski L748/preface) Amplified f.: inclusion of cities into the system (Martin L513/171,173) Analogical f.: see hyphenated f. (Stewart L637/12-2/10) Anarchical, anarchist f.: Proudhon's f. based on the autonomy of the smallest possible units (L48a/14s, L172/2450, L637/12-2/23) Antagonistic f.: (L637/12-2/21) Anti-vacuum f.: national priorities are enforced by national intervention because the states deliberately remain inactive (Shuman L746/12) Antiquated f.: (L637/12-2/24) Areal f.: related to subject matters (Reeves/Glendening L647/135) Aristocratic f.: pre-revolutionary France, especially before the Fronde movement (Voyenne L837/165s) Articulated f.: see hyphenated f. (Stewart L637/12-2/10) Asymmetrical f.: a federation composed of clearly distinguishable member units (Tarlton L173/16, L797/83); a form of association of states other than confederation

and federation, as for instance Switzerland/Liechtenstein (Stevens L637/7-4/177ss) Authentic f.: confederation (L169/135s); USSR f. (L422/77) 317 Balanced f.: financially balanced system (L789/966); pluralist distribution of power (L141/9); the antithesis of hegemonial f. (Harbich L339/152) Bamboo fence f.: (L637/12-2/21) Bargaining f.: political bargaining between levels of government about public services (Rosenthal L672/10, Fras L272/61s) Biblical f.: (L637/12-2/23) Blue-Light f.: (L637/12-2/24) Boston f.: (L637/12-2/23) Bourgeois f.: non-marxist f. in Soviet perspective (L422/77) Buber's f.: (L637/12-2/23) Bureaucratic f.: administrative co-operation without political control (L46/28) 318 Calhounian f.: see no.297 (L637/12-2/23) Capitalistic f.: (L637/12-2/23) Categorical f.: (L637/12-2/22) Centralized f.: opposite of peripheral f. (Dikshit L173/231, Riker L660/5, L449/178) Centralist f.: its end is maximum integration (King L419a/24ss) Centralized f.: (L637/12-2/23) Centralizing f.: (L637/12-2/23) Centrifugal f.: aims for greater independence (Ermacora L214/22s) Centripetal f.: aims for greater unity, e.g. in Europe (Ermacora L214/22); corresponds to creative f. (Desmond L746/12) Channelled f.: see focused f. (Wright L872/5) City f.: (L637/12-2/22) Civil f.: relations between citizens (Saint-Just L690/144) Classical f.: (L158/204) Cliental f.: (L637/12-2/22) Club f.: (L637/12-2/22) Coerced f.: (L637/12-2/21) Coercive f.: central direction (Cranston L153/ 128, Else-Mitchell L210/109, L519/xx,xxiv) Coinage f.: Austrian pre-modern standards of coinage (Informationsblatt des Institutes fr Fderalismusforschung 1/84) Collective f.: see communitarian f. (Djordjevi? L175/4) Colonial f.: as set up by European colonial powers, e.g. Afrique Occidentale Franaise (AOF), Afrique Equatoriale Franaise (AEF, Neuberger L205b/171) Combined f.: see expanded f. (Djordjevi? L176/11) Commercial f.: (L637/12-2/22) Commonwealth f.: (L637/12-2/22) Communal f.: Yugoslav f. (Dunn L637/12-2/19) Communitarian f.: based on national and cultural pluralism (Djordjevi? L176/4); cooperative f. (Esterbauer L221/28) Community defining f.: communal boundary redefinition through state or federal

help/intervention (Hart L342/155s) Compact f.: self-co-ordination (Schneider L721/30) Comparative f.: scientific discipline Compartmental f.: separation of levels of government (Sharp L535/287) Competitive f.: emphasis on its competitive function (L594/17); mutual animosity and distrust amongst levels of government (Gordon L637/4-1/45); economic acceptance of f. as a system of competing public corporations (Frey L271/2s) Complete f.: (L637/12-2/23) Compromise f.: see unachieved f. (Djordjevi? L176/10) F. by compulsion: (L637/12-2/21) Concentrated f.: (L637/12-2/23) Confederalism: (L637/12-2/23) F. via confederation: (L637/12-2/23) Confederational f.: see external f. Confrontational f.: Canada 1968-1972, lack of intergovernmental co-operation (McWhinney L534/1) Congregational f.: (L637/12-2/22) Congressional f.: synonymous word for dysfunctional f. (Walker L842/57) Consensual f.: (L637/12/2) Conservative f.: see defensive f. (Bieri L68/89) Constitutional f.: opposite of bureaucratic f. (L46/28); based on constitutional allocation of responsibilities (Duchacek L182/132) Constructive f.: method of motivating Cantons to conclude compacts (Stranner Basler Zeitung 12.5.1982) Consultative f.: (L637/12-2/21) Consumer f.: (L637/12-2/22) Contemporary f.: (L637/12-2/24) Continental f.: (L637/12-2/22) Contract f.: (Duclos L183/188, L449/173, Price L645/23) Contractual creative f.: (L637/12-2/22) Conventional f.: see old-style f. (Reagan L646/3) Co-operative f.: see no.346ss Co-optative f.: (L637/12-2/21) Co-ordinate f.: opposite of co-operative f. (Mathews L521/2s) Co-ordinated f.: see co-operative f. (Inns L388/39); also opposite of co-operative f. (Sawer L698/30); reorganization of federal relations and responsibilities (Schwartz L735/55) Co-ordinative f.: co-operation and shared responsibility (Mathews L519/xx, L153/121, L864/x) Corporate f.: (L158/204, L637/12-2/22) Corporatist f.: based on organized (e.g. professional) interest groups (Brugmans L94/62, L545/123); voluntary union of nationalities as in Estonia after World War I (Friedrich L275/3) Cosmopolitan f.: (L637/12-2/22) Counterfeit f.: (L637/12-2/24) Creative f.: see no.354ss

Creeping f.: grants to promote federal programmes in member states (L162/24, 84) Criminal-justice f.: (L637/12-2/22) Cultural f.: pluricultural co-operation (Lang L451/341); another name for the fellowship of man in America (Boorstin L79/60); see nationality f. (L422/37s) 319 Dead f.: (L637/12-2/24) Decadent f.: (L637/12-2/24) Decentralist f.: the emphasis is on the regime's national character with new forms of decentralization (Diamond L169/136); emphasis on the autonomy of smaller units (King L419a/39ss) F. by decentralization: (L637/12-2/23) Decentralized f.: see competitive f. (L271/2s.); also L449/178 Decentralized administrative f.: Swiss form of co-operative f. (Veiter L829/195) Defensive f.: no consensus on national goals (Bieri L68/89); defence of state autonomy (Siegrist L751/138) Degenerate f.: see particularist f. (Lang L451/34) Delegational f.: the member states' autonomy is based on central delegation (L271/3) Democratic f.: (L637/12-2/23) Destructive f.: (L637/12-2/21) Developing f.: (L637/12-2/23) F. by devolution: (L637/12-2/23) Dictatorial f.: (l637/12-2/23) Diplomatic f.: confederation (Duclos L183/186, L184/43) Direct f.: central programmes do not provide an option for the member states to join or not to join (Macmahon L501/109); direct central government - local government relations (Reagan L646/171) F. of divided responsibility: see dual f. (Halstenberg L106/139) Division of power f.: programmatical opposite to co-operative f. (L221/28) Documentary f.: (L637/12-2/23) Domestic f.: (L637/12-2/22) Dominant f.: (L637/12-2/21) Double f.: see dual f. (Scheuner L194/42) Drawing-board f.: technocratic aspects of German and other territorial reforms (Frenkel Vaterland 28.7.1979) Dual f.: strict separation of tasks and competition between central and state governments (Ehringhaus L194/42, L449/178); emphasis on separation of tasks and mutual independence (Elazar L198/20, L162/30) Dualist f.: see no.294 Dynamic f.: (L449/173, L637/12-2/21), no.345 Dynastic f.: historical phase of German f. (Dennewitz L161/24) Dysfunctional f.: resulting from centralist and conservative trends in the United States (Walker L842/53) 320 Ecclesiastical Economically Ecumenical optimal f.: f.: f.: (Theiler (L637/12-2/22) L799/101s) (L637/12-2/22)

Effective f.: efficient (L637/12-2/16) Eighteenth-century f.: (L637/12-2/24) Emergent f.: (L637/12-2/23) Entranced f.: (Krger L833/21/105) Entrenched f.: f. with old social roots (Haqqi L338/11) Epistomological f.: (L637/12-2/24) Equal f.: (L637/12-2/23) Equilibrated f.: see balanced f. (Lerche L339/152) Essex f.: (L637/12-2/24) Ethical f.: emphasis on standards of proper conduct (L637/12-2/14) Ethnic f.: ethnic factors as the basic determinant (Esterbauer L205b/146s, Hraud L220/75s) Ethno-territorial f. (integral or partial): correspondence of language to territory (Duchacek L637/7-4/15) Euro-African F.: quasi-federal links, i.e. French Union of the Fourth Republic, French Communaut of Gaullist France (Neuberger L205b/171) Evolving f.: see amplified f. (Martin L513/40) Execution f.: increasing burden put on the Swiss Cantons by their execution of federal legislation (L288), no.647 Executive f.: emphasis on negotiations between the different levels' executives and administrations (L753/5, Smiley L757/330, L758/17, L136/101s) Executive-legislative f.: central legislation, member state execution and judiciary (Merkl L180/270) Expanded f.: association of a state with a federation (Djordjevi? L176/11); see amplified f. Expansive f.: (L637/12-2/23) Experimental f.: experimental evolution of international relations (Portus L626/19) External f.: confederational f. (Duclos L183/186, Merle L540/5,11) Extralegal f.: (L637/12-2/23) Extreme f.: extensive non-centralization (Kock L430/37) 321 Faade f.: (L637/12-2/24) Failed f.: (L637/12-2/24) Federating f.: (L627/10) Federational f.: by contrast with regionalism, member states participate in sovereignty (Esterbauer L221/22) Feudal f.: stresses degree of autonomy of programme specialists and programmes (Wright L637/12-2/16) Feudal-functional f.: see picket-fence f. (L871/24) F. as fiction: (L637/12-2/24) Figurative f.: see hyphenated f. (Stewart L637/12-2/7) Financial f.: (L637/12-2/22) First New f.: Jane Perry Clark's introduction of the term New f. (Wright/White L873a/1, compare no.341) Fiscal f.: multilevel decentralization in economic theory of f. (Beer L58/22, Bieri L68/1, Musgrave L566/614, Oates L585/4)

Flowering f.: (L637/12-2/21) Focused f.: US grants system 1945-1960 (Wright L872/5) Formal f.: f. of territorial units as distinct from economic interests (Miller L548/8); f. as a form of government (Reagan/Sanzone L646/170) Fourth New f.: President Reagan's attempt at restoration of theconstitutional role of state and local government (Wright/White L873a/22ss) Fragmented f.: see picket-fence f. (Wright L872/5) Free f.: (L637/12-2/22) Full f.: (L637/12-2/23) Functional f.: pluralism (von der Gablentz L843/11, Miller L548/1, L116/14, L180/51); vertical functional interlacing (Beer L58/31); the central government decides on the volume of expenditures, the member states decide on their expenditure priorities (Hanusch L36/108s) Functioning f.: more than just formal (Dikshit L173/24) Fused f.: opposite of dual f. (Morstein-Marx L194/42, L158/204) Fused-foliated f.: U.S. f. 1958-1968 based on federal planning and grants (Wright L872/5) 322 Generic f.: large in contrast to old-fashioned f. (Dexter L167/6s) Genuine f.: (L637/12-2/23) Geographical f.: territorially circumscribed f. (L116/14) Good f.: (L637/12-2/22) Governmental f.: (L637/12-2/23) Group f.: (L637/12-2/22) Guild f.: (L637/12-2/22) 323 Hamiltonian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Hand-in-hand f.: interdependent responsibilities, e.g. shared tasks (Bundesblatt der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft 1971 volume II/1018) Hegemonial f.: one member state, e.g. Prussia, is strong enough to determine union policy (Dennewitz L161/24, L339/152) Hierarchical f.: contrast to co-operative f. (Ermacora L214/193) High f.: (L637/12-2/24) Higher f.: (L637/12-2/23) Historical f.: (L637/12-2/23) Horizontal f.: federal Umbrella for several African colonies and protectorates (e.g. Afrique Occidentale Franaise, Afrique Equatoriale Franaise, Neuberger L205b/171), intergovernmental co-operation (Starr L368/26) Hybrid f.: composite structure (L637/12-2/14) Hyphenated f.: f. with epithet (Landau L449/176) 324 Ideal f.: (L637/12-2/23) Ideological f.: based on opportunism not on history (Lenin L422/76) Imperfect f.: (L158/204) Imperial f.: (L637/12-2/23) Implicit f.: highly decentralized unitary constitution (Young L481/193)

Imposed f.: stage of German history (Dennewitz L161/24,52) Improper f.: (L637/12-2/24) Impure f.: (L637/12-2/24) F. in a broad sense: classification F. in a narrow sense: classification Incipient f.: (L158/204) Income f.: (L637/12-2/22) Industrial f.: (L637/12-2/22) Instituted f.: federation, confederation (Duclos L183/75) Institutional f.: see organic f. (Scelle L700/13) Instrumental f.: (L637/12-2/22) Integral f.: general principle of organization based on personalism (Kinsky L220/43ss, L420/26s, L695a/8) Integrated f.: see organic f. (Dikshit L173/9, L449/178) Integrative f.: (L637/12-2/23) Intercantonal f.: regional co-operation in Switzerland (Schumann L730/271) Intercommunal f.: commune based European union (Duclos L183/147) Interdependent f.: mutual interdependence of levels of government (L158/204, L255/727) F. of interests: excessive representation of special interests (Stadler L782/1033) Interlocked f.: see co-operative f. (L180/318) Internal f.: contrast to external f. (Merle L540/12); federation (Duclos L183/77) International f.: proposed European peace treaties, e.g. those of Kant and of St.Pierre (Riley L637/6-3/18); international collaboration in functionally defined areas (Friedrich L275/7); confederation (Duclos L183/77) International law f.: (Dennewitz L161/24) Interregional f.: co-operation of European regions (Duclos L183/147) Interstate f.: confederation (Burdeau L810/2, Duclos L183/77) Intertwined f.: see co-operative f. (L180/318) Intolerant f.: (L637/12-2/22) Intrastate f.: federation (Burdeau L810/2, Duclos L183/77) 325 Jeffersonian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Joint f.: (L637/12-2/23) Judicial f.: the American system of parallel state and federal judiciaries (Winkle L868/68) Juridical f.: (L637/12-2/22) 326 Kant's Kingly f.: (L637/12-2/23) f.: (L637/12-2/23)

327 Late f.: largely achieved integration (Zeh L708/138) Latin American f.: (L637/12-2/23) Layer-cake f.: emphasis on the separation of levels of government (McLean L637/122/9s, L872/5, compare no.246) Legal f.: see normative f. (Scelle L700/13); legally constituted f. (Saint-Just

L690/144) Liberal f.: (L172/2450) Limited f.: (L637/12-2/24) Limited dual f.: U.S.: the Taney Court's construction of the commerce clause (L8/47s) Lip-service f.: (L637/12-2/24) Little f.: (L637/12-2/24) Local f.: (L637/12-2/22) Locational f.: concept based on locale (L637/12-2/10) 328 Macro-f.: centre/state relations (Elazar L202/19) Marblecake f.: see no.246, emphasis on merged functions (Grodzins L310/3s, McLean L637/12-2/9s, L873a/2) Mk.1 (etc.) f.: ironical technical analogy to describe stages of American evolution (Davis L158/74ss) Marketplace f.: (no.516ss, L637/12-2/21) Marshallian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Maryland f.: (L637/12-2/23) Matrix f.: (L637/12-2/22) Mature f.: (L449/173) Maximal f.: (L637/12-2/24) Medieval corporative f.: (L637/12-2/24) Medievalist, medieval f.: corporative and regional basis (Riley L637/6-3/18, L637/122/24) Medievalist-constitutionalist f.: (L637/12-2/24) Mercantile f.: (L637/12-2/22) Metaphorical f.: see hyphenated f. (Stewart L637/12-2/7) Methodological f.: (L637/12-2/24) Metropolitan f.: (L637/12-2/22) Micro-f.: city/region relations (Elazar L202/19) Military f.: (L158/204, L637/12-2/22) Minimal f.: (L637/12-2/24) Modern f.: see co-operative f. (Hicks L358/18, Riley L637/6-3/18) and U.S. f. Monarchical f.: (L158/204) Monistic f.: increasing centralization (McWhinney L533/16s, L457/63s); see no.293 Monoethnic f.: (L637/12-2/22) Montesquieuan f.: (L637/12-2/23) Multi-dimensional f.: not restricted to internal state and national relations (Djordjevi? L175/7) Multilevel f.: more than the usual three levels of government, e.g. USSR (Duchacek L181/35) Multinational f.: (L637/12-2/22) Mutual f.: based on reciprocity (L637/12-2/16) Mutual interest f.: (L637/12-2/22)

329 Naive f.: clear constitutional allocation of responsibilities (Kock L430/52) Naked f.: un-hyphenated f. (no.349) Narrow-minded f.: egotistic f. (Frenkel L260/337) Nation-centred f.: tracing back the U.S. Constitution to popular and not to state will (Haskell L12/2s) National f.: functional expansion of grants (Clark L375/9, L449/178); opposite to dual f. (Nwabueze L583a/42) Nationality f.: Austro-Marxist non-territorial f. (L422/37s) Nationality-territorial f.: the Soviet Union (Tchistyakov L422/77s) Necessary f.: human rights are enforced independently of the member states' will (Shuman L746/12) Negative f.: against limiting member state autonomy (L165/293) Neighborhood f.: (L637/12-2/22) Neo-f.: claims more influence, more self-co-ordination, and more federal grants at the same time (Siegrist L782/572) New f.: see no.339ss New England f.: (L637/12-2/23) New-modelled f.: (L637/12-2/24) New new f.: (L449/173) New-style f.: (L637/12-2/24) New urban f.: (L637/12-2/22) Newest of new federalisms: focuses on large cities (Sharkansky L744/1) Nigerian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Nineteenth century f.: opposite to co-operative f. (Sawer L698/30) Nixonian new f.: see no.342 (L637/12-2/23) Nominal f.: (L637/12-2/24) Noncentralized f.: see no.226 (L637/12-2/23) Non-ethnic f.: units are not ethnic groups (Hraud L220/75) Non-federalism: (L637/12-2/24) Non-territorial f.: segmented political autonomy (L481/43) Normative f.: f. as differentiation of the legal order (Scelle L700/13) Not-full f.: (L637/12-2/24) Novanglian f.: (L637/12-2/23) 330 Old f.: (L637/12-2/24) Old-fashioned f.: emphasis on constitutional equality of the member states (Dexter L167/6s) Old-line f.: (L637/12-2/24) Old-style f.: clear division of responsibilities and mutual independence of central and state governments (Mathews L519/xx, Reagan L646/170) Old urban f.: (L637/12-2/22) Oligarchic f.: (L158/204) One-dimensional f.: restricted to territorialism (Djordjevi? L175/3) Ontological f.: (L637/12-2/24) Operational f.: emphasis on service character (Ostrom L591/1) Operative f.: functioning f. (Wildavsky L861/95)

Optimal f.: balancing constitutional acceptability and stabilization efficiency (Kock L430/98); optimal territorial organization of supply and demand (Pawlowsky L607/133) Organic f.: central direction and guaranteed autonomy (Sawer L173/9); see communitarian f. (Djordjevi? L176/4); f. as governmental differentiation (Scelle L700/13); naturally evolved sharing of responsibilities (Wiltshire L866/74) Organizational f.: harbouring elements of disintegration and secession (Stalin L766/71,80) Orthodox f.: (L158/204, L637/12-2/23) 331 Pacific f.: (L637/12-2/22) Pan-f.: pervasive (L637/12-2/14) Pan-African f.: (L637/12-2/23) Partial f.: (L158/204) Participatory f.: see polyvalent f. (L175/1) Particularist f.: emphasis on divisive aspects (Dennewitz L161/101, Lang L451/34, L91/393) Partnership f.: see marblecake f. (L637/6-4/164) Paternalist f.: critical of Canadian central government role (Newfoundland speech from the throne 12.7.1979) Perfect f.: (L158/204) Peripheral, peripheralized f.: confederational f. (Dikshit L173/231, Neal L573/3, Riker L660/5) Permissive f.: member state autonomy depends on the central government's concession (Reagan L646/157ss, L449/173) Personalist f.: see integral f. (L637/12-2/22) Petrified f.: creation of states in Germany (Frantz L632/157) Philosophical f.: based on an objective a priori (Laforet L448/39s) Picket-fence f.: U.S. governors have no control over federal grants and thus are mere bystanders (Wright L871/24); interests aim to overcome federal/state compartmentalization (L46/28); disinclination to co-operate (Tschni L578/1965/254) Piecemeal f.: (L637/12-2/21) Pinwheel f.: (L637/12-2/21) Pluralist f.: centrifugal tendencies (McWhinney L533/17, L534/1) Pluridimensional f.: see polyvalent f. (Djordjevi? L176/24) Polar f.: the Federalist's f. based on complementary institutions (Eulau L226/102) Polis f.: see small republic f. (L169/136) Political f.: federation (Duclos L183/186, L184/43, Lang L451/341, Mogi L550/1112); f. as a form of government (Saint-Just L690/144) Political-constitutional f.: (Laufer L456/24) Poly-ethnic f.: several ethnic groups as basis for federation (Duchacek L181/35) Poly-national/poly-ethnic f.: USSR (Kis L422/64) Polyvalent f.: social, functional and participatory f. (Djordjevi? L175/1, L176/24) Positive f.: renaissance of local self-administration (L165/293) Postf.: (L637/12-2/24)

Post-Civil War f.: (L637/12-2/24) Post-colonial f.: African federations after the colonial period (Neuberger L205b/172ss) Postmodern f.: (L637/12-2/24) Posttechnocratic f.: turning away from large entities (Elazar L201/239) Practical f.: (L637/12-2/22) Pragmatic f.: ad hoc redistribution of responsibilities (L8/2, Reeves-Glendening L647/136) Preceptive f.: textbook f. (Fras L272/62) Premodern f.: (L637/12-2/24) Primitive f.: (L637/12-2/24) Private f.: see contract f. (Reagan L646/171) Processual f.: (L637/12-2/22) Procrustean f.: U.S. structural intervention (Nathan L569/125, compare L264b/866ss) Professional f.: see co-operative f. (Aubert L37/402) Professionalized f.: see technocratic f. (Beer L57/80) Professorial f.: (L637/12-2/22) Proletarian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Proliferated f.: see fused-foliated f. (L872/5) Proper f.: (L637/12-2/23) Proprietary f.: (L637/12-2/22) Protean f.: (L637/12-2/21) Protof.: (L637/12-2/24) Proudhonian f.: see integral f. (Kinsky L420/7) Provincial f.: (L637/12-2/22) Pseudo-f.: evaluation of co-operative f. (Aubert L37/402) Public f.: (L637/12-2/22) Pure f.: (L637/12-2/23) Purported f.: (L637/12-2/24) 332 Quasi-f.: lack of a conceptually essential element (Wagner L838/29, Wheare L858/20); not political-constitutional (Laufer L456/24) 333 Racial f.: (L637/12-2/22) Rainbow cake f.: see marblecake f. (L637/12-2/10) Real f.: real differences of member units (Saint-Just L690/144) Realtype-actual f.: (Theiler L799/117) Reformed f.: (L637/12-2/24) Regional f.: territorial element (Walper L843/11); interprovincial co-operation (Fras L272/26) Regiopolitical f.: (L637/12-2/22) Religious f.: (L637/12-2/22) Renewed f.: the Canadian Trudeau government's 1978 constitutional reform proposals (L797/84s) Reoriented f.: see community defining f. (Hart L342/153) Representational f.: (Eulau L225/153, L226/91)

Republican f.: (L637/12-2/23) Respectable f.: (L637/12-2/22) Responsive f.: (L637/12-2/22) Restrictive f.: (L637/12-2/22) Restructured f.: the Canadian Pepin/Robarts constitutional reform proposals (L136/85ss, L796/81ss) Resurgent f.: (L637/12-2/24) Revised f.: (L637/12-2/24) Revolutionary f.: Marc's integral f. (L507/7) Rigid f.: (L637/12-2/22) 334 Second New f.: the 1960s f. (Wright/White L873a/6ss, no.347) Scientific f.: self-assessment of Soviet f. (L422/77) Self-managing f.: Yugoslav f. (Djordjevi? L176/47) Semi-f.: unitary state with federal institutions, e.g. Belgium (Lijphart L481/97) Separative, separatist f.: mutual compartmentalization, no co-operation (Kubel L165/276, Patzig L389/146, L637/12-2/22) Service f.: (L637/12-2/22) Sham f.: (L637/12-2/24) Shape f.: (L637/12-2/22) Shared, sharing f.: see co-operative f. (L158/201, L180/318) Small-city f.: (L637/12-2/22) Small republicf.: ancient city state confederations, authentic f. (Diamond L169/136) Social f.: (L158/204, L175/1) Socialist f.: USSR, Yugoslavia, Czechoslovakia (Djordjevi? L176/18); USSR Constitution article 70/1 Socio-cultural f.: as a contrast to political f. (Khan L418/1, Livingston L637/12-2/19) Sociological f.: see non-territorial f. (L481/98s) Southern f.: (L637/12-2/23) Soviet f.: (L637/12-2/23) Spaghetti f.: (L637/12-2/21) Stable f.: (l545/122) Stalwart f.: (L637/12-2/22) State f.: (L637/12-2/23) State-centered f.: (L637/12-2/23) State-emancipated f.: political f. not based on a nation state (Duclos L183/183) State-oriented f.: the U.S. Constitution is considered to be based on a treaty of the member states (Haskell L12/2) States' rights f.: (L637/12-2/23) Strict f.: narrow construction of federal responsibilities (Brady L535/409s) Student f.: (L637/12-2/22) F. sui generis: analytical classification of the USSR (Kis L422/1) Supple f.: emphasis on flexibility (Clark Devoir 30.12.1977) Supranational f.: (L637/12-2/23, Samsinger L695a/9) Symbolic f.: emotional, symbolic rather than rational-constitutional foundation, e.g. Austria (Gerlich L775/214)

Symmetrical f.: federation comprising completely homogeneous units (Tarlton L173/15s) 335 Technocratic f.:centralizing influence of the increasing professionalization of the public sector, intergovernmental collaboration (Beer L57/79s) Technological f.: (L637/12-2/22) Territorial f.: as a contrast to social f. (Haqqi L338/11) Theological f.: (L637/12-2/24) Third New f.: President Nixon's new f. (Wright/White L873a/10s, no.343) Three-way f.: see two-way f. (L513/109) Tie-wig f.: (L637/12-2/24) Total f.: (L158/204) Totalitarian f.: (L637/12-2/23) Town f.: (L637/12-2/23) Trade union f.: (L637/12-2/22) Traditional f.: vertical separation of powers (Bastien L52/47) Transnational f.: (L637/12-2/23) Tribal f.: German historical stage (Dennewitz L161/24) Trinomial f.: see no.295ss Tripartite f.: (L637/12-2/23) True f.: emphasis on non-centralization as against decentralization (Elazar L198/xii); secured existence of member states (Haqqi L338/61) Twentieth century f.: (Sharp L535/287) Twin-stream f.: (L637/12-2/21) Two-level f.: (L637/12-2/22) Two-sided f.: see dual f. (Brecht L194/42) Two-tiered f.: consisting of primary federations (AOF and AEF, see colonial f.) within the secondary federal French Union (Neuberger L205b/171s) Two-way f.: without inclusion of the local government level (Martin L513/109) 336 Ultra-f.: particularist f. (Lang L451/34) Unachieved f.: Commonwealth, Australia, Canada (Djordjevi? L176/10) Unco-operative f.: the central government acts only if required to do so by the constitution (Shuman L746/12, differing: Belknap L637/12-2/25ss) Uncreative f.: (L637/12-2/22) Undeclared f.: Belgian evolution (Lorwin L492/146) Unifying f.: (L637/12-2/22) Unitary f.: see delegational f. (Frey L271/3) Unstable f.: status and existence of the member states are at the mercy of central government (Barschel L49a/37, Thoma L304/158); outmanoeuvring the separation principle through co-operation (Grawert L304/158) Unworkable f.: ironical assessment of criticisms of the actual system (Ostrom L594/7) Urban f.: urban studies in a federal context (Mathews L522) Utopian f.: (L637/12-2/23)

337 Vertical f.: Viable Village f.: (L637/12-2/23)

see f.:

Euro-African f. (L637/12-2/22)

338 Water taps f.: see focused f. (Wright L872/5) Welfare co-operative f.: (L637/12-2/22) F. without Washington (Canberra etc.): emphasis on member state autonomy (Ehringhaus L194/96, Prybutok L637/12-2/79) Working f.: justification of intergovernmental structures (Gregg L305/77) World f.: (L637/12-2/23)

D.342 New, Co-operative, and Creative Federalisms

D.3421 New Federalism

Contents Index End

339 Every federal system is dynamic. The balance between centre and units, once achieved, does not remain static. It has to adapt itself continuously to new circumstances. The conceptual elements essential for federalism -autonomy and participation- remain, but their contents change. A new federalism emerges which in turn will again be supplanted by a newer one.
340 Thus directly after the foundation of the federation in 1848 the Swiss Baumgartner (L53/vi) wrote about this new federalism to distinguish it from the old confederation.

341 As a concept with programme or technical contents, new fed eralism plays a major role especially in the United States, where hyphenated federalisms abound anyway. At the beginning of the twentieth century new federalism stood for a judicial doctrine that arose out of the fact that there were certain functional areas where neither federal nor state governments were able to be active because some part of the necessary competences always belonged to the partner's jurisdiction. The courts handled this situation using two complementary approaches. They assumed tacit state acceptance of the relevant federal legislation. And they upheld federal laws removing federal legal obstacles to make way for state action. Federal legislation, for instance,

made it possible for the states to prohibit the sale of lottery tickets although such sales enjoyed the protection of the Federal Constitution's interstate commerce clause (188 USS 221, 1903, cited in Strong L787/507s,513, compare Clark L133/539ss, Wright/White L873a/1s). 342 This use of the adjective new was never very widespread. It is only in connection with co-operative federalism that we hear the term often in the United States, mostly as a synonym (see Martin L513/37, L789/970). With Nixon's presidency (L516/6s) the term came to be used as a special form of co-operative federalism, emphasizing the states' and local governments' role. In an Address to the Nation Nixon called it (8.8.1969, L302/41): A co-operative venture among governments at all levels... in which power, funds, and authority are channeled increasingly to those governments which are closest to the people. Nathan, one of the architects of Nixon's new federalism programmes, considered its main characteristics to be decentralization, the use of existing state and local authorities instead of creating new ones, priority of unconditional revenue sharing or block grants in the place of categorical federal grants, and a retreat from federal intervention to change state and local political structures (L569/111s). Seen in this way, new federalism was an attempt to correct an overly centralizing and structurally interventionist (compare Frenkel L264b/866ss) character of many co-operative federalism programmes. The goal was a more balanced assessment of federalism (see also Frst L281/22s).
343 Wright/White call Nixon's new federalism the Third New Federalism (after President Johnson's Second and before President Reagan's Fourth New Federalisms, L873a/10s,22s). There are still other new federalism concepts, but their use is more isolated. Thus the combination of individual freedom and rational state activity (Mogi L550/1112). Or new forms of interracial co-operation in the United States, between Blacktown and Whitetown (Ferry L461/29). In discussions I have encountered the word as a generic term for federal experiments in the third world. But mostly new is just meant to emphasize the originality of an author's thoughts on federalism (e.g. L116/1).

344 Next to the United States, the term new federalism seems to be most popular in Australia, which imported the word from the U.S.A. (L768/7). Here we find two different new federalisms. The first kind was used by the Whitlam Labor Government (1972 to 1975) to designate national priorities nationally and regionally implemented. It was a policy to circumvent state obstacles to the federal government's broad social reforms. The second type of new federalism, that of the Fraser Liberal-National Country Party Government (1975 to 1983) was not unlike the Nixon brand, stressing efficiency and clear divisions of responsibilities. It also favoured revenue sharing and general purpose grants relative to specific purpose grants (Sawer L698/23, Starr L768/24).
345 With the advent of the Hawke Labor Government in 1983 a new kind of federalism might need to be invented. Perhaps dynamic federalism should be considered! It is a nice progressive word which up to now has been surprisingly little used.

D.3422 Co-operative Federalism

Contents Index End

346 The term co-operative federalism was first used in the United States in 1938 by Clark in connection with New Deal grant methods (Beer L57/74). After 1936, the American courts would no longer construe the Federal Constitution's due process clause (amendment XVI/1) as a narrow limit to member state economic regulations. At the same time they refused to entertain taxpayers' complaints based on the allegedly lacking constitutional basis for public grants (L138/28). The point of departure was, as with new federalism, the assumption of mutual federal/state agreement (U.S. v. Bekins 58 Sup.Ct. 811ss, 1938; see Strong L787/504ss). The concept assumed greater political importance in the early sixties, when the federal government started to pursue far-reaching social and structural reforms. At the same time it acquired a new meaning described below. 347 In the sixties, the term also began to be adopted in other federations (see Ehringhaus L194/28). Thus in 1963 in Canada, it was used to describe the federalism programme of Prime Minister Pearson (L463/409, L534/1, L753/172s). In the Federal Republic of Germany co-operative federalism was first mentioned in 1966 at a meeting of the Freiherr-vom-Stein Association (Veiter L829/195). Its real introduction into political discussion can be traced back to the so-called Troeger Report of 1966 (L438/20s, L165/296s). At about the same time the term also appeared in Switzerland (Reich L782/1079), whence it was taken over by Austria (Ermacora L214/193). The concept was also introduced into Australian (Inns L388/22, Sawer L698/30), Indian (Haqqi L338/49) and Yugoslav (Djordjevi? L176/22) discussions. 348 The new epithet did not remain unchallenged. One type of objection pointed to its catchword character. Another took exception to the uncritical transfer of a concept from a constitutional system marked by the bifurcation of federal and state administrations to federations where, as is the case in Western European ones, administrative interlocking of levels of government was always a fact (Ehringhaus L194/17). And even for the United States Elazar (L198/20) showed that, contrary to traditional belief, a patterned sharing of responsibilities had been characteristic of the early years of union. Some other critics found fault with the hazy, legally elusive content of this neologism. Reid (L388/4) called it a hurrah-term. To Deuerlein (L165/284) it was an embellishment entailed by the times. And some other authors referred to the fact that the idea of co-operation is already part of the term fdus, federation (Frenkel L255/728). Saladin (L782/1079) calls co-operative federalism an ugly pleonasm. Laufer (L458/164) and Lang (L451/220) criticized the term as a linguistically confusing tautology.

349 Nevertheless, the task remains to analyse the essential elements ascribed to the new term. As I do not consider it to be systemic like naked federalism but rather programmatical (see Frenkel L255/729), I shall start the exposition with the term's actual acceptances. We will see that co-operative federalism influences both elements of federalism, autonomy as well as participation. 350 In the foreground we have co-operation. Practically all the attempts at defining co-operative federalism stress this aspect. Thus administrative collaboration (L148/23, L162/31), vertical co-operation (Deuerlein L165/298), functional institutions of cooperation (Ehringhaus L194/165s), forms or institutions of collaboration in federations (Frenkel L255/279), forms of voluntary or federal law-based co-operation amongst member states or between them and the central government (Hfelin L325/572), partnership collaboration (Kunze L446/130), balanced co-operation (Loebenstein L487/870), voluntary collaboration (Mathews L519/xx), new forms of co-operation (Laufer L458/164), consultation (Richardson L659/65), techniques for persuasion, diplomacy, and consultation (Simeon L753/172), multilevel relationships and polycentric collaboration (Tiemann L804/325,333), etc. The co-operation referred to is that affecting federal/state relations (this is at the centre of Australian discussion, Sawer L698/30), or interstate co-operation. Thus those Swiss who advocate resistance against central encroachment talk about the necessity for increased horizontal collaboration through co-operative federalism. But the proponents of additional central intervention also rely on this concept. This ambiguity and its adoption by quite diverse ideologies is a result of the emotional appeal of the term (who is not for cooperation!) and its being already an element in the concept of federalism. It is indeed the case that political texts confirm Laufer's impression (L457/178) that co-operative federalism is represented as a magical formula for the justification of each and any form of collaboration, whatever its real contents. 351 The partners co-operating are usually the executives and the administrations. Only rarely, by giving or withholding consent, do parliaments and populations become involved. That is because only executives and administrations are specialized and small enough to be able to negotiate. This has the result that it is mainly technical concerns which are the subject matter of co-operative federalism. But there is also a correlative tendency to transform political problems which traditionally are judged from ideologically different viewpoints, into technical ones which thereby are rendered administratively negotiable (compare my more detailed exposition of federal forms of collaboration in L264b/14288ss and of the interlacing of polities in L264b/1058ss). 352 But co-operative federalism also influences the allocation of functions and thus member state autonomy. Not for nothing the roots of this kind of federalism have to do with federal grants (no.346, Sawer L698/30) and thus with the central government's ability to affect the member states' priorities by imposing more or less stringent conditions. It is, in the words of Sharman (L745/13s), an inevitable result of the central government's grant jurisdiction. There are few authors who emphasize the need for a more clearly defined allocation of responsibilities (e.g. Loebenstein

L487/870, Pearson L753/172s). The tendency is rather for the extensive construction of federal jurisdiction and the gradual disappearance of constitutional limits to the central government's powers. Co-operative federalism is a pragmatical method for the flexible accomplishment of tasks (Ehringhaus L194/55). Compare also Smiley (L757/320), who stresses the piecemeal approach to the interpretation of constitutional responsibility provisions. The tasks are no longer separated. They are considered to be jointly allocated to central and state governments (compare Connally L789/619, Elazar L198/20, Martin L513/37s, Richardson L659/65). Co-operative federalism emphasizes joint responsibility of governments for the welfare of those they jointly govern (Ehringhaus L194/21). It reflects shifting power relationships instead of rigid independence (Birch L358/20). According to the strict construction of the federal constitution, the central government can intervene only when constitutionally mandated to do so. Further, federal law usually precedes state law (see Frenkel L264b/879ss) Therefore a broad construction primarily results in an expansion of central jurisdiction. The corresponding possibility of extended member state competence (as was originally the case with new federalism, no.341) remains mostly theoretical. Co-operative federalism thus has a centralizing tendency. This is stressed by many authors. It has been considered to be a justification for national usurpation (Baker L45/10) or, in the context of the problem of French culture in Canada, one of the century's most monumental trickeries (Lger L535/319s, L753/289).
353 Those federalists who emphasize horizontal collaboration arrive at somewhat different conclusions. They see less an expansion of central powers than a possibility of preventing or containing this through self-co-ordination (for a critical view: Frey L267/378). For them collaboration with the central government may help to give protection from further or excessive centralization. It is also centralization, but this centralization is milder because it better preserves member state participation and jurisdiction than would be the case with the traditional inclusion of additional tasks in the catalogue of central government responsibilities.

D.3423 Creative Federalism

Contents Index End

354 Hyphenated federalisms seem to be like drugs: continuous use weakens their effect. New epithets replace old ones. Thus in the United States the term creative federalism supplanted co-operative federalism. The term was introduced into political parlance in 1962 by Governor Rockefeller from New York (L789/704). It gained greater acceptance in 1964 when President Johnson used it in Michigan in May (L162/83) and then in his famous Great Society address in June (L162/29). Creative

federalism is not significantly different from co-operative federalism, but is rather a variant of the latter where the relative value of the constitutional allocation of functions becomes especially evident (compare Shuman L746/12 and Wright L746/77). The Great Society programmes had as their main target the overcoming of the social handicaps of the poor and mainly coloured urban population groups. Creative federalism, therefore, is mainly concerned with big city problems (slums and high infrastructure costs in the centres as compared with rich suburbs which do not share these costs, see L789/704) and associated federal/local relations (Ehringhaus L194/57). 355 It goes without saying that creative federalism has not escaped the criticism of being merely another political catchword (thus L449/178, L789/847). Its definition in political statements does sometimes indeed appear to be imprecise as when VicePresident Humphrey (L789/959) understood it to mean effective and timely cooperation between all levels aiding, comforting, propping up weak, obsolete, ineffective state and local government. However, creative federalism is not an empty formula. Its aims and its methods are obvious: social redistribution to be achieved through extensive federal welfare programmes which largely circumvent the traditional allocation of responsibilities and introduce a strong element of social and structural change. 356 Thus both creative and co-operative federalism are characterized by two elements: As to intergovernmental relations they stress co-operation and co-operative institutions in the place of autonomy. In some countries, direct federal/local relations are beginning to play a greater role. As to the allocation of responsibilities, the constitutional limitations on central government activities have largely lost their force, mainly because of the separation of the spending power from the constitutional distribution substantive powers and the possibility of imposing intergovernmental conditions on grants. In the United States there is an additional element of reshaping the rules of local political life to the advantage of underprivileged groups. This gives creative and co-operative federalism a special pluralist flavour (see Ehringhaus L194/190 and, for Germany, Hempel L352/221). 357 To a certain degree, increased collaboration and blurred jurisdictional limits are an almost inevitable consequence of the modern reinforcement of the interdependence that exists between levels of government in welfare states (compare Mathews L519/xx). Even without any stated programmatical goals, to-day's federalism is more co-operative than yesterday's. But, as has been shown, co-operative and creative federalism have further aims. The evaluation of these further aims is not easy because it depends in the final analysis on ideology. 358 Co-operative federalism (like creative federalism) is problem oriented. No problem must remain untackled just because the allocation of functions excessively delays solutions. Collaboration must be flexible so that all the demands the federation is faced with can be dealt with (Deuerlein L165/298, Martin L513/40, Wright L746/77). If a member state does not act it is the central government's right and duty

to intervene (Shuman L746/12). At the same time, co-operative federalism makes possible a concentrated use of public means for the solution of problems, something especially necessary in times of limited financial and human resources (see the Troeger Report L438/20s). This problem oriented approach has obvious idealistic traits. The guiding star is social justice (e.g. Pearson L753/172s). With the introduction of new forms of participation for those who benefit from welfare programmes a democratization goal also becomes apparent (Ehringhaus L194/193). 359 On the other hand, co-operative federalism's main motivation is a technocratic one (thus Hempel L352/221). This is evident from its problem orientation and its emphasis on the concentration of resources. The idealistic traits are mingled with technocratic elements insofar as co-operative federalism seems to be based on an assumption that there are objectively right measures which can be discovered by the application of good intentions. These are deemed to be a matter of course in central administrative agencies and more likely to be found with the central parliament than with state ones. As to the democratization goal -which in this context is mainly a United States problem- it is necessary to remember that we are dealing with forms of participation which, being centrally established and based on idealistic motives, compete with traditional forms of local democracy. Finally, co-operative federalism's executive and administrative orientation is also technocratic in its tendency.
360 The characteristic mark of technocracy is the shift from private sector influence -citizens, political parties, lobbies- to public sector autonomy, that is to say to the authorities themselves and to their experts (compare Beer L58/31).

361 Co-operative federalism has numerous disadvantages. Without anticipating a detailed discussion of the functions of federalism (no.404ss), the conflicts between traditional and co-operative federalism may be briefly mentioned here: In the context of consumer orientation (no.501ss), co-operative federalism favours nationally defined interests to the disadvantage of local ones. As to efficiency (no.476ss), it entails a reduction in local control and a diffusion of political responsibility (see also L352/221, L454/12, L698/30s, L757/327s). Constitutional adaptation is very unsystematic or piecemeal (Smiley L757/320). Vertical division of powers (nos.412ss and 623ss) is bypassed by co-operative federalism's institutions (see Beer L58/33s). This is, to my mind, one of its more questionable aspects. The member units' innovative capacity (no.434ss) is attenuated because of the lesser challenge to their initiative. The nationalization of policies weakens federalism's mechanisms for conflict resolution (no.551ss) and integration (no.570ss), although this at least assists in resolving other conflicts and, sometimes, in integrating other groups. The concentration of financial and human resources may conflict with the crisis stability which results from federalism's many redundancies (no.541ss). Finally, we should consider whether a kind of co-operative federalism that makes collaboration too much of a value in itself may not some day endanger federalism's function of legitimizing government (no.592ss).
362 In parliamentary federations, co-operative federalism poses additional problems. Parliament's powers are in any case considerably weakened because of the executive's control over the voting of

their majority parties in two or three party systems. Increased co-operation between federal and state executives adds to this reduction in parliamentary powers (compare Frenkel L264b/1483, Smiley L757/327s).

363 To say that co-operative federalism is technocratic and neglects some essential functions of federalism is not passing judgment. It is a statement of fact. In the final analysis we deal with ideology. The question whether it is national or local democracy that has a better claim to be the basis of government is perpetual and is always being renewed with fresh arguments. It is the question of federalism. The treatise presented here attempts to present criteria for evaluation. But the answer really depends mostly on the individual's own values and preconceptions. It cannot be scientifically proved. As to co-operative federalism, we may only assert with certainty that its programmes generally favour national over local democracy and executive authorities over legislative authorities and popular will. Under my conception of federalism, cooperative federalism is an inappropriate way to reform federalism. I do not disapprove of collaboration where it is appropriate. But I do object to its being elevated to programme status.

D.4 A BRIEF SURVEY OF FEDERAL HISTORY

Contents Index End

364 Modern federation had its origin in the United States Constitution of 17 September 1787. But the idea of federalism is much older. The eighteenth century political thinkers were wont to look to Greek antiquity for their examples (e.g. Madison and Hamilton L334/18). However, the city leagues of Greece were not the ancient world's only forms of political federalism (thus Montesquieu L551/9/1ss). 365 The classic nineteenth century exposition of ancient Greek unions was the work of Freeman (L251). He described the Achaean, the Aetolic, the Boeotic, the Lykian, and several other leagues. Freeman sought to prove that true federations were already to be found among the Greeks (L251/202, but for a contrary view see Giovannini L294/93). He did not consider the so-called amphictyonic leagues, i.e. those organized around a common place of worship, as political federations (L251/97s). His examples were city state leagues with worldly goals, for instance defence. This, incidentally, is also the picture we get from reading Aristotle (L34/2/2). According to this reasoning the independent city states came first. They later formed associations for limited ends with common authorities.

366 But the Greek city leagues which are best documented date from the comparatively late Hellenistic period (Giovannini L294/9s). Modern comparative research also suggests that the basic pattern was not an aggregation of independent political communities but the gradual consolidation of tribal units as they changed from a nomadic to a settled style of life. The common organization of the tribal cult in a central place remained as the essential characteristic binding the community together in an increasingly loose form (compare Voyenne L837/29s). Such amphictyonic unions could also comprise common interests of a more or less secular nature (e.g. mutual assistance, intermarriage, trade, etc.). 367 It is interesting to note that such amphictyonic leagues existed all over the ancient world, as for instance in Israel (Bright L89/129ss, Noth L583/37ss, Schechter L710/5, Zuber L883/100s), Greece (Alfldi L18/8, Freeman L251/97ss) and Italy (Alfldi L18/10ss, Freeman L251/558). A conspicuous and still unexplained fact in this context is the ubiquity of the number six and, more especially, number twelve in the organization of the association's units. (Bright and Noth trace this back to the necessity for monthly or bimonthly change in the care of the common shrine; L89/147, L583/85s, compare Alfldi L18/168.)
368 We find similar leagues in more recent times in communities that had attained a comparable level of civilization as, for instance, the mounted herdsmen of Northern Asia in the eighteenth century (Alfldi L18/11), the tribally based feudal order of Germany under Henry I (Dennewitz L161/29s, Jerusalem L385/9), and the famous Iroquois League of the Five respectively Six Nations which remained intact right up to the twentieth century (Calhoun L119/72, Parker L602/45, L603/61). 369 If this theory of the history of ancient leagues is correct, it would provide better support for Sidjanski's contention, based on his perception of the constitutional history of Austria, Brazil, and Mexico that federal unions also result from disaggregation (L747/10, no.674). But the state of research does not yet permit a final answer to the problem of understanding the development of the ancient leagues.

370 Rome was also a member of an amphictyonic association, the Latin league. After having vanquished another such union, the Etruscan one, Rome then assumed control over the Latin league (compare Alfldi L18). But antiquity did not develop a theoretical concept of federalism (Friedrich L274/67), and there is no direct succession leading from the old Greek and Italian leagues to medieval ones (Freeman L251/557s, Mogi L550/24). The Roman Empire which medieval lawyers encountered in the Digests (the code of Justinian) was a universal and hierarchic realm without federal traits. 371 This hierarchical model was to be grafted on to the completely different structure of the medieval empire (compare Eulau L224/2s): summa potestas was ascribed to the emperor, the princes were to be praeses provinciarum, the diet was compared to the senate, the free imperial cities were given the same status as the municipia. Even the many leagues of the late Middle Ages were regarded as comparable to the simple universitates of doctors, artisans etc. Up to the end of the sixteenth century, the Corpus Iuris remained for jurists trained in Roman Law the only source for the legal construction of the Holy Roman Empire of the Germanic Nation. This was so even though the post-glossator Bartolus had laid, in the fourteenth

century, the basis for a more realistic theory of government with his differentiation of universitates quae superiorem recognoscunt and universitates quae superiorem non recognoscunt, that is associations which are subordinate to a higher authority and those which are not (see Mogi L550/25). 372 The realities of the medieval state corresponded more to old German law institutions and actual power relationships than to the rigid Roman law categories of the learned doctors. In addition, the medieval church developed not only the theory of papal autocracy but also a federal theology based on the civitas dei which influenced political thinking. The Christian Family, called thus because of its dynastic pillars, in its external role had to defend the Christian faith against the infidels while internally it had to safeguard the independence of its members (compare Blck L104/3, Deuerlein L165/33, Reynold L654/228s). 373 With this as a background, several attempts were made to devise a theoretical division of responsibilities between the emperor and the princes. Thus the abbot Engelbert von Admont and Dante Alighieri, who both lived at the turn of the thirteenth to the fourteenth century, attributed to the emperor the realization of general well-being or the pursuit of common and higher interests. The states were to take care of the welfare of individual nations or of special interests (Deuerlein L165/23, Mogi L550/24). The Protestant university of Herborn was a stronghold of federal theology. This was the university Johannes Althusius joined in 1586. His contribution to federal doctrine was a theory of complete and incomplete federations.
374 There are different assessments of Althusius's role as a theoretician of federalism. For Djordjevi?, for instance, his grasp of federalism was much deeper than that of Montesquieu, Madison, or others (L175/3). For Riley, on the other hand, he was a late theoretician of the medieval state rather than a precursor of a federal doctrine, because Althusius's complete federation corresponded to full incorporation of one state into another whereas his incomplete federation involved any contractual relationship between states (L637/6-3/36ss).

375 Medieval history reveals a multitude of temporary and restricted alliances among states, with a few instances of relatively close and stable associations of states such as the German Empire (Jerusalem L385/9s), the Swiss Confederation (Hilty L360/8ss), the unions of Horodlo and Lublin between Poland and Lithuania (Wagner L383/15), and, later, the Netherlands in the sixteenth century (Boogman L78/5ss, Riker L660/9s, Voyenne L837/92s). At the end of the Middle Ages, in 1462, we then find King Georg Podiebrad of Bohemia's grand design for a European union, with common authorities and a common budget, which anticipated the still more encompassing federation project which Sully submitted some hundred and fifty years later to the French King Henry IV (Bernier L63/203). 376 Post-medieval legal science could no longer escape the task of elaborating a serviceable theory of federal associations of states. Besold was the first to formulate, in his 1614 thesis at the university of Tbingen, a new form of government with inferior states - res publicae subalternae or imperia subalterna - which did not enjoy full sovereignty and which were subject to a fully sovereign superior state.

These inferior states had their own structure of government which the sovereign could not change. In their own territory they had the same rights as were enjoyed by the sovereign in the empire as a whole (L638/39*). In 1648 the peace treaty of Osnabrck resulted in the definitive legal recognition of the autonomy and participatory rights of the estates of the realm (article VIII para.1s, von Puttkamer L639a/27s). In 1661, Ludolph Hugo introduced the concept of a state made up of states as a means of describing the actual form of territorial organization in Germany (Deuerlein L165/39s). At about the same time, in 1667, Samuel von Pufendorf published his famous analysis of the German imperial constitution which showed that the empire, if evaluated in the terms of traditional concepts, would have to be called an irregular body, similar to a monstrosity (L639/6/9, L639/7/8, L638/28s*). Pufendorf distinguished ordinary states, several regular forms of associations of states which retained the sovereignty of the individual states, and, finally, irregular forms of association between the two other kinds of forms of government (Bresslau L638/30s*). (Other German federal plans and pacts are described by von Puttkamer L639a/43ss.) 377 The political impact of the German ideas was surpassed by Montesquieu. He described the federal republic as a constitution which combined all the internal virtues of the republic with the external force of monarchy. This form of government is an arrangement whereby several political entities agree to become citizens of the greater state they wish to create. It is a society of societies that may be enlarged by new associates uniting themselves to it (L551/9/1). Although the corresponding section of the Esprit des Lois was very short its influence was great (Voyenne L837/132), especially for the development of North American federalism. Imboden considers the federal idea to have been even more far-reaching in its effects than the doctrine of the separation of powers which made the book famous (L387/29, but compare Nelson L576/9ss). 378 Montesquieu proposed a primarily organizational justification for federalism (safeguarding individual liberty also played a certain role, L551/9/1). In addition to this the framers of the American Constitution were influenced by the personalistic ideas of the social compact (nos.051ss, 282; Schechter L711/1ss). Since Hooker's work in 1594, these had greatly affected English Protestant thinking (L367/1/10/1, Jellinek L382/206s). To the English monarchomachs and covenanters the agreement of the ruled was a necessary prerequisite for legitimate governance. As a consequence, this personalist element was introduced into the compact of union between the states. This was the case with the confederation of the New England colonies from 1643 to 1684 (Bennett L59/39s). But this confederation, like the first American Federal Constitution of 1777 (Bryce L96/20s), united only the colonies and not their populations. 379 In the debates which preceded the 1787 Constitution (compare L232-35), modern federation was for the first time conceived as a form of government uniting both member states and their populations. The Union had its own population which it could deal with directly and by which it could itself be influenced without state

government involvement. To this double basis of governance corresponded the new Constitution's preamble: We the People of the United States,.... The American founding fathers had thus invented the modern, democratic federation. This form of government was soon to conquer large parts of the Old as well as the New World. But with increasing consolidation and centralization, it was also to accentuate conflict between big national and small local democracy.
380 The American founding fathers were quite aware that they had created something new (compare Diamond L169/133). Patrick Henry for instance illustrated this quite graphically (L516/75): We may be amused if we please, by a treatise of political anatomy. In the brain it is national: the stamina are federal - some limbs are federal, others national. The senators are voted for by the state legislatures, so far it is federal. Individuals choose the members of the first branch; here it is national. It is federal in its conferring general powers; but national in retaining them. It is not to be supported by the states - the pockets of individuals are to be searched for its maintenance. What signifies it to me, that you have the most curious anatomical description of it in its creation. To all the common purpose of legislation, it is a great consolidation of government. Or Madison (L334/39): The proposed Constitution... is, in strictness, neither national nor a federal Constitution, but a composition of both.

381 The influence of the American discussion about human rights profoundly influenced the French Revolution. For federalism, this was not the case. Some French politicians harboured federal ideas, it is true, as for instance Mirabeau (L328/180) and some early Jacobins (Billaud de Varenne 1791, L837/205ss). (Curiously enough, the Girondins, who later were to be decried as federalists by the Jacobins when the term had become an invective, did not establish such a federal programme, Voyenne L837/234ss.) In some provinces federalist movements came into being, first on 1 August 1789 in Lons-le-Saulnier, followed by actual oaths of confederation on 2 November 1789 in Besanon and on 13 December 1789 at Montlimar (L837/185ss). But the revolution took other turns. In Paris the absolutist core of Rousseau's acceptance of democracy triumphed and it swept everything in its way in the provinces too (compare Carlyle L123/230, Nelson L576/20).
382 The Revolution practically conferred taboo status on the French conception of the unitary and indivisible republic. Even if the occasional statesman such as Clemenceau (L742/46) has favoured federalism, this taboo has remained to our own times. A later revolution, the Parisian commune of 1871, was federalist in essence (L32/266). But its suppression was a decisive defeat for federalism. Only since the beginning of the Mitterand Presidency in 1981 have there been some real, albeit rather timid, indications of a departure from extreme unitarianism.

383 Even if France was not to become a federation, French thinkers played a major role in developing the idea of federalism. Thus the liberal Benjamin Constant (L147/315s), thus the theoretician of anarchy Pierre Joseph Proudhon (L634/361s,507s, L635/150, Hahn L328/257s,271s), and thus especially Alexis de Tocqueville (L806s). French foreign policy also favoured the creation of federations in the rest of Europe, for obvious strategic reasons. Thus NapoleonI sponsored the German Union of the Rhine (L161/52,113) and the Swiss Mediation Constitution (L359/554ss).

384 Much later, after the Second World War, it was again France that among the victorious powers most favoured non-centralizing elements in the structure of the Federal Republic of Germany (Laufer L454/19). Less successful were France's attempts in 1946 to transform its colonial empire into a federal union or, in 1958, into a Communaut (L540/4). 385 The close relationship between federalism and idealistic anarchism has been well illustrated by Jean Paul (after Krger L833/21/106): Ideally, the small federal states that always give free laws to themselves would divide into federal villages. And these in turn would fall into federal individuals who at any minute might adopt a new legal code.

386 In the nineteenth century the American example influenced German and Swiss federal developments primarily via the writings of Tocqueville. This has been described in some detail by Mogi (L550, compare Bluntschli L74/398). In Central and South America the concept of federation was more directly taken over from the United States (L408/33ss, L485/290ss, L608/viss, L830/151). The history of Canadian government which in 1867 adopted the first federal constitution of the Westminster type was more independent from the United States. 387 By the end of the nineteenth century, the following federations had been formed and they still exist to-day (even if in some of the Latin American ones federalism is very much attenuated, L173/163, L272/26ss, L830/150ss): Argentina, Brazil, Canada, Germany, Mexico, Switzerland, the United States of America, and Venezuela. Shortly afterwards, in 1901, the Australian colonies federated (after an experiment with confederation from 1885 to 1895 which should have included New Zealand and Fiji, L176a/113ss, L343/57). With the exception of some short-lived Central and South American federations, the federations founded in the nineteenth century proved to be stable. The same observation holds true for one of the two that came into being between the two world wars: Austria (the other one, the Soviet Union, partially lives on in Russia). 388 If Riker called the twentieth century the true era of federalism (L660/2, similarly Brugmans L94/13), if Elazar discerned a federal revolution (L202/2, L204/15, 205b/3ss,49ss), and if McWhinney perceives federalism to be a popular cure for the most diverse kinds of political ills (L533/92), these statements are concerned with the period after the Second World War. Indeed, since 1945 federations have multiplied. But most have disappeared again after a very brief existence. Of the new federations, those which still exist are Belgium, the Comores, India, Malaysia, Nigeria, Pakistan, Tanzania, the United Arab Emirates and, in a very much reduced state, Yugoslavia. 389 Statistical data (1986) Argentina Australia Austria Brazil Canada Comores Area (km ) 2'777'815 7'682'300 83'853 8'511'965 9'976'140 1'862
2

Populatio 27.86 14.42 7.46 123.00 23.90 0.30

Czechoslovakia F.R. of Germany India Malaysia Mexico Nigeria Pakistan Soviet Union Switzerland Tanzania United Arab Emirates U.S. of America Venezuela Yugoslavia Globe 51.82% 100.00%

127'877 248'624 3'159'530 333'507 1'967'183 923'773 796'095 22'400'000 41'288 939'701 92'100 9'160'454 912'050 255'804 70'391'921 135'830'000

15.18 61.44 683.00 13.30 69.40 81.00 80.20 264.50 6.35 17.60 1.04 226.50 14.54 22.30 1753.29 4387.72

390 Never before were there so many newly independent nations as after the Second World War. Because many of these were former colonies composed of different, mutually suspicious population groups living in geographically separated territories, it appeared natural to the colonial powers to grant independence to the colonies through a federal form of government. This may be one of the main reasons for the popularity of the federal formula after World War II. Belgium proceeded in this way with the Congo, the Netherlands with Indonesia, and France with French West Africa, to cite but a few examples. Proudhon (L634/537) had once called the English the most federal of all races, and the United Kingdom created a large number of federations not surprisingly, perhaps, since it had the biggest empire to dismantle (compare Macy L502/694, Riker L660/25s, Simandjuntak L752/290ss). Many of the new federations quickly changed their form of government or were stillborn.
391 Some consolidated themselves into unitary states; this was true of Burma (L180/2974), Cameroon (L771a/261), Congo (L770/1612s), the Ethiopian/Erithrean federation (L459/Vs), the Federation of South Arabia (L205b/196), the German Democratic Republic (L771a/510), Ghana (L384/136, L633/51s), Indonesia (L421/195s), Libya (L205b/195s), and Uganda (L180/229, L205b/175s, L583a/43). 392 Others broke up into their constituent parts. This was the case with East Africa (L249/16), the Federation of Arab Republics (L205b/196ss), the French Communaut (L539/16), French West Africa (L528/148), the Ghana-Guinea-Mali Union (L230/3), the Iraq/Jordan Federation (L205b/196), the Mali Federation (L230/2s, L528/148), Rhodesia and Nyasaland (L249/82, L528/132s), the United Arab Republic (L205b/195s, L771a/429), the United Arab States (L205b/196, L771/422, Neue Zrcher Zeitung 28.6.1977), partially the USSR and Yugoslavia, the Federation of Arab Republics (L205b/196ss), and the Federation of the West Indies (L223/19, L249/115s, L834/78). In the case of Malaysia, Singapore became a separate state leaving the rest of the federation intact.

393 The advocates of federal solutions for problems of Third World national integration (e.g. Agyeman L14/120ss, Leibholz L533/7, L343/54) often fail to realize -as was the case with the British colonial administrators- that cultural or territorial diversity does not by itself make federations viable. On the contrary, it may very often be a threat to survival. Any federal system makes certain demands on the political culture, and a federation usually comes into being only if specific environmental conditions are met (compare no.664ss). The cultural elements especially are often lacking in the Third World, in particular the willingness to share control and to tolerate competing centres of power. The political culture is based on other principles (see Frenkel L261/260ss, Nordlinger L582/31ss). Still, it must not be excluded that federalism might help to solve some particularly difficult conflict as for instance the conflict between Israel and neighbouring Arab countries (for a comprehensive discussion of federalist alternatives see Elazar/Sharkansky L205a/243ss).
394 Modern Cyprus represents a curiosity. After the downfall of the pluralist constitution in 1974, there was an agreement in 1977 between the leaders of the Greek and Turkish communities on the creation of a bi-communal federation (L622/205s). This agreement has not yet been implemented, but the Turkish population group considered itself until recently to be a member state of a federation with its own government, postage stamps, Turkish currency, etc. In 1984, they have opted for independence. The Greeks live in a unitary state. Internationally the Greek-Cypriot government is usually recognized as the only Cypriot authority despite its somewhat questionable constitutional basis. 395 A comparatively recent development is Senegambia which was founded on 1 January 1982 as a confederation with a common army, a partially common executive but with separate economic regions (Neue Zrcher Zeitung 31.12.1981). Here a former British (Gambia) and a former French (Senegal) colonial territory with ethnically related population groups joined in a federal structure after the Senegalese army helped to suppress a coup d'tat in Gambia. 396 Whether the United Kingdom is also federally organized is a question worthy of scrutiny. Mason (L516/12) describes eighteenth century England as a federal empire, pointing to the distribution of responsibilities between central and local government at that time (compare L251/59, L385/11s). Also a number of federal institutions have been associated with the special legal and parliamentary status of Scotland, Northern Ireland, and, to a minor degree, Wales. Mill (L547/375) explained the far-reaching legal and administrative separation of Scotland from England with words that would equally apply to a federal system: A people having that unbounded toleration which is characteristic of this country for every description of anomaly, as long as those whose interest it concerns do not feel aggrieved by it, afforded an exceptionally advantageous field for trying this difficult experiment. But following the consolidation of the doctrine of parliamentary sovereignty at the end of the eighteenth century, British federalism had no chance of developing, except for the special case of Northern Ireland (for a relevant proposal see Burrows/Denton L117/16ss). When the question of some legislative and executive autonomy for Scotland recently became an issue, its advocates went to great pains to avoid the term federalism. They talked about devolution instead (compare L599).

397 Three of Europe's federations were communist: Czechoslovakia, the Soviet Union, and Yugoslavia. Yugoslavia coulc even claim to have the most federalist of federal constitutions, one which provided for single member state veto. We are therefore faced with the problem of the Marxist approach to federalism (as to the history of Soviet federalism see Kis L422/37ss, Lepjoschkin L476/130ss). The relationship is ambiguous. Marx was clearly anti-federalist (Lenin L472/97, Mogi L550/847). Engels had in mind a highly decentralized unitary state with great local

autonomy (L550/849). According to Lenin (L472/47s), Marxists are as a matter of course enemies of federation and decentralization for the simple reason that capitalism for its development needs as large and as centralized states as possible... But as long as diverse nations form a unified state, marxists shall on no account defend federalism or decentralization... Still, it would be unpardonable to forget that with our defence of centralism we only mean democratic centralism.... Democratic centralism does not only not exclude local autonomy or regional autonomy characterized by... specific circumstances. On the contrary, it requires both. The right to federate is nonsense because federation is a treaty between two parties.... As to autonomy, marxists do not defend a 'right to autonomy' but autonomy itself as a general, universal principle of a democratic state with colourful national composition and highly diverse geographical and other conditions (L472/97). But Lenin also considered national selfdetermination to be essential (L473/58ss) and thereby arrived at the recognition of federal or confederal forms of government. Thus, in 1919, he prophesied a world-wide Soviet federal republic (L63/207). And for Russia he called for a confederation essentially restricted to defence and foreign policy (L790/2s, for Lenin's ambivalent attitude compare also L422/28ss). There his position was opposed to Stalin's, who preferred a policy of annexation. Stalin also recognized, in principle, the theory of national self-determination (L766/261). But he easily found a justification for its qualification: There are cases where the right to self-determination gets to be at variance with another, higher right, the right of the working class risen to power to consolidate this power. In such cases -this must be said quite clearly- selfdetermination cannot and must not be an obstacle to the working class' right to dictatorship. The first right has to take second place. That is why we were forced in 1920 to march on Warsaw in the interests of the defence of the working class risen to power (L766/220).
398 The modern left in Western Europe is much influenced by the petty-bourgeois (Lenin L550/851) anarchic ideals of Proudhon and Bakunin. Therefore, federalism as a principle (as opposed to its existing manifestations) is advocated by both bourgeois representatives of personalism (e.g. Alexandre Marc, Ferdinand Kinsky, Denis de Rougemont) and exponents of the new left (e.g. Kappeler L782/563, Zwerin L884/142), based on the same Proudhonian foundations.

399 As to future developments of political federalism, we must start from the realization that the period of colonial emancipation will very soon be a thing of the past. It is an open question whether and when there might again be conditions under which the many miniature states that profit by the geopolitical situation might seek to federate in some way or other. It appears that there may be three other circumstances of special importance to future forms of federalism: the evolution of transnational intercourse, the need to have additional pluralist interests participate in government, and the demand for more local autonomy in highly centralized states. 400 The dream of a united Europe is old. In its federal variant we may trace it back to the fifteenth century (no.375, Bernier L63/203). It is little known that Benjamin Franklin also thought about a European federation after the pattern of the American Constitution of 1787 (L234/131). But it was mainly in the nineteenth and in the early twentieth century that proposals for a federal Europe became common (compare

Bakunin L47/15ss, Bernier L63/208, Blck L104/21, Four L248/149ss, Proudhon L364/335, de Rougemont L675/94, L694/78ss). In the fifties of this century the European Communities (EC, now the European Union) were founded and with them an entity that was dedicated to become the nucleus of a future pervasive union. The European Union with its regulations for certain functional areas represent a form of partial federation (thus Klein L425/36s, compare Scheuner L833/21/123). And certainly the political aspirations are of a federalist nature. EU law constitutes a new level between national and international law (Bernier L63/237). It may be argued that this kind of unification, having mainly functional goals, lacks the common, constitutional ideology that was typical of last century's federations (thus Imboden L387/67). Again, we must not preclude the possibility that the EU might be evolving into a fully fledged union. This was certainly the idea of the founders. Direct elections to the European Parliament and a common currency, the Euro, may herald such a future. A constitutional convention is actually preparing the legal groundwork for it. But it is just as well possible that the soon the be enlarged EU, suffocating in bureaucracy and in paper, has arrived at the end of its tether and that other communities will open up the way, if at all, to more genuine European federalism. 401 Plans for world federation have aims which are even more remote and uncertain. Duchacek (L180/48) calls them daydreams so long as a union closer and more effective than the United Nations is not necessary for the defence of common interests against other planets (compare L180/350, Beres L60/75,86s, Secrtan L740/60, Streit L785a/238ss). It is nevertheless possible that some world-wide functional associations will undergo the same transformation from transnational into supranational institutions as has already happened at the regional level. 402 The second possible development mentioned above (no.399), the need to allow additional pluralist interests participate in government, is dealt with elsewhere (nos.203ss and 589). Undoubtedly this development greatly influences United States federalism. 403 The third tendency is the demand for more local autonomy in highly centralized states. This phenomenon can be encountered in all large unitary states, such as France, the United Kingdom, Italy, and Spain. The institutions designed to meet these demands resemble federal institutions more and more (e.g. autonomous regions in Italy - L558, L681/129ss, L852 - and in Spain, Constitution article 143ss). One is tempted to elaborate some kind of federal theory of convergence: Whereas most federations have become more centralized during recent decades, unitary states have become more decentralized. This is a somewhat simplistic view. In particular, it does not do justice to recent developments in the federal allocation of functions, where the pendulum has again swung in the direction of localism. This can probably be attributed to the same renaissance of localism (no.704) that gives impetus to demands for autonomy in unitary states. But these thoughts show that a neat differentiation of federations and unitary states may become increasingly difficult in the future, because federalism will be less tied to confederation or to federation as the only forms of political implementation. It is quite possible that the twentieth century's contribution

to federal practice - apart from transnational superstates - will be the part-regionalized autonomist state, i.e. a state where some, but not all, regions enjoy the kinds of autonomy and participation that are usually reserved for member states in federations. Examples of such forms of government are land in Finland, the Aosta valley in Italy, and the Basque province (as well as other provincial statutes) in Spain.

E. FUNCTIONS OF FEDERALISM

Contents Index End

404 Federalism is a principle for the organization of political decision making. Its characteristics are on the one hand the autonomy of territorial groups and on the other hand their participation within the framework of an encompassing structure (no.210). If we look now at the functions this principle is deemed to apply to, we must first consider local as against national performance of tasks. Most arguments for federalism are addressed to this aspect. But this is not sufficient. The special quality of federalism is its two-sided nature. It is national as well as local. 405 There is something else, also. If we think of the goals of federalism we usually have a federation in mind. In all classical federations we encounter a three-tier structure. The member states are themselves federally organized. The member state, therefore, has three attributes. It is local in comparison with the national centre. Seen thus those considerations apply that have to do with the functions of locality. It is, secondly, central in relation to local government, which renders the corresponding set of central functions relevant. Thirdly the member state is a middle level within a whole, which poses the problem of the specific functions of such a middle level for a federal system. This last question is usually neglected by students of federalism. Empirical studies are lacking even more in this respect than for the effects of local autonomy. I shall nevertheless try to deal with the functions of the middle level also.

406 My exposition of the functions of federalism corresponds to the model outlined above (no.24ss). First (no.416ss), we deal with functions that have to do with the system's capacity to learn. Then there are the functions that stabilize the system (no.540ss). Finally we will examine assigned functions (no.614ss) such as the promotion of individual freedom, civic participation, etc.
407 The ambivalence of the goals of federalism (Diamond L169/130) is obvious in the writings of classical authors. Thus Montesquieu (L551/9/1) said about confederation: Composed of small republics it enjoys their good government in the interior and, as to the outside world, it has through the force of association all the advantages of the great monarchies. Similar thoughts may be found in Rousseau L679/5, Tocqueville L806/232, and amongst modern authors Duchacek L180/199s and Kafka L833/21/108s. If today the values of localism are in the foreground of arguments for federalism, this may have to do with the fact that increasing centralization of federations and a tendency on the part of scientists towards hierarchical thinking provoke the emphasizing of autonomy. The following selection of catalogues of goals may serve as an introductory survey. 408 Aubert (L782/1081): 1.Federalism guarantees - to the extent that a system may guarantee anything.. - the proximity of power. ... 2.Federalism serves to vulgarize power. 3.It assures the division or separation of power. 4.It preserves power as the opposite to anarchy. 409 Friedrich (L277/57s): Federalism 1) increases the opportunities for dissenting minorities to make their views known to other citizens and policy makers; 2) multiplies the opportunities for citizens to participate in political life; 3) enhances consensus in political discussion in the sense that solutions are sought that will reduce the size, resentments, and coercion of defeated minorities; 4) greatly improves the chances of the peaceful resolution of conflicts; 5) aids the solving of urgent policy questions by providing an opportunity for experimenting with solutions on a limited scale; and 6) enhances confidence in and loyalty to a constitutional polity. 410 Journal Zeit (cited in L457/85): Advantages of the federal system: It makes for vertical division of powers and thereby furthers rule of law; it provides a multitude of economical, political, and cultural centres and favours a balanced regional structure of the Federal Republic of Germany; it facilitates a diverse political composition of federal and state governments thereby integrating the pluralist country as a whole; and, finally, it increases demand for political cadres thus creating a broad basis for testing young political talent. 411 Laufer (L454/33s): The federal organization is more adequate to democracy.... Federation furthers the separation of powers and intensifies rule of law.... Federalism makes multiformity possible and strengthens competition. 412 Thieme (L800/148): If today we look for the meaning of the federal system we find seven different and partially related viewpoints being proffered: 1. Regional influence on the solution of political problems, 2. administrative influence on the decision of overarching questions taking place already in the stage of political planning, 3. an element of division of powers in a situation where the division of powers between Parliament and government has been largely overridden, 4. experimentation and competition, 5. safeguarding of minorities, 6. unburdening of central institutions, and 7. realization of the subsidiarity principle. 413 Once I myself proposed a catalogue of justifications for federalism for the use of the Swiss experts' commission on the total revision of the federal constitution. I was asked to make do with one half page. The result was the following text (L577/1975/52) which, to judge from their final report, in no way influenced the experts' centralizing bias: 414 Federalism is no statement of law. Federalism is no confession of faith. Federalism, for Switzerland, is an organizational principle of political sagacity. Federalism, for Switzerland, is federation.

Switzerland is a federation because this organization

Switzerland has, on the other

allows: 1. to keep the distance narrow between citizens and polity; 2. to distribute power amongst the many without its becoming anonymous (guaranteeing participation and stability); 3. to tailor public services to different local demands (efficiency as consumer orientation);

hand, to put up with: 1. occasional cleavage between costs and benefits (territorial spillovers; 2. overtaxing of political cadres (cumulation of roles);

3. relative significance only of the federal constitution's equality clause; 4. to minimize administrative costs because of short 4. neglect of economies through distances for information processing and democratic large scale consolidation control (efficiency as cost minimization); (economies of scale); 5. the regions to pursue their development goals with 5. sluggishness in determining and vigour; carrying out national priorities; 6. different cultures, languages, and temperaments to live 6. renunciation of coherent together without destructive conflicts. 'national' politics.

415 For the purposes of this study I do not attempt to trace federalism back to some specific ideological or religious position. It is obvious that such positions would emphasize certain functions to the disadvantage of others. The history of federalism (no.364ss) provides us with a colourful palette of such ideological starting points for federal solutions. And today it is not only conservatives who don the cloak of federalism but also progressives (for the USA see, for instance, L181/9s). As to religion it may well be that the attempt to justify federalism with some commandment of God (thus Lang L451/101) or with the Christian faith as such (L451/110ss, Reynold L654/114) is relevant in a given situation because of the integrative power of religion. But I doubt that such a situation now exists. And for a scholarly analysis the ideological point of departure is too restrictive.

E.1 FEDERALISM AND THE POLITICAL SYSTEM'S LEARNING CAPACITY

416 We shall first examine the functions of federalism which are related to the maintenance of the political system's learning capacity. Then we will consider those functions that have to do with the perception of demands and the quality of solutions.

E.11 Maintenance of the Political System's Learning Capacity

Contents Index End

417 Federalism maintains the political system's learning capacity by not overloading a single centre with too many problems (no.418ss), by forcing the system to learn continuously through division of powers and competition (no.424ss), and by furthering local experimentation (no.434ss). Furthermore, federalism provides for decision-making rules (thereby freeing the system's capacities for new learning processes). These rules will not be considered here. They are an essential element of given constitutional arrangements which are outlined in the German companion volume (L264b). To put it in a nutshell: their characteristic is that they create a balancing or optimizing framework for small scale and large scale democracy. The justification for this framework, on the other hand, is the subject of the following analysis of the functions of federalism.

E.111 Relief of Decision Centres

Contents Index End

418 Overload of decision centres has two aspects. One has to do with the demands which are placed on the system by the outside world. The other aspect is the system's capacity to deal with a given number of demands. 419 There is reason to believe that, as compared with a unitary state of similar size, a federation will have to confront a lesser sum total of demands. This is because most problems will only be perceived as problems through the working of the political

process. Let us suppose, for instance, that in a federation there are several population groups with markedly different attitudes to world politics (to some extent this is true for Canada and Switzerland). Then we may expect foreign policy to be more passive than elsewhere because this will help to diminish potential internal conflicts about foreign policy directions (compare Lorwin L491/42s). The more passive is foreign policy the less likely it is that there will be problem overload of the federal system stemming from this sector of politics. (In some extreme cases, if a federation is so weak internally that it kindles foreign appetites for interference or annexation, the result may however be the opposite.)
420 This is what Wheare (L858/186) makes allusion to when he states: Federalism and a spirited foreign policy go ill together (see also Hahn L328/273s, Tripp L813/69).

421 We may also propose the thesis (which requires to be empirically validated) that most of the mechanisms which generate political demands are nationally organized and oriented. This is especially true for the mass media and large-scale interest groups. Problems that are generally considered to be outside the scope of this level are not treated by these mechanisms -the grid is too wide-meshed- and they are thus not perceived as problems. In a unitary state they may find their way into the political arena more easily, thereby heightening demand. Scharpf's findings (L705/19s) point in the same direction. The multitude of interrelated decision centres in a federal system make it much more difficult to carry particular demands through all of them, thereby limiting the generation of too many such demands. 422 Nevertheless, some qualities of federalism counteract this relief function. For one thing, federal systems tend to be confronted with a considerable number of demands which are energetically supported by regional authorities. This may for instance be the case for regional economic development (it would be interesting to have a comparative study of this question). And then there is the additional task of harmonizing the different policies among the different levels of government. This is a typically federal political problem of co-ordination (see Simeon for Canada L753/295). 423 Let us now address the second aspect mentioned above (no.418), the ability to deal with a given number of demands. Here we may talk of federal systems having a clear advantage. The existence of several autonomous decision centres makes for a division of labour which prevents the piling up and overload of problems at one national centre (Bryce L96/353). Two conditions have to be met if this relief is to be fully realized. It is necessary that the system be a federal one, that is a non-centralized as distinguished from a decentralized one (for the difference see no.226). It is also desirable that not too many policy sectors are organized as joint tasks for more than one level of government (see L264b/1043ss), adding demands to the load of each of them (compare also Ostrom L593/229, Scharpf L702/81s, L705/22).

E.112 Competition and Division of Powers

Contents Index End

424 The existence of various and largely autonomous power bases is characteristic of a federal system. Such a situation entails competition and makes for a form of vertical division of powers which is at the centre of most theoretical justifications of federalism (as to the general doctrine of division of powers see Frenkel L253/8ss). For the purpose of the present analysis, the functions of division of powers and competition are treated as different aspects of federalism. Here we deal with maintaining the political system's learning capacity. Later we shall look at the processing of demands (no.501ss) and the support of liberty (no.625ss). 425 Competition takes place horizontally between the member states. To the extent that this maintains learning we shall deal with it in the context of innovation (no.434ss). 426 In the foreground of discussion is the vertical division of powers between the central government and the member states. We start with the observation that centralized organizations are in danger of being unable correctly to perceive and process local information. This is one of the critical properties of all large-scale systems. The authorities must act in an atmosphere of partial ignorance, considerable misinformation, and consequently of great uncertainty (Easton L188/415). Every bureaucracy has a tendency to base its decisions on data which are in the final analysis self-engendered rather than taken from the outside world (compare Deutsch L166/215). And as Ostrom points out (L595/252), central agencies rarely surround themselves with critics, thereby restricting the search for alternatives and augmenting the probability of errors (also L593/214).
427 It was Tullock who especially drew attention to this fact (cited by Ostrom in L595/251): In his Politics of Bureaucracy, Gordon Tullock has demonstrated how a hierarchically-oriented structure functions as a transmitter of information and develops selective biases at each link in the communication chain. This process results from two assumptions Tullock makes about centralized structures: that superiors have a controlling influence over the career advancement of subordinates and that subordinates as selfinterested individuals will act so as to advance their career potentials. Thus, Tullock argues, at each link in the hierarchical chain of command subordinates will advance information reflecting favorably, and repress information reflecting adversely, upon their career potential - thus causing a selective biasing or distortion of information. Or Chesterfield: ... they thought I informed, because I pleased them (L131/221).

428 The federal structure counteracts this tendency by creating hierarchically autonomous centres of decision making (Truman L817/45). A member state

government is, as a rule, not too dependent on the goodwill of the central government. The kind of information it adds to decision making is independent of the information available to the central bureaucracy. Thus, the diverse structures and processes of government decision-making contribute to a due process of inquiry, and can correct for the distortion of information and proneness to error that inhere in highly integrated, large-scale bureaucracies. This is only possible when the diverse structures can function independently of the central executive authority (Ostrom L595/253). To this we may add that such data cannot be neglected, because they emanate from authorities which have their own power base and are conflict-efficient (Scharpf L705/52) because their consent is necessary or highly desirable in many areas.
429 Competition between different political parties, stemming from differences in the composition of central and state legislatures, goes in this direction (Laufer L457/9s), as does the linguistically motivated special status Qubec claims for herself in Canada (Macmahon L501/17). But it must be said that the conventional view generally has little comprehension for such considerations, preferring frictionless proceedings (Frenkel L255/730). The former Canadian Prime Minister Trudeau appears to be one of the few national politicians who, when in government, commented favourably on such conflicts (L816/14s): It may not be recognized, for example, that the system is working well when a government whose programs are affected by another government's legislation, complains about that legislation and brings about the removal of a harmful or wasteful provision. ... Federalism in Canada will never be free of disagreement. ... For it has been said that a crucial benefit of federalism is the unlikelihood that the governments of the constituent parts and the central government will all decide at the same time to do the same foolish thing to people.

430 This function of federalism applies not only to federations proper but also to subsystems like political parties, associations, etc. Thus Fetscher, Hesse, and Tiemann consider the federal principle to be the essential factor for democratic relaxation of party hierarchies in the Federal Republic of Germany (L239/166, L804/316). It may well be that the organization of such subsystems is better evidence for the reality of federalism in a federation than the latter's written constitution (see no.682ss). 431 A threat to the federalism function of division of powers may be seen in the practices of so-called co-operative federalism (no.351ss), which in their tendency replace conflict by co-operation. If such a maxim should become the accepted standard in the politicians' and the public's imagination, competition will be weakened in importance and legitimacy. The cult of an ideology of collaboration, coupled with the fact that the goals of such collaboration will tend to be defined by central interests according to national criteria, will bring to co-operative federations a markedly hierarchical structure with all the concomitant results of rigidity and of distortion of information mentioned above. To this there will be added an element of displacement of politics by administration, as co-operative federalism is mainly geared to the collaboration of administrations (L264b/1552, compare also Grawert L304/158, Hempel L352/221, Laufer L454/12). 432 On the other hand, federal competition may also appear as a pretext. In the nineteenth century Constantin Frantz observed (L487/850): Most often what is presented to us as federalism has no intrinsic positive meaning, being but resistance to centralism. The German Hesse writes (L356/9): It is well known that today quarrels

between the Federal Government and the Lnder are, as a rule, no longer true federal conflicts, but conflicts between different political tendencies in the public realm clothing themselves in the garments of federalism to have a standing in constitutional jurisdiction. 433 Nevertheless, in summing up we may say that federalism's function in enlarging information through competition and division of powers is enhancing democracy by furthering both the weight and the breadth of the information flowing from the periphery to the centre.

E.113 Innovation

Contents Index End

434 A sound justification for regional segmentation of political power is connected with the diversity of initiatives stemming from a variety of decision centres. (Hempel L352/218). The pressure on the several levels of government to show results furthers activity and imagination (Tiemann L804/316).

435 This innovative function of federalism is one that is very often emphasized. In this context, the American Supreme Court Justice Brandeis designated the states as laboratories of democracy (L548/3). There are many examples. In the United States, at the beginning of the century, Wisconsin was leading in the fields of social insurance, vocational training and budgetary procedures (L114/329). New types of insurance (no-fault insurance) were first introduced in some states (L30/4). Grants-inaid for the fight against cystic fibrosis were innovated by Connecticut (L22/232). New techniques for sewage treatment are usually developed in localities of 15'000 or fewer inhabitants (L201/293s). A new generation of American progressives has withdrawn from the federal political arena because they see more opportunities for social change at the local and state levels (Steele, The Guardian Weekly 3.9.1978). In Switzerland the institutions of direct democracy, such as constitutional or legislative referenda, popular initiatives, and proportional elections, were first introduced in the cantons before they became part of the Federal Constitution (L243/209). The Canton of Glaris was first in continental Europe to adopt a law on factories. The first Swiss ombudsman, to take a recent example, started his work in 1971 in the city of Zurich, the Cantons of Zurich and Basle-Country following in 1978 and 1984, respectively. Numerous other illustrations from these and other federations might be cited.

436 It would be misleading, however, to ascribe innovative effects uniformly to federalism. It is also often the case that federalism prevents, or is said to prevent, nationwide innovation. Thus Neidhart, in Switzerland, perceives unco-operative cantonalism which, according to him, plays a major role in rendering changes in the Swiss system of government difficult (L575/37, L782/612). In a general way it may well be said that the many powers of veto in a federal system slow down change. They are intrinsically conservative (Dicey L170/173s, Friedrich L275/10). This is not negative in itself. We may, with McWhinney (L533/7), also consider it to be the political realization of the need for wide national consensus before attempting largescale experimentation. But the fact of curbing innovation remains. Porter (L753/281) puts forth the hypothesis that member states are more inclined to conservatism than the federation as a whole because they are more lacking in means as well as more exposed to the influence of lobbies. This still has to be tested. I have some doubts. It may be true that there are other lobbies at work. But looking at federations in general I think that national lobbies and media are at least as influential as, if not generally more influential than, their member state counterparts. The disparities in the willingness to innovate in certain fields might also be due to the greater distance between federal parliaments and electors and the more bureaucratic or intellectual quality of central decision making. This hypothesis is also worth serious consideration.
437 We should consider the possibility that restraints on national innovation are not so much a characteristic of federations as the result of any highly complex governmental structure. They are, therefore, also to be found in other countries.

438 Scharpf writes (L703/183) that plural systems with relatively independent subsystems on the one hand increase the probability of initiatives. But, on the other hand, these initiatives are usually solutions for the subsystem's own problems whereas a fragmented polity has a tendency to neglect overarching issues. This observation is certainly valid for federal pluralism. Compared to this, centralized systems appear to be less sensitive for their subsystems' problems, ... Decentralization, on the other side, furthers those innovations for which consensus might be arrived at within individual subsystems but not with the system as a whole (L703/183). 439 In this area also the practices of co-operative federalism (no.346ss) probably have a rather negative result. The member states governments are tempted not to solve their problems but to eschew them, pointing to the advantages of waiting for the central government's decisions in the matter. Or the member states may attempt to introduce common solutions even in fields where this is not necessary. This is especially the case in the Federal Republic of Germany, where there is constant media pressure to unify anything that smacks of diversity. Thieme notes that the various intergovernmental Lnder-conferences... have therefore found their main occupation in unification much more than in experimentation, to rather prevent individual solutions than to further them (L800/151s). A similar situation obtains in the United States. We are confronted with more than the largely removable side-effects of a methodical/administrative kind (Ehringhaus L194/179).

440 A further barrier to innovation may be erected by intergovernmental competition. Legislation on environmental protection, labour codes, new taxes etc. is not very probable if it entails the threat of an exodus to other member states of those adversely affected (Wright L746/75s). In such cases the central government may further member state experimentation by restricting the possibilities for interstate dumping. The American system of unemployment insurance is an illustration of this (Freund L746/47).
441 These hindrances may be the reason why some authors, who expect perhaps too great a degree of diversity in federations, are rather disappointed at the actual number of experiments (compare Macmahon L501/3s,143ss, Miller L548/3s). During the 1975 election campaign the Austrian Chancellor Kreisky went as far as to describe the practice of the member state parliaments as petrified and to deny the existence of any real member state politics (L587/23).

442 Baker (L45/10) calls for more detailed research into this whole question of federalism and innovation. I cannot but concur.

E.12 Solving Problems in Pluricentral Organizations

Contents Index End

443 Disputes on the advantages and disadvantages of federalism are at the same time discussions about this system's efficiency, that is to say about its ability to solve problems in an adequate way. There is, then, a tendency to place fragmentation, overlapping and inefficiency on one and the same footing. If there exists a kind of political rhetoric that tends to correlate federalism with goodness itself, there is also, in everyday life, a set of arguments at least as politically influential which suggests that the alleged weaknesses of federal performance may be overcome by methods of so-called modern management. It is said that eighteenth or nineteenth century federalism has not been designed to deal with the problems of the twentieth century. As the United States moves into the 1970s, it is clear that our federal system is not working (Reuss L594/1). Our present federal structure is a relic from the horse-andbuggy past - a structure fundamentally intractable to successful grappling with today's complex social and economic issues (Humphrey L594/1).
444 These critics usually ask for a more clearly structured, hierarchical government organization, free of redundancies, along patterns developed in the business world. There is a certain irony in the fact that such proposals are put forth at a time when economic evolution favours the loosening up of

big centralized hierarchies to render the individual parts more autonomous; or, in other words, when business begins to see virtues in federalism (compare Elazar L202/21, L637/6-4/10, Porter L625/84s).

445 Efficiency is one of those words that, whilst indicating a direction, do not have a uniformly accepted meaning. If we were to equate efficient with functional the whole of the present analysis of functions of federalism would also involve the analysis of efficiency. But we are nearer to the general acceptance of the term if we think especially of the cost and quality of solutions when we deal with efficiency in relation to federalism. In talking about costs, we would stress production aspects whereas quality is concerned with the demand for public services in terms of preferences and the satisfaction of wants. 446 Finally, we should not overlook a further source of criticism which might well be the most important one. It is what I call intellectual sthetics (no.531ss). These matters are now considered in turn.

E.121 Costs of Federalist Solutions

Contents Index End

447 Federal systems in general tend to be extravagant in the use of governmental manpower (Sawer L698/50). Trouble, expense, and delay due to the complexity of a double system of legislation and administration (L99/341). - Experience presents us with counter-evidence: if we sum up we arrive at the conclusion that administration organized under the principle of subsidiarity will cost less and will be more economical than centralized administration (Marcic L509/431).

448 The positions are clear and contradictory. We might expect a wealth of empirical studies to support them. This is not the case. As with nearly all aspects of federalism very little research has been undertaken (Ostrom L590/33). In theory, some costs which have to do with territorial disparities between providers and beneficiaries of public goods (spillovers), or with the impossibility of providing such goods for too small a population (economies of scale), militate for a high degree of centralization. Costs of decision and control, on the other hand, point rather in the opposite direction (Frey L267/371). The optimal degree of centralization under the cost criterion has yet to be determined. In order to establish it, we would have to confront centralization not only with non-centralization, but also with decentralization (see no.225). And given the prevailing centralizing bias we would also have to ascertain whether economies of scale are not, in some instances, accompanied by diseconomies of scale (Walsh L844/16s).

449 According to a European Community inquiry (L437/34) it appears that the proportion of the gross national income used for public expenditures at all levels of government tends to be somewhat lower in federations than in unitary states. But the countries thus analysed are not representative enough, and the difference is too small, to make clear-cut assertions admissible (also Beer L57/89s). On the other hand, it appears that local government expenditures in the Western World have expanded faster since the Second World War than central government ones (Gould L798a/226ss). This may be a consequence of the increased delegation of responsbilities to the local level and, possibly, a larger growth of some service oriented governmental functions as e.g. health and education (local) if compared to others like defense (national, L798a/228).

450 I am inclined to think that the question of costs is not a decisive one. Certainly not if we identify costs with money. The political costs or advantages connected with other functions of federalism are more important. However, both theoretical considerations about the costs of information processing (empirical studies are especially lacking here) as well as the analysis of advantages and disadvantages of size lead us to perceive merits with non-centralized or partially centralized forms of organization. The hypothesis that central agencies will more efficiently allocate scarce means (Neidhart L575/37) cannot be upheld, at least not from a financial viewpoint.
451 I shall deal more specifically with the costs of information, of mobility, of scale, and of externalities. It goes without saying that all my considerations on functions of federalism could be clothed in the form of reflections about costs. This would be a consistently economical approach. Such an approach is for instance at the basis of the theory of Albert Breton and Anthony Scott (see L87/31ss, L307/44ss). These authors distinguish between costs of signalling, of mobility, of administration, and of co-ordination. Yet such a limitation on the provision of public goods and services cannot but very clumsily do justice to the political and psychological aspects of, for example, the function of integration. I prefer a less pure but, in my view, more meaningful approach.

E.1211 Costs of Information

Contents Index End

452 Processing information involves costs. These will be minimal where the distance between the origin of data and their final use is small. This happens to be one of the justifications for the subsidiarity principle (no.231ss). Each step of transmission of information engenders two kinds of costs: there are the actual costs for the necessary intermediary agencies (salaries, administrative infrastructure, etc.; compare Proudhon L635/99s). But there are in addition the costs arising from the distortion of information which any hierarchy is prone to and which may lead to expensive misjudgment. The modern American theory of bureaucracy deals especially with these

questions; allusions to this have already been made above (no.426ss, see also Deutsch L166/215, Walsh L844/17s). Examples will be given below (no.485ss). 453 On the other hand, federations may have to face additional costs of information. This may for instance be the case if for some territorially far-reaching decision there is distortion of information due to the fact that only local data are taken into consideration. This is typically the case with spillover problems (no.472ss). But we may also think in this context of the costs for consensus and co-ordination due to the veto positions of additional units of government, like member states or local governments, which render agreement more difficult (for Canada see Sproule-Jones L763/123ss) or necessitate additional flows of information. 454 Still another viewpoint is that of the individual citizen. A federal system provides him with multiple access points for his demands (Landau L449/190) and, at least to some degree, shorter distances. The other or cost side of the coin is a more demanding standard of civic education necessary for the utilization of such a system (Ostrom L591/231).

E.1212 Costs of Mobility

Contents Index End

455 Below (no.503) I shall discuss the so-called Tiebout hypothesis. It is based on the theory that citizens or individual firms may, in a federation with different service structures in its member states, show their preferences by changing their domicile. This, for the individual, is an advantage. For member states and other territorial units the corresponding competition brings costs because some measures which entail the danger of an exodus of tax-payers, such as increases in taxation, are thereby constrained. This is also one of the reasons why some tasks such as income redistribution and economic stabilization policy can only be exercised by member states to a limited degree (L264b/901a). 456 Even for the individual citizen the federal structure may bring about mobility costs (apart from the obvious costs of moving according to the Tiebout hypothesis). It may well be that member states render interstate immigration or movements of goods more difficult (sometimes also emigration, as formerly in Switzerland, C62). This is usually connected with linguistic or economic protection. With the exception of Canada (where article 6 of the 1982 Constitution addresses this very problem) these

impediments to mobility are usually without importance in modern federations. They are certainly not more important than in unitary states.

E.1213 Costs of Scale

Contents Index End

457 Proudhon said (L634/469s): I have pointed out ... that general government costs increase in direct and geometric connection with centralization. In the Canton of Vaud the average tax yield per head of the population is fr. 15.77. Together with the federal contribution which amounts to fr. 6.89 per head, we arrive at a total of fr. 22.66. This same average corresponds to fr. 30.-- in Belgium and fr. 54.-- in France. On the other hand there are 25 cantonal governments as well as a federal one in Switzerland for a population of 2'392'760 inhabitants. - Though the subject is largely unexplored, a recent pioneer study suggests that the economists, who are undecided as to whether a large nation is significantly cheaper to administer than a small nation, would agree that a federal state might be less able to achieve economies of scale than a unitary state (Hicks L358/45).

458 It may be admitted as a fact that the village where I live is unlikely to be able to shoot a satellite into orbit. For the United States this is no longer a problem. It is rather obvious, too, that a town must be of a certain size before it is in a position to support an ensemble of first-class opera singers or an art gallery (paradoxically, American studies have come to the conclusion that, on the other hand, such institutions are visited in inverse proportion to a city's size: L156a/117). Very often a central computer might serve without significantly higher costs a very much larger area than it is actually used for. All this is to say that a certain minimal area and, therefore, a certain degree of centralization are necessary prerequisites for the provision of some public services or, at least, for their cost-efficient provision. Centralization makes for economies of scale. This is a quite popular and politically strong argument against federal fragmentation. 459 The existence of economies of scale is evident. Diseconomies of scale also exist: costs that rise disproportionally with size. Economies of scale are usually the result of a better exploitation of fixed facilities. But in the context of the local government amalgamations which have been fashionable during recent years in both federations and unitary states, these economies often had a tendency to be offset by diseconomies. Hawkins (L346/212s), on the basis of his empirical studies, said in respect of the U.S.A.: Yet what cannot be dismissed is the consistency of the conclusions - that while diseconomies of scale appear, economies of scale do not. Elazar (L203/72) pointed out that in cities of more than a million, the average per

person costs were 51% greater than those of cities with populations between 100'000 and 250'000 and were 100% greater than the costs of services rendered in cities having fewer than 25'000. In 1968, Hirsch arrived at the conclusion that for many services efficiency gains were highest for a size of population in the range of 50'000 to 150'000, with the exception of specific services which require a large amount of capital like water supply, public transport, and sewage treatment (L595/119).
460 The English local government reorganization of 1974 was also designed to result in high efficiency gains. The subsequent experiences were particularly painful for the populations concerned. According to Richards (L658/96) the new local governments very often raised taxes by about 50 per cent, in some extreme cases by nearly 100 per cent.

461 Knaub (L428/162ss) has analysed the French cost/population ratio in different sized communities for the year 1968:
Current expenditures per inhabitant Population 5000-10'000 10'000-20'000 20'000-50'000 50'000-100'000 100'000-300'000 300'000+ Personnel expenditures per inhabitant Cost Population 245F Below 2000 276F 2000-5000 335F 5000-20'000 362F 20'000-50'000 417F 50'000-100'000 388F 100'000 Infrastructure costs for each additional inhabitant Cost Population 64F Below 10'000 86F 10'000-20'000 124F 20'000-50'000 165F 50'000-100'000 191F 100'000-200'000 236F 200'000+ Cost 17'300F 24'100F 24'400F 33400F 36'700F 37'000F

462 Thurner's study (L802/41ss) on the relationship between the number of public employees and population size in local governments in Upper Austria points to the same conclusion.

463 What are the reasons for such rapidly mounting diseconomies of scale? Costs for the treatment of information as mentioned above (no.452ss) probably constitute one set of reasons. But then we are also confronted with personnel expenditures and increases in the demand for public services. 464 There are several inducements for personnel costs to rise disproportionately. Thus in the Federal Republic of Germany, this may result from local government amalgamation followed by pension payments for redundant, often part-time, functionaries. Still more important is professionalization of the public service. Functions that heretofore were honorary posts, paid with a song and a whistle, now command a salary that is likely to be higher than the sum of the cost economies. In addition, full-time employees need offices and other facilities. Personnel employed before the reorganization will need to be better paid for additional responsibilities (after all, their unions' agreement to the amalgamation plans need to be recognized in some tangible way). Notwithstanding anything that might be contemplated at the outset, it would be naive to believe that personnel who become superfluous under the new arrangements will be dismissed. On the contrary, Parkinson's law will make for new jobs, especially in relation to staff functions. In addition, the problems of information treatment and raised expectations about services will encourage the

growth of bureaucracies. Overstaffing is enemy number one with local government reformers ('in England'), who point out that since 1955 town hall staff have almost doubled in numbers... After the recent reorganisations of councils into bizarresounding new areas, the staff, whose function remained the same, went up by six per cent and is now ten per cent up on the old total. 'Where there are cutbacks, it tends to be the services, not the staff, that get the chop' (Sale, Punch 26.5.76).
465 According to Hawkins (L346/213) a 1974 State of California study found it would cost fiftyfour percent more to have the State Division of Forestry provide service to rural areas presently receiving fire services from special districts. The California Local Government Reform Task Force found that special district sewage treatment facilities were just as efficient, at comparable levels of quality, as city and county operations. A study conducted by the Environmental Protection Agency found that private garbage collection was only fifty-seven percent as costly as equivalent services provided by the public sector. And a private fire company in Scottsdale, Arizona, not only reduced local fire insurance rates but also reduced per capita fire costs by forty-seven percent. According to the evidence, large size does not appear to be a critical factor. In fact, size is often positively associated with decreasing levels of effectiveness. On the contrary, there are now bits of positive evidence that the quality of service declines (below a minimum level) with increasing size. Using a variety of measures of student performance in California, for example, Niskanen and Levy find that 'School district size has a consistent negative relation to student performance' (Wildavsky L861/119).

466 While such studies as are available suggest that economies of scale do exist (Metwally L543/42), they are to be found primarily in connection with services that require capital rather than manpower. It is thus probable that big computers can be more efficiently exploited in areas with large populations than in less populous areas. A public welfare agency, on the other hand, will incur additional costs as it grows, because of the need to employ additional personnel for direction and control. This tendency is accentuated by the absence of a competing market in the public sector. Public enterprises are comparatively inattentive to management costs that rise disproportionally with increased size. This may lead to the point where the management costs engendered by each additional official are higher than his productivity so that diseconomies of scale rather than economies result (compare Grewal L308/11ss, Ostrom L592/59s). 467 Public services hardly ever require either much capital and no manpower or considerable manpower and no capital. Public services need personnel as well as expensive equipment. If the organization of such services required a mutually exclusive choice between different patterns of organization, we would have no choice but to neglect benefits of scale in order not to increase personnel costs, or to neglect rising personnel costs in order to keep capital investment within sensible limits. But in reality we have more choice. Special districts or single-purpose authorities, contracting out, and other organizational arrangements make it possible even for small agencies to achieve most of the benefits of scale through co-operation with others without losing the cost advantages of small size (see Hawkins L346/212). Evidently these hybrid forms also have their disadvantages. Public control of joint institutions is more difficult and their operational performance might be difficult to monitor. Both situations may result in increased costs.

468 If we assume that public services are to be financed from a local government's own funds (i.e. without grants-in-aid) we may presume that smaller governments keep house more economically than bigger ones. I have the impression that, in Switzerland, the connection between the cost of a new service and the level of taxation plays a greater role in local politics than in the Cantons, where it again seems to be a more important consideration than in national politics. There are several possible reasons. There is the fact that in a large budget an individual item of expenditure has a comparatively small influence. Then there is the psychological inability to visualize big sums, or to oversee and co-ordinate a large scale bureaucracy with all its services. Increasing professionalization of centralized politics (full-time politicians, large staffs of administrators and interest groups etc.) encourages the level of demand in the political arena (compare Birgersson L71/265s, Friedman L273/343). Finally, in large groups it becomes much easier for free riders to profit from public services without participating in the costs of their provision (L430/60).
469 It seems to be a consequence of local government amalgamation in various European countries that the different patterns of public services in the old jurisdictions are not only maintained in the original areas but are extended to the whole of the expanded jurisdiction. This obviously results in an overall increase of expenditures (Frenkel L263/24).

470 In an abstract way and without relation to actual public services within a given polity, it is difficult to conclude whether scale produces economies or diseconomies. But since public discussion seems to assume that there are economies of large scale, it is especially in this direction that a caveat is necessary. In addition, we should not forget that the above considerations about costs are primarily related to the production side of public services. They shed little light on the problems of how these services are made available to the public and do not say much about optimal political organization, especially when we recognize that for each public service the optimal area will be different. In a general way and returning to the question of federalism, we may say that a federal system, with its three or more different sizes of government, provides for a certain balance of economies and diseconomies of scale (thus Ostrom L593/229).
471 Naturally, there are trade-offs between size and number. From the federal viewpoint, the curse is taken off size by number: the larger the number of units involved, the larger each unit can be without decreasing effective delivery of services. The value of size, then, depends on number: the smaller the number of units, the more large size contributes to ineffective delivery of services (Wildavsky L861/107).

E.1214 Spillovers

Contents Index End

472 Under economic theories of federalism, spillovers or spatial externalities constitute an important cost factor. Spillovers are the result of public as well as other goods being offered or produced in one area, but also benefiting (or burdening) the inhabitants of other areas who do not participate in their costs (or who do not enjoy corresponding advantages, compare Beer L57/63ss, Pawlowsky L607/17s). Some examples are state universities, theatres, and local industries. State universities in Switzerland are financed by one canton and attended by students from other cantons which, until recently, did not contribute to the costs. Theatres often involve a heavy financial burden for their cities. But the theatregoers who profit from their existence may very well come from other localities which contribute nothing to the deficits. The opposite situation may arise in the case of industries that pollute a wide area, while tax and other benefits accrue only to their own local governments. 473 If we look at spillovers from a purely financial viewpoint without taking into account considerations of justice, we may ask whether in the context of the national economy their existence has a tendency to lead to oversupply or to undersupply of public goods. Economists are not unanimous on this subject (see Frey L266/96, Pawlowsky L607/59). At least until recently the advocates of the undersupply thesis were in the majority. They base their case on the assumption that member states only produce a public good until its marginal costs coincide with the marginal benefits for the states' own inhabitants (L266/96s). Against this Williams and Frey demonstrate that spillovers, in terms of the national aggregate may result in excessive expenditures if, in addition to the reactions of governments, private investment and labour force mobility induced by infrastructure expenditures are also taken into account. Because individual regions utilize infrastructure expenditure as an instrument for regional economic development there will be an oversupply in infrastructure if all governments adopt the same policy (Frey L266/97, Pawlowsky L607/59s,64). 474 Of course it would be ideal if, for each public good, the spatial boundaries of service provision could be circumscribed in such a way as to have no benefits or costs transgressing them. Spillovers would then be internalized. Such a solution, consisting in creating a special district for each public good, is at most a theoretical possibility (compare public choice theory, no.516ss, Pawlowsky L607/122). Some externalities will always remain. They may be small scale, as for instance local border effects as described by Tullock (L820/27). Or they may be large scale, as illustrated by economic stabilization or redistribution effects. Perfect internalization presupposes unitary government (in strict logic it is only feasible under world government, L820/27). Considerations such as these cause Riker to claim: Hence in all cases a uniform policy is cheaper from the point of view of external costs than a non-uniform policy (L660/147). Decisions made by constituent units are invariably minority decisions that impose high external costs on the national majority. This assertion is wholly irrefutable on the level of theory (L660/151). The flaw in this reasoning is its use of an analytical instrument for discrete relationships as a recipe for government organization which is always multi-dimensional. Or as Pawlowsky describes what is

in his eyes the basic weakness of spillover analysis (L607/75): It is an attempt to solve a macro-economic problem with a micro-economic tool. 475 Spillover analysis is a valuable instrument if the problem is how to organize regional financial transfers or to define the area of a special district. Spillover considerations play a prominent part in the justification of federal grants-in-aid (L264b/1114). To use them as a basis for large-scale governmental reorganization may be tempting because of the spillover concept's one-dimensionality and apparent clarity. But it is this one-dimensionality which leads us down a blind alley, probably in theory and certainly in reality. Spillovers are on their own no sufficient justification for the creation of larger areas of government or for the centralization of public services (Pawlowsky L607/133, compare Bird/Hartle L70/51ss).

E.122 Quality of Federalist solutions


Contents Index End

476 It seems clear on the basis of both theory and example that uniform national decisionmaking is invariably more efficient... than is local decision making (Riker L660/147). Etzioni warned: City and state administrations, hard as it is to believe, are generally, on every account, more inefficient and ineffectual than are the federal agencies (L181/8). - The philosophical argument of federalism is based on the highest possible utility, in the conditions of a particular time and place, in the course towards decentralisation or towards centralisation. This being the philosophical assertion of federalism, federal theory in our own time should be based on pragmatic utilitarianism (Mogi L550/1059). The test of federal theory is federal action - superior delivery of services (Wildavsky L861/106).

477 These citations show that, for both critics as well as apologists of federalism, the quality of service delivery is an important aspect. To what degree is it, then, possible to make valid generalizations about a federal system's efficiency as compared to a centralized one? 478 The first problem we encounter is the concept of efficiency itself. It is a popular term. But it is a difficult one if we want to use it as a workable instrument for analysis (L346/212). Scharpf's definition is cost oriented (L704/100, see also Robinson L667/9): Efficiency, to define it within a goal/instruments model, is either the attaining of a given end with minimal use of resources, or the use of given resources to achieve a maximum degree of goal fulfillment. This is the aspect I dealt with above (no.447ss). But the concept of efficiency may well be a broader one, such as Lehmbruch's (L465/94s): We might define it as the capacity of a political system to resolve, within a reasonable time, the problems considered as vital or important by substantial segments of public opinion, including those problems that can be expected

to gain such importance in the foreseeable future. Such a definition, which we will now focus on, emphasizes the quality of solutions. 479 For the sake of clarity, a qualification is called for. We are concerned only with problems that society's decision-making process defines as problems which need to be solved. These we also term problems in everyday linguistic usage. They range from small problems, involving for example the building of a school or the regulation of liquor retailing, to large-scale concerns, such as national defence or the reduction of regional economic disparities. On the other hand, we are not here concerned with system problems, that is problems connected with the existence of a social system as a system (compare no.23). Such problems would involve a system's learning capacity (adaptability, change, efficiency, etc.) or its stability (integration, legitimation, etc.). These are the themes of our concern with the functions of federalism generally. 480 If by efficiency we mean to designate the quality of a solution we use the term as the basis for evaluation. We need yardsticks. These do not exist per se. They result from the same social decision-making process that defines the problems to be solved. Efficiency, then, is the degree to which a solution attains its end and thereby makes the problem disappear, without causing other avoidable problems. Efficiency is the successful management of problems. Efficiency is relative. Absolute efficiency is an unattainable ideal. 481 It is unlikely that we can arrive at a clear-cut judgment about the efficiency of federalism. We may say that the organization and maintenance of this form of political structure in a given society is an indication, by and large, that it is considered to be efficient. But it is obvious that for each of the society's members the assessment will depend on his or her personal conception of the hierarchy of public goals. If someone values an energetic foreign policy highly (e.g. Chenaux-Repond L782/1011) he will rate federalism with its tendency to complicate this differently from someone whose paramount aim is the peaceful living together of groups with markedly different value systems and who therefore prefers weak central government to none at all (e.g. McWhinney L533/6). 482 For the purpose of the following analysis I distinguish between two dimensions of quality: technical adequacy and public satisfaction. Technical adequacy means that a given problem is solved correctly according to the state of technical expertise in the relevant field. A data processing problem, for instance, is solved correctly when the computer used has been chosen, programmed, and fed with information in a way that will satisfy a computer expert that the solution uses the equipment's possibilities according to specifications, economically, and in a manner which does not foreclose future changes. Public satisfaction, on the other hand, obtains where a solution is considered to be the right one by the public, including the beneficiaries, those who bear its costs, and outsiders. In this view the data processing problem mentioned is correctly solved when the citizen is satisfied that a solution is really in his interest, that it does not occasion unnecessary costs, and that it does not invade his privacy more than is strictly necessary. It is obvious that these aspects are not mutually exclusive:

technical adequacy per se does not exist. It also requires evaluation. But the differentiation between criteria which are deduced from the properties of a problem itself and those that are founded in social attitudes does elucidate the two essential dimensions of the concept of quality.
483 These two faces of quality may also be found in practical politics. To-day's reform postulates usually demand more efficient, i.e. technically adequate, solutions which should not result in more bureaucracy but, on the contrary, bring about more citizen participation. Proposals to merge communes, with a view to achieve more efficient local government, are nearly always accompanied by statements to the effect that the citizens' preferences would be better heeded or that their participation would be increased under the new regime because of more political accountability or better neighbourhood representation (Schwartz L736/326s).

484 Before delving further into the theme another qualification has to be made. Here I treat only the general suitability of federal organization for the efficient solution of problems. I do not go into the question of the efficient allocation of functions amongst the different levels of government in a federation. This is the subject of a chapter in volume II of my German text (L264b/894ss).

E.1221 Quality as Technical Adequacy

Contents Index End

485 I dealt above (no.457ss) with economies or benefits of scale. Wherever they are attainable they presuppose larger jurisdictions. They are therefore centralizing. The benefits do not necessarily have to be of a financial nature. They may also be qualitative ones. A university must have a minimum number of students, a hospital must have a minimum number of patients to be able to maintain a certain qualitative level of specialist services. Some political tasks also demand a large or national scale, as for instance defence, interregional economic adjustments, and some aspect of equality. 486 However, this does not answer the question of how these tasks are to be organized. There are different ways for that: centralized, decentralized, partcentralized (e.g. through central skeleton laws), co-operative (e.g. through interstate compacts), or non-centralized (e.g. harmonizing effects of quasi-market mechanisms, using the invisible hand). Any federal system utilizes nearly all of these organizational elements. But it is primarily the qualitative problems of local problem

solving (modelled to the pattern of subsidiarity, no.231ss) that are the focus of the following considerations. 487 First, territorial differences of all kinds often make it essential to regionally differentiate public policy. Thus, it has often been claimed that federal organization is best suited to the evolution of large-area government because it combines political unification with regional adaptation (Bryce L96/351, Dikshit L173/14). The expediency of having regional adaptation within and by the politically organized regions is based on several factors. 488 Distortion of information in multi-level hierarchies has already been mentioned (no.427). The probability of disparities between a centre's ideas about the effects of some policy and the policy's actual effects in the local context is thus quite high. Attempts to correct deviations through increased control very often bring results that are no longer justifiable in relation to the resources deployed (Ostrom L592/60). Then there is the natural tendency of any centre to view local adaptation as involving failures of central controls which have to be rectified with more controls. This may be an inadequate response if the mistake lies with central planning to begin with (van Gunsteren L320/19). 489 We may also perceive a certain loss of selectivity through increased distance. The farther away a centre of decision and the more encompassing its responsibilities, the more difficult it is for it to deal adequately with small problems or problems of a predominantly local character. A megalopolis like New York is not able to repair potholes or to keep pavements clean (L593/223). In Los Angeles, since the amalgamation of school districts, it has become impossible to deal with cockroaches in school buildings (L592/121). It does seem apparent, though, that ceteris paribus the more localised the benefits generated by the service, the more likely it is that this 'uniformity inefficiencies' argument will support localised political provision (Walsh L844/20). Tasks with technologies that require mutual adjustment and/or have environments which are shifting and heterogeneous require an organizational structure which includes small, localized units. To be effective, these units should be endowed with considerable discretion, for they must make judgments about appropriate responses to clients or decide how to cope with complicated environmental situations (Porter L625/91s). Such autonomous units are to be found in the elements of federal systems.
490 Scharpf's argument uses the same approach (L705/22): Political tasks and problems may arise locally or be functionally delimited. They may then be dealt with by local or functional decision centres which are narrowly circumscribed but which have a higher problem sensitivity and a swifter responsiveness than is the case with larger centres with pervasive responsibilities. Tocqueville arrived at similar conclusions (L806/132): Central power, however enlightened, however wise it may be, will never be able unaided to grasp all the details of a great people's life. It cannot do so because it is humanly impossible to achieve such an aim. If it nevertheless attempts to create on its own so many different things and have them work it will either be content with a result that is very incomplete, or it will exhaust itself in futile efforts.

491 The reasons for quality advantages in local solutions are their lesser proneness to information distortion - usually described as greater familiarity with local situations (L267/370) -, faster information treatment (L682a/15), and the more direct interest in sensible decisions of those who are at the same time their authors and the bearers of the consequences.
492 This last kind of interest was classically formulated in 1839 by the Earl of Durham in his famous report on Canada. Although concerned with the autonomy of a colony, his words are also applicable to problems of federalism (L384/166s): The colonists may not always know what laws are best for them, or which of their country-men are the fittest for conducting their affairs; but, at least, they have a greater interest in coming to a right judgment on these points, and will take greater pains to do so, than those whose welfare is very remotely and slightly affected by the good or bad legislation of these portions of the Empire. If the colonists make bad laws, and select improper persons to conduct their affairs they will generally be the only, always the greatest sufferers; and, like the people of other countries, they must bear the ills which they bring on themselves, until they choose to apply the remedy.

493 Society's demands have steadily risen during recent decades. This has brought about a corresponding growth in government responsibilities and increased political complexity (see Neidhart L573/39). The adequate response to this problem is not the design of a less complex, i.e. a more centralized political system, as is the current fad of political journalism and many scientists. The proper approach is rather the settingup of a differentiated governmental structure, as for instance a federalist one. This provides for requisite variety to deal with environmental complexity, thereby reducing the latter and making it amenable to processing (compare Baars L42/1, Huber L782/1160s, Ruffieux L782/1152). 494 Still another advantage of the federalist principle may be seen in its furthering of quasi-market mechanisms (Ostrom L593/230). The citizen sees with his own eyes that public tasks may be tackled differently and sometimes with unequal success. This may result in a quality-improving learning process. I refer here to considerations already presented in the context of federalism and innovation (no.434ss). 495 Finally, it is obvious that the many and mostly part-time public positions and functions which exist in a federalist system result in a much larger part of the population gaining political and public managerial expertise than is the case in unitary states. Cadre selection and preparation rest on a considerably broader base. 496 But local solutions are not uniformly better. They also have specific disadvantages. It is only partially true to say, for instance, that local government is more accessible to the individual citizen than big government, thereby making it more likely that decisions will be technically correct. It may well be that there is less openness in middle-sized communes than in larger communities which are more closely monitored by the media (Kock L430/49, L513/189ss). The elite might find it easier in middle-sized communities to push their private interests to the detriment of the public ones.

497 An additional negative point is the tendency of local solutions to consider only local costs and benefits and to neglect disadvantages for others (as to spillovers see no.472ss) and superior goals (e.g. an expenditure policy in agreement with national economic aims). Frey (L268/35) gives the example of hospitals or mountain resorts where city people pass their holidays. If it were but the citizens of the localities and Cantons concerned who decide on the service infrastructure the national welfare would be diminished. Intergovernmental competition may also result in the same disadvantage because self-interested behaviour of each government may sometimes result in the failure of each of them to take the most appropriate measures. Such is the case when no member state may raise its level of taxation because each of them fears that some of the richest taxpayers would in such an eventuality migrate to another one who, thereby, might solve its own revenue problems through a hold-out strategy. A similar illustration is the weakening of public control over large enterprises because of interstate competition in the United States (Stevenson L779/40). 498 Again, local solutions may be inadequate if they are confronted with material problems the extent of which transgresses the limited authority (responsibilities, competences, resources, and goals) of the individual decision centres (Scharpf L705/22). The reduction of a system's optimizing potential may also be considered a negative aspect, i.e. the lessening of the possibility of combining individual problems which have little to do with one another in such a way as to achieve a result which, from a technical point of view, may not be the best for each of them but which is optimal in a global perspective. Examples of this may be found in the distribution of scarce resources or in foreign policy making. 499 If we attempt a summing up of the aspects of technical adequacy, it appears that local solutions have great advantages which result from close distance. But this, to be meaningful, has to be seen in the context of an overarching system that sets the threshold values as well as the rules of the game and which provides for co-ordinating machinery.
500 A striking parallel to this embedding of a small system in a larger one is provided by Scott's inquiry into corruption, especially in the form of the former political machines in U.S. cities (L739/156): The general line of reasoning developed above suggests that the machine flourishes best at the subnational level,which is where it was confined in the United States. That is, the durability of this political form is maximized where there is an external guarantor of the electoral process, where the machine is part of a larger growing economy that can afford its expensive habits, and where its bosses do not have a monopoly of coercive authority. A large measure of the instability of machines in developing nations may thus derive from their national rather than local character.

E.1222 Quality as Public Satisfaction

Contents Index End

501 The State should offer those services that correspond to its citizens' preferences.... If we start from an assumption which is by no means incorrect, i.e. that in a given civil community there are no homogeneous value acceptations to deal with the organization of its economy and its environment, but that there are different groups that... differ in their concepts, it is easy to realize a federal structure's advantages. Federal decentralization is better apt to take into account the different preferences of the community's members than are extremely unitary states with their schematically uniform approach.... Political decisions always entail the submission of a more or less substantial minority to the wishes of the majority which, for them, results in a sacrifice of welfare. A federal structure lessens the numbers of those who find themselves in a minority position (Frey L268/27).

502 Before we may solve a problem we have to know what it is. It is again the social decision-making process that makes society's problems exist, i.e. perceived as such. This leads us to inquire federalism's part in the definition of problems. We may say in this context that the federalist perception is more responsive than a centralist one to the citizens' actual wishes. There are several reasons for this. Negative central aspects are the professionalized creation of demands and the lesser adaptability to local preferences and variations. Both factors have been dealt with above (nos.468, 488). Positive, non-central aspects flow from the more direct contact with the problems at hand (no.507) and with the option to choose among different sets of public services, that is to say with the introduction of some sort of market-mechanism. 503 The latter phenomenon may be illustrated by the opportunity which the citizens of a federation have to choose their place of residence among different member states with differing patterns of policies. Thus, the public services and the different levels of taxation are valued nearly as in a market-place (Frey L266/96, compare Ostrom L593/230, Pawlowsky L607/130). The same kind of choice is made by the students of the University of Michigan who prefer to be arrested by the local chief of police rather than by the more adamant sheriff. Or we may point to U.S. lawyers, who are often able to start an action in either a state or a federal court and who will obviously choose the court they consider more sympathetic to their case (L46/49). Tiebout has argued that public authorities at all levels are not very sensitive to citizens' wishes. But in a decentralized system this is not so important as long as there are variations of services offered amongst the various units of government which make it possible for the individual citizen to select that pattern of services and taxes which most closely corresponds to his personal preferences (L803/34, see King L419b/28ss, Pestieau L585/173ss, Walsh L844/18). A federation, in this view, appears as a continuing consumer plebiscite with the consequential gains in welfare as postulated by neoclassical market theory (Winkel L867/57ss). The Tiebout hypothesis sounds plausible. There are cases for which it may serve as a direct explanation, as for instance for migrations resulting from sudden local tax increases. But by and large the applicability of the hypothesis is limited. To vote with one's feet may be considerably impeded by the fact that the costs of migration are higher than the advantages expected elsewhere. This is especially so if we also include intangible

advantages and disadvantages (Frey L268/28). In addition to that, Buchanan and Goetz have demonstrated (L421/12, L844/19) that individuals have usually but very fuzzy ideas about the cost/benefit effects of their choice of residence. 504 Notwithstanding the actual relevance of the Tiebout hypothesis, for the reasons mentioned we may say that from the viewpoint of public satisfactions there are distinct advantages in locally organized problem perception. But we must take care not to be too dogmatic about this. It may be that local decision-making is oriented too exclusively to the interests of a small group because of a lack of accountability (no.496). It may also be that local majorities are very intolerant when dealing with minorities. In addition, far from encouraging wide discussion and the extensive canvass of alternatives, politics in the community setting can be oppressive and intolerant.... The pressures for ideological conformity and purity flourish in small and communal settings (Eisinger L197/147). Sometimes, because of that, minorities will find a better audience for their demands with central politicians than with local ones, because it is often easier to organize themselves and to wield clout at the national level. Blacks have learned to trust the federal government more than state and local governments because the federal government has been more protective of their rights and responsive to their needs (Baines L44/117, compare no.512, L46/46s, L533/65).
505 Riker (L660/153ss) uses this argument as a basis for his scathing criticism of U.S. federalism: The judgment to be passed on federalism in the United States is therefore a judgment on the values of segregation and racial oppression.... Thus, if in the United States one approves of Southern white racists, then one should approve of American federalism. If, on the other hand, one disapproves of the values of the privileged minority, one should disapprove of federalism. Thus, if in the United States one disapproves of racism, one should disapprove of federalism. These polemics, which cast away the good with the bad and which are somewhat fortuitous in the context of Riker's analysis, do not represent a balanced assessment. The real beneficiaries of federal programmes for underprivileged coloured minorities are often city-hall unions and bureaucracies that work for them rather than the minorities themselves (Long L490/24s, compare Derthick L637/6-2/121ss).

506 Here we are confronted with the most clear-cut conflict between federalism and democracy. But it is in reality a conflict between two dimensions of democracy: largescale and small-scale democracy. Before addressing myself in more detail to this problem (no.519ss) I will discuss further federalist solutions and public satisfactions, that is the standards of efficiency themselves. 507 It is rarely the case that a problem is technical to such a degree that the standards for its solution may be directly derived from the matter at hand. The yardstick is itself an object of the process of social decision making. In other words: efficiency is not absolute. In the final analysis it is a value judgment. To the extent that we deal with public services it therefore makes sense to use the appraisal of a service's putative beneficiaries or cost-bearers as a yardstick for the solution's efficiency. This, incidentally, is also the standard most in agreement with democratic theory. 508 Only recently has empirical research started to look into the relationship between consumer satisfaction with public services and organizational arrangements,

and this especially in the United States. Elinor Ostrom, for instance, has tested the validity of the hypothesis that amalgamation of police districts in urban agglomerations entails more efficient policing than it is possible for fragmented autonomous departments to achieve (L590/33ss). Several comparable agglomerations with differently organized police forces were analysed in depth. The results of her inquiry point rather in the opposite direction. It has become clear that most of the specialized technical services which can only be organized for a large area, and which are usually the starting point for projected mergers, may also be contracted for by small districts or made otherwise available to them. On the other hand, urban areas with small-scale police organizations show a marked tendency to greater satisfaction of inhabitants with the police services available to them. This is in addition to the fact that these departments are comparatively less costly. One of the reasons for these findings may be the fact that large police organizations invest more of their funds in administration and crime detection than small ones, which operate patrols directed to crime prevention and thereby more visible to citizens (V. Ostrom L593/225s). After statistical analysis of a variety of indicators E. Ostrom concludes (L590/70): The evidence presented here should not be interpreted to support contentions that all efforts to consolidate police departments are likely to lead to less effective or efficient performance. That some of the relationships appear to be curvilinear suggests that departments in the 10 to 76 range may have higher levels of performance on some variables than either the small or large departments. Consolidation of small departments into a medium-sized department may indeed increase effectiveness. However, the a priori judgment that very small departments are necessarily ineffective and should be eliminated is not supported by this evidence. In fact, the evidence finds the severe problems of law enforcement in the large departments. If future study commissions wish to focus on the most ineffective segment of the police industry, they should shift their focus to the large.
509 The California Local Government Task Force (L346/214), after polling some 1500 citizens, also arrived at the conclusion that citizen satisfaction with local government is directly related to small size (we should, however, bear in mind the possibility that smaller units of government in California may also be comparatively rich and not burdened with too many social problems). Conclusions similar to that of Elinor Ostrom are to be found in a survey of empirical studies about school organization (L590/73). Also a Harris poll of some 16'000 Americans came to the conclusion (L346/214): 1. Citizens found larger cities to be more disorganized than did their counterparts living in smaller cities, which are serviced by more units of government. 2. Citizens living in smaller units of local government tended to use their local governments more than those in large cities. 3. Citizens in smaller jurisdictions tended to have higher levels of satisfaction than those in large cities. An inquiry by Rogers (L669/19ss) about public service evaluation by the residents of two similar suburbs concluded: It became quite obvious that the assumptions supporting metropolitan consolidation were not supported by our findings. Consistently, residents of the small, independent community, Berry Hill, expressed higher degrees of satisfaction with 1) the level of public services provided, and 2) the concern of local officials for the welfare of the community than did residents of Woodbine - the community serviced by a large, metropolitan government (L669/32). 510 It is evident that these American findings must not be applied directly to other countries. But if we consider the critical attitude of the U.S. media towards local efficiency we may nevertheless assume that similar results may be arrived at in countries where criticism is not as harsh as there. In addition, these results are consistent with the theoretical considerations presented above.

511 Government organized according the principle of subsidiarity also entails greater citizen efficacy. The individual citizen's impact on policy formulation is relatively significant (Ostrom L593/229, Prewitt L736/223). Each merger of local units and every centralization of public responsibility will bring about higher political costs for the individual citizen. The probability that his preferences are similar to those of the median voter decreases; the probability that majority decisions deviate from his own wishes increases (Pawlowsky L607/131).
512 This holds true primarily for individuals who are in agreement with the local, homogeneous majority. The effectiveness of dissidents, on the other hand, will be smaller because of the absence of allies and the lesser importance of political competition. They will presumably find a more heterogeneous, larger governmental unit more responsive (Dahl/Tufte L156a/138, no.504).

513 One additional form of citizen effectiveness in a federally structured state is provided by the opportunity for citizens to voice their demands at all levels of government without taking into account the constitutional allocation of tasks. They may thus make one level of government their advocate in relation to another one, where they will directly intervene, or play one government against the other (May L528/6).
514 But to think, as it is sometimes done (e.g. Usteri L826/11), that in a federation the individual citizen's voice has a double weight because of the double majorities needed to carry constitutional referenda - votes aggregated nationally as well as by member states - is an error. Double weights can only be exercised by voters who happen to belong to their local majority but whose states are not the most populous ones. The individual citizens of the large states are disadvantaged by the double majority system.

515 If we sum up our findings about efficiency in relation to satisfactions, we arrive at very similar conclusions to those about efficiency as technical adequacy (no.499). There is a considerable array of both theoretical and empirical reasons for a local bias. Local solutions correspond often more closely to public interests than is the case with a more professionalized central approach. This holds true especially for solutions that have primarily local effects and where local adaptation is important. But today it has become difficult to define problems clearly as either local or national. And the public is not only local. There is also a regional one, a national one, etc. This again supports the case for a complex, pluricentral system. Or with Dahl and Tufte: No single type or size of unit is optimal for achieving the twin goals of citizen effectiveness and system capacity (L156a/138). 1) Only a complex polity consisting of a number of interrelated political units above and below the level of the nation-state has the capacity to respond adequately to the collective preferences of citizens of nationstates. 2) Therefore units at and below the level of the nation-state should not be wholly autonomous (L156a/25).
516 The most complex model of federalism is the public choice or marketplace model that is associated with the names of Olson, Tullock and the two Ostroms (especially L596/129ss). Its starting point is that of the production and consumption of public goods. The residents of a certain area form a collective-consumption unit for one or more public goods, as water provision, education, road maintenance, security, etc. Such goods are produced by production units (or industries), individuals, public organizations. The collective-consumption unit concerned (or another one) may act

as such a production unit. We now have a quasi-market mechanism as between the consumption and the production units. This is expected to bring about an optimal supply of public goods for the consumers. Marketplace federalism is consistent insofar as it is not limited to three levels of government: local, state, national. Its characteristic is the multitude and multiformity of special districts of every size. The emphasis lies with relatively small units. For this kind of federalism, overlaps and redundancies are not shortcomings. They are, on the contrary, desirable because they enhance market competition and are themselves influenced by the market to be economically efficient. 517 Up to now the public choice model has primarily served as an analytical tool for the explanation of a federalist allocation of functions as well as of complexity. It has also been used in inquiries on the relationship between efficiency and organizational arrangements in the production of public goods. Conscious attempts to make this model the basis for reorganizations are, on the other hand, not often found. Illustrations are provided by Californian local and county governments that invite tenders from each other for the provision of certain services (e.g. sewage treatment). The governmental unit with the best offer gets the contract for the whole area for a specified number of years (Lakewood plan L308/13s, L592/121). Another example is the voucher system for public grants-in-aid. Under this system education grants, for instance, are no longer directly paid to the schools. Instead parents receive vouchers that enable them to pay the fees, or part of the fees, of that school whose curriculum they consider best for their children. This forces schools to take into account the preferences of their consumers (Friedman L273/193ss, Hutchins L375/59s, King L419b/250ss, Porter L624/73s, Rivlin L665/135ss, Warner L846/97s). A certain relationship to public-choice theory -but without its essential market element- may also be seen in the organization of Yugoslav self-management. At least in theory this was based on contractual arrangements between production units, consumers' and other social organizations, local governments, etc. (Kardelj L407/242s, Stefanovic L772/18s).

518 It is to be expected that marketplace federalism has its critics. As to the market economy aspects, it has been noted that it would be an illusion to expect a perfect market. Therefore, the same kind of market distortions arise as in all market economies (Williams L46/46). As to citizen effectiveness it has been asked whether such a multitude of special units may be monitored and controlled by individuals (compare Frey L268/115, but also Tullock L820/33). As to intergovernmental relations, which are based on an integration of various consumer/producer units at the several levels, the marketplace model has been critized because it splits governmental units into mere production functions and neglects comprehensive concerns (Sharman L745/24). Or, in Vile's formulation (L596/24): You ('Ostrom') seem to see no role for the state as such. You describe a kind of anarchy, really, of individual producing units in particular functions, and nobody having the role or function of insuring the overall structure of the state. In your description there seems to be no role for some kind of collectivity which is responsible not for any specific function -not for producing national defense, as you put it, or education- but for performing a function which historically governments have performed, certainly since the 18th century, of being responsible for the collectivity. All this seems to be totally missing from what you describe. I find this profoundly disturbing from my point of view because it does seem to be a feudal kind of pluralism. It has to be said that Tullock (L820/32) does envisage units whose duty is the internalization of externalities brought about by the other units. This comes near to the function of government as alluded to by Vile. But it probably has to be accepted as a weakness of the federalist - or pluralist marketplace model that it is not very suitable for dealing with governmental functions that cannot be regarded as involving the production of goods without doing violence to the concept, as for instance justice, income redistribution, personal integration, etc.

(similarly Elazar L637/6-2/1s). The theory's usefulness for federalism is its analytical role in inquiries into the relationships between efficiency and size. This provides us with an economic counter to the centralizing tendency of the theory of spillovers proposed by another school of political economy (no.472ss).

E.123 Large-scale and small-scale democracy

Contents Index End

519 Federalism is non-democratic. This statement is correct. It is non-democratic that minorities may frustrate the will of a national majority when, for instance, it is necessary for constitutional amendments to be carried not only by a majority of the people but also by a majority of the member states. 520 Centralism is non-democratic. This statement, too, is correct. It is nondemocratic that democratically unimpeachable resolutions by local citizens may be set aside with a stroke of the pen by bureaucrats in a far-away centre. 521 Yet there is no contradiction. The two statements refer to different democracies. One is democracy conceived as majority decision (compare no.156ss). But then there is also democracy in the form of participation (no.184). Therefore both statements are false if we apply each of them to the other kind of democracy. It is obvious that large-scale and small-scale democracy will often come into conflict. Such a conflict may not be resolved logically, even where it is the same quality of democracy that leads to opposition between the large and the small area: Since the mid 1950's, the Supreme Court of the United States has intervened to limit the autonomy of local communities to determine social and moral policies that shape the local social climate, particularly in the areas of censorship, social behavior and the relationship between government and religion. The Court has done so on the premise that the nation as a whole must be the basis for determining 'contemporary community standards,' i.e. that it must be considered the primary community of the citizenry (Elazar L202/256). (It appears that the Court has become more cautious in this field.) 522 Why should national democracy be more democratic than the local one? Or, to give an international dimension to the question: Why should democratic Norway with some four million inhabitants be better qualified than democratic California which has about five times Norway's size? References to sovereignty and the lack of it attempt to answer this question. But the notion of sovereignty only shifts the problem without

solving it. Why should a national decision making process be preferred to that of a member state, simply because final jurisdiction is the essential element of sovereignty and only accrues to states directly subject to the law of nations? But if final jurisdiction is indeed the essential element of sovereignty, then we reason in logical circles if we attempt to base final jurisdiction on sovereignty (as to sovereignty compare no.274ss). 523 The same kind of flawed reasoning obtains where we postulate the preeminence of national over merely local interests. Prime Minister Trudeau said in Grande Prairie, Alberta, tonight... that the energy policy dispute between Alberta and the federal government is a simple conflict of interests. He said the problem can be solved by deciding what is best for the entire country (Broadcast News Summary 5.2.1975, Federal/Provincial Relations Division, Ottawa). There are no national interests per se. National they are if a national consensus makes them such. But why a national consensus should take precedence over a local one is precisely the question. It cannot also be the answer. 524 We might be tempted to say that national decision making is more democratic because more citizens contribute to it. This is true. But it is also true that the intensity of this participation is much less, as has been shown by Dahl/Tufte in the context of world democracy (L156a/2s): At the limit, if every smaller unit were simply an agent of a world government and political participation consisted entirely of voting in elections with several billion other citizens, what meaning would be left in the word democracy? Democracy that aspires to be something more than the simple mechanism of counting, and which sets out to guarantee the highest possible degree of individual influence and participation, is more easily organized on a small scale. But this, again, is not to say that small-scale democracy is better than the other type. Dahl/Tufte: The goal of maximizing citizen effectiveness on matters that are highly important to him can and does conflict with the effort to maximize the capacity of the system (and hence ultimately, though in a different sense, the citizen's effectiveness) for dealing with these matters. In the extreme case, a citizen could be maximally effective in a system of minimal capacity for dealing with major issues (e.g. international violence) or minimally effective in a system of maximal capacity for dealing with major issues (L156a/138). 525 We may take exception to the fact that in one member state concubinage is still prohibited when it is perfectly acceptable in another one (L833/19/133). Or that in the Swiss Canton of Thurgau car owners have to pay 96 francs for their licence, whereas it costs 266 francs in the neighbouring Canton of St.Gall (Basler Zeitung 28.4.1977). Or that in one Canadian province the federally prohibited possession of marijuana is prosecuted with vigour when this is not the case in the next province (L312/8s). But which of the several attitudes is the right one? It is impossible to deduce the answer from the nature of things. Neither by reason nor by deductive decision may we determine whether for some offence forty or rather forty minus one lashes... be just. But one lash too many is... injustice. - It is reason herself that acknowledges a certain, if restricted sphere and authority for accidentalness, contradiction, and appearances,

and that does not attempt to make such contradictions consistent and just. In these cases it is only the interest of implementation, the interest that there is, after all some decree or some decision,... that exists (Hegel L348/214). 526 Or might homogeneity be a standard? Bismarck considered 'the stimulating friction of 25 German centres' to be an advantage. The present time prefers the smooth synchronism of the eleven parts. Quick lateral connections, seamless synthetics, standardized products, as well as rationalized or, in the near future, automated procedures, these appear to be the average citizen's wants in the area of public administration, too (Schneider L721/19). Safeguarding the uniformity of social conditions (Wahrung der Einheitlichkeit der Lebensverhltnisse), as postulated by the Bonn Basic Law (article 72/2), is taken to mean rules that are the same on all levels, and that exclude or considerably impede exceptions and experimentation. Politicians and civil servants have adopted this goal thus defined and use it to justify not only the contents of policies but also, and even more so, organizational arrangements for vertical co-ordination (Baars L41/185). Kock (L430/52): In the constitutional reality of the German Federal Republic the principle of uniformity of social conditions has to a large degree triumphed over the federalist principle of separation via the evolution of social legislation and the extensive use of concurrent legislation (for this type of legislation the criterion of Einheitlichkeit der Lebensverhltnisse had originally been introduced, see also L433/20). 527 As soon as national standards have asserted themselves and some new sector of public activity has been centralized, a new democracy deficit often emerges: lack of citizen participation. Then the same people, such as the U.S. progressives, who advocated national guidelines start to look for ways and means to infuse them with local democracy. This is usually done through mechanisms of decentralization (compare L264b/870). But a disappointment is waiting for them: Whereas contemporary liberals generally endorse warmly the idea of decentralization for the sake of greater participation by the people in their government, their friendship is cooled by the fact that administrative decentralization can be a cover for inequalities and perhaps inequities that may exist between different administrative units (Koritansky L443/63). And thus their labours begin anew. 528 In the central decision-making process of federations, an additional type of conflict can be added to federalist competition between large-scale and small-scale democracy. This is illustrated by the requirement of a double majority -of citizens and of the member states- for amendments to the federal constitution, as is the case in Australia and in Switzerland. This conflict of two different bases for the legitimation of national decisions also cannot be solved by logic (Messmer L542/228s, Wheare L858/142,215). On the one side national majorities appear as the natural arbiter for national questions. On the other side it is possible to justify regional weighting of votes with the fact that individuals do not live as isolated atoms. They are rather living as groups which are differentiated primarily through the manner opinions are formed (traditions, economic interests, impact of regional media, associations, etc.). Given the fact that voters' opinions are to a large extent conditioned by their group affiliations, a

case can be made for granting these groups an independent voice. If universal and equal franchise be a necessity for nationally legitimizing governance and preventing its disintegration (no.156ss), then we should also take into consideration that the real danger is not defection of individuals but of groups. It is these groups that have to be integrated. 529 To recapitulate: The tension between large-scale and small-scale democracy cannot be disposed of logically. It may only be relieved by continually balancing both kinds of democracy. Here we face a process of social optimization that guarantees just so much national or local democracy as is allowed at any given moment by the population's perceptions of the correct degree of consideration for national or local interests. Federalism provides this mechanism for optimization, and federalism is also the result of such a one: If the opinion of a majority is a sufficient guide for public policy in a community, then it is unlikely that a federal system will have been established in that community. The fact that it has been established is a clear indication that such a majority is not an adequate guide (Livingston L485/314).
530 Today and in the foreseeable future, people will live in a multiplicity of political units. Because democratic theorists, with notable exceptions, have focused on the problem of democratizing one sovereign unit -first the city then the nation-state- they have overlooked the problem of democratizing a political system that consists of small primary associations in which direct democracy is at least theoretically possible to larger entities in which direct citizen rule is impossible. Rather than conceiving of democracy as located in a particular kind of inclusive sovereign unit, we must learn to conceive of democracy spreading through a set of interrelated political systems, sometimes though not always arranged like Chinese boxes, the smaller nesting in the larger. The central theoretical problem is no longer to find suitable rules, like the majority principle, to apply within a sovereign unit, but to find suitable rules to apply among a variety of units, none of which is sovereign (Dahl/Tufte L156a/135).

E.13 Intellectual sthetics and Federalism

Contents Index End

531 Our environment is immensely complex. To us it appears as but loosely structured chaos. The political reality of even a single country is so complicated that an individual person cannot grasp it in its totality. But human intellect strives for clarity. Man has to see things as a whole. He wants to be at peace with the world. He wants it to be meaningful and certain. When the world is uncertain and lacks meaning man is ontologically insecure and experiences anxiety (van Gunsteren L320/139). Scientific intellect especially wants to understand things (for the end of

Understanding is not to prove and find reasons, but to know and believe Carlyle L121/190). The scientific approach is to reduce complexity to that which is understandable and distinct. 532 Such reduction is an indispensable tool for scientific analysis. There is no doubt about its admissibility. As a method it becomes questionable only when we attempt to change reality itself to make it understandable. This is inadmissible where it is mainly due to some intellectual need for clarity or, in other words, to sthetics. Lawyers, having been trained in the rigours of a normative system without logical contradictions or gaps, often succumb to the temptation to construe life in such a way as to make it fit their own mental requirements (this has already been pointed out by Weber L850/30). 533 This school of thought is rather at a loss when it has to deal with federalism's many disparities of size, power, and interests, its abundance of overlaps and redundancies, or its conflicts and contradictions. The categories of such thinking are hierarchy, co-ordination, disentanglement, etc. (L861/96s). Federations appear as decentralized unitary states not only legally but also in reality (compare L782/1028). Conflicts amongst member states are not taken as normal. They have to be prevented through co-ordinative mechanisms (L255/730, no.525s). Federal allocation of functions appears as a jungle which has to be cleared with the help of new task sheets for central and state governments (these analogies have been used in recent Swiss discussions). 534 It is, then, only consistent if reform proposals follow hierarchical models, e.g. conceiving federation as if it is a business combine with branch offices. Or if they superimpose a co-ordination network on it, as Sundquist did for the United States (L792/277s): In this study we have presented a series of models that, taken together, will constitute a system of intergovernmental program co-ordination extending from the President through the federal regional centers and the states to the communities.... The principles and the doctrine we have sought to outline. The guidance, however, can come from but a single source of authority - the President. The Swiss central government's alleged weakness of co-ordination and performance is to be answered with increased framework legislation and more intensive co-operation (Saladin L691). 535 It is not so much the reform proposals themselves that astonish me. They are often quite reasonable. But what is striking is the incongruity between analysis and conclusions. The analysis of the actual state of affairs is nearly always quite superficial. In Switzerland, for instance, up to now there has never been a broad empirical study to demonstrate the real disadvantages stemming from the ostensibly much too interlaced division of functions between the federal government and the cantons. Such disadvantages are always assumed to be obvious, resulting from the actual allocation of powers, and removable. Neither is it asked whether a modern division of functions may be comprehensively disentangled at all, except in some particular areas (compare L264b/894ss). The fact that the actual situation is difficult to survey is sufficient proof for the observer that it has to be changed. (Edelman

L191/186: Observation of politics is not simply an effort to learn what is happening but rather a process of making observations conform to assumptions.) In truth, the reforms proposed will not usually bring about large scale disentanglement. With common tasks, framework legislation, etc. they will actually lead to event more complex entanglements. But these would be easier to conceive intellectually because there would not be co-existence of competing powers where co-ordination is achieved in a not always evident process. Such powers would now be part of a hierarchical and uniformly structured order. It is ignored that there might be a price to be paid in undesirable consequences for a change whose greater clarity is but formal. Under the new organizational arrangements the multitude of affairs that have to be dealt with by government will still require a corresponding multitude of mechanisms for the gathering, transmission, and processing of information. The actual complexity of decision making in unitary France is probably not much less than in the United States of America. But as it takes place within a closed system it appears to be much less complex than in the United States, where all the intermediary levels are evident to the public eye.
536 Ostrom: The essential difficulty in all of these analyses is that they are based upon a logic of ideal forms. The costs of overlapping jurisdiction and fragmented authority are emphasized. No effort is made to assess the costs of large-scale bureaucracies. Such one-sided forms of cost calculations produce an inevitable bias against federal solutions, and in favor of extensive merger of political jurisdictions with increased reliance upon larger and larger bureaucracies (L592/201). Perhaps we need to be more attuned to the principle of relative advantage in our policy analyses than to the logic of ideal forms (L592/122). Weidner: The patterns of national-state relations can be changed or 'improved'. But since these patterns reflect the values of individuals engaged in these relations, any change in the patterns is likely to heighten value conflict, at least temporarily (L853/216). 537 Tocqueville (L806/377): It is true that democracy ('Tocqueville has the federal democracy of the United States in mind'), even where local circumstances and popular inclinations permit it to maintain itself, does not present the aspect of administrative regularity and methodical order in government. Democratic liberty does not execute every one of its concerns with the perfection of intelligent despotism;... but, in the long run, it achieves more than the latter. It does things less well, but it does more of them. 538 Van Gunsteren (L320/145s): Inter-dependence and complexity make it seem imperative to view the world as whole, to take a universal point of view... The success of modern science is tempting. We want to use it in the public realm... We use scientific theories as if they were the reality in which we have to act.... But notice that a two-step process is involved in realizing this kind of problem solution. Before we can start bringing about the changes which are possible in terms of the theorist's model, we must make the world fit for the application of the model. Before we can transfer the method and results of science to it, public life must acquire the characteristics of a controlled experiment. It must be constructed, controlled and isolated.

539 It would be wrong to simply dismiss reform and criticism of federalism as intellectual sthetics. But it is an equally grave mistake not to be aware of this motive. I, for one, maintain that it is a much more common reason than is generally realized. The satisfying impression of clarity that intellectuals may gain from reducing federalist complexity through centralization is quite often paid for dearly with the resulting alienation of the citizen from his political environment (compare Imboden L386/94).

E.2 FEDERALISM AND THE POLITICAL SYSTEM'S STABILITY

540 This bundle of functions of federalism has to do with crisis management, conflict resolution (including demographic integration), and legitimation. With each of these considerations the stability of the political system is in the foreground. But in order to forestall possible misunderstandings I stress that the delimitation between these functions and those of political learning capacity just dealt with is not rigid. Both groups of functions interact, and both are equally concerned with the systemic goal of self-preservation (no.024). The differentiation of the two bundles is based on centres of gravity that make the relationships within each appear more pronounced than those between them.

E.21 Stabilization and System Reliability

Contents Index End

541 It is a matter of fact that the organization of all federations appears to be messy. It shows evidence of redundancies, overlap, disproportions, inconsistent distribution of powers, etc. But once we free ourselves from the popular, and psychologically understandable (no.531ss), conception that redundancies are of necessity inefficient, then we are ready to look at the possibility that they may also have a systemic function. 542 From the viewpoint of information theory, any federation's units are part of a system of checks and balances. Each entity acts as a speed-up or brake mechanism for the whole system, thus regulating the rate or direction of change of the over-all system. The system of checks is based upon self-regulation, and it can function

relatively independently of other systems because of its circular characteristics. The major system as such is not solidly knit and represents really an envelope for the various sub-systems (Landau L449/182). According to Platt (L449/183) this model is virtually equivalent conceptually to a system of negative feedbacks -what engineers call 'stabilization feedbacks'. These work to prevent stresses from building up to the point where some part of the structure breaks down 'suddenly and dangerously'. When properly operative, they produce a dynamic equilibrium that continually responds to pressure, allowing the system to change in an orderly fashion and in a responsible period of time.... The system does not assume good will - it doesn't need to.
543 For an illustration see Pranger L628/105. Platt sees the United States as such a self-stabilizing system. According to him the Fathers of the Constitution understood the principle of negative feedbacks much better than many of today's political theorists. Landau, on the other hand, also stresses certain limitations to this approach. Thus, in mechanical models the centre that triggers the disturbance or feedback is placed outside the system. But in political systems this signal usually originates from within the system itself. And as a political system always pursues many diverse and partially inconsistent goals, the signal is not always clear and unambiguous. In addition to that, there are not always sufficient feedback channels available in political reality.

544 Another guide to the understanding of the possible functionality of overlap in federal systems is provided by the theory of redundancies. If, with respect to a particular system, the probability of a failure is 1 in 100, what would the probability of simultaneous failure be if there were 2 such systems, each statistically independent, each rated equally? What would the probability for simultaneous failure be for 3 such systems; for four, etc.? For 2, the probability would be 1 in 10'000; for 3, 1 in a million; for 4, 1 in a hundred million. The reader will notice that the probability of failure here decreases exponentially with arithmetic increases in duplication. This principle lies at the foundation of the theory of redundancy - which, properly applied, reduces the injurious effects of trauma and thereby enhances the reliability of a system (Landau L449/187). In its modern form, this question was posed by Von Neumann as follows: Is it possible to take a set of individually unreliable units and form them into a system 'with any arbitrarily high reliability?'... Yes - any system can be made more reliable, more effective, more responsive, more able to withstand shock and damage than any of its parts: provided that sufficient and appropriate redundancies are introduced. These must follow the multiplication theorem or product rule of independent events and this means that systems must be so organized that when parts fail they do not and cannot impair other parts. The idea is to multiplex a system, to duplicate its parts and to arrange these in parallel; to multiply the number of independent channels for any structure or function where failure can be disastrous. Where such arrangements are incorporated into a system, the breakdown of any one part cannot and does not irreparably damage the whole (Landau L449/187s). 545 Landau sees such redundancies in the architecture of the American Constitution - and we might add in that of other federal constitutions - at every turn. What appears is a truly messy system - one that is anathema to our prevailing conceptions of a viable organization (L449/188). Messy, but more stable. This is an advantage of federations that had already been pointed out by Montesquieu (L551/9/1): This state may perish in one place without perishing in other places. The popular image of that is the ocean

liner with its several independent air chambers. Even with a leak, such a vessel continues on its course, when another ship whose air spacing is not divided in compartments would already have sunk (thus Aubert L782/1082s, Bryce L96/353). 546 Thus, federalism is an organizational postulate for crisis management. If by ill chance, some day, the nations' authorities should be overturned by some cataclysm, there would be no power vacuum in our country. There would still be 25 other centres of decision (Aubert L782/1083, compare L184/18s, L297/52, L593/230). And it is not only the disintegration of a system that may be prevented. The reconstruction of destroyed parts is easier because of their connection with the rest of the system (van Gunsteren L320/152).
547 A very old and quite interesting case in point is provided by the history of the federally organized order of the Benedictine monks. Without the reception net of the other independent abbeys it would sometimes have been quite difficult, if not impossible, to restore the spiritual discipline and the economic base of monasteries afflicted by internal or external disasters (Moulin L562/2). Such considerations have also found a constitutional expression on the Comores (C44): If the regular functioning of the federation's constitutional institutions should be interrupted by force, this constitution's dispositions concerning such institutions are suspended, and every island exercises provisionally on its territory the totality of the powers previously attributed to the Federal Republic. 548 The evolution of modern large-scale technology with its highly efficient energy and communications networks demonstrates what may happen if a system contains an insufficient number of redundancies. These networks are often at the same time highly complex and economically structured. Therefore the coincidence of unrelated and accidental disturbancies may -and will because it is statistically to be expected- cause system failures of great magnitude. This was the case when on 9 November 1965 New York experienced a fourteen hours' failure of electricity which caused the complete breakdown not only of public transportation but also of private traffic, because petrol pumps depended on electricity. Or we may think of the breakdown of all telephone connections in a part of the same city during several days in autumn 1969 because of the temporary slight overload of one exchange (L828/63). The Italian writer Vacca (L828/12ss) deduces from such incidents the thesis that a complete breakdown of our civilization must be statistically expected somewhere in the future as the result of a simultaneous paralysis of several of the continuously growing and increasingly vulnerable technological megasystems.

549 Seen in this light, federal redundancies may be considered as factors of safety. But whether the highly centralized nature of today's federations leaves enough independence to member states to provide viable redundancies is a somewhat open question. The practices of co-operative federalism especially (no.346ss) have reduced autonomy at all levels, but primarily at that of the member states, through horizontal and vertical interlacing. Therefore Landau envisages the disappearance of territorially organized federal forms of redundancy and their replacement by functional/technical forms of organization (L449/191ss). But it may be difficult to do without the territorial element if we accept that the existence of several highly independent centres of power is the critical element in the theory of redundancies, and that in a democratic polity all these centres have to be democratically legitimized. We might conceive pluralist models. But according to experience it is difficult to legitimize them without recourse to some form of territoriality. Even today, it would probably be easier to reduce, or at least not to increase, institutional intergovernmental entanglements, rather than to try to democratize functional/technical forms of decentralization.

550 Redundancies may guarantee stability. But they also entail costs. Thus the existence of several independent centres of power has a retarding effect on common decision making, favouring conservative positions rather than progressive ones (see Eckstein L189/193s, Walsh L844/32, no.436). From a systemic point of view, this will only be a problem when the pressure of demands grows to such an extent that the slowness of their processing brings about a substantial loss of welfare for the population, or endangers the viability of the political system itself (Scharpf L705/20s). But these are situations that are rather less likely to occur than critics of the federal allocation of tasks or of institutions of direct democracy assume. If they do occur, it appears empirically that federations have usually been able to introduce the necessary acceleration mechanisms (emergency legislation, executive delegation, etc.). Under normal circumstances, the federal system itself constrains the pressure of demands (no.418ss).

E.22 Conflict Resolution

Contents Index End

551 Any political system may be seen as an optimizing mechanism which, to remain stable, has to balance many and often contradictory interests in such a way as to give no population group the impression that, in the long run at least, its aspirations are unacceptably passed over (foreign policy stresses being left aside in this context). A stable political system is one that is characterized by successful reduction and treatment of latent tensions (Eckstein L190/256). Conflicts are integrated within the system. 552 As to conflicts we will find in the foreground either factual aspects or demographic ones. Federalist organization deals with both. 553 Of the two applications, federalism's contribution to the solution of factual conflicts is less pronounced. We may for instance think of the parallelism of centres of power -national and regional ones- which make it possible to pursue simultaneously different interests, thereby rendering a conflict-prone decision for or against one of them unnecessary if the interests are not irreconcilably contradictory (L753/8). The shifting play of majority decisions at different levels takes the edge off their rigour (Lehmbruch L465/95s, Ostrom L595/252ss). The necessity to take other autonomous centres of power into account furthers the search for consensual and thus low-conflict solutions instead of relying on majority decisions. (This, on the other hand, makes politics lack in entertainment value for the spectators, as for instance in Switzerland; see also Friedrich L277/58.) In addition to this, it is a fact that dissenting opinions are usually relevant and able to produce conflict only if they combine in a group. In small communities this threshold of dissent often cannot be crossed because dissenting

opinions remain isolated (Dahl/Tufte L156a/91). Because of this, and without attempting a value judgment, federalist organization is, again, in its tendency minimizing conflict and thus stabilizing the system.
554 An additional type of conflict, specific to federalism, is based on the fact that in federations there are authorities at different levels which may act against each other (Riker/Schaps L753/8s). But this form of conflict may also be seen as having positive aspects from the viewpoint of the division of powers (nos.424ss, 631ss).

555 Nevertheless, there are clear limits to federalism's ability to deal with factual conflicts. It cannot solve basic social conflicts. Scharpf's considerations (L702/52s) on the pluralist structure in general apply here, too. It tends to politically frustrate those groups that strive for large-scale changes in the social balance.... The pluralist model... is a model for the peaceful accommodation of the limited goals of basically saturated groups. Its specific danger is the possible accumulation of repressed conflicts. These will either have to be forcibly suppressed, abandoning the model's liberal aims, or they may destroy the pluralist system itself in an eruptive crisis. We are faced here with the central, irreconcilable contradiction of democracy and federalism or, to be more specific, between large-scale and small-scale democracy. For all that, this conflict is to some extent mitigated by the fact that all participants belong to an overarching system and are involved through communal institutions, media, etc. in a common process of social learning that furthers conflict resolution, albeit with a considerable sacrifice of time.
556 Redistribution of incomes and wealth involves such a basic conflict in all classical federations. The redistribution postulate is successfully advanced by political groups mainly in densely populated areas and at the national level. To this we may add that subnational units - member states and local governments - are restricted in their opportunities of pursuing drastic redistributive policies. This is because of intergovernmental competition and the mobility of taxpayers, which seems to be greater within federations than internationally (Oates L585/5, Pommerehne L623/285s, Wright L871/59). But it is evident that in federations there is redistribution of incomes and wealth. It would be interesting to investigate empirically the differences in pace and in extent that may be due to the federal structure.

557 More important than federalism's stabilizing contribution to factual conflicts is its role in relation to demographic ones.

E.221 Integration of Individuals

Contents Index End

558 Federalism as an integrative principle in the national context has lost its significance as a historically active force (Hesse L356/31s). This is an assertion about the Federal Republic of Germany (for a similar statement about Switzerland see Neidhart L782/1047). It is at the same time right and wrong. It is right insofar as the historical task of integrating the many petty states into one German national state has been accomplished (L454/32). It would be wrong, however, to think that federalism has no longer a function in maintaining this unity. And it is too narrow in suggesting that the integrative role of federalism is limited to nation building. 559 What, then, is integration? Seen from the standpoint of the political system, individuals and groups are integrated when and insofar as their attitude shows loyalty, i.e. a generalized readiness to support the system (Deutsch L166/126). In its relation to the integration of individuals, federalism has two tasks: integration within the political community as such and integration in the different levels of government. 560 Integration is mainly a matter of emotion, the sense of living under the right order. Or as Cuttat (L731/147) once expressed it in the context of a Swiss problem of integration: The Jura problem is not to be explained in five minutes, not with historical and economical reasons. But it will be solved when the baker around the corner and the farmer approve of the state they live in. Surveys (e.g. L156a/14s) show that under normal circumstances it is easier to have affective relationships with smaller communities rather than with large ones. This has probably less to do with rational reasoning (L606/62) than with greater immediacy and accessibility. 561 Still, such accessibility is not necessarily accessibility of political decision making. In certain respects it is even obvious that such accessibility is less at the local level than it is at the national one, where the political process is closely monitored by the media as well as being exposed to party competition (Zoll L882/37ss). Easier assessability of the benefits of local projects may be of limited importance in this respect, although economists emphasize its role (L607/128). It is more probable that the feeling of dealing with known and understandable things is the decisive element. This feeling is strengthened by education, by daily contact with one's environment, by the greater intelligibility of local problems (it is easier to envisage a school building than it is to understand a law on vocational training), and by the fact that local happenings are more likely than distant ones to be related to individuals one personally knows.
562 In urban agglomerations, the integration of citizens is lessened by the effects of spatial differentiation of living, working, recreation, etc. This differentiation makes identification with one's political environment more difficult (L782/878s). Integration in megacities is especially difficult: either there are no integrating intermediary groups and the result is political indifference, or integration takes place in neighbourhoods (e.g. underprivileged minorities in New York) that have no political function and the result for the polity is disintegration.

563 A further integrative element in local areas is the heightened chance of participation. One single vote carries more weight in a village of some 1'000 inhabitants than in a country of one million. But even here psychological aspects seem

to be the decisive factor. Comparative analysis (Dahl/Tufte L156a/65) reveals an interesting phenomenon: actual participation and a sense of conviction about its political influence seems to correlate not with a country's size but rather with the size of its subdivisions. It appears that the critical factor is not the absolute weight of the individual vote but its relative importance in relation to the weights at different levels of government.
564 This may explain the fact that in Sweden, according to an exhaustive inquiry (L156a/64ss), such conviction of effective civic participation is to be found in communes up to 8'000 inhabitants, when Elazar (L201/277) sets the threshold at 100'000 for the United States. On the other hand, actual participation may be much less, as for instance in the Swiss township of Solothurn where, of some 15'000 inhabitants, usually only 20 to 40 and rarely more than a few hundred citizens take part in the communal assembly (L782/847).

565 As I have pointed out at the beginning of this chapter (no.559), federalism is not only concerned with an individual's integration in the polity as such, but also with his integration in the different levels of government. This function is of primary importance when federations are founded. But even when they have been established for some time, it is still vital. 566 Historically, the central government's main problem has been to prevent a loyalty deficit. Patriotism was state patriotism. The states were living, organic persons: the union was an arrangement (Wilson L863/1076). Through the federalist mechanism of indirect loyalty of those who were Virginians first and by virtue of this citizens of the United States, an American sense of nationality was able to emerge outside the confines of an elite (for Mexico: L27/401s). This graduated arrangement still obtains in countries like Switzerland where, at least in some cantons, people still think of themselves as citizens of the canton first and only then as Swiss (L675/132, L782/899, L813/81; generally: L188/250, L659/315, L670/48). This transfer of civic loyalty has centralizing effects and may lessen identification with intermediary levels (Hahn L327/72, Merriam L541/304, Patterson L606/63, Riker L660/104,110). But as long as the transfer of loyalty is not complete, the emphasis may be shifted without doing away with the function of simultaneous integration in different levels.
567 This mechanism of integration is not always without problems. The difficulties are illustrated by Canada, where a strong nation-wide sense of nationality is still lacking (Noel L581/127). System identification, pride, commitment, and loyalty may be associated with political subsystems as well as with the national entity, and a sequence or matrix of identifications may be either cleavage-tending or consensus-building. A high degree of pride, loyalty, and identification with Indiana may contribute to national unity in the particular circumstances of the United States, but identification with Quebec contributes to cleavage and system-periling disunity in Canada (Patterson L606/55, also McRae L532/253). In Canada loyalty and thus integration of many Franco-Canadians does not cross the borders of Quebec. - In the United States, on the other hand, General Lee's dilemma Am I a Virginian or an American (L599a/102) would today no longer cause problems. 568 To my mind, Dahl/Tufte's theory (L156a/140s), that successful integration in federations presupposes a hierarchy of loyalties where the strongest loyalty is to the central government, is going too far. This may be necessary, but hardly likely, where there are very deep tensions or conflicts of interest between the central government and the member state. The theory also does not take into account the integrative faculties of consociational democracy (no.143ss).

569 An illustrative document on the theme of loyalty transfer is Philipp Anton von Segesser's letter of 9 February 1848, in the founding period of the Swiss federation (L578/1938/50): The only interest in Switzerland I have is the fact that the Canton of Lucerne - this is my country - is in it. If the Canton of Lucerne should no longer exist as a free and sovereign part of the Swiss confederation, I couldn't care more about the latter than I do about the greater or the lesser Tartary.

E.222 Integration of Groups

Contents Index End

570 Tarlton makes a distinction between symmetrical and asymmetrical federalism (according to L173/15s). The ideal type of symmetrical federation consists of member states which are exactly similar as to their size, population, economy, language, climate, etc. It is obvious that, in such a federation, integration of groups would be no problem if we leave the question of governing large countries aside. But it would also be difficult to justify politically the existence of such a homogeneous federation (Wolff L833/21/138). In reality, all modern federations are asymmetrical.
571 Even where the demographic and other characteristics of member states were largely similar in the beginning - this has been advanced for Australia (L99/268, L660/113) -, the development of distinct political and social institutions as well as different economic evolution may lead to clearly differentiated member states. Australian federalism is a case in point.

572 All federations show demographic differences. In this context, we usually think first of linguistic diversity, which may also be the basis of ethnic differences. Thus, in nine of today's twenty federations (no.389) language is a major integration problem. But from a comparative viewpoint it is not as central as it is sometimes held to be. Of the six classical federations, only two are plurilingual in the sense that language is an essential element of territorial organization: Canada and Switzerland (as to linguistic minority questions in other European federations see Viletta L835a/16ss). Plurilingualism was quite widespread in Europe before the emergence of the democratic nation state in the nineteenth century, and it was not a major political issue (Masnata L515/127). With the exception of Switzerland it was not a factor leading to federation. It was rather a decisive factor in the building of monolinguistic nation states with, perhaps, linguistic minority problems. 573 There are other important demographic distinctions: religion, culture, economy, history, institutions, politics, media range, etc. They may all lead to feelings of we/them which differentiate groups and which lead to a community of knowledge, sentiments, and values within the group (Berg-Schlosser L61/86), to a community of

recollections in Mill's words (L547/360). We see these ('orientations') as contributing to a milieu in which the recognition of common interests and concerns can emerge into a group consciousness, one with potential for political mobilization (Schwartz L736/241). (In connection with intergroup diversity, compare the text on legitimation and federalist political culture, no.602ss.)
574 It is often assumed that in federations there exist different political views even in neighbouring and demographically quite similar member states. In countries that hold nationwide referenda this is also empirically evident. But there are very few scientific analyses that address this topic. Amongst them we find Stevens's study of the political attitudes in the border region of Michigan, Ohio, and Indiana (L777/111ss). Summing up his findings, he says (L777/124s): The states do make a difference. We found that people do different things from state to state in the border region. We found differences in what they know about politics. We found fewer - but still some - differences in their attitudes and their opinions. And we found that the border itself has an effect on attitudes... which was not anticipated. As our investigation moved away from the specific and the concrete... to the nonspecific and the abstract... the findings diminished, the pay-off decreased.

575 One of federalism's mechanisms for group integration is member state autonomy provided through the federal division of powers (this is treated in detail in L264b/886ss). Such autonomy allows national minorities to become local majorities in questions which are of particular importance to them (L203/59s, L829/174s, L834/32). It is thus usually the minorities that place particular emphasis on member state autonomy (for a Swiss deviation and its reasons see Bucher L773/46). This emphasis will shift when majorities change (for Belgium see L180/334). Minorities become majorities by simple division. Democracy is increased in direct proportion to the decrease in the size of the unit (Zwerin L884/147). The price of local autonomy and, thereby, of local democracy is a certain loss in national freedom of action and in large-scale democracy. The states' rights discussion on the issue of slavery in the United States showed that this price may in certain cases also endanger integration (L541/253). 576 Member state participation in national decision making (L264b/1301ss) is another integrative instrument. The groups as such gain a politically significant position which, as a rule, privileges minorities. Their political weight approximates that of the more populous parts of the country (e.g. in one of the two houses of the national Parliament). The latter are predominant in other areas (e.g. in nationwide referenda). The whole is a finely attuned system of interlocking guarantees against mutual infringements. Thus it has integrative effects. 577 It is not easy to justify these apparent minority privileges in view of the importance of numbers for the acceptance of democracy. Mill thus criticized local rights when discussing the case for a unitary state (L547/270): But I cannot see why the feelings and interests which arrange mankind according to localities should be the only ones thought worthy of being represented; or why people who have other feelings and interests, which they value more than they do their geographical ones, should be restricted to these as the sole principle of their political classification. The notion that Yorkshire and Middlesex have rights apart from those of their inhabitants, or that Liverpool and Exeter are the proper objects of the legislator's care, in

contradistinction to the population of those places, is a curious specimen of delusion by words. Chief Justice Warren's argument in the famous case of Reynolds v. Sims, where the Court declared unconstitutional a scandalous instance of gerrymandering of state electoral districts follows the same direction (377U.S.533, 1964, cited in L409/144): Legislators represent people, not trees or acres. Legislators are elected by voters, not farms or cities or economic interests. 578 On the other hand, this democratic rhetoric may be countered in Madison's words (L334/49): If it be true that all governments rest on opinion, it is no less true that the strength of opinion in each individual, and its practical influence on his conduct, depend much on the number which he supposes to have entertained the same opinion. The reason of man, like man himself, is timid and cautious when left alone, and acquires firmness and confidence in proportion to the number with which it is associated. Or with Bryce (L97/253): In examining the process by which opinion is formed, we cannot fail to note how small a part of the view which the average man entertains when he goes to vote is really of his own making. His original impression was faint and perhaps shapeless: its present definiteness and strength are mainly due to what he has heard and read. He has been told what to think, and why to think it.... Each man believes and repeats certain phrases, because he thinks that everybody else on his own side believes them. (Also compare L238/45, L461/40.) 579 Be this as it may, it is a fact that social groups can be understood from the viewpoint of information treatment. They appear as networks of privileged information whereas there are information barriers towards the outside world (Frenkel L782/1056, Schwartz L736/9s). In this view the media structure and subsystems of parties and associations (no.682ss) appear to be the essential elements of regional opinion forming. There is no logically stringent answer to the question of whether it is more correct to have each individual's vote carry the same weight, or whether it is better to provide for an equal weighting of families of votes (thereby treating individuals unequally). The decisive aspect is the common conviction that the yardstick in use is the right one, and the readiness of the different interests to accept the results of this system. We are, therefore, not faced with a problem of correct perception but with one of legitimation. This problem is solved in all federations otherwise they would not be federations - by a more or less regionally unequal weighting of votes.
580 How this may work out in practical politics is shown by a statement of the French Swiss member of the Council of States Guisan (L782/1070): As to the political problem we have perfectly understood that the game of minorities is to make the majority feel guilty when they abuse their strength. There you have your minority protection, and every regulation only tends to lessen this bad conscience. The francophone Swiss have to make the germanophone Swiss feel ill at ease if the latter do not take into account their minority position. Or we may add an Anglo-Canadian minister's insight (L753/208): Certainly Quebec has more weapons than the other provinces. The biggest weapon in Quebec is that it is the only province that could wreck Confederation. This is their main weapon. They can make the threat and be taken seriously.

581 In the preceding lines two of the elements of my definition of federalism (no.210), local autonomy and participation in central decision making, have been

treated as mechanisms for integration. But we have not yet answered the question why these mechanisms should have an integrative and stabilizing influence for the whole system. They could just as easily have the opposite effect. Local autonomy could be used as a power base for the systematic thwarting of national goals. Participation could be a pretext for the paralysis of central decision making (experiences with federalism in the Third World have often had this result, Frenkel L261/262). 582 For successful integration there have to be further prerequisites. Federal culture is amongst the most important ones. I shall deal with it below (no.602ss). Another important element is provided by the so-called cross-cutting cleavages (Lipset, Lijphart, and others, L480/7ss, L481/75ss). 583 We may illustrate cross-cutting cleavages in the following way. In everyday politics there are nearly always competing interests. In federations many of them correspond to individual member states, i.e. they represent majority opinions in different member states. If, for instance, political cleavages always separate the same member states there is a clear danger that they will be entrenched in such a way that the resulting tensions will threaten the federation's stability. But if the member state alliances shift continuously because each of them stands for a different mix of interests, and because day-to-day politics always address other interests, then the tensions will cancel each other out. The individual cleavage never becomes too deeply entrenched, and the system is stabilized despite continuous conflicts. 584 Amongst these interests we find language, religion, party affiliation, economic structure, geographic position, urbanization, transportation, mentality, etc. For crosscutting cleavages to have a stabilizing effect, it is necessary that the diverse interests are distributed in different combinations over the country. They should also be expressed independently, i.e. they should not be always dominated by a single interest as for instance by language (for Belgium see Grgoire Le Soir 25.3.1976; Canada: McRae L532/256s, Scott L738/17, L796/21ss; India: Dikshit L173/125, Riker L660/114). Despite all the sophisticated theories about the decisive influence of material and economic interests, it appears that linguistic and ethnic differences have a tendency to overshadow the rest. Switzerland represents an example of a comparatively successful integration of linguistic diversity in a system of cross-cutting cleavages. Here, probably because of the great number of cantons (26) in the country's small territory, interests continuously cross-cut. But even here linguistic politics play a special role (L98/370,457, L515/206, L717/10s, L750/134). 585 For this mechanism to function, a substantial number of member states is a prerequisite (Bumlin L54/124, Duchacek L180/248) and none of them must be a power aspiring to hegemony as was the case with Prussia in Imperial Germany. The other side of the coin - from the viewpoint of the states - is the weakening of their relative position compared to the central government, because the greater number of partners and their shifting interests make it more difficult for them to arrive at common positions (Dikshit L173/214, May L528/22, Nwabueze L583a/44s, Sharman L745/26ss).

586 The theory of the stabilizing influence of cross-cutting cleavages has been especially dealt with by Lipset. He considers them also in the light of democracy stimulation. This makes him prefer federations to unitary states: If crosscutting bases of cleavage make a more vital democracy, it follows that, all other factors being constant, two-party systems are better than multi-party systems, that the election of officials on a territorial basis is preferable to proportional representation, and federalism is superior to a unitary state (cited from L480/99).

587 To my knowledge the Nigerian Constitution of 1979 (which has been to a large extent put into abeyance by decree no.1 of the Federal Military Government of 31 December 1983) is the first constitutional text to make express provision for crosscutting cleavages (in its article 15): 3) For the purpose of promoting national integration it shall be the duty of the State to... c) encourage intermarriage among persons from different places of origin, or of different religious, ethnic or linguistic association or ties; and d) promote or encourage the formation of associations that cut across ethnic, linguistic, religious or other sectional barriers. 4) The State shall foster a feeling of belonging and of involvement among the various peoples of the Federation, to the end that loyalty to the nation shall override sectional loyalties.

E.2221 Limits of Federalist Integration

Contents Index End

588 The integration of groups in the political community is one of the more important functions of federalism. But as the territorial aspect is essential for the federalist organization of the state, the groups to be integrated should have a territorial base. This is not to say that the demographic differences have to be distributed so as to make each member state homogeneous internally and heterogeneous when compared with the rest. This might indeed have destabilizing effects (no.581). It is only necessary that the representatives of any given characteristic are given their chance in one or more member states continuously (e.g. in the case of language) or from time to time (e.g. in the case of party orientation) in such a way as to make them accept the political system that makes this possible. 589 U.S. federalism, for instance, has successfully integrated extremely diverse groups. But with one of the most important groups, the black population, this has not yet been the case (this, incidentally, had been envisaged by Tocqueville L806/514,535, L807/349s). This part of the population is distributed over practically the whole country. But it is only in a few places and areas that it has the political influence it demands. There have been proposals for the creation of black States

(L180/55, L461/29). But these have been quite controversial among the blacks themselves and they have never been more than theoretical. The result of this state of affairs is that the black population makes its influence felt mainly at the federal level, where they can concentrate their forces, thus having a centralizing influence (L4/2). As matters stand today, unitarism is a better integrating mechanism than federalism. To argue with Lang (L451/80, similarly Messmer L542/184) that there are no minority problems in a healthy federalist system is, therefore, to go too far. It involves circular reasoning because the term healthy is itself a value judgment. 590 In addition, there exist demographic differences which may be clearly territorially based, but to the integration of which federalism can make a contribution only if there is a corresponding ideology. This may be the case with the distribution of wealth. There is little comfort for have-nots to live in their own state if wealth is concentrated in other states and if there is no ideology of solidarity (which, in federations, usually exists). On the other side, the temptation to secede is great for a rich member state that finds itself alone amongst poor ones. This has been amply illustrated by the history of Nigeria (Biafra) or of the still-born Federation of the West Indies. 591 A further limit to federalist integration is the fact that federalist institutions also guarantee the survival of regional differences. Unitary states may integrate differences by dispersing them over the whole territory or by forced unification, thereby making them practically disappear. In federations the same differences will always have their own power base, which will ensure their continued existence. It may even happen that regional identities not only live on, but that they are strengthened because member state institutions and the special position of the member states themselves within the federal structure are considered to be an important element of this identity (for Canadian studies see Schwartz L736/15,51,307,324, also Trudeau L816/10). This may even a reach a point where regional identities are strengthened to such a degree as to endanger the federation's stability. This seems to be the case in India where today, with one exception, there are now only monolingual states (Haqqi L338/8,38).

E.23 Legitimation

Contents Index End

592 The inculcation of a sense of legitimacy is probably the single most effective device for regulating the flow of diffuse support in favor of both the authorities and the regime. A member may

be willing to obey the authorities and conform to the requirements of the regime for many different reasons. But the most stable support will derive from the conviction on the part of the member that it is right and proper for him to accept and obey the authorities and to abide by the requirements of the regime. It reflects the fact that in some vague or explicit way he sees these objects as conforming to his own moral principles, his own sense of what is right and proper in the political sphere (Easton cited from L736/185).

593 I have already pointed out (no.030) the crucial function of any regime to legitimate the political system as such. In this light, too, we have to look at federalism. First, federalism is a means, in countries where diversity is pronounced, of accommodating government to the consent of the governed (Macmahon L501/5, also Friedrich L277/58). What, then, is the basis for federal legitimacy convictions? For the purposes of the following presentation I distinguish between compact and compromise on the one hand and the correspondence to political culture on the other one.

E.231 Compact and Compromise

Contents Index End

594 In the final analysis, all social integration is only possible through compromise. After all, majority itself can only be achieved by compromise (Kelsen L415/31).

595 Compromise is one of the roots not only of a political system's legitimation, but also of the legitimation of federalism and federation. The latter is an equilibrium arrived at in a given historic moment, balancing separatist and unitary tendencies. For some federation is a concession of autonomy to dependence on an overarching community that is only just supportable. For others it is a transition stage on the road to the unitary state (compare Bilfinger L69/44s, Dicey L550/311s, Duchacek L180/158, Freeman L550/312, Lenin L473/8, Schollenberger L727/285, von Segesser L714/697, Wilson L863/1379). 596 The first two modern federations are the result of compromise: the United States and Switzerland. The American constitutional discussion during the Philadelphia Convention in the second half of the 18th century brought forth separatists, confederalists, and supporters of the complete abolition of the states (L8/27ss, L32/306, L96/350, L169/135s, L232/202). The resulting compromise was a hybrid of a unitary state and a confederacy: federation. Such a compromise was also arrived at in 1848 in Switzerland between conservative advocates of the highest possible degree

of cantonal independence and the radical protagonists of national unity (L360/338s,409, L675/97). For other federations similar observations can be made, e.g. for Austria (L20/15s), Germany (L28/17, L477/72), and the Soviet Union (L473/68s). 597 The legal equivalent of the compromise is the convention or compact. This incidentally corresponds to the Latin root fdus in federalism. 598 With this we come to an old concept to be found among many nations as an instrument securing peace: the compact or covenant. Governance is legitimated by treaty. The agreements which influenced the evolution of occidental political theory most were the covenant between God and Noah (1st Moses 9,9) and especially the later one between God and the Jews (2nd Moses 24,7). This was the theological and ideal starting point for the social compact theories which were then used for the legitimation of modern democracy (no.051ss). It may well be that the roots of the legitimacy of modern federations could also be found in the same tradition (thus Elazar L198/xiiis, L200/58, Schechter L710/3s). In any case, the theologically based covenant played an essential role in the founding of political communities at the time of the English settlement in North America. The first and best known of these was the Mayflower compact of 1620, named after a pilgrim ship (L541/16s). Similar claims about possible religious sources may also be made for other old leagues, as for instance the Swiss one of 1291. 599 Be that as it may, the contractual basis of federal legitimacy has been of importance for the evolution of federalist theories and practices from the beginning right through to modern times (compare Pernthaler L616/128, Proudhon L634/318s, de Reynold L654/99, Tocqueville L806/554, Voyenne L837/27s). During the American slavery dispute the Southern States asserted that the Union, i.e. the North, had impinged on the basic arrangements of the constitutional compact. As a practical consequence the South came up with the theories of nullification, that is to say state repeal of federal laws repugnant to the compact (L24/168, L541/266), and of the states' right to secede from the Union (L24/274s, L541/279ss). The South's military defeat dealt these theories a decisive blow. Still, the idea of the compact retained some of its legitimizing importance. 600 Today, it would be difficult to ascertain to what extent the idea that a federation was founded by agreement is still a legitimizing force for federation in the minds of the citizens. It certainly is part of the concept of traditional legitimacy in Weber's sense. And traditional legitimacy is probably even now essential for emotional ties (Hangartner L336/31). But the compact argument as such has only retained importance for elites, if at all, and only in cases where discussions about a federation's future jeopardize the compromise mentioned above (no.595s). Generally the compact or compromise has a legitimating function mainly for federations that are not yet fully consolidated. For others legitimation is no longer dependent on historical facts. It has been taken over as a traditional and quite strong element by political culture and the latter's function of legitimation.

601 It is interesting to note that, in highly centralized Austria, the advocates of increased member state autonomy stress the confederate elements of the federation's foundation in their argument with the Kelsen inspired legal acceptance of this foundation (L214/41, L587/10). Amongst these elements we may note the contractual personal unions of the Habsburg rulers with their Austrian core possessions (Ermacora L214/29) and, after both World Wars, the revolutionary emergence of the lnder with their resolutions and laws to unite in a federation (Altenstetter L20/14s, Ermacora L214/41ss,218, Pernthaler L609/725ss, L611/50ss). In Canada, too, the compact theory has found application in the context of arguments between the English and the French speaking parts of the country. But here there is evidently no talk about a compact between the various provinces, but rather about one between the two linguistic groups (Livingston L485/44ss, McWhinney L457/61, Rapport Tremblay L139/137ss, Stanley L767/275ss). (As to other federations, see for Australia L17/22, Germany L28/15, Switzerland L654/103.)

E.232 Political Culture

Contents Index End

602 Napoleon, who gave Switzerland her 1803 Constitution (the so-called Act of Mediation, L406/115) described her as federal by nature. That Switzerland could not be organized otherwise than federally is a recurring theme in political literature. Switzerland will be federal or altogether cease to be: de Reynold (L654/98, also Kgi L404/13, L578/1944/44, Wick L578/1938/55). It is not only for more ideal reasons... that Switzerland should retain it ('federalism'). Realistically considered, Switzerland cannot possibly abolish federalism. The federal structure is an ineradicable element of the country (Huber L782/1159, compare L598/419a, L654/166,198). It is not so much written constitutional arrangements that are seen to be the basis for federalism, but rather the existence of a specific form of political culture (see L485/5, L573/5s).
603 Similar statements exist for other federations, e.g. Brazil (L483/3, L660/115), Canada (L758/7), Germany (L632/250), and India (L338/11, L418/38, L537/2). On the other hand, a supposedly federalist form of political culture does not necessarily lead to federation. This is demonstrated by the examples of Great Britain (L180/344) and of Italy (L635/116s, L852/3). We may even find situations where, as for instance in France, demographic diversities will be used as reasons against a possible federation, which elsewhere would favour its introduction.

604 In the context of the functions of democracy I have already discussed political culture and its legitimating role in relation to the political regime (no.167ss). The question now to be answered is the specific nature of federal political culture. There exist very few empirical studies about this (e.g. L205/38ss). But I will nevertheless attempt to identify a few characteristics.

605 It is somewhat difficult to distinguish between causes and effects. There is an intimate relationship between federal culture and federal organization. The latter is not only legitimated by the former. It also guarantees the federal culture's survival. Tradition, one of the essential elements of the social value system, is a very clear illustration. The historic reality of member state autonomy (Schwartz L736/310, Veiter L829/138) and federalist conventions as well as rules shape popular perceptions about the appropriate regime. But they are themselves revived by civic education in its largest sense: life in a given political system. 606 Nevertheless, there are a few characteristics of political culture which, according to experience, must obtain if it is to be called federal. I distinguish patterns of political behaviour on the one side and aspects of their territorial distribution on the other. 607 The first of Switzerland's still extant confederal agreements dates from 1291. It is considered to be the founding charter of the Swiss confederation. In this charter we find the phrase (L360/20): By common counsel and goodwill we have also promised and ordained, that, in the valleys mentioned above, we shall recognize or accept in any way no judge... who is not an inhabitant of our territory. This is the essence of the federal determination to remain independent. There is rather less of a desire to manage actively one's own affairs. That may be an inevitable consequence. It is much more the expression of an aversion to having outsiders manage it for us. Zwerin (L884/142ss) calls this MOB-freedom (MOB = Mind one's Own Business). Evidently, the we/them syndrome is a universal principle of group dynamics. Nevertheless, it appears to flavour federal comportment in a particularly strong way. And it is also especially well supported by federalist mechanisms. 608 Another element of federal political culture is the readiness not to consider politics as a zero-sum game or a game where the only alternatives are complete power and total powerlessness (as to the underlying theory of games see Brams L84/280ss, Riker L661/28ss). In countries such as those of the Third World, where politics correspond to zero-sum games, there is no place for a regime that is based on spatial division of power. This is because, for the central rulers, the existence of independent power bases is a constant threat. The regional rulers themselves will try, for the same reasons, either to do away with their rivals (persons or groups) or to secede. But federalism's game is toleration (L485/106). This means a willingness to claim noninterference not only for oneself but to grant it to others, as well as the perception of compromise and power-sharing as appropriate mechanisms for conflict resolution. 609 The expression of all this is to be found in rules, that is in conventions and legal norms. A further characteristic of federalism, therefore, is constitutionalism. Indeed, the rise of modern federalism coincides with that of constitutionalism, and the major theorists of constitutionalism have elaborated federalism (Friedrich L277/63, also Dicey L170/179). Constitutionalism here is not to be understood as a specific form of government (Loewenstein L493/27ss) but rather as a basic policy orientation favouring limited power and calculable procedures. (Eckstein, L190/235:

Constitutionalism refers to the subjection of the elite to a broad and highly explicit impersonal framework of rules, procedural and substantive, where this framework of rules operates as the principal limitation on the autonomy of the elite.) 610 Is it necessary that the federal and the democratic political cultures go together? This depends on the kind of federalism we are talking of. A loose confederation may well group non-democratic governments. In this case we can agree with Friedrich (L275/10): Federalizing tendencies do not necessarily presuppose a democratic political order in the component units. But federation is something different. The necessity to settle certain issues by majority decisions presupposes a minimal democratic standard as part of the relevant political culture. Absolutist democracy, on the other hand, which has no place for limits to power, is incompatible with federation (L485/308, L825/348s). But, generally speaking, federal political culture may be elitist or populist. 611 As to the spatial viewpoint mentioned above (no.606), the question is: How far may the organizations of federally united partners vary from each other? Or: To what extent is it necessary that the authority patterns of central and member state governments coincide? 612 For confederations, Pufendorf required that the associated countries have a similar regime (L639/7/7, compare L80/45). For federation, also, scholars have stressed the necessity of a certain homogeneity of political structures (e.g. Lerche L477/85ss, Messmer L542/119s, Usteri L825/345). If we consider modern federations we may indeed perceive a great harmony of patterns of government within each of them (with the possible exception of Malaysia). This is not to say that the structure of government has to be nearly identical. Swiss cantonal constitutions, for instance, show quite distinct differences. But everywhere we find homogeneity in the pattern of conflict resolution, or federalist homogeneity (Lerche L477/87). Basically divergent authority structures will sooner or later lead to tensions which have to be relieved by assimilation. This was the case when, in the last century, the Swiss Canton of Neuchtel was a Prussian principality (L728/227ss,357ss), or when, after independence, Indian states had former absolute rulers, rajpramukhs, as heads of state (L537/465). However, modern limited monarchies could conceivably coexist with republics because the basic authority patterns are similar. 613 What has been said is also essential for the relationships between the political structures of the federal government on the one side and state governments on the other. The homogeneous political cultures of the states correspond, in their aggregate, to the political culture of the federation. It is to be expected that the latter's institutions and problem-solving mechanisms will show a high degree of similarity to those of the states.

E.3 ASSIGNED FUNCTIONS OF FEDERALISM

Contents Index End

614 Having dealt with federalism's systemic functions, I shall now address the other functions which political theory and practice assign to federalism (compare no.026ss). They are not related to the survival of governance or organization as such. Assigned functions are those added ones that the social ideology expects federalism to translate into reality.
615 It goes without saying that systemic functions are also ideologically coloured. Such value judgments have been presented in some depth in the preceding pages. In a certain sense the following so-called assigned functions may be seen as necessary elements for the existence of the federal system (not the political system per se). My approach has the advantage of separating two largely distinct points of view. The price of increased logical stringency would be greater length. For practical reasons that bifurcated approach has only been followed in the case of federalism and division of powers (nos.424ss,625ss).

616 Such assigned functions are numerous, whether empirically provable or only ideologically postulated. Minority protection, for instance, is part of them, as well as other social or group values that have been treated here in connection with systemic functions. We may also add personalism as proposed by integral federalists (no.324, L169/131, L576/54), or the assertion that federalism is applied law of nature (Lang L451/117). But there are two principal types of assigned functions which we shall deal with in more detail: citizen participation (no.617ss) and civic liberty (no.625ss).

E.31 Citizen Participation

Contents Index End

617 Tocqueville 1835 (L806/137): What I admire most in America is not decentralization's administrative effects but its political results. - Richardson 1976 (L637/6-4/5): Finally, however, for me, the telling argument in favor of decentralization turns neither on the issue of responsiveness

nor on the points of precedent and practice, but rather on the question of civic participation. My own sense of the importance of civic participation reflects a set of beliefs which is fundamental not only to the values of American society but to a western philosophy of politics and personal fulfilment that stretches back at least to Aristotle. Chief among these beliefs is the idea that, insofar as practically possible, each person ought to have the opportunity to control the conditions of his life and, in concert with others, the conditions of community life; and that the exercise of rationalself-control as individuals and as citizens is indispensable both to our development as moral and social beings and to our sense of self-worth.

618 The highest ranking political value of Greek antiquity was the fulfilment of human potential in the polis. This was its vision of the good life (L169/131). Such good life was attainable only through the political discussion of free citizens, and thus only in the small polity. It was the attempt to preserve this in modern large-scale government that led the American Fathers of the Constitution to invent federation (e.g. Franklin L232/199). This is very well instanced in the later thinking of Jefferson, the name of whom is linked to so-called ward democracy, i.e. to the small community as the cornerstone of government: As Cato concluded every speech with the words, Carthago delenda est, so do I every opinion with the injunction, 'divide the counties into wards' (L32/248s). Arendt (L32/255): If the ultimate end of revolution was freedom and the constitution of a public space where freedom could appear, the constitutio libertatis, then the elementary republics of the wards, the only tangible place where everyone could be free, actually were the end of the great republic whose chief purpose in domestic affairs should have been to provide the people with such places of freedom and to protect them. The basic assumption of the ward system... was that no one could be called happy without his share in public happiness, that no one could be called free without his experience in public freedom, and that no one could be called either happy or free without participating, and having a share, in public power.
619 Direct influence of citizens on political decisions is a very old postulate of occidental political philosophy. It has been especially a guiding light for the thinkers who attempted to free the state from absolutist domination. A culmination of this thinking occurred in the eighteenth and nineteenth century. Thus Mill said (L547/207): There is no difficulty in showing that the ideally best form of government is that in which the sovereignty... is vested in the entire aggregate of the community; every citizen not only having a voice in the exercise of that ultimate sovereignty, but being at least occasionally, called on to take an actual part in the government, by the personal discharge of some public function, local or general. It was during these times that modern federation emerged. But in the same way that nearly every revolution takes over its predecessor's authority patterns (Arendt L32), so absolutism triumphed after the democratic revolution in the form of absolute democracy (no.054). In large-area states the people became, in theory, omnipotent. But the actual influence of the individual citizen was again reduced to near insignificance.

620 After the Second World War, especially, the elements of local direct democracy in federations acquired the reputation of being dusty and antiquated. Global planning, efficient use of resources,co-operative federalism were the vogue words (see no.346ss). It was only in the 1970s that there began a renaissance of localism and of the Jeffersonian model of federalism. This renaissance is demonstrated in texts, but is especially evident in the political behaviour of the population (L430/37, L445/20, L689/102, L712/6).

621 Hallman (L333/222s): Much of our thinking in public administration is founded on a commitment to a hierarchical form of organization.... In contrast, community control says that several thousand local corporations around the country will have the right to decide the priorities for spending a certain segment of public funds. This is bound to boggle the mind of well-schooled administrators. But if feelings and citizen participation are valued as well as efficiency, then alteration of traditional administrative practices is inevitably required.

622 The Swiss constitutional lawyer and national politician Aubert has graphically described the value of participation in federations, where a much larger segment of the political elite is activated (L782/1081s): Federalism vulgarizes power.... What do I mean by that? If there were, in Switzerland, a unitary regime, if we would do away with the cantons, and if we would empty local government of its contents, how many people would there be left to occupy themselves with public affairs? I do not think that Parliament would be considerably enlarged, neither would the Executive. If you add to this the most important administrators, influential journalists, as well as the captains of industry, you will arrive at some 500 to 1'000 persons who take care of public affairs. But if you add to this unitary state further levels of political decisionmaking you will, with the cantons, arrive at some 5'000 persons that are directly concerned with politics. If you add local government, too, there will be not only 5'000 such persons, but some 50'000 or 100'000. I, for one, think that it is a considerable advantage for democracy to have, in a country of but six million inhabitants, not only 1'000 but rather 5'000, 50'000, or 100'000 persons that take an active interest in politics. 623 Federalism's participatory function has been justified in different ways. On the one hand, there are the aspects of efficiency (no.501ss), of stability or integration, of cadre recruitment. They have been treated in preceding pages. But for the occidental tradition mentioned above there is another motive that is in the foreground: civic education. This has always been considered to be an essential element of personal development and, thus, a pre-eminent goal of government. In many cases, though individuals may not do the particular thing so well, on the average, as the officers of government, it is nevertheless desirable that it should be done by them rather than by the government, as a means to their own mental education - a mode of strengthening their active faculties, exercising their judgment, and giving them a familiar knowledge of the subjects with which they are thus left to deal (Mill L547/164). Thus, it is by entrusting the citizens with the management of the small affairs, rather than with having them take charge of the big ones, that they may be interested in the public welfare (Tocqueville L807/142).
624 In the communist world, too, this motive seems to have had some importance. This is evidenced by Yugoslav authors, as e.g. Stefanovic (L772/17) and especially Djordjevi?, who considers Yugoslav federalism to be the realization of a true human right to self-institutionalization (L175/13s).

E.32 Civic Liberty

Contents Index End

625 To one who believes in the majoritarian notion of freedom, it is impossible to interpret federalism as other than a device for minority tyranny. ... In summary, the abstract assertion that federalism is a guarantee of freedom is undoubtedly false (Riker L660/142,145).

626 Nobody could reproach Riker with repeating a well-known tune. The usual argument is quite different: The aim of federalism... is to give to each nationality, every province or commune, the highest possible amount of life, activity, and independence; to every individual the highest possible amount of liberty (Proudhon L635/150). The coexistence of several nations under the same state is a test as well as the best security of freedom (Lord Acton L180/92). 627 It is easy for Riker to demonstrate, in support of his thesis, that the federalist ideology was used during the American Civil War especially for the defence of slavery and, later on, of other racist customs in the South (L660/140). But what principle is immune to being used for the most diverse ends! It is in the nature of things that an organizational model that strengthens local majorities as against national ones will appear as most unjust, where local values are contrary to national ones in fields where society does not allow for compromise. But it is not admissible to deduce a general rule from such a particular instance (Kgi L402/689s). There remains the task of analysing the alleged parallelism of federalism and civic liberty (see L147/316, L378/1, L446/133, L825/347s). 628 We are again faced with the tension between large-scale and small-scale democracy. This has been described above (no.519ss) as the individual's numerically greater influence in the smaller community, a theme already treated by Rousseau who, ironically, later became the theoretician of absolutist democracy (L677/574): If the people number 100'000 the status of the individual citizen does not change, and every one of them always bears the whole empire of the laws, whereas his vote, reduced to one hundred thousandth, has ten times less influence in their redaction. Thus, as the subject always remains as an individual, his relationship with the sovereign increases as a result of the numbers of citizens. Therefore, liberty decreases in direct relation to the growth of the state. It was the central preoccupation of the Philadelphia Convention to retain the greater civic liberty in small republics for the new large-scale government (L201/274).
629 Madison (L334/10), for one, turned the size argument around in a way that would accommodate Riker's point of view (also L156a/10s, L169/133ss, L806/222): The smaller the society, the fewer probably will be the distinct parties and interests composing it; the fewer the distinct parties and interests, the more frequently will a majority be found of the same party; and the smaller the number of individuals composing a majority, and the smaller the compass within which they are placed, the more easily will they concert and execute their plans of oppression. Extend the sphere and you take in

a greater variety of parties and interests; you make it less probable that a majority of the whole will have a common motive to invade the rights of other citizens; or if such a common motive exists, it will be more difficult for all who feel it to discover their own strength and to act in unison with each other.... Hence, it clearly appears that the same advantage which a republic ('indirect democracy') has over a ('direct') democracy in controlling the effects of faction is enjoyed by a large over a small republic - is enjoyed by the Union over the States composing it.

630 Constitutionalism as an element of federalist political culture has been mentioned before (no.609). Thus, it is only to be expected that the libertarian effects of the rule of law are often assimilated with federalism. So Bumlin: Although rule of law is not only based on federalism it is nevertheless not by chance that this ideal has been in the best way realized, up to now, in federations (L54/152, this does not entirely do justice to Great Britain). Or Kgi: Already in the past it has been emphasized that federal organization of government offers the better guarantees for normativity.... The federal units become 'guardians of the constitution' (L403/48, compare L184/10, L593/230, L804/317). 631 Constitutionalism is the harnessing of power through a system of norms that is calculable and which may be changed by legal procedures only. This obviously introduces the division of powers theme: division of powers as a result of the necessity to use specific legal forms (L253/26). But division of powers as a guarantee for liberty has an additional relationship with federalism: vertical separation of levels, as distinct from the traditional separation of legislative, executive, and judicial powers (L253/49ss).
632 Other forms of vertical division of powers are political liberties (L253/50), the principle of subsidiarity (no.231ss, L253/51s), and pluralism (no.201ss, L253/53, L493/295).

633 Nowadays, horizontal separation of powers has become problematical. The theory was developed during a period when there were real conflicts of interest between the royal executive and a more or less democratic parliament. But Montesquieu (L551/XI/VI, compare Constant L147/8) pointed to the possibility of the sociological identity of legislature and executive: If there were no monarch, and if executive power were entrusted to a certain number of members from amongst the legislature, liberty would no longer obtain because both powers would be united. The same people would sometimes, and could always, be part of both. This coalition of the executive and the legislature is now largely reality in parliamentary systems, especially in those with two- or three-party systems. There it is no longer parliament that controls the executive. Because the political survival of a parliamentary majority rests on the fact that its government is not defeated in a vote, it is really the executive that controls the legislature through its majority. Great Britain is a prime example: Her Majesty's loyal opposition is free to do what it wants. But all it can achieve is advanced electioneering and other action to force the government to justify its position in a public debate. The majority party's MP, for his part, must not do anything which might endanger the government's majority, especially in the case of the latter's being narrow. Which leads us to the seemingly paradoxical observation that it is the parliamentary system itself that stands in the way of parliamentary control. The reason for this perverse development is to be found in the emergence of modern political

parties, i.e. in the triumph of the democratic principle as embodied in parliament over the aristocratic executive. Today, both powers rest on the same sociological foundation and legitimation. And if we look only to legitimation, even nonparliamentary regimes (e.g. Switzerland and the USA) have set out in the same direction, although the traditional functions of control and competition still function better there. Of the three powers it is only the judicial one that has more or less retained its independence (compare L159/25, L496/84ss, L800/148). 634 Given this situation, it is obvious that federalism has acquired a new emphasis as a guarantee for individual liberty. The principle of federalism is the first and most important factor of today's separation of powers (Peters L617/24, see also L165/318, L180/335, L277/63, L356/21, L487/870, L533a/8, L806/139s, L884/64). It is quite likely that it is the very fact that it is the democratic division of powers, albeit involving two different kinds of democracy (small-scale and large-scale), which legitimizes this principle. This is in accordance with Montesquieu's expectation (L551/5/5): Every inequality in a democracy has to rest on the nature of democracy itself, and on the principle of equality.
635 This function of federalism has not been perceived only recently. It was present in the minds of the American Fathers of the Constitution (L374/124). Also Proudhon (L634/348): Let Paris, within her walls, have revolutions. But if Lyon, Marseille, Toulouse, Bordeaux, Nantes, Rouen, Lille, Strasbourg, Dijon, etc., if the Departments, being their own masters, do not follow? Paris will remain alone --- Thus, federation is the people's salvation: by dividing them, it saves them at the same time from their leaders' tyranny and from their own foolishness. 636 I think that Lerche (L477/80ss) errs when he holds division of powers and federal structure to be two quite different factors, and their parallelism to be but pseudo-logic, missing originality, tradition, and sense of federal union or division. It is this parallelism that is important. Federalism is well able to exercise the function of the division of powers, i.e. to help in realizing the goal of securing freedom. But it is wrong to equate both principles. They coincide in certain areas only.

637 The ability to have second thoughts is one of man's greatest assets, one which can be used to subordinate passion to prudence and impetuosity to considered or deliberate action. Any political structure claiming to serve the ends of liberty must have substantial opportunities for second thoughts built into it (Elazar L201/252). The crucial element of federalism's function in relation to the division of powers, or of its ability to have second thoughts, is the existence of independent yet still mutually interdependent centres of power. These centres do not only have their own spheres of tasks. They also rest on sociologically different bases.
638 It would be an error to identify federalist division of powers with the weakening of the state. As Arendt has pointed out in her analysis of U.S. constitutional history (L32/150ss), the combination of member state and central powers has also had a stabilizing and strengthening influence for government as such. 639 For the Federal Republic of Germany, Hesse sees the role of the federalist separation of powers as being concerned with horizontal rather than vertical checks (L356/27): As a matter of fact, in today's constitutional reality the federal structure does less for the vertical than for the horizontal checking and balancing of powers. In modern democracies, the factors for such balance are not the 'legislature' and the 'executive' in the sense of some 'classical' theory of division of powers. The factors are rather the actual political powers that should control and balance each other, decisively

aided by the judicial power. These are the parliamentary majority and the government on the one side, and the opposition on the other side. Next to this balance, we find in modern federation the one of the Federal Parliament and the Federal Government as against the Federal Council ('Bundesrat'), where... the real power in the Federal Council is not so much the specifically federalist aspect of the Lnder as individualities but rather the element of the Lnder bureaucracies. Without wishing to enter into a controversy with Hesse's thesis about the balancing of powers between majority and opposition, I may add that even the correctly described strengthening of the horizontal balance has to have its sociocultural roots in the vertical if it is to remain viable (compare L430/45, L457/9, L551/9/1, L696/108s, L833/21/122s).

640 There is no denying that today the division of powers function of federalism is endangered. For the media - always on the lookout for reform targets - federalist inequality is a prime subject for criticism. In nearly any isolated case it is easier to see the advantages of unification than to justify differences with abstract principles of general theory. (This is problematical because there is always the tendency to consider the difference itself as a disadvantage without even inquiring whether such difference is an actual burden for anyone.) The German Basic Law's uniformity of the conditions of life (C72/2, 'Einheitlichkeit der Lebensverhltnisse') may be invoked against nearly every federalist inequality (L430/52), just like the yardstick of the national interest (see L264b/928). Together with the bureaucrats' natural desire for securing their arrangements, these facts have favoured the emergence of a kind of public rhetoric which sets the ideals of collaboration, comprehensive planning, and trust against conflict and waste. Thus, both the term and the institutions of cooperative federalism and of other federalisms came into being (see no.339ss). The result is a fateful erosion of the multi-level federal structure. More and more partinstitutionalized and non-institutionalized cross-connections between the different autonomous entities thwart and outmanoeuvre the traditional regional differentiation (Imboden L387/70). This weakens federalism's division of powers function.
641 Role cumulation, too, potentially thwarts the vertical division of powers. This we may find, for instance, in Switzerland, where different political roles may be exercised by the same person - local mayor, cantonal councillor, and federal member of parliament (Neidhart L575/81). This system does have its advantages: economical use of scarce political cadres in a small country and increased member state influence on central decisions. But it is obvious that there is also a relaxation of the separation of powers.

642 If we have emphasized, here, the freedom-serving function of federalism, we also have to remember that there may be groups the civic liberty of which is better secured by the centre than by the member states, e.g. the coloured population of the United States. They have little to expect from federalist division of powers. Their civic liberty must first be attained before it can be safeguarded (no.589, L194/192). 643 Thieme's assessment is correct when he doubts (L800/151) that the idea of an additional balance of powers in a federalist system produces any political dynamics. However, it is possible that vertical separation of powers, as well as the horizontal division, will some day meet with increased acceptance in public opinion. The rejection of the public sector's increased growth, with its freedom-restricting consequences, is, after all, a mark of our times. This might lead to a renaissance for all

of the forms of division of powers which still function, amongst them the federalist one.

E.4 FUNCTIONS OF MIDDLE LEVELS

Contents Index End

644 Federalism deals with a specific organization of the relationships between a whole and its parts. The existence of two levels is therefore essential. But in political reality there is no two-level federation. All federations have three levels - local, middle, and national. Some federations have more (no.653, also L264b/710). Whenever examples were given for specific aspects of federalism in the preceding pages, they sometimes referred to the local or communal level, sometimes to the member state or middle level. This could be justified because we were concerned with the general relationship between the local viewpoint -of whatever level- and the central one in a federal system. But are there perhaps also specific middle level functions in federations? Why do we practically always find three levels, whatever the country's size, and not two or four?
645 Before entering into details let us once more realize that the essential systemic property of member states is the fact that they are centres of decision making, largely independent from the national one, with their own complete government organization based on a legitimacy of their own. Or, to use the words of the North Carolina Governor Sanford (L696/109): They cannot be shunted around, or have their structure altered, or be summarily dismissed, as can units of government created by legislative or executive acts of the national government. In a word, they are the only governments as constitutionally secure as the national government (compare L416/38).

646 Are there any specific middle level functions? In every political system there are concerns which are considered to be national and others that are local. Local affairs usually deal with the provision of services that may be financed locally. The number of possible levels of government increases with the degree of translocality. National affairs are typically those that cannot be handled except nationally (as to the substantive allocation of tasks see L264b/909ss). But national solutions very often need to be adapted to local conditions, while local concerns are very often in need of some translocal but not necessarily national arrangement. In other words, the desirability of having some clearing house with adequate capacities (information, resources, authority) is evident. Baar (L42/229): Every system of a certain size and complexity -government, private industry, etc.- is forced to introduce division of labour in such a way as to delegate functions to different subsystems. From the point

of view of systems theory these subsystems are the 'points of requisite variety' where the information and the qualifications for the tasks' optimal solution are to be found in a concentrated form as the result of these points being at the intersection of information channels from the system as a whole (from the centre and from other subsystems) as well as from the environment (this latter as a result from contacts related to the provision of services). It is obvious that this is a problem which is not exclusively federal. As a matter of fact, practically all modern states have introduced some regional middle level with some form of general competence (England, L112/40, seems to be an exception). 647 There exists a popular notion that centralization in federations has been arrived at by transferring tasks from the member states to the centre. This is not altogether true. In reality, there is rather a coincidence of primary centralization (from the private to the public sector) and secondary centralization (from the member states to the centre). This is so because the transition from the regulatory to the service state was accompanied by tasks of a mainly cross-cutting or redistributive character. Before, most of these functions were not assumed by any level of government. But as such public responsibilities were the natural domain of the central government (L264b/909ss) the latter's responsibilities were enlarged at the expense of the private sector rather than of the member states. However, this development changed the relative importance of the various levels of government. At the same time the concentration of public responsibilities at the centre increased the demand for member state adaptation. The emerging picture is one of a shift in the different functions of the middle levels from original and independent ones to delegated tasks. The result of adaptation as an exogenous and decentralist phenomenon is a political weakening of middle levels (in unitary states there is a contrary evolution, no.677). In Switzerland, this is sometimes designated as federalism of execution ("Vollzugsfderalismus"). 648 The additional element in federations is the middle levels' comparatively great autonomy. This autonomy has its specific functions. Loyalty transfer (see no.566) is one of them. A further important function is mobilization of consent as described by Beer (L57/85): Insofar as states perform successfully as intermediate decisionmaking bodies in a national polity, one reason is that they are not mere regional administrative agencies, but rather political systems, each of which is endowed with a full panoply of elections, parties, pressure groups, legislators and executives, as well as functionally organized bureaucracies. When one looks at the failure of recent experiments with regard to administrative regions in England, one appreciates the importance of this highly political aspect. It would seem that in an advanced modern polity, the administration of these massive and complex programs cannot be confined to its bureaucratic core, but must be embedded in a context of politics which will educate the clientele, win their co-operation and endow them with some real power of influencing outputs. I call this function the mobilization of consent.
649 The international symposium on national and regional planning, held in May 1975 in Helsinki, also stressed the necessity of a middle level for planning purposes (ECE press release 24.6.75): An intermediary regional planning level between the national and the local levels is of ever growing importance for the articulation of goals (translation from the French text). A further systemic

relationship, the importance of the other two levels for the middle one, is alluded to in Hegel's presentation of the function of another type of middle level, a country's political estates: It is one of the most important logical insights that a given factor which occupies the position of an extreme as long as it is in opposition to another one loses this quality and acquires an organic one as soon as it occupies at the same time a middle position. It is especially important to stress this side because it is one of the more common and highly dangerous prejudices to see the estates primarily in the context of their antagonism to government, as if that were their primary function. From an organic point of view, i.e. considered in its totality, the estates are evidenced primarily by their intermediary function. Thus, the antagonism itself is reduced to a semblance.

650 There is another function which results from the member states' intermediary role: the shielding of communes from central government. Only actual regional authority has the ability to bring forth, protect and nourish communal liberty (Servan-Schreiber L742/48s). This is so, because, on the one hand, local government's political influence is greater within the member state than in a national government farther away.
651 This assertion needs some qualification: It is a fact that local governments have been swept away by wholesale mergers in federalist Germany as well as in unitary Great Britain (L264b/806). To be able to change local government boundaries and structures is one of the real-type characterisics that set member states apart from mere regions in unitary states (compare no.270). And then it may be that the gerrymandering of electoral districts may lead to a situation where some categories of local governments, especially large cities, will find a more sympathetic audience at the national level rather than with their state government. (There is also the central government's tendency to enter into direct relationships with local governments for the advancement of its own priorities, L264b/766ss.)

652 The other shielding function of middle levels is the support they lend to local demands by putting their own weight behind them at the centre. But this presupposes that the interests concerned are comparatively important ones within the member state, and that they are not distributed in an essentially homogeneous way throughout the whole federation (see Wagener L106/440). 653 Let us now look at the above-mentioned (no.644) problem of the number of levels. From the point of view of public tasks, a nearly infinite number could be justified (no.646). Practically every public good or public demand has its own spatial dimension. Political economy's public choice approach does indeed postulate a corresponding variety of public entities (no.516ss, L593/219). But political reality consistently makes do with but two or three levels of government, i.e. levels that are fitted out with an important arsenal of political rather than merely administrative tools. Two-level organization is to be found in unitary systems (central and local governments). Three levels are usual for certain regionalized systems (no.677) and for federations.
654 Four-level federations exist. The Soviet Union and Yugoslavia contained member states which were themselves federally organized. But this is true only of some of the member states and not all of them. And where we find it, it is only a part of the territory that is involved. Thus, the two autonomous Yugoslav Provinces of Kosovo and Vojvodina contained only about 38 per cent of the Republic of Serbia (L771a/1616) to which they belonged. It is also obvious that in both countries these additional levels were rather member states with a somewhat lesser status than other intermediaries. In Switzerland the Cantons of Grisons and Schwyz operate on a political level

between that of cantons and communes. Originally, these districts were in each Canton the only locallevel subdivisions. The communes came into being only later (L722/254), but the districts were retained with a comparatively restricted set of tasks. In the United States, also, there are in most states politically organized counties (L504/447). Their attributions are very varied and they do not enjoy a position similar to that of member states within their respective states (L504/451). 655 Special types of local government, such as school districts, parishes, and citizens' communes exist in one form or other especially in Switzerland and in the United States. They are not additional levels of government, but rather specific forms of local government (see also L264b/752).

656 Three levels are typical for federations. It is striking that this pattern seems to be completely independent of the actual federation's size. It obtains in Switzerland, in the Federal Republic of Germany, and in the United States, to name but three very differently sized countries. This is very much contrary to, and therefore not heeded by, the modern theories of reorganization that are perpetually trying to find optimally sized units according to spillover and service delivery criteria (see L264b/804). Why this ubiquity of the three-level model in federations? This is a question that has been tackled only very seldom up to now. It is my conviction that searching for optimal numbers is much more fruitful than attempting to define optimal size.
657 Dahl/Tufte are among the few who have dealt with this problem (L156a/141s): Thus one task of democratic theory may be to specify not an optimal unit but an optimal number of units with comparatively fixed boundaries. The boundaries of each unit would be too small or too large for all functions assigned to it; but the costs of a smaller number of units with relatively fixed boundaries would be less than the costs of any larger number of units, or of constantly shifting boundaries.

658 Amongst the more important reasons for three-level federations are historical ones. Eighteenth and nineteenth century federations came into being by uniting twolevel states. Three levels were a logical consequence of this. Reality, then, influenced the image of federation's ideal type. Later federations took over this pattern as a matter of course (the political bases were also similar, no.379ss).
659 With Imboden's (L386/56ss) and Marti's (L511/68s) attempts at construing the theory of the division of powers as a kind of secularized trinity, we might also point to the deeply entrenched roots of the number three in at least occidental man's thinking (see also L253/65). But such an interpretation is highly speculative and does not lend itself to empirical analysis. I therefore will not pursue it.

660 In addition to that we may add considerations based on systems theory: In a three-tier system it is possible to directly influence the next level and indirectly influence the level next but one, so as to give people experience of the system in a physical and not only abstract way. For instance, if a member state's authorities support a local concern at the centre, this concern is then automatically on the latter's agenda. But if there should be an additional level in between, the probability of such action would be less. Furthermore, we may consider the three-level solution to be an optimizing device, involving an economical provision of political forums for the localization of problems, whose individual position on the gradient of centralization would be very varied (no.470s, Bird/Hartle L70/60s). King, too, sums up his detailed economic analysis with an acknowledgment (L419b/84s) that when subcentral authorities provide many services it may be unwise to have a separate tier of optimalsized authorities for each function; rather, it may be best to have a few tiers, each with

an authority size reasonably suitable for a number of major services. If additional levels cannot be avoided it is, therefore, common not to give them constitutional status. They are not comprehensive political entities linking equally comprehensive neighbours to each other.
661 In political discussion, the main argument against the introduction of a regional level in federations is usually the alleged inability of citizens to identify themselves emotively with a fourth level of government. It is an open question whether such inability is likely where this fourth level is not some artificial new structure but rather something already existing. A U.S. study shows that young people can easily visualize the architecture of a given set of governmental tiers (L647/141). On the other hand, experiences gleaned from local government amalgamations (L264b/858) demonstrate the difficulty of creating in citizens a feeling of belonging to some new areal unity where there is no original relationship to build on. It might thus be that the difficulty of fostering a feeling of identity with a new level of government is a transition problem rather than a barrier. On the other hand, this argument could be countered with the observation that the proposed regional units are usually designed to perform comparatively few tasks. This may again render them somewhat abstract and of little emotive appeal. It is a pity that empirical research does not address itself to these questions, which are important for so-called regional policy. 662 If some day we should see the emergence of a European federation, existing federations in Europe would have to face the problem of which of their levels would become obsolescent (this is to assume that a European federation would take the given nation states as building blocks). A partially four-tiered federation is logically feasible. But it is quite likely that in the long run it is the autonomy of the existing federations' member states that would suffer most. This is obviously a political and not primarily a legal problem. Contrary to Klein's thinking (L425/44s), it has certainly nothing to do with the assertion that a federation is, in the final analysis, a decentralized unitary state (no.229).

F. GENESIS AND DURABILITY OF FEDERATIONS

663 If we should attempt to place federation on a scale of regimes from the perfect consolidation of the units in a centralized unitary state to their complete autonomy as independent countries under the law of nations, it would appear somewhere in the middle (no.222). This does not mean that federation combines the best of two worlds. By itself no regime is better than any other one. The choice amongst them dependes

on the political conditions under which they have to operate. In the following pages, therefore, I will address the reasons that make for the emergence of federations. After that, I will inquire into the reasons for the continued existence of federations. This latter theme is not very often treated by students of federalism (exceptions are Dikshit L173/233ss, Riker L660/111).

F.1 GENESIS OF FEDERATIONS

Contents Index End

664 It has been said by J.P. Morgan of a certain expensive yacht that if you have to ask its price, you can't afford it. Something comparable may be said of federalism. If one has to justify it in terms of specific secondary and tertiary short-term benefits: tariffs, subventions, votes, jobs, racial balance, it probably cannot succeed. A nation can neither be fully explained nor constituted in accountants' terms. Where what is wanted is not a new nation but a pragmatic solution to certain problems of trade and marketing, population movement, defense or foreign policy, some other solution different from classic federalism may be more realistic and so, more successful (Franck L249/183).

665 There are authors who do indeed attempt to invent arithmetic formulas for the explanation of federations. Thus Dikshit offers a complete battery of equations for different kinds of federalism (L173/231ss). His equation for a centralized federation with strong dualist tendencies, for instance, is A1,3,4,5,6,+B1(a+b+c) = Fcp (A stands for unifying factors, B for dividing ones). A similar exercise is that proposed by Sharma (L445/7) where federations come into being because of F = f(x+y+z)+c (x= environment, y=history, z=socio-economic conditions, c=desire for unification). I do not set great store by this approach. If there is something that is revealed by it, it is merely the fact that there are always factors favouring unitary government and others promoting complete independence (Dikshit L173/227s, Friedrich L277/52s). 666 Deutsch has formulated a quite comprehensive list of elements that are essential for federations (according to L660/15): 1) mutual compatibility of main values; 2) a distinctive way of life; 3) expectations of stronger economic ties or gains; 4) marked increase in political and administrative capabilities of at least some participating units; 5) superior economic growth on the part of at least some participating units; 6) unbroken links of social communication, both geographically between territories and sociologically between different social strata; 7) a broadening of the political elite; 8) mobility of persons at least among the politically relevant strata; and 9) a multiplicity of ranges of communications and transactions. A further detailed catalogue is Kiang's (L419/177ss).

667 Attempts to explain the emergence of federations in legal terms do not lead far (Jellinek L382/777ss, see the controversy between Fleiner and Schollenberger L726/51). The correct legal interpretation of the founding act may be important for the construction of the federation's normative system. But in reality it is obvious that the interpretations very much depend upon the different authors' political postulates (for examples see nos.301,599).

668 What, then, are the reasons for a given federation's genesis? We have to distinguish between two different instances: union of independent states or disintegration of unitary systems. 669 As to union, it is evident that it will take place only where there are common interests to be satisfied, for which existing borders are too narrow (Dahl/Tufte L156a/129s). This is often the case with external affairs and economic concerns. 670 The frequency of some kind of foreign pressure at the time of federation is striking. Riker deduces that this pressure is a necessary prerequisite for union (L660/12s, that it is also a sufficient one, he only presents as a speculation): I infer the existence of at least two circumstances encouraging a willingness to strike the bargain of federalism: 1) The politicians who offer the bargain desire to expand their territorial control, usually either to meet an external military or diplomatic threat or to prepare for military or diplomatic aggression and aggrandizement. ... 2) the politicians who accept the bargain giving up some independence for the sake of union, are willing to to do so because of some external military-diplomatic threat or opportunity. The stringency of Riker's personalization of the founding process is not evident to me (see Sharman L745/17). But otherwise his approach is plausible. It is, after all, not new as increased strength in foreign affairs is one of the classic justifications for federation. 671 As a matter of fact, there has always been some external pressure at the time of a federation's founding. This has been the case even for Australia (L660/27) and Switzerland (L73/149s). But there are many cases where even in the face of such pressure no federation emerges, e.g. the West Indies (L695/100). And we should not forget that the existence of external threats is a permanent condition in international relations. To designate their existence with Riker as decisive for any federation's emergence appears to be somewhat far-fetched in the cases of Australia (L660/27), Austria after the Second World War (L660/38), the Federal Republic of Germany (L660/37, the Prussian aspirations for hegemony in the nineteenth century would have offered a better illustration), Nigeria (L660/31), and Yugoslavia (L660/40). Monocausal explanations are neat and tidy. But this one neglects all the other socio-political factors. Whether external pressures are actually perceived as a justification for union, and for federation, depends very much on political factors that may rarely be traced back to only one motive. All we can say with empirical certainty is that external pressure is a very important factor for federation. 672 A further reason for federation, perhaps even more so for confederacy, is the economic one: bigger markets or a stronger position in international trade negotiations. On the other hand, economic considerations sometimes have a negative

influence on federation. If for example the wealth disparities are such that rich member units have the impression that they will (or do) not benefit from subsidizing poorer ones, they may be tempted not to join (or to leave) the federation. This may wreck the latter's chances of emergence (or survival). Illustrations may be found with the Mali Federation (L230/2s), Nigeria (L528/143), and the West Indian Federation (L223/19, L249/115s, L384/72s, L834/78, for further examples see L528/15,129). A somewhat different example is provided by the Federation of Rhodesia and Nyasaland, where despite economic advantages the federation broke up because of Southern Rhodesia's racist policies (L249/82, L528/132ss).
673 It would appear that federation is not exactly a regime for have-nots. A study of Vieira (according to L744/175) comes to the conclusion that the greatest degree of centralization is to be found in the poorest countries whereas highly decentralized ones are usually rich. The same result is arrived at by Sharkansky in a comparison of U.S. states. Here, too, it is in the rich states where local autonomy is especially developed.

674 The second mechanism for federation mentioned above (no.668) is disintegration of unitary states. In the real world, this has rarely been successful. Only Brazil, Czechoslovakia, and the Soviet Union, from all modern federations, have such an origin, and these countries are not usually considered to be typical illustrations of federalism. Indeed, the latter two proved to be rather unstable. It is sometimes said that the Federal Republic of Germany was built on the ruins of unitary Nazi Germany. But in fact the federal tradition of Germany is much older and has been very influential in shaping the post World War II federation. We would also have to recognize that, technically speaking, the German lnder after 1945 were organized as states some years before the emergence of the Federal Government. The case of Austria after the Second World War is similar. As to the Austrian federation after World War I, we have to admit that its predecessor was not a federation. But it was a multinational empire, based on the unification of its parts and with many federalist elements. Yugoslavia after the Second World War was created by unifying its parts. The country disintegrated into federation before the unitarian regime became really consolidated. And it has now disintegrated even further.
675 Scelle holds (L700/12): Contrary to what is often maintained, segregation, by legal differentiation, is the original form of federalism. This is true only if we equate federalism to decentralization, thus rendering the first concept superfluous, i.e. logically unnecessary. Before a legal system may be differentiated it has to be built. We could only follow Scelle if we considered the legal hierarchy of norms as existing by itself, and if we would define federalism in the somewhat unusual way of Fleiner (L782/1028) as the renunciation of the supreme level of government to fully enforce its sovereignty ... in favour of the autonomy of territorially circumscribed units (no.293).

676 Bumlin is probably right when he insists (L54/147) that viable federalism is only possible where the parts antedate the whole: Federalism is, on the other hand, hardly possible where it is introduced from above. It is unlikely that units created from above may ever strip off their artificial character, and that they, as creatures of the national state, may ever become a focus for social power.
677 If the emergence of federations by disintegration is historically exceptional, it may nevertheless be the case that in the future this way may become more important. I am not thinking of the formation

of federations proper, but of part-regionalized states where some, but not all, regions are given a degree of autonomy that is similar to that of a federation's member state (no.403).

F.2 DURABILITY OF FEDERATIONS

Contents Index End

678 'You can sell federalism like soap or anything else, and that's exactly what we have to do', says Jean-Claude Nolin. Nolin, president of the anti-independence Quebec-Canada movement, is getting ready to launch what he hopes will be one of the most effective jobs Quebec has ever seen the selling of Canadian federalism (P.C.O. Regional Analysis Unit 26.5.1977).

679 Maybe to guarantee the survival of a federation is not as easy as that. Any federation stands for a state of equilibrium. Equilibriums may change into complete consolidation or total disintegration. The very dynamics of federalism tend toward its own destruction: a centralized state in one case, a dissolution into fragments in the other (Friedrich L277/64). Which direction is taken or whether the original status is maintained depends on a great variety of factors. 680 The question of durability is that of a federation's stability. This, in turn and one step further, is the problem of the stability of the political system as such. It is one that has been extensively treated in the connection of federalism's role in the political system's stability (no.540ss). What has been said there generally applies here also - it is therefore unnecessary to repeat it. Here as there, political culture has a key function (L451/92). The political conventions and institutions especially again play a double role. On the one hand, they are the mechanisms to achieve consensus in daily politics. But on the other hand, their very existence furthers the survival of regional subcultures which are then the reason for the continuation of the federal structure (no.591, L486/28s, L533/19s, L660/111). In federations where federalism is but weakly expressed, as for instance in South America, this weakness may be traced back to the absence of a strong federalist political culture (Dikshit L173/165ss, Vliz L830/150ss). 681 Another factor in federal stability has to do with the size and numbers of member states. This aspect is dealt with in the German companion Volume (L264b/713ss). It is evident that the continued existence of the reasons that lead to a federation's emergence, e.g. foreign pressure, will further consolidate it.

682 It is the structure and the behaviour of other socialsub-systems, such as associations, political parties, churches, and the media, that have an additional and decisive influence on the continuity of federalist institutions. It is these we shall now examine. Public institutions which have the same kind of influence are analysed in the German companion Volume: division of powers (L264b/886ss, 1553ss), public finance (L264b/1095ss), constitutional review (L264b/1244ss), member state participation (L264b/1301ss), etc. 683 Government is a society's most visible impersonation. But it is at the same time the society's most elaborately formalized aspect. Thus it is not always easy to perceive the constitutional reality behind the constitutional rhetoric. The social sub-systems just mentioned are less entangled in formal restrictions. Therefore, we may assume that they are relatively good indicators of political forces and evolutionary tendencies. If it is but a hypothesis that a society's diverse authority and organizational patterns run parallel, it is at least a plausible hypothesis and one that is strengthened by comparative politics. A study of federal sub-systems also shows that they are relevant for statements about the federalist character of the formal structure of a federation and the centralizing and decentralist forces at work. 684 Amongst these sub-systems we find associations and societies of all kinds. Insofar as they correspond with broadly based interests, distributed over the whole national territory, they usually follow the federalist model. There are local shooting, gymnastics, trade union, and other societies. These have their state sections and they are united in national associations. That by itself does not sufficiently characterize their federalist nature, which is mainly dependent on the organization of decision making. As to this, we may see that in Switzerland local aspects in an association's decision making process very much colour even national questions (L782/492,514,947). In Austria, on the other hand, it is conspicuous that similar associations have a rather centralist influence, i.e. that there is a clear pre-eminence of national over local viewpoints (L20/56ss, L214/123). USA is in a middle position. There has also been an emergence of decentralist groups in connection with the growth of decentralist central government programmes. They have come about as a result of the cartelization, at the federal level, of congressional, administrative, and beneficiary interests, which have then been decentralized to other levels (L45/19, L840/31). 685 The type of association most suited and best analysed for our purposes is the political party. 686 If in a single-party system the dominant party is monolithic, that is, totalitarian or authoritarian, and internally not federated, such a party cannot permit its monopolistic power to be in any real sense decentralized, divided, distributed, or diluted. The one-party monopoly puts in grave doubt the reality of federalism in countries such as the Soviet-Union, Latin-American federations, ... Pakistan, ... Yugoslavia, and Czechoslovakia (Duchacek L180/330). Although the parties even in the countries just mentioned show a federalist structure (for Czechoslovakia see

L313/21s), their will is not formed through federalist processes but mainly by central decision (this corresponds to the ideology of democratic centralism, no.100ss). Still, it is possible that the formal structure is increasingly used for the expression of noncentral concerns. This was, for instance, quite obviously the case in Yugoslavia. When I wrote this paragraph in 1986 I said: Where this might lead is still open. Yugoslavia has an extremely federalist constitution that, in certain respects, is rather akin to a confederacy (e.g. the individual member state's power of veto, C295s). At the same time, the demographic tensions are strong. If the decentralist tendencies were not balanced by a centralizing ideology embodied in the League of Communists, the stability of the whole system might well be endangered. What I did not foresee was the bloody nature of this "instability".
687 India is another federation riddled with a great number of divisive tensions. Since its foundation, the Congress Party has played a similarly unifying and stabilizing function for India as the League of Communists has for Yugoslavia. But as a result of the deconcentration of the Congress Party and with the disappearance of the unifying ideology of the independence struggle, the Party has become less cohesive, i.e. a closer parallel to Indian demographic reality. Local lobbies play an increasingly important role. It is, therefore, quite uncertain what the future of this highly centralized (highly centralized at least on paper) federation will be, if we consider the disintegration of some of its main unifyingsub-structures (L307/71ss, L338/38, L660/121s, L672/4s; as to similar problems in Malaysia see L213/5,24; in Cameroon an opposite development led to the emergence of a unitary state, L459/120,134, L682/150).

688 Political parties have a double function in relation to the durability of a federation. On the one hand, they stabilize the federation because their activities are connected to a large degree with the latter's existence. On the other hand -and this is different from federation to federation- they also stabilize member state identity. 689 As to the first aspect, Rose/Urwin concluded as follows in their analysis of regional differentiations in the Western world (L670/46): Parties play a unifying role in the maintenance of the state insofar as they accept the authority of the regime within the boundaries it claims ... Stated positively, the chief finding in this paper is that party competition today is a force that maintains (i.e., it fails to challenge) the integration of the state. As a rule, branches of national parties are to be found in all regions. Only in Belgium, Canada, and Switzerland do we find parties that limit themselves to specific parts of the country, or national parties that are practically nonexistent in certain parts of it (L670/24,31,37s,44). 690 The stabilizing influence on regional identity, on the other hand, is based on local and member state influences on party politics. 691 These influences are very important in Switzerland. A typical political career starts at the local level, proceeds to the canton, and culminates at the federal level. It is not unusual for some member of the federal parliament to be at the same time also a member of the cantonal one. He may even still hold an executive office in his commune. Observers agree that the most influential political level of Swiss parties is their cantonal one (L491/43, L782/588s, 1039,1154). Because there are many nationwide polls in Switzerland, in addition to elections, it is possible to infer differences

between the parties' levels from deviations in their recommendations. If we take the parties represented on the federal government (numerically the most important ones), this deviance is between 13,4% (Social Democrats) and 40% (Radicals) of the total sum of such recommendations (L730/125s). The comparatively low degree of centralization of Swiss parties corresponds to their very restricted central staff which cannot act as a centralizing force (L818/143s, Swiss party staff are small on any level). 692 In the United States, also, both national parties are to a high degree noncentralized. Since there is no legal connection between state and national party organizations, each American political party is separately organized on the national and state levels. In other words, a major party is made up of fifty different state organizations and a single national organization that has no legal authority over the state components (Maddox L504/270, see L46/30s, L113/196ss, L194/70, L310/8, L660/129, L835/21). The national party organization's existence is mainly linked to national elections and especially to that of the President. Neither Democrats nor Republicans have great staffs because these are directly at the service of the individual members of Congress. An additional characteristic of American parties is their nonideological basis, because they do not require any qualifications for membership. The possibility of becoming a member of a specific party is a constitutionally guaranteed individual right (Loewenstein L493/400). In the words of Bryce (L98/131): The two great American parties have been compared to empty bottles, into which any liquor might be poured, so long as the labels were retained. All these factors make for a federal legislature with distinctly local flavour. But this is not to say that the policies of Congress are particularly friendly to the states in general. Preference is rather given to the furthering of specific substantive local or state concerns. Nevertheless, the important element for the durability of the federal system is the fact that the political parties as such do not have a centralizing tendency (see Riker L660/91,101). 693 The great Canadian parties are represented nation-wide. But it is typical for them organizationally to make a clear distinction between the national and the provincial levels. Both are relatively independent from each other. Links between the national and the provincial levels of government are provided through the operation of political parties with the same name. For the most part, organizational ties between these parties are so loose, that solidarity often exists in name only (Schwartz L736/306, also L349/131s, L753/31s,196, L758/12s). It is a peculiarity of the Canadian party system that at the federal level the government is regularly in the hands of one of the two main parties. In the provinces, on the other hand, these two parties often face a strong regional party which is at best a splinter-party nationally (L660/118). This may be one of the reasons why more than half of the electors vote differently in federal and in provincial elections (L736/153s, L763/132s). As to political career patterns, these are more influenced by the British parliamentary system than by the Swiss or U.S. counterparts: members of the national parliament usually enter politics directly at that level, without first running for member state office (L758/12). To sum up: the Canadian party system's influence on the federation's

durability is such that it does not bridge the differences between the centre and the member units. It even tends to consolidate them. 694 The Australian parties, too, are organized differently at federal and state levels. This holds true for both the Liberals (and the National Country Party, their allies on the federal level) and for the Australian Labor Party (L660/119). As to federalist ideology, Labor has been more inclined since federation towards centralism, whereas the Liberals have been more favourable to federalism. Once in power, all national parties tend to adopt centralizing policies (L148/26, L523/86, L768/18ss). But this last phenomenon is not exclusive to Australia (L813/87). The party system demonstrates that, despite frequently proffered assertions, Australia is nowadays divided into markedly differentiated regions that make the continued existence of federation very probable. It is true that there are not many ethnic differences among states. But the fact that the political and other sub-systems are based on a federalist pattern, and the existence of various geographical as well as economic differences in interests, have led to the emergence of a markedly federalist political culture. 695 In Austria the most important parties are the Sozialistische Partei sterreichs (SPOe, Socialist Party of Austria) and the sterreichische Volkspartei (OeVP, Austrian People's Party). Their strength is different in the various parts of the country. The OeVP has its power bases in the North, the West, and the Southeast, the SPOe is strong in Vienna, Carinthia, and in some other, mainly industrialized, regions (L20/33). This is by itself a strong guarantee for the continued existence of the federal system. But apart from that Austrian parties are quite centralized. The question why Austria's political parties are not more federalist in their organization, is easy to answer from a sociological point of view. The principal offices of the most influential parties are established in Vienna. The Socialist and the Freedom parties are largely centralized. It is only the conservative-liberal OeVP that has a certain federalist structure which might contribute to the furthering of federalist interests (Ermacora L214/115). But even the political parties in the lnder don't show real federalist particularities. They are Vienna-oriented. It does seem that there is a certain internal augmentation of the influence of Landeshauptmnner ('member-state premiers') ... The pull of the Landeshauptleute in federal politics or, to be more correct, in the politics of the party headquarters, is on the increase (Ermacora L214/115). But in his summingup Ermacora nevertheless arrives at the conclusion: Party interests have swallowed federalism (L214/65). 696 The situation in the Federal Republic of Germany is again different. Bothe (L782/1131s): The party system mirrors in a certain way the federal divisions. ... Central leadership uses reins which are more or less in evidence with the different parties. They are tightest in the case of the Social Democrats. The 'Lnder barons' do have a considerable regional allegiance, but this is already a matter of federal politics. The parties are by far not as decentralized as in Switzerland, and their policies are formulated to a much greater degree by the centres. Laufer (L454/76): The political parties consider federal and lnder politics mainly from the viewpoint of national strategy, and they shape their tactics accordingly. Therefore, permanent attempts of

the federal party organizations at bringing the lnder organizations into line are obvious. They try to campaign in lnder elections under federal slogans, and to influence in the formation of lnder governments under the aspect of the party composition of the Federal Council. (Also Lehmbruch L466/125ss.) The German parties have large central staffs which have a certain technocratic and thus centralizing influence on politics (no.468). It is probable that the existence of the German Federal Council (Bundesrat), with the lnder's exceptionally strong position in Bonn (L264b/1355ss), has had a decisive influence on the emergence of central dominance in the political parties (as to the Weimar Republic see L218/47). On the other hand, member state and local influence on central decisions is still quite obvious, supported as it is by lnder power bases (L356/29). And because the only chance of a large opposition party to exercise power in the parliamentary system of Germany is to be found in the lnder and, through them, in the Federal Council, it is in the interest of the parties to maintain this system (Thieme L800/152). All this may leave the reader with a functionalist/mechanistic impression. This is consistent with the predominant ideology of federalism in the greater part of Germany (except Bavaria), where the technical aspects of federalism are emphasized and uniformity of conditions (C72/2) is a powerful stimulus to centralization. 697 Nigeria's problem is completely different. Here it is the existence of tribal loyalties that endangers the federation's stability. The Constitution of 1979 (largely in abeyance since the end of 1983) therefore attempted to force the parties into transtribal organization. Thus article 202 specified amongst other things: No association by whatever name called shall function as a political party, unless ... b) the membership of the association is open to every citizen of Nigeria irrespective of his place of origin, sex, religion or ethnic grouping; ... c) the name of the association, its emblem or motto does not contain any ethnic or religious connotation or give the appearance that the activities of the association are confined to a part only of the geographical area of Nigeria; ... and f) the headquarters of the association is situated in the Capital of the Federation. The internal organization of the parties was also regulated to achieve the same goal (C203): 1) The constitution and rules of a political party shall ... b) ensure that the members of the executive committee or other governing body of the political party reflect the federal character of Nigeria. 2) For the purposes of this section ... b) the members of the executive committee or other governing body of the political party shall be deemed to reflect the federal character of Nigeria only if the members thereof belong to different states not being less in number than two-thirds of all the states comprising the Federation. It is obvious that such regulations may be formally respected while materially neglected. Up to the military take-over in December 1983 a certain but rather modest decrease in tribal tensions seemed to have taken place. But whether the intentions of the 1979 constituents will be realized in the long run is very much an open question (Nwabueze L583a/27). I have a feeling that politically Nigeria would be more stable if it were split up into two or three federations. 698 A further sub-system that has a decisive influence on the evolution of federalism is the information industry, especially television, radio, and the printed

press. To the extent that these have a local or sub-national character they add to the survival of the corresponding regional identities. There are not many studies addressing this question. In Switzerland with her many national votes it would be quite interesting, for instance, to see whether there is any correlation between the distribution of the regional media and regionally cast votes. 699 But generally the media seem also to have a strongly centralizing impact. To some degree this may be traced back to technology. Until now, because of the costs involved, technological progress has been accompanied by an enlargement of the distribution area. This has especially been the case for television and for newspaper printing techniques. As to the latter, the result has been the national circulation of some papers and the emergence of press conglomerates where mainly uniform texts are printed under the headings of formerly independent newspapers. National media have to address a national public. This of necessity leads to a certain neglect of regional issues (at least in the smaller federations). In the words of LaRoche, editorin-chief of the biggest Swiss tabloid (L782/1108s): What should we print about the cantons? How much of cantonal life might interest the big public which is not a political elite? - Any fairly extensive opinion poll will immediately show that there is only an interest for specifically cantonal happenings if they a) have folkloristic entertainment value, or if they b) concern some spicy question ... that is common to all cantons. If these two factors are missing, the interest for some extra-cantonal event is minimal. It is a sort of national hybrid culture that is thus furthered. The chance of local variation has declined. This may be a function of ... mobility ..., but more likely it is a function of a general national effort to approximate a national middle-class culture, as set forth by movies, magazines, news agencies, television, etc. (Riker L660/110). Looked at closely, this national hybrid culture is mainly the sum of the media makers' values and experiences at the media headquarters (L198/30, L201/260). Or it is the sum of urban and mainly big city values. If we further consider that the larger part of any population is politically apathetic, consuming political information from the national media (mainly television) in a greatly simplified form if at all, the centralizing effects are even more pronounced.
700 The existence of different languages in some federations is, on the other hand, to that extent a strong barrier to the centralizing influence of the media. 701 The further evolution of technology might also bring about a certain reversal of the tendencies just described. I am especially thinking of the new possibilities for local television.

702 Economy also has a special position. In the economic field, it is the building of the larger market which makes the development of mass production industries possible that has provided the main objective. Indeed, this objective is likely to prove in the long run the more permanent substructure of a federal edifice than the interest in common defense. A comparative study of federal systems shows that a large market promotes a multitude of common interests and an accompanying dense network of interpersonal relations, from mere verbal communication as expressed in a lingua franca to connubium as the acknowledged expression of close community (Friedrich L275/8). If economic structure has generally had a stabilizing influence on federation in the sense of countering disintegrationist tendencies (as evidenced by the federalist

European Economic Communities), it is also centralizing because most socialist interventions in the economy (e.g. nationalization of private enterprises) can only be organized at a central level. Furthermore, national and in some instancestrans-national economic concentration tends to sap the autonomy ofsmall-area governments (L637/5-2/118). 703 Social Science is a further sub-system. In federations it has had mainly centralizing effects (newer developments in the United States excepted). Legal science is mainly concerned with the central government. The variety of member state institutions is neglected as being of secondary importance. Hfliger, for instance, comments on the state of Swiss procedural codification with the following words (L782/772s): The diversity of the codes of procedure also obstructs their scientific penetration. Fully fledged lawyers as well as students looking for a thesis are little tempted to start an inquiry into, for instance, seizure under the legislation of Solothurn. There are too few prospective readers. Penal law demonstrates that legal unification furthers scientific treatment. Since its codification the scientific treatment of Swiss penal law has received a fresh impetus. This argument is not without merit. Still, there is another possible explanation for the centralizing tendency of scholarly inquiry, this one psychological. Beer (L57/79): But there is a more deep-seated reason why scientific knowledge should tend to produce centralization in higher jurisdictions and why persons trained in scientific disciplines should seek wider arenas for the application of their technique. By its nature scientific knowledge is general: that is, it has validity free of reference to any particular time or place. The knowledge that the professional and scientist brings to public policy is theoretical. It can be applied to similar problems whenever and wherever they arise. The very mental equipment of such a person therefore leads him to turn to that government which can deal with all such problems on the widest possible scale. As John Stuart Mill once remarked: '... centralization is based on general ideas; that is, the desire for power to attend in a uniform and general way, to the present and future needs of society.' Scientific rationalism (like rationalism of any sort) has this strong tendency toward uniformity and centralization. The connection with intellectual sthetics as discussed above (no.531ss) is evident. 704 This short list of sub-systems demonstrates that several of them have not only stabilizing but also centralizing effects. Nevertheless and despite centralizing tendencies, all classical federations show that federalism retains a remarkable tenacity. Recently, this has been strengthened by a renaissance of localism. I think that this revived localism has its roots in the existential insecurity of the individual in a world that has become incalculably complex and is faced with catastrophic extinction. The only thing that has remained clear and distinct, thereby imparting a sense of security, is man's local environment. This is something he may grasp with his senses. As to federations, many opinion surveys of the last few years show that, contrary to rationalistic expectations, local governments and, especially, member states are again considered to be more efficient than central governments, and that since the Second World War the number of those who favour the abolition of member states has been declining (Canada: L736/216, L753/205s; Federal Republic of Germany: L107/1ss;

USA: L637/7-1/33s, L647/153,162, L871/60s). Either centralizing tendencies have not had sufficient time to succeed fully, or they have been counteracted to a considerable degree by demographic differences and a fragmented political culture. It also seems that, at least in the classical federations, the advantages of federalism's problem solving mechanisms are being increasingly recognized by the citizens of those federations.

CONSTITUTIONS
(articles prefaced C in the text)

Contents Index End

Argentina: Constitucin de la Nacin Argentina (as amended up to 1983) Australia: Commonwealth of Australia Constitution Act (as altered to 1 July 1985 Austria: Bundes-Verfassungsgesetz in der Fassung von 1929 (as amended up to 15.9.1983) Bundesverfassungsgesetz vom 21. Jnner 1948 ber die Regelung der finanziellen Beziehungen zwischen dem Bund und den brigen Gebietskrperschaften (Finanz-Verfassungsgesetz, as amended up to 15.9.1983) Brazil: Constituio da Repblica Federativa do Brasil (as amended up to 31.10.1982) Canada: Constitution Act 1867 (as amended up to 1984) Constitution Act 1982 Comores: Constitution (1.10.1978) Czechoslovakia: Constitution of the Czechoslovak Socialist Republic (as amended up to 1.9.1978) Constitutional law on the Czechoslovak Federation of 27.10.1968 (as amended up to 1982) Constitutional law on the status of the nationalities in the Czechoslovak Socialist Republic of 27.10.1968 No.144 Germany: Verfassung des Deutschen Reichs vom 16.4.1871 Verfassung des Deutschen Reichs (Weimar Constitution) vom 11.8.1919 Grundgesetz fr die Bundesrepublik Deutschland (as amended up to 1.10.1985) India: The Constitution of India (as amended up to 1.11.1983) Malaysia: Federal Constitution (incorporating all amendments up to 15th December 1983) Mexiko: Constitucin Poltica de los Estados Unidos Mexicanos (as amended up to March 1983) Nigeria: The Constitution of the Federal Republic of Nigeria (with the amendments up to September

28, 1979) Decree No.1 of the Federal Military Government (31.12.1983) (With this decree the democratic structures of Nigeria as well as the federal allocation of functions fall largely into abeyance) Pakistan: The Constitution of the Islamic Republic of Pakistan (as amended up to 28.7.1983) The Provisional Constitution Order, 1981 (as amended up to 30.8.1982; this order abrogates primarily Pakistan's democratic and parliamentary structures) Soviet Union: Constitution of the Union of Soviet Socialist Republics of 7.10.1977 (as amended up to 31.1.84) Switzerland: Bundesverfassung der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft (as amended up to 1.10.1985) Tanzania: The Constitution of the United Republic of Tanzania (as amended up to 1983) Treaty for East African Co-operation (6.6.1967) United Arab Emirates: The Provisional Constitution of the United Arab Emirates (as reconducted and amended through February 1982) U S A : The Constitution of the United States of America (as amended through October 1985) Venezuela: Constitucin de la Repblica de Venezuela (as amended up to 15.2.1984) Yugoslavia: Constitution of the Socialist Federal Republic of Yugoslavia of 21.2.1974 (with the amendments of 9.7.1981)

BIBLIOGRAPHY
(prefaced L in the text, including those cited in L264a and L264b)

Contents Index End 001 Abendroth, Wolfgang: Demokratie als Institution und Aufgabe, in: L524/156-170 002 Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations: The Advisory Commission on Intergovernmental Relations, Washington 1967 003 Federalism and the academic community, Washington 1969 004 In search of balance - Canada's intergovernmental experience, Washington 1971 005 Significant Features of Fiscal Federalism, 1976 edition, 1. Trends, Washington 1976 006 Significant Features of Fiscal Federalism, 1978-79 edition, Washington 1979 007 Significant Features of Fiscal Federalism, 1979-80 edition, Washington 1980 008 Pragmatic Federalism, Washington 1976 009 Summary and Concluding Observations, The Intergovernmental Grant System, Washington 1978 010 The Federal Role in the Federal System, Washington 1981 011 Advisory Council for Inter-government Relations: Annual Report, Canberra 1979ss 012 Intergovernmental Relations in the United States, Canberra 1979

013 Towards Adaptive Federalism, Canberra 1981 013a The Australian Loan Council and Intergovernmental Relations, Canberra 1982 014 Agyeman-Dickson, John de' Graft Duah: Federation in West Africa, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1953 015 Akinyemi, A. Bolaji / Cole, P. Dele / Ofonagoro, Walter I.: Readings on Federalism, Lagos 1979 016 Albright, Spencer D. / Walters, Jess H.: Virginia, in: L198/68-76 017 Alexander, Fred: Australia since Federation, Reprint, Melbourne 1969 018 Alfldi, Andreas: Das frhe Rom und die Latiner, Darmstadt 1977 019 Almond, Gabriel A. / Verba, Sidney (eds.): The Civic Culture revisited, Boston 1980 020 Altenstetter, Christa: Der Fderalismus in sterreich, Heidelberg 1969 021 Intergovernmental Profiles in the Federal Systems of Austria and West Germany, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 (final version inL637/5-2/89-116) 022 The Rediscovery of Federalism, in: L395/217-237 023 American Academy of Political and Social Science: The Annals (various volumes) 024 Ames, Herman V.: State Documents on Federal Relations, New York 1970 025 Anastopoulos, Jean: L'Ordre Financier de la Fdration Sovitique, in: L222/203-316 026 Les Aspects Financiers du Fdralisme, Paris 1979 027 Anderson, Roger Charles: The functional Role of the Governors and their States in the Political Development of Mexico, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1971 028 Anschtz, Gerhard: Der deutsche Fderalismus in Vergangenheit, Gegenwart und Zukunft, in: L833/1924/11-34 029 Die Verfassung des Deutschen Reiches vom 11. August 1919, 11. Auflage, Berlin 1928 030 Antieau, C.J.: Forecasting the Future of Federalism, manuscript, Ottawa 1974 031 Anton, Thomas J.: Macht, Pluralismus und Lokalpolitik, in: L882/202-222 032 Arendt, Hannah: On Revolution, London 1973 033 The Human Condition, 9th impression, Chicago 1974 034 Aristoteles: Aufzeichnungen zur Staatstheorie (sog. Politik), Kln 1967 (cited by chapter) 035 Ashizo, Uzuhiko: Courtly Grace and Military Rule, in: Japan Echo, vol. III/1, 1976 036 Assmann, Karl / Goppel, Thomas: Fderalismus, Mnchen 1978 037 Aubert, Jean-Franois: Essai sur le fdralisme, in: Revue du Droit Public et de la Scince Politique, Paris 1963 038 Trait de Droit Constitutionnel Suisse, vol. I,II Neuchtel 1967, vol. III Neuchtel 1982 (cited by number) 039 Awa, Eme O.: Federal Government in Nigeria, Berkeley 1964 040 Ayoade, John A.A.: Secession Threat as a Redressive Mechanism in Nigerian Federalism, in: L637/31/57-74 041 042 043 044 045 046 047 048 048a 049 049a 050 051 052 053 054 055 056 057 058 059 060 061 Baars, Bodo A.: Koordininierung zwischen Gebietskrperschaften, in: L42/184-241 Baars, Bodo A. / Baum, Karl B. / Fiedler, Jobst: Politik und Koordinierung, Gttingen 1976 Bacon, Francis: Essays, London 1962 Baines, Tyrone R.: Categorical Grants and the Local Community, in: L637/5-4/101-121 Baker, Earl M.: The Federal Polity, Agenda, Philadelphia 1974 The Federal Polity, Review and Digest, Philadelphia 1974 Bakounine, Michel: Oeuvres, Tome I, cinquime dition, Paris 1907 Baloup, Grard: Le Snat des Rgions, Rivista d'Europa, Roma Maggio 1981 Barclay, Harold: People Without Government, London 1982 Barry, Brian M.: Neue Politische Oekonomie, Frankfurt 1975 Barschel, Uwe: Die Staatsqualitt der deutschen Lnder, Heidelberg 1982 Barton, Charles: Regional Development in Queensland, in: L636 vol.iv/1 p.73-76 Barton, Weldon, V.: Interstate Compacts in the Political Process, Chapel Hill 1967 Bastien, Richard: Federalism and decentralization, Ottawa 1981 Baumgartner, J.: Schweizerspiegel, Zrich 1851 Bumlin, Richard: Die rechtsstaatliche Demokratie, Zrich 1954 Bayer, Hermann-Wilfried: Die Bundestreue, Tbingen 1961 Beaudoin, Grald A.: Le Fdralisme de Demain, manuscript, Ottawa 1974 Beer, Samuel H.: The Modernization of American Federalism, in: L637/ 3-2/49-95 A Political Scientist's View of Fiscal Federalism, in: L585/21-46 Bennett, Walter Hartwell: American Theories of Federalism, 2nd printing, Alabama 1967 Beres, Louis Ren: Examining the Logic of World Government, in: L637/ 4-3/75-87 Berg-Schlosser, Dirk: Politische Kultur, Mnchen 1972

062 Bernhardt, Rudolf: Der Abschluss vlkerrechtlicher Vertrge im Bundesstaat, Kln-Berlin 1957 063 Bernier, Ivan: International Legal Aspects of Federalism, London 1973 064 Beyle, Thad L.: New Directions in Interstate Relations, in: L23/416/109-119 065 Beyme, Klaus von: Demokratie, in: L103/12-31 066 Die Funktionen des Bundesrates, in: L106/365-393 067 Bieri, Stephan: Politische Planung in der Schweiz, in: Die Unternehmung 1/1976/39-53, Bern 1976 068 Fiscal Federalism in Switzerland, Canberra 1979 069 Bilfinger, Karl: Der deutsche Fderalismus in Vergangenheit, Gegenwart und Zukunft, in: L833/1924/3559 070 Bird, Richard M. / Hartle, Douglas G.: Modern Fiscal Issues, Toronto 1972 071 Birgersson, Bengt Owe: The Service Paradox, in:L597/243-267 072 Blair, Philip M.: Federalism and Judicial Review in West Germany, Oxford 1981 073 Blumer, J.J. / Morel, J.: Handbuch des schweizerischen Bundesstaatsrechtes, 1. Band, 3. Auflage, Basel 1891 074 Bluntschli, Johann Caspar: Politik als Wissenschaft, Stuttgart 1876 075 Allgemeine Staatslehre, 6. Auflage, Stuttgart 1886 076 Boadway, Robin W.: Intergovernmental Transfers in Canada, Toronto 1980 077 Bonnard, Claude: Fdralisme coopratif, Soleure 1969 (cited by numbers) 078 Boogman, J.C. / van der Plaat, G.N. (ed.): Federalism, The Hague 1980 079 Boorstin, Daniel J.: Democracy and its Discontents, New York 1975 079a Bopp, Lon: Philosophie Fdrative, Genve 1952 080 Borden, Morton: The Antifederalist Papers, (Michigan) 1965 081 Borter, Willy: Demokratiegebot und interkantonales Vertragsrecht, Freiburg. i.Ue. 1976 082 Bothe, Michael: Die Kompetenzstruktur des modernen Bundesstaates in rechtsvergleichender Sicht, Berlin 1977 083 Boustedt, Olaf: Grundriss der empirischen Regionalforschung, Teil I, Hannover 1975 084 Brams, Steven J.: Game Theory and Politics, New York 1975 085 Break, George F.: Financing Government in a Federal System, Washington D.C. 1980 086 Brecht, Arnold: Politische Theorie, Tbingen 1961 087 Breton, Albert / Scott, Anthony: The economic constitution of federal states, Toronto 1978 088 Brierly, J.L.: The Law of Nations, 6th ed., reprint, London 1976 089 Bright, John: Geschichte Israels, Dsseldorf 1966 090 Briner, Hans: The Three Country Region of Basle, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 091 Brockhaus Enzyklopdie: Band 6, Wiesbaden 1968 092 Brougham, Henry: Historical Sketches of Statesmen who flourished in the Time of George III, New Series, Paris 1844 093 Browning, Rufus P. / Marshall, Dale Rogers: Implementation of Model Cities and Revenue Sharing in Ten Bay Area Cities, in: L395/191-216 094 Brugmans, Henri: Le Fdralisme, in: L95/9-69 095 Brugmans, Henri / Duclos, Pierre: Le Fdralisme Contemporain, Leyden 1963 096 Bryce, James: The American Commonwealth, New Edition, vol. I, New York 1919 097 The American Commonwealth, New Edition, vol. II, New York 1919 098 Modern Democracies, vol. I, London 1921 099 Modern Democracies, vol. II, London 1921 100 Buchanan, James / Tullock, Gordon: The Calculus of Consent, Ann Arbor 1974 101 The Politics and Bureaucracy of Planning, in: L390/255-273 102 Buchmann, Kurt: Die Brgergemeinde, St.Gallen 1977 103 Buck, Hans-Robert: Demokratie, Mnchen 1974 104 Blck, Hartwig: Fderalismus als internationales Ordnungsprinzip, in: L833/1964/1-65 105 Bulletin International des Sciences Sociales: Bulletin trimestriel, Unesco, Paris 106 Bundesrat: Der Bundesrat als Verfassungsorgan und politische Kraft, Bad Honnef 1974 107 Mitteilung an die Presse, 2/76, Bonn 10.1.1977 108 Burckhardt, Walther: Methode und System des Rechts, Zrich 1936, Nachdruck 1971 109 Die Organisation der Rechtsgemeinschaft, 2. Auflage, Zrich 1944, Nachdruck 1971 110 Aufstze und Vortrge 1910-1938, Bern 1970 111 Burke, Edmond: Reflections on the Revolution in France, London 1964 112 Burkhead, Jesse: Federalism in a Unitary State, in: L637/4-2/39-61 113 Burns, James MacGregor: Congress on Trial, New York 1949 114 Burns, John: The Sometime Governments, New York 1971 115 Burns, Ron M.: Political & Administrative Federalism, Canberra 1976

116 Burrows, Bernard / Denton, Geoffrey / Edwards, Geoffrey: Federal Solutions to European Issues, London 1978 117 Devolution or Federalism? London 1980 118 Butler, David / Ranney, Austin: Referendums, Washington 1978 119 Calhoun, John C.: A Disquisition on Government, New York 1943 120 Canadian Study of Parliament Group: Seminar on the Senate, Ottawa 1979 121 Carlyle, Thomas: Essays, Scottish and other Miscellanies, London 1964 122 Essays, English and other Miscellanies, London 1964 123 The French Revolution, Volume Two, London 1973 124 Carter George E.: New Directions in Financing Canadian Federalism, Canberra 1980 125 Cassirer, Ernst: The Myth of the State, 13th printing, New Haven 1975 126 Celler, Emanuel: The Constitution of the United States of America, Washington 1967 127 Chapman, Brian: The Profession of Government, London 1959 128 Chapman, Ralph J.K.: Moderating Institutions, manuscript, Hobart 1980 129 Regionalism, national development and governmental arrangements, Canberra 1982 130 Charlesworth, James C.: Allocation of Responsibilities and Resources among the Three Levels of Governments, in: L23/359/71-80 131 Chesterfield, Philip Dormer Stanhope: Letters to his Son and Others, London 1969 132 Churchman, C. West: The systems approach, 8th printing, New York w.o.d. 133 Clark Jane Perry: Interdependent Federal and State Law as a Form of Federal-State Cooperation, in: L399/539-564 134 Cole, Taylor: Federalism in the Commonwealth, manuscript, Geneva 1964 135 Commission de dveloppement des responsabilits locales: Vivre ensemble, Paris 1976 136 Commission de l'unit canadienne: Se Retrouver, Ottawa 1979 137 Dfinir pour choisir, Ottawa 1979 138 Commission on intergovernmental relations: Final Report, Washington 1955 139 Commission Royale d'Enqute sur les Problmes Constitutionnels: Rapport, vol. II w.o.pl. (Qubec) 1956 140 Rapport, vol. III tome I, w.o.pl. (Qubec) 1956 141 Committee for Economic Development: A Fiscal Program for a Balanced Federalism, New York 1967 142 Commonwealth Grants Commission: First Report on Financial Assistance for Local Government, Canberra 1974 143 Forty-eighth Report, Canberra 1981 144 Second Report on Special Assistance for the Northern Territory, Canberra 1981 145 Conseil de l'Europe: Bulletin d'Information, Questions municipales et rgionales, Strasbourg 1981 146 Dcentralisation de l'administration locale au niveau des quartiers, Strasbourg 1981 147 Constant, Benjamin: uvres Politiques, Paris 1874 148 The Constitutional Convention: A new attempt at Australian constitutional review, w.o.pl. (Canberra), w.o.d. (1974) 149 Cooper, James Fenimore: The American Democrat, Harmondsworth 1969 150 Council of State Governments: State Government News, Lexington 151 State Government, Quarterly, Lexington 152 The Book of the States 80/81, Lexington 1980 153 Cranston, Ross: From Co-operative to Coercive Federalism and Back? Federal Law Review vol. 10/2, Canberra 1979 154 Crepeau, P.-A. / Macpherson, C.B. (ed.): The Future of Canadian Federalism, Toronto 1965 155 Daalder, Hans: On Building Consociational Nations, in: L532/107-124 156 Dahl, Robert: After the Revolution? 11th printing, New Haven 1976 156a Dahl, Robert / Tufte, Edward R.: Size and Democracy, Stanford 1975 157 Dahrendorf, Ralf: Fundamentale und liberale Demokratie, in: L103/103-117 158 Davis, Rufus S.: The Federal Principle, Berkeley 1978 159 Dehler, Thomas: Das Parlament im Wandel der Staatsidee, in: L498/9-56 160 Dlgation gouvernementale suisse: Rapport sur la Confrence des Ministres europens responsables des collectivits locales 8./9.9.1978, w.o.pl. (Berne) w.o.d. (1978) 161 Dennewitz, Bodo: Der Fderalismus, Hamburg 1947 162 Department of Agriculture: Creative Federalism, Washington 1967 163 Federalism Today, Washington 1969 164 Department of Environment, Housing and Community Development: The Australian Housing Allowance Voucher Experiment, Canberra 1976

165 Deuerlein, Ernst: Fderalismus, Mnchen 1972 166 Deutsch, Karl W.: The Nerves of Government, New York 1967 167 Dexter, Lewis Anthony: Statement on H.R. 11200, Proposing a Compact of Permanent Union between The United States and Puerto Rico, manuscript, Washington 1976 168 Di Marzo, Luigi: Component Units of Federal States and International Agreements, Alphen aan den Rijn 1980 169 Diamond, Martin: The Ends of Federalism, in: L637/3-2/129-152 170 Dicey, A.V.: Introduction to the study of the law of the constitution, 10th edition, London 1962 171 Dichter, Ernest: Strategie im Reich der Wnsche, Mnchen 1964 172 Dictionnaire Encyclopdique Quillet: Paris 1969 173 Dikshit, Ramesh Dutta: The Political Geography of Federalism, New York 1975 174 Dimensionen des Rechts: Gedchtnisschrift fr Ren Marcic, Berlin 1974 175 Djordjevi?, Jovan: Remarks on Yugoslav Federalism, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 (final version in L637/5-2/77-88) 176 Les concepts du Fdralisme et du Rgionalisme et leur Evolution, manuscript, Beograd 1979 176a Doerkes-Boppard: Verfassungsgeschichte der Australischen Kolonien und des Commonwealth of Australia, Mnchen 1903 177 Domes, Jrgen: Politische Soziologie der Volksrepublik China, Wiesbaden 1980 177a Donnithorne, Audrey: Centre-Provincial Economic Relations in China, Canberra 1981 178 Dormann, Albert: Interkantonale Institutionen mit Hoheitsbefugnissen, Zrich 1970 179 Dubs, Jakob: Das ffentliche Recht der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft, Zweiter Theil, Zrich 1878 180 Duchacek, Ivo D.: Comparative Federalism, New York 1970 181 External and Internal Challenges to the Federal Bargain, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 (final version in L637/5-2/41-76) 182 Power Maps, Santa Barbara 1973 183 Duclos, Pierre: Le Fdralisme institu, in: L95/71-191 184 L'Etat et le Fdralisme, sixime congrs mondial AISP, manuscript, Genve 1964 185 Durand, Charles: Confdration d'Etats et Etat Fdral, Paris 1955 186 Duverger, Maurice: Institutions politiques et droit constitutionnel, sixime dition, Paris 1962 187 Introduction la politique, Paris 1964 188 Easton, David: A Systems Analysis of Political Life, Chicago 1979 189 Eckstein, Harry: Division and Cohesion in Democracy, Princeton 1966 190 A Theory of Stable Democracy, in: L189/225-288 191 Edelman, Murray: The Symbolic Uses of Politics, 5th printing, Urbana 1972 192 Edner, Sheldon: Intergovernmental Policy Development, in: L395/149-167 193 Ehmke, Horst: Planung im Regierungsbereich, in: L567/311-334 194 Ehringhaus, Henner: Der kooperative Fderalismus in den Vereinigten Staaten von Amerika, Frankfurt am Main 1971 195 Eichenberger, Kurt: Die oberste Gewalt im Bunde, Zrich 1949 196 Eisenhower, Dwight D.: Address to the 1957 Governors' Conference, in: L198/188-193 197 Eisinger, Peter K.: Community Control and Liberal Dilemmas, in: L637/2-2/129-148 198 Elazar, Daniel J.: The Politics of American Federalism, Lexington 1969 199 The Themes of a Journal of Federalism, in: L637/1-1/3-9 200 Civil War and the Preservation of American Federalism, in: L637/1-1/39-58 201 Cursed by Bigness or Toward a Post-Technocratic Federalism, in: L637/3-2/239-298 202 Urbanization in Federal Systems, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 203 Suburbanization, in: L637/5-1/53-79 204 Urbanism and Federalism, in: L637/5-2/15-39 205 The American Cultural Matrix, in: L206/13-42 205a Self Rule / Shared Rule, Ramat Gan 1979 205b Federalism and Political Integration, Ramat Gan 1979 206 Elazar, Daniel J. / Zikmund II, Joseph: The Ecology of American Political Culture, New York 1975 207 Ellwein, Thomas: Das Regierungssystem der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Kln 1963 208 Fragen - Voraussetzungen - Begriffe, in: L103/118-141 209 Der Entscheidungsprozess im Bundesrat, in: L106/213-233 210 Else-Mitchell, R.: The Rise and Demise of Coercive Federalism, in: Australian Journal of Public Administration, vol. vi/2 109-121 211 Elyot, Thomas: The Governor, London 1970 212 Enders, Wolfgang: Der mexikanische Bundesstaat, Bern 1977

213 Enloe, Cynthia H.: The Neglected Strata, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 (final version in L637/5-2/151170) 214 Ermacora, Felix: sterreichischer Fderalismus, Wien 1976 215 sterreichische Bundesverfassungsgesetze, achte Auflage, Stuttgart 1979 216 ber die bundesstaatliche Kostentragung gemss 2 F-VG, Wien 1979 217 Eschenburg, Theodor: Demokratisierung und politische Praxis, in: L103/142-160 218 Bundesrat - Reichsrat - Bundesrat, in: L106/35-62 219 Esterbauer, Fried: Stellung und Reform des Bundesrates, Bayerische Verwaltungsbltter 8/1980/225-229 220 Esterbauer, Fried / Hraud, Guy / Pernthaler, Peter: Fderalismus als Mittel permanenter Konfliktregelung, Wien 1977 221 Esterbauer, Fried / Thni, Erich: Fderalismus und Regionalismus in Theorie und Praxis, Wien 1981 222 Etudes et Documents de Droit Budgtaire Fdral: Paris 1974 223 Etzioni, Amitai: The West Indian Federation, 6th World Congress IPSA, manuscript, Geneva 1964 224 Eulau, Heinz: Theories of Federalism under the Holy Roman Empire, Reprint, Philadelphia w.o.d. 225 Polarity in Representational Federalism, in: L637/3-2/153-171 226 Eulau, Heinz / Wahlke, John C.: The Politics of Representation, Beverley Hills 1978 227 Expertenkommission fr die Vorbereitung einer Totalrevision der Bundesverfassung: Verfassungsentwurf, Bern 1977 228 Bericht, Bern 1977 229 Eynern, Gert von: Wrterbuch zur politischen Oekonomie, Opladen 1973 230 Ezera, Kalu: Federalism and the Quest for National Unity in Africa, 6th World Congress IPSA, manuscript, Geneva 1964 231 Fagagnini, Hans Peter: Kanton und Gemeinde vor ihrer Erneuerung, Bern 1974 232 Farrand, Max: The Records of the Federal Convention of 1787, revised edition, volume I, New Haven 1966 233 Volume II, New Haven 1966 234 Volume III, New Haven 1966 235 Volume IV, New Haven 1966 236 Favre, Antoine: Droit Constitutionnel Suisse, Fribourg 1966 237 Federal-Provincial Relations Office: Federal-Provincial Programs and Activities, Ottawa 1982 237a do., Ottawa 1984 238 Le fdralisme: Problmes et mthodes, in: L105/1952 239 Fetscher, Iring: Pluralistische Demokratie in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, in: L103/161-168 240 Field, G.C.: Political Theory, London 1963 241 Fischer, Walter: Das Austrittsrecht aus Staatenverbindungen, Winterthur 1957 242 Fleiner, Fritz: Bundesstaatliche und gliedstaatliche Rechtsordnung, in: L833/1929/2-24 243 Ausgewhlte Schriften und Reden, Zrich 1941 244 Fleiner, Fritz / Giacometti, Zaccaria: Schweizerisches Bundesstaatsrecht, Neudruck, Zrich 1965 245 Fleiner, Thomas: Die Interstate Compacts in den Vereinigten Staaten, in: L781/21-28 246 Die Gesetzgebung im dreistufigen Bundesstaat, in: Festschrift Hans Nef, p.43-54, Zrich 1981 247 Flora, Federico: Le Finanze degli Stati Composti, Torino 1900 248 Four, Yann: Towards a Federal Europe, Swansea 1980 249 Franck, Thomas M.: Why Federations Fail, New York 1968 250 Franz, Gnther: Staatsverfassungen, 2. Auflage, Darmstadt 1964 251 Freeman, Edward A.: History of Federal Government in Greece and Italy, 2nd edition, London 1893 252 Freisinnig-Demokratische Partei der Schweiz: Stellungnahme zur Totalrevision der Bundesverfassung, Bern 1979 253 Frenkel, Max: Institutionen der Verwaltungskontrolle, Zrich 1969 254 Die Verfassungsmssigkeit von Art. 4/1a und 4/2 der Interkantonalen bereinkunft zur Verstrkung der polizeilichen Sicherheitsmassnahmen vom 28.3.1968, in: Schweizerische Juristen-Zeitung 1970 p.129-135 255 Kooperative und andere Fderalismen, in: Schweizer Monatshefte Januar 1975 p.725-736 256 Die Mitwirkung der Glieder bei der Willensbildung des Bundes in Bundesstaaten, manuscript, Zuchwil 1975 257 Die Finanzierung interkantonaler Organisationen, in: L392/202-209 258 Fderalismus, in: Schweizer Dokumentation fr Politik und Wirtschaft, Bern 1976 259 Fderalismus als Partnerschaft / Partnership in Federalism, Bern 1978 260 Swiss Federalism in the Twentieth Century, in: L495/323-338 261 The viability of the federal formula for new nations, in: L15/260-267 262 Vernehmlassungsverfahren Halbkantone, Dokumentation, Solothurn 1980

263 Optimizing What? Riehen 1980 264 Besser - Billiger - Brgernher, Bern 1981 264a Fderalismus und Bundesstaat, Band I: Fderalismus, Bern 1984 264b Band II: Bundesstaat, Bern 1985 265 Frenkel, Max / Blaser, Toni: Konkordatsregister, Riehen 1981 266 Frey, Ren L.: Infrastruktur, 2. Auflage, Tbingen 1972 267 Der schweizerische Fderalismus, Zeitschrift fr Schweizerisches Recht 1974 p.359-378 268 Zwischen Fderalismus und Zentralismus, Bern 1977 269 The Interregional Income Gap as a Problem of Swiss Federalism, in: L585/93-104 270 Anstze zu einer langfristigen Reform der bundesstaatlichen Aufgabenverteilung, in: Schweizerische Stabilisierungs- und Finanzpolitik p.57-76, Diessenhofen 1978 271 Die konomische Theorie des Fderalismus, Vortragsmanuskript, Innsbruck 1979 272 Fras, Pedro Jos: El Comportamiento Federal en la Argentina, Buenos Aires 1970 273 Friedman, Milton and Rose: Free to Choose, London 1981 274 Friedrich, Carl Joachim: Ursprung und Entwicklung des Begriffs des Fderalismus in den Vereinigten Staaten von Amerika, in: L533a/66-80 275 New Tendencies in Federal Theory and Practice, 6th World Congress IPSA, manuscript, Geneva 1964 276 Pathologie der Politik, Frankfurt 1973 277 Limited Government, Englewood Cliffs 1974 278 Fritschler, A. Lee / Segal, Morley: Intergovernmental Relations and Contemporary Political Science, in: L637/1-2/95-122 279 Fromme, Friedrich Karl: Gesetzgebung im Widerstreit, Stuttgart 1976 280 Funk, Bernd-Christian: Das System der bundesstaatlichen Kompetenzverteilung im Lichte der Verfassungsrechtsprechung, Wien 1980 281 Frst, Dietrich: Fderalismusentwicklung, Finanzausgleichsproblematik und ihre wissenschaftliche Abbildung in den USA, manuscript, Konstanz 1980 282 Gablentz, Otto Heinrich von der: Einfhrung in die Politische Wissenschaft, Kln 1965 283 Gallant, Edgar: The Machinery of Federal-Provincial Relations, in: L535/254-265 284 Ganser, Karl: Politikverflechtung zwischen Bund und Lndern, in: L355/45-73 285 Garn, Harvey A. / Springer, Michael: Formulating Urban Growth Policies, in: L637/5-4/25-49 286 Gasser, Adolf: Staatlicher Grossraum und autonome Kleinrume, Basel 1976 287 Gerloff, Wilhelm: Die Finanzgewalt im Bundesstaat, Frankfurt a.M. 1948 288 Germann, Raimund E.: Vollzugsfderalismus in der Schweiz als Forschungsobjekt, in: Die Verwaltung 1976/2/223-241, Berlin 289 L'excution d'une loi, in: Schweizerisches Jahrbuch fr Politische Wissenschaft 17/169-191, Bern 1977 290 Ausserparlamentarische Kommissionen, Bern 1981 291 Geser, Hans: Bevlkerungsgrsse und Staatsorganisation, Bern 1981 292 Giacometti, Zaccaria: Die Verfassungsgerichtsbarkeit des Schweizerischen Bundesgerichtes, Zrich 1933 293 Das Staatsrecht der schweizerischen Kantone, Zrich 1941 293a Allgemeine Lehren des rechtsstaatlichen Verwaltungsrechts, Bd. 1, Zrich 1960 294 Giovannini, Adalberto: Untersuchungen ber die Natur und die Anfnge der bundesstaatlichen Sympolitie in Griechenland, Gttingen 1971 295 Glaser, Hermann: Das ffentliche Deutsch, Frankfurt a.M. 1972 296 Glum, Friedrich: Die Organisation der Riesenstadt, Berlin 1920 297 Goldwin Robert A.: A Nation of States, 1st edition, 4th printing, Chicago 1966 298 A Nation of States, 2nd edition, Chicago 1974 299 Goppel, Alfons: Fderalismus - Bauprinzip Europas, in: L36/9-19 300 Grlitz, Axel: Handlexikon zur Politikwissenschaft, 2. Auflage, Mnchen 1972 301 Gramlich, Edward M.: Intergovernmental Grants, in: L585/219-239 302 Graves, Thomas J.: IGR and the Executive Branch, in: L23/416/40-51 303 Graves, W. Brooke: Influence of Congressional Legislation in the States, in: L399/519-538 304 Grawert, Rolf: Verwaltungsabkommen zwischen Bund und Lndern, Berlin 1967 305 Gregg, Phillip M.: Units and Levels of Analysis, in: L637/4-4/59-86 306 Greilsammer, Ilan: The Ideological Basis of French Regionalism, in: L637/5-3/83-100 307 Grewal, Bhajan S.: Fiscal Federalism in India, Canberra 1974 308 Economic criteria for the assignment of functions in a federal system, in: L13/1-57 309 Grisel, Etienne: La question des demi-cantons, in: Zeitschrift fr Schweizerisches Recht 1980 I p.47-78 310 Grodzins, Morton: Centralization and Decentralization in the American Federal System, in: L297/1-23 311 Grll, Florian: Die Gemeinde im bundesstaatlichen System, in: L351/127-171

312 Grosman, Brian A.: Regional and Internal Disparities in the Operation of Criminal Justice Systems in Canada, Ottawa 1974 313 Grospi?, Jiri: Characteristic features of Czechoslovak Federation and some experience with its function, manuscript, Beograd 1979 314 Groupe de travail parlementaire sur les accords fiscaux entre le gouvernement fdral et les provinces: Le fdralisme fiscal au Canada, Ottawa 1981 315 Grumm, John G. / Murphy, Russell D.: Dillon's Rule Reconsidered, in: L23/416/120-132 316 Gsovski, Vladimir / Grzybowski, Kazimierz: Government, Law and Courts in the Soviet Union and Eastern Europe, London 1959 317 Guggenbhl, G.: Vom Geist der Helvetik, Zrich 1925 318 Guggenheim, Paul: Trait de Droit international public, Tome I, 2me dition, Genve 1967 319 Gunlicks, Arthur B.: Restructuring Delivery Systems in West Germany, in: L597/173-196 320 van Gunsteren, Herman R.: The Quest for Control, London 1976 321 Gustafsson, Gunnel: Local Government Reform in Sweden, Lund 1980 322 van den Haag, Ernest: Notes on the Ideology and Psychology of Planning, in: L390/295-306 323 Habermas, Jrgen: Politische Beteiligung, in: L524/316-322 324 Hacker, Andrew: Wie die Machtelite ihre Macht gebraucht, in: L882/91-99 325 Hfelin, Ulrich: Der kooperative Fderalismus in der Schweiz, Basel 1969 326 Aktuelle Fragen des Konkordatsrechts, in: Schweizerische Juristen-Zeitung 1973 p.249-262 327 Hahn, Harlan: Attitudes toward Federalism and the Localism-Cosmopolitanism Dimension, in: L637/43/65-74 328 Hahn, Karl: Fderalismus, Mnchen 1973 329 Halifax, George Savile: Complete Works, Harmondsworth 1969 330 Political Thoughts and Reflections, in: L329/191-212 331 Haller, Heinz / Biel, Walter: Zukunftsgerechte Finanzreform fr die Schweiz, Zrich 1971 332 Haller, Walter: Supreme Court und Politik in den USA, Bern 1972 333 Hallman, Howard W.: Neighborhood Control of Public Programs, New York 1970 334 Hamilton, Alexander / Madison, James / Jay, John: The Federalist Papers, New York 1961 (cited by paper) 335 Hane, John D.: The Governmental Structure of Metropolitan Areas, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1970 336 Hangartner, Yvo: Die Kompetenzverteilung zwischen Bund und Kantonen, Bern 1974 337 Haqqi, S.A.H.: Federalism, Single Dominant Party and the Problem of Linguistic Autonomy in India, 6th World Congress IPSA, Geneva 1964 338 Union-State Relations in India, Meerut 1967 339 Harbich, Jrgen: Der Bundesstaat und seine Unantastbarkeit, Berlin 1965 340 Harrington, James: Oceana, Heidelberg 1924 341 Harris, C.P.: The Structure of Public Sector Borrowing by the Australian States, Canberra 1981 342 Hart, Henry C.: The Dawn of a Community-Defining Federalism, in: L23/359/147-156 343 Hatschek, Julius: Allgemeines Staatsrecht, III. Teil, Leipzig 1909 344 Httich, Manfred: Das Toleranzproblem in der Demokratie, in: L524/397-430 345 Hattis, Susan Lee: The Bi-National Idea in Palestine during Mandatory Times, Haifa 1970 346 Hawkins, Robert B. jr.: Regional Versus Local Government, in: L390/209-223 347 Self Government by District, Stanford 1976 347a Hayes, John A.: Economic mobility in Canada, Ottawa 1982 348 Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich: Grundlinien der Philosophie des Rechts, Stuttgart 1970 (cited by ) 349 Heidenheimer, Arnold J.: Comparative Political Finance, Lexington Mass. 1970 350 Hellbling, Ernst C.: Bundesstaat auf der Waage, Salzburg 1969 351 Theorie und Praxis des Bundesstaates, Salzburg 1974 352 Hempel, Wieland: Der demokratische Bundesstaat, Berlin 1969 353 Henle, Wilhelm: Zuweisung der finanziellen Mittel, in: L559/331-353 354 Heraklit: Fragmente, Mnchen 1976 354a Herland, Michel: Naissance d'une confdration: La Sngambie, in: L'Europe en formation, Paris, Juin 1982, p.20-30 355 Hesse, Joachim Jens: Politikverflechtung im fderativen Staat, Baden-Baden 1978 356 Hesse, Konrad: Der unitarische Bundesstaat, Karlsruhe 1962 357 Heubl, Franz: Fderalismus in der praktischen Bewhrung, in: L36/65-80 358 Hicks, Ursula K.: Federalism and Economic Growth, 2nd impression, London 1963 359 Hilty, Carl: ffentliche Vorlesungen ber die Helvetik, Bern 1878

360 Die Bundesverfassungen der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft, Bern 1891 361 Hippel, Ernst von: Allgemeine Staatslehre, Berlin 1963 362 His, Eduard: Geschichte des neuern Schweizerischen Staatsrechts, Dritter Band, Basel 1938 363 Hobbes, Thomas: Leviathan, London 1965 (cited by chapter) 364 Hoby, Gottfried: Die zuknftige Stellng der Kantone im Bund, w.o.pl. 1974 365 Hffe, Otfried (ed.): Thomas Hobbes, Freiburg i.Ue. 1981 366 Hhn, Ernst / Hensel, Johannes / Kppeli, Josef: Das Einkommenssteuerrecht der Kantone, Bern 1972 367 Hooker, Richard: Of the Laws of Ecclesiastical Polity, London w.o.d. (about 1907, cited by book, title, and paragraph) 368 van Horn, Carl E. / van Meter, Donald S.: The Implementation of Intergovernmental Policy, in: L395/3962 368a House, Peter W. / Steger, Wilbur A.: Modern Federalism, Lexington 1982 369 Huber, Hans: Staat und Verbnde, Tbingen 1958 370 Hughes, C.J.: The Theory of Confederacies, 6th World Congress IPSA, Geneva 1964 371 Hulcher, Wendell: In Support of Strengthening the American Federal System, in: L637/2-1/138-146 372 Hume, David: A Treatise of Human Nature, Volume I, London 1968 373 Hunger, Erich: Zur Idee und Tradition des Fderalismus, Karlsruhe 1929 374 Huston, Tom: Federalism, in: L637/2-1/116-131 375 Hutchins, Robert M.: Two Faces of Federalism, Santa Barbara 1961 376 Jaag, Tobias: Die Zweite Kammer im Bundesstaat, Zrich 1976 377 James, Judson L.: Federalism and the Model Cities Experiment, in: L637/2-1/69-94 378 Jaques, Elliott: A General Theory of Bureaucracy, London 1976 379 Jay, W. Robert C.: Implications of specific purpose grants for equalisation policies, in: L518/85-112 380 The Shift to Specific Purpose Grants, in: L519/41-120 381 Jayakumar, S.: Constitutional Law Cases from Malaysia and Singapore, 2nd edition, Singapore 1976 382 Jellinek, Georg: Allgemeine Staatslehre, 3. Auflage, siebenter Neudruck, Darmstadt 1960 383 Jennings, Ivor: The British Constitution, 4th edition, Cambridge 1962 384 The British Commonwealth of Nations, 4th edition, reprinted, London 1967 385 Jerusalem, Franz W.: Die Staatsidee des Fderalismus, Tbingen 1949 386 Imboden, Max: Die Staatsformen, Stuttgart 1959 387 Politische Systeme / Staatsformen, 2. Nachdruck, Basel 1974 388 Inns, Graham J.: The Public Service and Co-operative Federalism, in: L636 vol.iv/1 p.19-44 389 Institut Finanzen und Steuern: Die Gemeinschaftsfinanzierungen von Bund und Lndern, Bonn 1981 390 Institute for Contemporary Studies: The Politics of Planning, San Francisco 1976 391 Institute of Intergovernmental Relations: Intergovernmental Liaison on Fiscal and Economic Matters, in: L535/265-285 392 Interkantonale Kontrollstelle fr Heilmittel: 75 Jahre interkantonale Heilmittelkontrolle, Bern 1975 393 Joint Federal-State Action Committee: Final Report to the President of the United States and to the Chairman of the Governors' Conference, Washington 1960 394 Jon?i?, Ko?a: ber die Beziehungen zwischen den Vlkern und den nationalen Minderheiten in Jugoslawien, Beograd 1969 395 Jones, Charles O. / Thomas, Robert D.: Public Policy Making in a Federal System, Beverley Hills 1976 396 Ionescu, Georghe Ghita: Federalism and Regionalism in the contemporary World, manuscript, Beograd 1979 397 Jouvenel, Bertrand de: Du pouvoir, Paris 1972 398 Les dbuts de l'Etat moderne, Paris 1976 399 Iowa Law Review: A Symposium on Cooperative Federalism, vol. xxiii/4, Iowa City 1938 400 Kabierschke, Thomas Michael: Die Bevollmchtigten der Lnder beim Bund als Element fderativer Verfassungsordnung, Mnchen w.o.d. (1971) 401 Kgi, Werner: Zur Entstehung, Wandlung und Problematik des Gewaltenteilungsprinzipes, Zrich 1937 402 Selbstbestimmung und Mitverantwortung, in: Schweizer Monatshefte 39/8 p.686-696 403 Die Verfassung als rechtliche Grundordnung des Staates, Nachdruck, Darmstadt 1971 404 Warum noch Fderalismus? Solothurn 1971 405 Rechtsstaat und Demokratie, in: L524/107-146 406 Kaiser, Simon / Strickler, Joh.: Geschichte und Texte der Bundesverfassungen der schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft von der helvetischen Staatsumwlzung bis zur Gegenwart, Bern 1901 407 Kardelj, Edvard: Democracy and Socialism, London 1978 408 Karnes, Thomas Lindas: Attempts to Confederate the States of Central America, University Microfilms,

Ann Arbor 1952 409 Katz, Ellis: Apportionment and Majority Rule, in: L637/1-1/141-161 410 Kehrli, Hans Peter: Die interkantonalen Konkordate, in: L781/6-14 411 Kelsen, Hans: Das Problem des Parlamentarismus, Wien 1926 412 Die Bundesexekution, in: Festgabe fr Fritz Fleiner p.130ss, Tbingen 1927 413 General Theory of Law and State, Cambridge Mass. 1949 414 What is Justice? Berkeley 1960 415 Allgemeine Staatslehre, Nachdruck, Bad Homburg v.d. Hhe 1966 416 Kesselman, Mark / Rosenthal, Donald: Local Power and Comparative Politics, London 1974 417 Kevenhrster, Paul: Rtesystem - ein Organisationsmodell fr moderne Industriegesellschaften? in: L103/95-102 418 Khan, Rasheeduddin: Socio-Ethnic Dimensions of India's Federal Polity, manuscript, Beograd 1979 419 Kiang, Chien-Kuen: Conditions for Federation, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1956 419a King, Preston: Federalism and Federation, London 1982 419b King, David: Fiscal Tiers, London 1984 420 Kinsky, Ferdinand: Fdralisme et Personnalisme, Paris 1976 421 Kirsch, Guy: Fderalismus, Stuttgart 1977 422 Kis, Thofil I.: Le fdralisme sovitique, Ottawa 1973 423 Klecatsky, Hans R.: Perspektiven des alpenlndischen Fderalismus, in: L36/51-64 424 Klein, Ernest: A comprehensive etymological dictionary of the English language, volume I, Amsterdam 1966 425 Klein, Karl Heinz: Die bertragung von Hoheitsrechten, Berlin 1952 426 Kleines Politisches Wrterbuch: 3. Auflage, Berlin 1978 427 Klnne, Arno: Zum Begriff und zur Realitt von politischer Gemeinde, in: L882/249-255 428 Knaub, G.: De l'Incidence des Regroupements de Communes sur leur Autonomie Financire, Revue de Droit Public et de la Science Politique, p.155-168, Paris 1974 429 Knoke, Thomas: Die Kultusministerkonferenz und die Ministerprsidentenkonferenz, Hamburg 1966 430 Kock, Heinz: Stabilittspolitik im fderalistischen System der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Kln 1975 431 Kohr, Leopold: The breakdown of nations, London 1957 432 The overdeveloped nations, New York 1978 433 Koja, Friedrich: Das Verfassungsrecht der sterreichischen Bundeslnder, Wien 1967 434 Die Vertretung der Lnderinteressen im Bund, in: L350/9-31 435 Der Bundesstaat als Rechtsbegriff, in: L351/61-126 436 Kolb, Ernst: Das Frderungswesen unter dem Blickwinkel des Legalittsprinzips, Wien 1964 437 Kommission der Europischen Gemeinschaften: Bericht der Sachverstndigengruppe zur Untersuchung der Rolle der ffentlichen Finanzen bei der europischen Integration, Band I, Brssel 1977 438 Kommission fr die Finanzreform: Gutachten ber die Finanzreform in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Stuttgart 1966 439 Kommission fr die berprfung der strukturellen Gliederung des Kantons Zrich: Der organisatorische Neubau des Kantons Zrich, Zrich 1977 440 Konferenz der kantonalen Finanzdirektoren: Modell fr eine Neuverteilung der Aufgaben zwischen Bund und Kantonen, Bern 1978 441 Kopp, Hans W.: Inhalt und Form der Gesetze als ein Problem der Rechtstheorie, Zrich 1958 442 Parlamente, Frankfurt a.M. 1966 443 Koritansky, John C.: Decentralization and Civic Virtue in Tocqueville's New Science of Politics, in: L637/5-3/63-81 444 Kuhn, Thomas S.: The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, Chicago 1920 445 Kuic, Vukan: Federalism as a Model of Political Association, in: Politics '72, Trends in Federalism, p.520 446 Kunze, Renate: Kooperativer Fderalismus in der Bundesrepublik, Stuttgart 1968 447 La Forest, Gerard V.: The Allocation of Taxing Power Under the Canadian Constitution, 2nd edition, Toronto 1981 448 Laforet, Georg: Fderalismus und Gesellschaftsordnung, Augsburg 1947 449 Landau, Martin: Federalism, Redundancy and System Reliability, in: L637/3-2/173-196 450 Lane, W.R.: Financial Relationships and Section 96, in: L636 vol.iv/1 p.88-97 451 Lang, Kaspar: Die Philosophie des Fderalismus, Zrich 1971 452 Lange, Klaus: Die Organisation der Region, Siegburg 1968 453 Lansdown, R.B.: Two Years of Co-operative Federalism, in: L636 vol.iv/1 p.88-97 454 Laufer, Heinz: Der Fderalismus in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Stuttgart 1974

455 Reform des Bundesrates? in: L36/21-37 456 Fderalismus in der Kritik, in: L36/21-37 457 Laufer, Heinz / Pilz, Frank: Fderalismus, Mnchen 1973 458 Laufer, Heinz / Wirth, Jutta: Die Landesvertretungen in der Bundesrepublik Deutschland, Mnchen 1974 459 Le Vine, Victor T.: The Cameroon Federal Republic, Ithaca 1971 460 Leach, Richard H.: Interstate Relations in Australia, w.o.pl. 1965 461 Federalism, in: L637/3-2/11-47 462 Lederman, Leonard / Windus, Margaret: Federal Funding and National Priorities, New York 1971 463 Lederman, W.R.: Some Forms and Limitations of Co-operative Federalism, in: The Canadian Bar Review XLV/1967 p.409-436 464 Legislative Reference Service: The Constitution of the United States of America, Washington 1964 465 Lehmbruch, Gerhard: A non-competitive pattern of conflict management in liberal democracies, in: L532/90-97 466 Parteienwettbewerb im Bundesstaat, Stuttgart 1976 467 Liberal Corporatism and Party Government, in: L720/147-183 468 Lehmbruch, Gerhard / Schmitter, Philippe C. (ed.): Patterns of Corporatist Policy-Making, London 1982 469 Lehne, Richard: Benefits in State-National Relations, in: L637/2-2/75-93 470 Leibholz, Gerhard: Der Strukturwandel der modernen Demokratie, in: L524/171-244 471 Lejeune, Yves: Recueil des accords internationaux conclus par les cantons suisses, Berne 1982 472 Lenin, Wladimir Iljitsch: ber die nationale Frage, Teil I, Berlin 1930 473 ber die nationale Frage, Teil II, Berlin 1931 474 Marxismus und Staat, Berlin 1960 475 Lenk, Kurt: Demokratische Methode und klassischer Demokratiebegriff, in: L103/32-43 476 Lepjoschkin, A.I.: Der sowjetische Fderalismus in der Periode des entwickelten Sozialismus, in: Gesellschaftswissenschaftliche Beitrge Nr.2/1976 p.127-136 477 Lerche, Peter: Fderalismus als nationales Ordnungsprinzip, in: L833/1964/66-104 478 Leverdays, E.: Les Assembles Parlantes, Paris 1883 479 Levy, Thomas / Munton, Don: Les dimensionsfdrales-provinciales des relations canado-amricaines, in: Perspectives internationales mars 1976 p.25-30, Ottawa 480 Lijphart, Arend: The Politics of Accommodation, 2nd edition, Berkeley 1975 481 Democracy in Plural Societies, New Haven 1977 482 Lilienfeld, Robert: The Rise of Systems Theory, New York 1978 483 Lipson, Leslie: The Federal Principle and the Brazilian Reality, 6th World Congress IPSA, Geneva 1964 484 Livermore, Shaw jr.: The Twilight of Federalism, Princeton 1962 485 Livingston, William S.: Federalism and Constitutional Change, Oxford 1956 486 A Note on the Nature of Federalism, in: L535/19-30 487 Loebenstein, Edwin: Das Frderungswesen unter dem Blickwinkel des Legalittsprinzips, Wien 1964 488 Der Fderalismus, in: L174/827-872 489 Locke, John: Second Treatise of Civil Government, London 1962 (cited by ) 490 Long, Norton E.: The Three Citizenships, in: L637/6-2/13-32 491 Lorwin, Val. R.: Segmented Pluralism, in: L532/33-69 492 Belgium, in: L532/179/206 493 Loewenstein, Karl: Verfassungslehre, Tbingen 1959 494 Beitrge zur Staatssoziologie, Tbingen 1961 495 Luck, J. Murray: Modern Switzerland, Palo Alto 1978 496 Ludwig, Werner: Regierung und Parlament im Frankreich der IV. Republik, Wrzburg 1956 497 Lukas, Josef: Bundesstaatliche und gliedstaatliche Rechtsordnung, in: L833/1929/25-56 498 Macht und Ohnmacht der Parlamente: Stuttgart 1965 499 MacIver, Robert Morrison: The Web of Government, New York 1947 500 The Modern State, London 1964 501 Macmahon, Arthur W.: Administering Federalism in a Democracy, New York 1972 502 Macy, Jesse / Gannaway, John W.: Comparative Free Government, New York 1918 503 Maddick, Henry: Democracy, Decentralization and Development, reprint, Bombay 1966 504 Maddox, Russell W. / Fuquay, Robert F.: State and Local Government, reprint, Princeton 1963 505 Maitland, Frederick: The Constitutional History of England, Cambridge 1920 506 Mao Tse-Tung: On New Democracy, Peking 1960 507 Marc, Alexandre: La dmocratie contre le peuple, L'Europe en formation, Paris, mai/juin 1981 p.7-22 508 Marchessou, Philippe: Les institutions Budgtaires de la Fdration des Etats Unis d'Amrique, in: L222/103-201

509 Marcic, Ren: Vom Gesetzesstaat zum Richterstaat, Wien 1957 510 Verfassung und Verfassungsgericht, Wien 1963 174 Dimensionen des Rechts (Gedchtnisschrift), Berlin 1974 511 Marti, Hans: Urbild und Verfassung, Bern w.o.d. 512 Martin, Paul: Fdralisme et relations internationales, Ottawa 1968 513 Martin, Roscoe C.: The Cities and the Federal System, 2nd printing, New York 1966 514 Martnez, Rodolfo: The Mexican Federal System, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1968 515 Masnata, Albert: La lutte des Nationalits et le Fdralisme, Lausanne 1933 516 Mason, Alpheus Thomas: The States Rights Debate, 2nd edition, New York 1972 517 Mathews, Russell L.: Patterns of Educational Finance, in: Australian Economic Papers, vol.12/21 p.145161 518 Fiscal equalization in a federal system, Canberra 1974 519 Responsibility sharing in a federal system, Canberra 1975 520 Australian Federalism 1978, Canberra 1979 521 Revenue sharing in federal systems. Canberra 1980 522 Urban Federalism, Canberra 1981 522a Public Sector Borrowing in Australia, Canberra 1982 522b Federalism in Retreat, Canberra 1982 522c Public Policies in Two Federal Countries, Canberra 1982 523 Mathews, Russell L. / Jay, W. Robert C.: Federal Finance, Melbourne 1972 524 Matz, Ulrich: Grundprobleme der Demokratie, Darmstadt 1973 525 Maunz, Theodor / Drig, Gnter: Grundgesetz, 2. Auflage, Mnchen 1964 (cited by article, paragraph, and note) 526 Maxwell, James A.: The Adequacy of State and LocalTax-Effort, in: L637/1-2/69-76 527 Federal Grants in Canada, Australia, and the United States, in: L637/4-2/63-75 528 May, R.J.: Federalism and Fiscal Adjustment, Oxford 1969 529 May, Thomas Erskine: Treatise on the Law, Privileges, Proceedings and Usage of Parliament, 16th edition, London 1975 530 McLaren, Robert J.: Les relations internationales de la Saskatchewan, in: Perspectives internationales, Septembre 1978, Ottawa 530a McMillan, Melville L.: Natural Resource Prosperity, Canberra 1982 531 McNairn, Colin H.H.: Governmental and Intergovernmental Immunity in Australia and Canada, Toronto 1977 532 McRae, Kenneth: Consociational Democracy, Toronto 1974 533 McWhinney, Edward: Comparative Federalism, Toronto 1962 533a Fderalismus und Bundes-Verfassungsrecht, Heidelberg 1962 534 Federalism and the Accommodation of Regionalism, manuscript, Ottawa 1974 535 Meekison, J. Peter: Canadian Federalism, 2nd edition, Toronto 1971 536 Une nouvelle dimension du fdralisme, in: Perspectives internationales, mars 1977, p.8-12, Ottawa 537 Menon, V.P.: The Story of the Integration of the Indian States, London 1956 538 Merkl, Adolf: Allgemeines Verwaltungsrecht, Nachdruck Darmstadt 1969 539 Merle, Marcel: Fdralisme et Problmes d'Outre-Mer en France, 6me Congrs Mondial AISP, Genve 1964 540 Le cas franais, manuscript, Beograd 1979 541 Merriam, Charles Edward: A History of American Political Theories, reprint, New York 1968 542 Messmer, Georg: Fderalismus und Demokratie, Zrich 1946 543 Metwally, M.M.: The Size of States and Cost of Government Services in Australia, in: L636 vol.iii/1 p.36-42 544 Meyer, Ernst: Rmischer Staat und Staatsgedanke, Zrich 1948 545 Meyers Enzyklopdisches Lexikon: Mannheim 1973 546 Meylan, Jean / Gottraux, Martial / Dahinden, Philippe: Schweizer Gemeinden und Gemeindeautonomie, Lausanne 1972 547 Mill, John Stuart: Utilitarianism, Liberty, and Representative Government, London 1929 548 Miller, Arthur S.: Functional Federalism in thePost-Industrial State, manuscript, Ottawa 1974 549 Ministre des Affaires extrieures: Revue annuelle 1975, Ottawa 1976 549a Mock, Alois / Schambeck, Herbert: Bundesstaat Heute, Wien 1983 550 Mogi, Sobei: The Problem of Federalism, London 1931 551 Montesquieu, Charles-Louis de Secondat et de la Brde: De l'Esprit des lois, Paris 1962 (cited by book and chapter) 552 Lettres persanes, Paris 1964 (cited by letter)

553 Monypenny, Phillip: Interstate Relations, in: L23/359/53-59 554 Monz, Heinz: Das Verhltnis der Bundeslnder untereinander, Gttingen 1964 555 Morris-Jones, Wyndraeth Humphreys: Parliament in India, London 1957 556 The Government and Politics of India, 3rd edition, London 1971 557 Morscher, Siegbert: Rechtliche Probleme bei der Schaffung innerstaatlicher grenzberschreitender Einrichtungen und Organe durch die sterreichischen Bundeslnder, Wien 1978 558 Land und Provinz, Wien 1981 559 Morstein Marx, Fritz: Verwaltung, Berlin 1965 560 Mosler, Hermann: Die vlkerrechtliche Wirkung bundesstaatlicher Verfassungen, in: Festschrift fr Richard Thomap.129-172, Tbingen 1950 561 Moster, Antoine: La Constitution Financire de la Rpublique Fdrale d'Allemagne, in: L222/5-102 562 Moulin, Lo: Le Fdralisme dans l'Organisation Politique des Ordres Religieux, 6me Congrs Mondial AISP, Genve 1964 563 Mudd, John: Beyond Community Control, in: L637/6-4/113-135 564 Mller, Heiri: Bundesrepublik Nigeria, Beilage zu Verfassung und Recht in bersee 1979/3 565 Musgrave, Richard A.: Essays in Fiscal Federalism, reprint, Westport 1977 566 Musgrave, Richard A. / Musgrave, Peggy B.: Public Finance in Theory and Practice, New York 1976 567 Naschold, Frieder / Vth, Werner: Politische Planungssysteme, Opladen 1973 568 Nathan, Richard P.: New Federalist No.3, in: L637/2-1/132-137 569 The New Federalism Versus the Emerging New Structuralism, in: L637/5-3/111-129 570 Methodology for Monitoring Revenue Sharing, in: L395/65-79 571 Nathan, Richard P. / Nathan, Mary M.: America's Governments, New York 1979 572 National Governors' Association: Export Development and Foreign Investment, Washington D.C. 1980 573 Neal, Fred Warner: Some Thoughts on Federalism and the International System, manuscript, Beograd 1979 574 Neidhart, Leonhard: Plebiszit und pluralitre Demokratie, Bern 1970 575 Reform des Bundesstaates, Bern 1970 576 Nelson, Ralph: The Federal Idea in French Political Thought, L637/5-3/7-62 577 Neue Helvetische Gesellschaft: Mitteilungen 578 Die Schweiz - La Suisse, various dates and places 579 Nicholls, David: Three Varieties of Pluralism, London 1974 580 Nikoli?, Pavle: Reprsentation des Units fdrales dans les Organes de la Fdration et leur Participation la Constitution de ceux-ci, manuscript, Beograd 1979 581 Noel, S.J.R.: Political Parties and Elite Accommodation, in: L535/121-140 582 Nordlinger, Eric A.: Conflict Regulation in Divided Societies, 2nd printing, Harvard 1977 583 Noth, Martin: Das System der zwlf Stmme Israels, Nachdruck, Darmstadt 1978 583a Nwabueze, Ben O.: The Presidential Constitution of Nigeria, London 1982 584 585 586 587 588 589 590 591 592 593 594 595 596 597 1977 598 599 Oakeshot, Michael: Hobbes on Civil Association, Oxford 1975 Oates, Wallace E.: The Political Economy of Fiscal Federalism, Lexington 1977 Offe, Claus: Politische Herrschaft und Klassenstrukturen, in: L882/262-274 hlinger, Theo: Der Bundesstaat zwischen Reiner Rechtslehre und Verfassungsrealitt, Wien 1976 Vertrge im Bundesstaat, Wien 1978 Olson, Mancur jr.: Das Prinzip fiskalischer Gleichheit, in: L421/66-76 Ostrom, Elinor: Size and Performance in a Federal System, in: L637/6-2/33-73 Ostrom, Vincent: Operational Federalism, in: Public Choice, vol.VI, 1969 The Intellectual Crisis in American Public Administration, Alabama 1973 Can Federalism make a Difference? in: L637/3-2/197-237 The Study of Federalism at Work, in: L637/4-4/1-17 Some Paradoxes for Planners, in: L390/243-254 The Political Architecture of American Federalism, in: L259/87-142 Ostrom, Vincent / Bish, Frances Pennell: Comparing Urban Service Delivery Systems, Beverly Hills Oswald, Wilhelm: Die Gewaltentrennung im schweizerischen Staatsrecht, Basel 1943 Our Changing Democracy: Devolution to Scotland and Wales, London 1975

599a Paddison, Ronan: The Fragmented State, Oxford 1983 600 Paine, Thomas: The Rights of Man, London 1969 601 Parker, Arthur C.: Parker on the Iroquois, 2nd printing, Syracuse 1971

602 The Code of Handsome Lake, the Seneca Prophet, in: L601 603 The Constitution of the Five Nations, in: L601 604 Parsons, Talcott: The system of modern societies, Englewood Cliffs 1971 605 Pasi?, Najdan: Federalism and Relations between Nationalities and National Groups in Yugoslavia's contemporary Development Period, manuscript, Beograd 1979 606 Patterson, Samuel C.: The Political Culture of the American States, in: L206/51-71 607 Pawlowsky, Peter: Rumliche externe Effekte lokaler ffentlicher Leistungen im fderativen Staat, Basel 1972 608 Peloso, Vincent Charles: The Politics of Federation in Central America, University Microfilms, Ann Arbor 1970 609 Pernthaler, Peter: Die Konstituierung des Bundesstaates Republik sterreich aus der Sicht der selbstndigen Lnder Tirol und Vorarlberg, in: Festschrift Nikolaus Grass, Band I, Innsbruck 1974 610 Die Zustndigkeitsverteilung zwischen Bund und Lndern auf dem Gebiet der Verwaltungsorganisation, Wien 1976 611 Die Staatsgrndungsakte der sterreichischen Bundeslnder, Wien 1979 612 Theorie und Praxis der Bundesaufsicht in sterreich, Wien 1979 613 Direkte Demokratie in den Lndern und Gemeinden, Wien 1980 614 Das Forderungsprogramm der sterreichischen Bundeslnder, Wien 1980 615 Dezentralisation und Selbstorganisation (Hrsg.), Wien 1982 616 Pernthaler, Peter / Esterbauer, Fried: Die Entstehung des sterreichischen Bundesstaates als geschichtlicher Vorgang und staatstheoretisches Problem, in: Montfort p.128-156, Dornbirn 1973 617 Peters, Hans: Die Gewaltentrennung in moderner Sicht, Kln 1954 618 Pimlott, J.A.R.: Public Relations and American Democracy, Princeton 1951 619 Platon: Band 3 und 6 der Gesammelten Werke, Hamburg 1959 (cited by number) 620 Plunkett, T.J.: The Urban Municipality in the Canadian Federal System, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 621 Polsby, Nelson W.: Machtuntersuchungen in Gemeinden, in: L882/173-179 622 Polyviou, Polyvios G.: Cyprus, London 1980 623 Pommerehne, Werner W.: Quantitative Aspects of Federalism, in: L585/275-355 624 Porter, David O.: Responsiveness to Citizen-Consumers in a Federal System, in: L637/5-4/51-77 625 Federalism, Revenue Sharing and Local Government, in: L395/81-101 626 Portus, G.V.: The Concept of Sovereignty, Carlton 1948 627 Pour un vrai rgionalisme: E Diversitate Unitas, Bruxelles w.o.d. 628 Pranger, Robert J.: The Decline of the American Government, in: L637/3-2/97-127 629 Presse- und Informationsstelle: Frstentum Liechtenstein, Vaduz 1978 630 Prest, W.: Theories of Fiscal Equalisation, in: L518/39-57 631 Presthus, Robert: Die Bedeutung des Pluralismus, in: L882/81-83 632 Preuss, Hugo: Reich und Lnder, Berlin 1928 633 Price, J.H.: Political Institutions of West Africa, 3rd impression, London 1969 634 Proudhon, Pierre Joseph: Du Principe Fdratif et uvres diverses sur les problmes politiques europens, Paris 1959 635 La Fdration et l'Unit en Italie, in: L634/77-251 636 Public Administration: The Journal of the Australian Regional Groups of the Royal Institute of Public Administration, Sydney 637 Publius: The Journal of Federalism, Philadelphia (since 1971) 638 Pufendorf, Samuel von: ber die Verfassung des deutschen Reiches, Berlin 1922 639 Die Verfassung des deutschen Reiches, Stuttgart 1976 639a Puttkamer, Ellinor von: Fderative Elemente im deutschen Staatsrecht seit 1648, Gttingen 1955 640 Radbruch, Gustav: Die Natur der Sache als juristische Denkform, reprint, Darmstadt 1964 641 Rapp, Brian / Patitucci, Frank: Improving the Performance of City Government, in: L637/6-4/63-91 642 Rawlyk, G.A. / Hodgins, B.W. / Bowles, R.P.: Regionalism in Canada, Scarborough 1979 643 Ray, Bharatti: Evolution of Federalism in India, Calcutta 1967 644 Raz, Joseph: The Concept of a Legal System, London 1970 645 Reagan, Michael D.: The New Federalism, New York 1972 646 Reagan, Michael D. / Sanzone, John G.: The New Federalism, 2nd edition, New York 1981 647 Reeves, Mavis Mann / Glendenning, Parris N.: Areal Federalism and Public Opinion, in: L637/6-2/135167 648 Regamey, Marcel: La Formation de l'Etat dans les six Cantons romands, Lausanne 1982 649 Regierungsrat des Kantons Aargau: Kantonaler Finanzhaushalt und interkantonaler Lastenausgleich, Aarau 1978

650 Rehm, Hermann: Geschichte der Staatsrechtswissenschaft, Darmstadt 1967 (reprint of the Freiburg i.B. edition of 1896) 651 Reich, Richard: Local Influence on Federal Consultation Procedures, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 (final version in L637/5-2/117-126) 652 Rein, Martin: Sozialplanung, in: L567/203-235 653 Reiter, Erich: Organisatorische Massnahmen zur Wahrung der Lnderrechte im Bundesrat, in: Freie Argumente 1980/1 p.30-41, Wien 1980 654 Reynold, Gonzague de: Conscience de la Suisse, 3me dition, Neuchtel 1939 655 Rhinow, Ren A.: Wesen und Begriff der Subvention in der schweizerischen Rechtsordnung, Basel 1971 656 Rhoodie, Nic: Intergroup Accommodation in Plural Societies, London 1978 657 Rice, William Gorham: A Tale of Two Courts, Madison 1967 658 Richards, Peter G.: The Reformed Local Government System, 2nd edition, London 1975 659 Richardson, J.E.: Patterns of Australian Federalism, Canberra 1973 660 Riker, William H.: Federalism, 3rd printing, Boston 1964 661 The Theory of Political Coalitions, 3rd printing, New Haven 1967 662 Rill, Heinz Peter: Gliedstaatenvertrge, Wien 1972 663 Rivero, J.: Remarques historiques et mthodologiques pour l'tude des unions d'Etats, in: L105 vol.III/2 664 Rivier, Alphons: Lehrbuch des Vlkerrechts, Stuttgart 1889 665 Rivlin, Alice M.: Systematic Thinking for Social Action, Washington 1971 666 Roberts, J.L.: Decentralisation in New Zealand Government Administration, London 1961 667 Robinson, A.J.: Federalism and Efficiency, Canberra 1980 668 Roemheld, Lutz: Integraler Fderalismus, Band 2, Mnchen 1978 669 Rogers, Bruce D. / Lipsey, C. McCurdy: Metropolitan Reform, in: L637/4-4/19-34 670 Rose, Richard / Urwin, Derek W.: Regional Differentiation and Political Unity in Western Nations, London 1975 671 Rosenbaum, Walter A.: Political Culture, London 1975 672 Rosenthal, Donald B.: Federalism, Local Power and the Problem of Effecting Rapid Change in India, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 673 Roth, Ueli: Grenzregionsprobleme zwischen Genf und Basel, Bern 1981 674 Rothmann, Rozann: Political Method in the Federal System, in: L637/1-2/123-141 675 Rougemont, Denis de: La Suisse ou l'Histoire d'un peuple heureux, Paris 1965 676 Fdralisme culturel, Neuchtel 1965 677 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques: Emile ou de l'Education, Paris w.o.d. 678 Du Contrat Social, Paris 1962 (cited by book and chapter) 679 Considrations sur le Gouvernement de Pologne et sur sa rformation projete en avril 1772, in: L678 (cited by chapter) 680 Rowat, Donald C.: The Problem of Federal-Urban Relations in Canada, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 681 International Handbook on Local Government Reorganization, London 1980 682 Rubin, Neville: Cameroun, London 1971 682a Ruppe, Hans Georg: Finanzverfassung im Bundesstaat, Wien 1977 683 Ruppert, Andreas: Die Integrationsgewalt, Hamburg 1969 684 Russell, Peter H.: Leading Constitutional Decisions, revised edition, reprinted Toronto 1975 685 Ruys, Petrus Hendrikus Maria: Public goods and decentralization, Tilburg 1974 686 Rydon, Joan / Wolfsohn, H.A.: Federalism in West Germany, Canberra 1980 687 Sabetti, Philip: The Structure and Performance of Urban Services in Italy, in: L597/113-145 688 Sabourin, Louis: L'action internationale du Qubec, in: Perspectives internationales, mars 1977 p.3-8, Ottawa 689 Safire, William: New Federalist Paper No.1, in:L637/2-1/98-115 690 Saint-Just, Louis Lon de: Fragments sur les institutions rpublicaines, in: L'esprit de la Rvolution, Paris 1963 (cited by fragment and paragraph) 691 Saladin, Peter: Gleichgewichtssicherung als Staatsaufgabe, Neue Zrcher Zeitung 21.8.1976 692 Rahmengesetzgebung im Bundesstaat, in: Zeitschrift des Bernischen Juristenvereins Band 114 (1978) p.505-530 693 Salamon, Lester M.: Follow-ups, Letdowns and Sleepers, in: L395/257-284 694 Salis-Bilfinger, Heidi von: Fderalismus und Verantwortung, Zrich 1981 695 Salmon, C.S.: The Caribbean Confederation, new impression, London 1971 695a Samsinger, Elmar: Fderalismus, Wien 1984 696 Sanford, Terry: Storm over the States, New York 1967 697 Sawer, Geoffrey: Cases on the Constitution of the Commonwealth of Australia, 3rd edition, Sydney 1964

698 Australian Government, 12th edition, Carlton 1977 699 Constitutional Issues in Australian Federalism, in:L637/7-3/21-34 700 Scelle, Georges: Fdralisme et Proudhonisme, in: L634/9-23 701 Scharpf, Fritz: Die politischen Kosten des Rechtsstaats, Tbingen 1970 702 Demokratietheorie zwischen Utopie und Anpassung, 2. Auflage, Konstanz 1972 703 Planung als politischer Prozess, in: L567/167-202 704 Politische Durchsetzbarkeit innerer Reformen, Gttingen 1974 705 Theorie der Politikverflechtung, in: L707/13-70 706 Die Theorie der Politikverflechtung, in: L355/21-31 707 Scharpf, Fritz / Reissert, Bernd / Schnabel, Fritz: Politikverflechtung, Kronberg/Ts. 1976 708 Politikverflechtung II, Kronberg/Ts. 1977 709 Schaumann, Wilfried: Vertrge zwischen Gliedstaaten im Bundesstaat, in: L833/1961/86-130 710 Schechter, Stephen L.: Federalism and Community in Historical Perspective, in: L637/5-2/165-185 711 The Founding of American Local Communities, manuscript, Philadelphia 1979 (final version in L637/52/1-14) 712 Scheuner, Ulrich: Zur Neubestimmung der kommunalen Selbstverwaltung, in: Archiv fr Kommunalwissenschaften 1973/1/1-44 713 Schindler, Dietrich: ber die Bildung des Staatswillens in der Demokratie, Zrich 1921 714 Schindler, Dietrich jun.: Entwicklungstendenzen des schweizerischen Fderalismus, Schweizer Monatshefte 8/1959 p.697-709 715 Schweizerische Eigenheiten in der Staatslehre, Zrich 1975 716 Schlgel, Birgit: Grenzberschreitende interkommunale Zusammenarbeit, Berlin 1982 717 Schmid, Carol L.: Conflict and Consensus in Switzerland, Berkely 1981 718 Schmid, Gerhard: Fderalismus und Stnderat in der Schweiz, Zeitschrift fr Parlamentsfragen 3/1977 p.334-350 719 Schmitter, Philippe C.: Still the Century of Corporatism? in: L720/7-52 720 Schmitter, Philippe C. / Lehmbruch, Gerhard: Trends Toward Corporatist Intermediation, London 1979 721 Schneider, Hans: Vertrge zwischen Gliedstaaten im Bundesstaat, in: L833/1961/1-85 722 Schollenberger, J.: Grundriss des Staats- und Verwaltungsrechts der Schweizerischen Kantone, I. Band, Zrich 1900 723 Grundriss des Staats- und Verwaltungsrechts der Schweizerischen Kantone, II. Band, Zrich 1898 724 Grundriss des Staats- und Verwaltungsrechts der Schweizerischen Kantone, III. Band, Zrich 1899 725 Das Bundesstaatsrecht der Schweiz, Berlin 1902 726 Das Bundesstaatsrecht der Schweiz, 2. Auflage, Berlin 1920 727 Politik in systematischer Darstellung, Berlin 1903 728 Bundesverfassung der Schweizerischen Eidgenossenschaft, Berlin 1905 729 Schumacher, E.F.: Small is Beautiful, 8th reprint, London 1978 730 Schumann, Klaus: Das Regierungssystem der Schweiz, Kln 1971 731 Schwander, Marcel: Jura, Basel 1971 732 Schwartz, Bernard: An Introduction to American Administrative Law, 2nd edition, New York 1962 733 A Commentary on the Constitution of the United States, Part I, Volume I, New York 1963 734 A Commentary on the Constitution of the United States, Part I, Volume II, New York 1963 735 Schwartz, Jean-Jacques: Fdralisme coordonn, Bern 1978 736 Schwartz, Mildred A.: Politics and Territory, Montreal 1974 737 Scolari, Saverio: Istituzioni di Scienza Politica, Pisa 1871 738 Scott, Frank R.: Civil Liberties and Canadian Federalism, reprint, Toronto 1961 739 Scott, James J.: Comparative Political Corruption, Englewood Cliffs 1972 740 Secrtan, Jacques: Nations Unies ou Fdralisme? Paris 1958 741 Senelle, Robert: La Rforme de l'Etat Belge, Tome III, Bruxelles 1980 742 Servan-Schreiber, Jean-Jacques: Le Pouvoir Rgional, Paris 1971 743 Shaffer, William R. / Weber, Ronald E.: Policy Responsiveness in the American States, London 1974 744 Sharkansky, Ira: Urban-centered Federalism in the United States, manuscript, Philadelphia 1973 745 Sharman, G.C.: The Bargaining Analogy and Federal-State Relations, in: L115/12-38 746 Shuman, Samuel I.: The Future of Federalism, Detroit 1968 747 Sidjanski, Dusan: Du Fdralisme national au Fdralisme international, Lausanne 1954 748 Fdralisme amphictyonique, Lausanne 1956 749 Siegfried, Andr: Le Canada, Paris 1937 750 La Suisse - dmocratie tmoin, Neuchtel 1948 751 Siegrist, Ulrich K.: Die schweizerische Verfassungsordnung als Grundlage und Schranke des interkantonalen kooperativen Fderalismus, Band I, Zrich 1977

751a Die schweizerische Verfassungsordnung als Grundlage und Schranke des interkantonalen kooperativen Fderalismus, Band II, Zrich 1978 752 Simandjuntak, B.: Malayan Federalism 19451963, London 1969 753 Simeon, Richard: Federal-Provincial Diplomacy, Toronto 1972 754 Simmons, Robert H. / Chapman, Ralph J.K. / Davis, Bruce W. / Wood, Michael: A Need for New Perspectives, in: L636 vol.iii/1 p.60-75 755 Sismondi, J.C.L.: Recherches sur les Constitutions des Peuples Libres, Genve 1965 756 Smekal, Christian: Wirtschafts- und finanzpolitische Probleme des sterreichischen Finanzausgleichs, in: L351/173-219 757 Smiley, Donald V.: Co-operative Federalism, in: L535/320-337 758 Federal-Provincial Conflict in Canada, in: L637/4-3/7-24 759 Snell, Ludwig: Handbuch des Schweizerischen Staatsrechts, Erster Band, Zrich 1837 760 Socialism in Yugoslav Theory and Practice: University of Beograd, Beograd 1977 761 Spadijer, Bala: Mechanism and Problems in Decision-Making and Adjusting Interests at Federation Level, manuscript, Beograd 1971 762 Spencer, Herbert: The Man versus the State, Harmondsworth 1969 763 Sproule-Jones, Mark: An Analysis of Canadian Federalism, in: L637/4-4/109-136 764 Stadler, Hans: Subsidiarittsprinzip und Fderalismus, Freiburg i.Ue. 1951 765 Konkordate, in: L781/45-48 766 Stalin, Jossif Wissarionowitsch: Der Marxismus und die nationale und koloniale Frage, 3. Auflage, Berlin 1955 767 Stanley, George F.G.: The Federal Bargain, in: L532/275-287 768 Starr, Graeme: Federalism as a Political Issue, in: L637/7-1/7-26 769 Statesman's Year-Book: Year 1965-1966, London 1965 770 Year 1978-1979, London 1978 771 Year 1981-1982, London 1981 771a Year 1984-1985, London 1984 772 Stefanovic, D.V.: Community Development and Popular Participation in Yugoslavia, New York 1975 773 Steiner, Jrg: Das politische System der Schweiz, Mnchen 1971 774 The Principles of Majority and Proportionality, in: L532/98-106 775 Steiner, Kurt (ed.): Modern Austria, Palo Alto 1981 776 Sterne, Laurence: Tristram Shandy, London 1964 (cited by book and chapter) 777 Stevens, Arthur R.: State Boundaries and Political Cultures, in: L637/4-1/111-125 778 Stevens, R. Michael: Asymmetrical Federalism, in:L637/7-4/177-203 779 Stevenson, Garth: The Control of Foreign Direct Investment in a Federation, in: L115/39-70 780 Stiftung fr eidgenssische Zusammenarbeit: Jahresberichte, Solothurn 1968ss 781 Das schweizerische Konkordat, Bern 1970 782 Fderalismushearings - Le fdralisme rexamin, Zrich 1973 783 Die schweizerischen Direktorenkonferenzen, Solothurn 1976 784 Stiftungsurkunde, Solothurn w.o.d. (1976) 785 Kantone und Aussenpolitik, Solothurn 1979 785a Streit, Clarence K.: Union Now, London 1939 786 Stromberg, Lars: Electors and the Elected in Sweden, in: L579/269-302 787 Strong, Frank R.: Cooperative Federalism, in: L399/455-518 788 Studienkommission fr die Neuverteilung der Aufgaben zwischen Bund und Kantonen: Erste Vorschlge zur Neuverteilung der Augaben zwischen Bund und Kantonen, Bern 1979 789 Subcommittee on Intergovernmental Relations U.S. Senate: Creative Federalism, Washington D.C. 1967 790 Sucheki, Wiktor: Controversial Problems in Research on Soviet Federalism, 6th World Congress IPSA, Geneva 1964 791 Suffian, Mohamed / Lee, H.P. / Trindade, F.A.: The Constitution of Malaysia, Kuala Lumpur 1978 792 Sundquist, James L.: Making Federalism Work, Washington 1969 793 Swanson, Roger Frank: L'ventail des relations directes entre les Etats amricains et les provinces canadiennes, in: Perspectives internationales, mars 1976, Ottawa 794 Intergovernmental perspectives on the Canada - U.S. Relationship, New York 1978 795 795a 796 797 798 Tamm, Nikolaus: Die schwierige Region, Riehen 1981 Kooperation im Bundesstaat, Riehen 1982 Task Force on Canadian Unity: A Future Together, Ottawa 1979 Coming to Terms, Ottawa 1979 A Time to Speak, Ottawa 1979

798a Taylor, Charles Lewis: Why Governments Grow, Beverly Hills 1983 799 Theiler, Jrg: Fderalismus, Bern 1977 800 Thieme, Werner: Fderalismus im Wandel, Kln w.o.d. (about 1970) 801 Thoma, Richard: Wesen und Erscheinungsformen der modernen Demokratie, in: L524/66-106 802 Thurner, Hermann: Verwalten Grossgemeinden billiger? in: freie argumente 1978/4 p.39-44 803 Tiebout, Ch.M.: Eine konomische Theorie fiskalischer Dezentralisierung, in: L421/36-50 804 Tiemann, Burkhard: Gemeinschaftsaufgaben von Bund und Lndern in verfassungsrechtlicher Sicht, Berlin 1970 805 Tinker, Hugh: Foundations of Local Self-Government in India, Pakistan and Burma, New York 1968 806 Tocqueville, Alexis de: De la Dmocratie en Amrique, tome premier, Paris 1951 807 De la Dmocratie en Amrique, tome second, Paris 1951 808 L'Ancien Rgime et la Rvolution, Paris w.o.d. (cited by book and chapter) 809 Toll, Henry W.: Modern Machinery for Interstate Cooperation, in: L399/573-585 810 Tornaritis, Criton G.: Federalism and Regionalism in the Contemporary World, manuscript, Beograd 1979 811 Triepel, Heinrich: Die Reichsaufsicht, Nachdruck, Darmstadt 1964 812 Streitigkeiten zwischen Reich und Lndern, Nachdruck, Darmstadt 1965 813 Tripp, Myron Luehrs: The Swiss and United States Federal Constitutional Systems, Paris 1940 814 Tropper, Alfons: Internationale Politik - Regionale Aussenbeziehungen, Graz 1980 815 Trudeau, Pierre Elliott: Federal-Provincial Grants and the Spending Power of Parliament, in: L535/216234 816 A Time for Action, Ottawa 1978 817 Truman, David B.: Federalism and the Party System, in: L198/40-51 818 Tschni, Hans: Parteien Programme Parolen, Aarau 1979 819 Tsunoda, Ryusaku / de Bary, Wm. Theodore / Keene, Donald: Sources of Japanese Tradition, Vol.I, sixth printing, New York 1964 820 Tullock, Gordon: Fderalismus, in: L421/27-35 821 Tuor, Peter: Das schweizerische Zivilgesetzbuch, 8. Auflage, Zrich 1973 822 Ullmer, Rudolf Eduard: Die staatsrechtliche Praxis der schweizerischen Bundesbehrden aus den Jahren 1848-1860, Zrich 1862 823 Union Interparlementaire: Parlements, Paris 1961 824 Uren, Tom: The Federal Principle and National Planning, in: L636 vol.iv/1 p.98-112 825 Usteri, Martin: Theorie des Bundesstaates, Zrich 1954 826 Die Funktion der Regierung im modernen fderalistischen Staat, Wien 1977 827 Utz, Arthur-Fridolin: Formen und Grenzen des Subsidiarittsprinzips, Heidelberg 1956 828 Vacca, Roberto: Demain, le Moyen Age, Paris 1973 829 Veiter, Theodor: Die Verfassungswirklichkeit des schweizerischen Fderalismus, in: L350/123-197 830 Vliz, Claudio: The Centralist Tradition of Latin America, Princeton N.J. 1980 831 Verbindungsstelle der Bundeslnder: Forderungsprogramm der Bundeslnder, Wien 1976 (also in L549a/93ss) 832 sterreichische Finanzwirtschaft, Gesamtband, Wien 1978 833 Vereinigung der Deutschen Staatsrechtslehrer: Verffentlichungen, Berlin 1924ss 834 Viatte, Auguste: La Francophonie, Paris 1969 835 Vile, M.J.C.: Federal Theory and the New Federalism, manuscript, w.o.pl., w.o.d. (1978) 835a Viletta, Rudolf: Grundlagen des Sprachenrechts, Zrich 1978 836 Vouga, Jean-Pierre: De la Fosse aux Ours la Fosse aux Lions, Vevey 1976 837 Voyenne, Bernard: Histoire de l'ide fdraliste, Paris 1976 838 Wagner, W.J.: The Federal States and Their Judiciary, 's-Gravenhage 1959 839 Walker, David B.: New England and the Federal System, in: L637/2-2/9-50 840 The Localities under the new Intergovernmental System, manuscript, Washington 1978 841 American Multistate Regionalism, manuscript, Beograd 1979 842 Dysfunctional Federalism, in: L151/1981/53-57 843 Walper, Karl Heinz: Fderalismus, Berlin 1966 844 Walsh, Cliff: Economic aspects of multi-level Government and the distribution of fiscal responsibilities, in: L519/1-40 845 Walter, Robert: Der Bundesrat, in: L350/199-290 846 Warner, David C.: Fiscal Federalism in Health Care, in: L637/5-4/79-99

847 Warren, Roland L.: Zum Problem der Gemeindeautonomie, in: L882/256-262 848 Weaver, Paul H.: On Adversary Government and the Liberal Audience, in: L390/307-324 849 Weber, Karl: Kriterien des Bundesstaates, Wien 1980 850 Weber, Max: Rechtssoziologie, 2. Auflage, Neuwied am Rhein 1967 851 Wechsler, Herbert: The Political Safeguards of Federalism, in: L198/31-38 852 Weibel, Ernest: La Cration des Rgions Autonomes Statut Spcial en Italie, Genve 1971 853 Weidner, Edward W.: Decision-making in a federal system, in: L198/202-216 854 Welan, Manfried: Grundsatzgesetzgebung und Ausfhrungsgesetzgebung, in: L351/9-60 855 Wells, Henry: Puerto Rico's Association with the United States, 6th World Congress IPSA, Geneva 1964 855a Wenger, Karl / Brnner, Christian / Oberndorfer, Peter: Grundriss der Verwaltungslehre, Wien 1983 856 Wettenhall, R.L. / Power, J.M.: Regionalisation and Public Administration in Australia, in: L519/187-209 857 Wheare, K.C.: La Rpartition des Comptences, in: L105 vol.iii/2 p.306-313 858 Federal Government, 4th edition, London 1963 859 Modern Constitutions, 2nd edition, 3rd impression, London 1975 860 Wiener, Norbert: The human use of human beings, 2nd edition, New York 1954 861 Wildavsky, Aaron: A Bias Toward Federalism, in:L637/6-2/95-120 862 Wildhaber, Luzius: Treaty-Making Power and Constitution, Basel 1971 863 Wilson, Woodrow: The State, London w.o.d. (after 1909, cited by section) 864 Wiltshire, Kenneth: Administrative Federalism, St.Lucia 1977 865 Working with Intergovernmental Agreements, in: Canadian Public Administration, vol. 23/3 (1980) p.353-379 866 Administrative Criteria for the allocation of functions between levels of government in a federation, in: L13/59-216 867 Winkel, Harald: Die Volkswirtschaftslehre der neueren Zeit, Darmstadt 1973 868 Winkle, John W. III: Dimensions of Judicial Federalism, in: L23/416/67-76 868a Winkler, Vinzenz: Die Entstaatlichung in demokratische Selbstverwaltungskrper, Diessenhofen 1984 869 Witmer, Jrg: Grenznachbarliche Zusammenarbeit, Zrich 1979 870 Woldring, Klaas: The South African SPRO-CAS Study Projects on Christianity in Apartheid Society, in: L637/7-1/41-57 871 Wright, Deil S.: The States and Intergovernmental Relations, in: L637/1-2/7-68 872 Intergovernmental Relations, in: L23/416/1-16 873 Intergovernmental Relations and Policy Choice, in: L637/5-4/1-24 873a Wright, Deil S. / White, Harvey L. (ed.): Federalism and Intergovernmental Relations, Washington 1984 874 Wst, Felix: Die interkantonale Vereinbarung ber die Kontrolle der Heilmittel vom 16. Juni 1954, Bern 1969 875 Wyss, David: Politisches Handbuch fr die erwachsene Jugend der Stadt und Landschaft Zrich, Zrich 1796 876 877 878 878a 879 880 1973 881 882 883 884 Xu Chongde: Rforme des organes locaux du pouvoir, in: Beijing Information 24.12.1979 p.18-21 Zech, Dieter: Die gemeinsamen vertraglichen Einrichtungen deutscher Lnder, in: L781/15-20 Vertrge zwischen Gliedstaaten im Bundesstaat, Erlangen w.o.d. (1972) Zeitschrift fr Parlamentsfragen: Opladen /Wiesbaden Zimmermann, Frederick L. / Wendell, Mitchell: The Interstate Compact since 1925, Chicago 1951 Zimmerman, Joseph F.: The Role of the States in Metropolitan Governance, manuscript, Philadelphia Zines, Leslie: Commentaries on the Australian Constitution, Sydney 1977 Zoll, Ralf: Gemeinde als Alibi, Mnchen 1972 Zuber, Beat: Vier Studien zu den Ursprngen Israels, Freiburg i.Ue. 1976 Zwerin, Michael: A Case for the Balkanization of Practically Everyone, London 1976

INDEX

Contents End

Accommodation: 139 sthetics: intellectual: 531ss 703 Allocation of tasks: 264 271 352 535 Argentina: 037 242 256 263 386s 389Assimilation: 139 Ass ociations: 684 Australia: 035 037 214 263 298 336 344s 347 350 362 387 389 466 5 28 571 601 671 694 Austria:037 144 204 263 290 298 305 329 347 362 369 387 389 441 462 596 601 671 674 695 Authorities: organization of: 262 Autonomist state:403 Autonomy: 213 264 607 Belgium: 144 204 336 390 375 584 689 Benedictines: 243 537 Brazil: 037 207 256 263 369 386s 389 603 674 Bureaucracy: 427 468Burma: 305 391 Cameroon: 391 686 Canada: 037 144 214 240 263 290 318 331 333 336 347 352 36 2 386s 389 429 456 492 523 525 567 572 584 591 601603 678 689 693 704 Central government: preeminence of: 245 Centralism: 222 democratic: 100ss France: 191 Centralization: 222 566647 683ss intellectual sthetics: 531ss media: 640 698ss Centre for federal financial relations: 035 China: 036 101 242 Colombia: 144Commonwealth: 336 Communa ut franaise: 384 392 Comores: 037 263 388s 547 Competition: 117ss 497 Confedera tion: 247ssfederation: 251 289ss Congo: 390s Consociationalism: 143ss Cooperatio n: 350s 640 Coordination: 533 Corporativism: 206sCorporativist state: 206 Costs: 445ss information: 452ss mobility: 455ss of scale: 457ss Crosscutting cleavages: 140 582ss 697 Culture:democratic: 171ss political: 167ss 602ss Cyprus: 143 205 394 Czechoslovakia: 037 101 256 263 334 388s 397 674 686 Decentralization: 222ss noncentralization: 226 Deconcentration: 224 Deference: 175 Delegations system: 077ss Yugoslavia: 080Demand: inflation of: 131ss 421 468 Democracy: apathy: 173ss concept of: 044s 060ss consociational: 143ss democratization: 075developing countries: 105 dictatorial: 100ss equality: 186ss and federalism: 011 39ss 074 143 194 506 519ss 555s 575 579 586 610 628sform of government: 060ss forms of: 057ss functions of: 107ss history of: 047ss increase of demands: 131ss learning capacity: 111ss legal

concept: 043 legitimation: 151ss liberty: 186 192s majority principle: 156ss media: 180s pluralism: 194 political culture: 167ss problem solving capacity: 121ss stability: 134ss Demoscopy: 090ss 509 Devolution: 224 Diseconomi es of scale: 459ss Division of powers: 120424ss 542 631ss East Africa: 392 Economic interests: 672 702 Economies of scale: 457ss Efficiency: 443ss 476ss 704 Elites: 072ss 125 179 Equality:186ss 525s 577ss 699s Estonia: 205 318 Ethiopian/Erithrean Federation: 391 Europe: 324 375 400 662 European Economic Communities (European Union): 249 400 449 Externalities: 472ss Federalism: citizen satisfaction: 507ss compact theory: 364ss 594ss compromise: 594ss concept of: 195ss 210ss 312ss conflict regulation:551ss conservatism: 436 550 consociationalism: 150 constitutionalism: 609 cooperative: 312ss 346ss 431 439 640 corruption: 500 costs:445ss crisis management: 546s criticism: 038 040 443s 505 533ss 625 cross-cutting cleavages: 582ss decentralization: 225s democracy: 011039ss 074 143 194 506 519ss 555s 575 579 586 610 628s developing countries: 608 division of powers: 424ss 513s 631ss economic theory:451 472ss 516ss efficiency: 476ss 507ss 704 functions of: 404ss history: 364ss inequalities: 525s 533ss 577ss innovation: 434ss integration:5 58ss intellectual sthetics: 531ss 703 intergovernmental relations: 221 learning capacity: 416ss 495 legal concept: 043 legitimation: 592ssliberty: 625ss local government: 270 618 marble cake: 246 333 Marxism: 397s minorities: 504s 512 588s non-territorial minorities: 504s 588sopinions, variety of: 577ss 699s participation: 617ss 628 pluralism: 196ss 220 549 political culture: 602ss 680 problem reduction: 418sspyramid: 244s 532s redundancies: 028 443s 541ss stability: 540ss sub sidiarity principle: 231ss territorial link: 211s term: 214 transparency:560s unitary states: 242 403 Federation: 036s 254ss allocation of tasks: 264 271 352 640 communist 397s compact theory: 594ss concept of:200 254 293ss 377 confederation: 251 302ss constitutional guarantees: 265 cooperation: 350ss decentralized unitary state: 228s 292 533durability: 678ss economic interests: 702 European: 400 661 foreign policy: 419s genesis: 664ss history: 364ss 647 languages: 572 levels of government: 653ss 644ss local government: 270 media: 698ss member state: 261ss 644ss middle level: 566 644ss political culture: 602sspolitical parties: 685ss reform of: 443s 533ss regions: 662 rle cumulation: 641 science: 531ss 703 sovereignty: 259 272ss 289ss sub systems: 682ss unitary: 264 639 welfare disparities: 590 672 world government: 401 Fidji: 387 Finland: 403 Fiume: 206 Framework legislation: 535 France: 055 065 103 139 190s 214 230 259 282s 316 375 381ss 390 403 461 635 Free rider: 468 French West Africa:390 392 Functions: 025ss assigned: 025 031s 183ss 614ss learning

capacity: 025s 111ss 416ss stability: 025 027ss 134ss 540ss see Tasks Germany: 037 206 232 259 263s 277 290 298s 302 316 319 324 331 335 347 362 36 8 371ss 384 386 389 391 430ss 439 464 526 558 585596 601 603 639s 651 656 671 6 74 696 704 Ghana: 391 Ghana-Guinea-Mali Union: 392 Government: goals of: 014ss theory of: 001ssGreat Britain: 055 139 242 282 390 393 396 403 460 464 603 633 647 651 Greece: 048s 3 64ss 370 618 Hierarchy: 246 532ss corruption of information: 426ss

India: 037 240 263 347 362 388s 584 591 603 612 future: 687 Indonesia: 105 390s I nformation: 114ss Innovation: 434ss Integration:029 558ss Interventionism: struc tural: 085ss 342 Iroquois League: 368 Israel: 144 367 393 598 Italy: 206 242 367 370 403 603 Justice: 015ss Lebanon: 143 205 Legitimacy: 030 151ss Liechtenstein: 316 Lithuania: 375 Local government: 270 federalism: 270 618 special districts: 516ss reform: 459ss 483 size: 563s transparency: 496 561 Localism: 620 70 4 Majority principle: 156ss 524 628 Malaysia: 037 263 388s 612 687 Mali Federation: 392 672 Marketplace model: 516ss Media: 180s640 698ss Member state: 261ss 286 292s 566 644ss 704 autonomy: 264 cooperation: 350ss designation : 263 homogeneity: 570s 611s652 identity: 591 participation: 265ss 576ss secession: 304s 672 Mexico: 037 256 263 298 369 386s 389 Micronesia: 037 Netherlands: 144ss 175 204 375 390 New Zealand: 387 Nigeria: 037 263 388s 587 590 671s 697 Noncentralization: 226 Norway: 141175 522 Opinion: survey: 090ss 509 variety of: 578s

Pakistan: 037 105 263 388s 686 Participation: 073 075ss 184 265ss 528 563 617ss 628 Particularism: 222 Parties: political: 685ssPluralism: 179 194 201ss federalis m: 196ss Poland: 375 Politics: symbolic: 128s 165 Portugal: 206s Public choice model: 163 474516ss Quality: 485ss Redundancies: 028 443s 541ss Region: 516ss 662 Responsibility: see Tasks Rhode sia and Nyasaland: 392 672 Rome: 050 370 Rule of law: 018 Secession: 304s 672 Self management: 227 Senegambia: 395 Social

compact: 051ss 282 598 South Africa: 149 205 Sovereignty: 051274ss federation: 289ss Spain: 206 242 403 Speci al district: 516ss Spillover: 472ss State: autonomist: 403 corporativist: 206 goals:01 4ss member state: see Member state optimizing system: 022 033 part regionalized: 403 system: 023ss unitary: 222 228s 242 292 403533 States' rights clause: 240 Structural intervention: 085ss 342 Subsidiarity: 231ss Sweden: 564 Switzerland: 037 069 13 9 144 204207 242 259 263 270 290ss 298 302 316 318ss 324 340 347 350 375 386s 3 89 413s 432 435s 456 468 472 525 528 560 564 566 569 572580 584 596 598 601s 60 7 612 641 654ss 671 684 689 691 699 703 Symbolic politics: 128s 165 System: feedback 359s learning capacity: 025s 111ss political: 023ss self preservation: 024ss stability: 025 027ss Systems theory: 007ss ideology: 034 Tanzania: 037 263 388s Tasks: allocation of: 264 271 352 535 shared: 423 Technocracy: 360 Tiebout hypothesis: 455s 503s Uganda: 391 United Arab Emirates: 037 264 388s United Arab Republic: 124 392 United Arab States: 392 United Nations: 249 253United States of America: 037 055 085ss 094 103 181 204 214 218 246 250 263 270 290 297 308 318 s 321 327s 331 341ss 346 352 354s364 378ss 386s 389 402 435 439s 443 459 465 48 9 500 505 508ss 517 521 527 534 589 543 545 562 564 566s 574s 577 596 598s 6186 27ss 635 642 655ss 661 673 692 704 Unity: 222 Uruguay: 144 USSR: 037 101 139 242 256 263 269 305 309 328s 331 334 387 389 397596 654 674 686 Venezuela: 037 256 263 386s 389 Volont West gnrale: 054 Voucher system: 517

Indies: 392 590 671s World

government: 397 401 524

Yugoslavia: 037 080 206s 240 242 256 263 269 306 318 334 347 388s 397 624 654 6 71 674 future: 686

Contents Index Top HOME


Rev. 13.1.2007

You might also like