You are on page 1of 21

COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2

Cagayan State University


Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

EASTERN – PHILOSOPHY-ETHICS

INTRODUCTION TO EASTERN
PHILOSOPHY:
An Exploration of Eastern Philosophical Ideas
from Laozi to Han Feizi1

ARCHIMEDES CARAG ARTICULO, M.Phil.


Chair, Department of Social Sciences & Philosophy
College of Arts & Sciences
Cagayan State University
chitocsu@gmail.com

Section 1. Introduction

No one knows why philosophy started when it did. However, we have at least a
good idea when and how it started: Philosophy was born when man began to wonder.
The history of Philosophy is the story of man’s struggle to answer his questions, to
satisfy his curiosity. Philosophy, then, is with us long before the time of our
acknowledged first philosophers.

Philosophy, as most teacher of Philosophy correctly claim, often involves a keen


interest in major questions about ourselves, our experience, and our place in the
scheme of things in the cosmos. It should be added, however, that Philosophy is also
reflectively concerned with the methods its practitioners employ in the effort to resolve
such questions. It is not all about wondering but a knowing and reflective activity, critical
and systematic. When doing Philosophy is manifested in this way, the History of
Philosophy formally began.

1
Based on Chapter 2 of Articulo, Archimedes C. The Experience of Philosophy. Manila: REX
Publishing, Inc. 2008.

1 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

And this is what this paper/ lecture is all about. It contains interesting information
about famous Philosophers, of both biographical and philosophical nature, in roughly
chronoligical order, covering the Eastern tradition.

Section 2. Eastern Philosophy as a Divisions and Tradition of Philosophy

The History of Philosophy is usually divided into Western and Eastern


Philosophy. "Western philosophy" refers solely to the philosophic traditions of
European/American civilizations while "Eastern philosophy" broadly subsumes the
philosophic traditions of all Asia. Both terms group together diverse, even incompatible
schools of thought. These two broad divisions are further sub-divided into Ancient,
Medieval, Modern and Contemporary periods. Again, under these broad divisions are
other sub-divisions representing the dominant themes, under a particular period, in the
long history of philosophical thought in both worlds:

2 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

ANCIENT PHILOSOPHY TIMELINE (650-200 BCE)


WESTERN PHILOSOPHY EASTERN PHILOSOPHY
650 B.C.E.
Thales 624-546; Ionian Philosopher
Anaximander 611-547 Ionian Philosopher
Laozi 610-575
Chinese Philosopher, founder of
Daoism
600 B.C.E. Anaximenes 599-524; Ionian
Philosopher
Pythagoras 570-?
Ionian Philosopher
Gautama Buddha 560-480 Indian
Philosopher, founder of Buddhism
550 B.C.E.
Confucius 551-479
Chinese Philosopher, founder of
Confucianism
Heraclitus of Ephesus 540-460
Ionian Philosopher
Parmenides 540-?
Eleatic Philosopher
500 B.C.E.
Anaxagoras 500-428; Pluralist Philosopher
Empedocles 490-430 Pluralist Philosopher
Protagoras 481-411; Sophist Philosopher
SOCRATES 470-399 Mozi 470 – 390, Chinese Philosopher,
founder of Mohism
Democritus 460-370; Atomist Philosopher
450 B.C.E. Sunzi 450-380, Chinese philosopher,
military strategist
PLATO 428-347

400 – 200 ARISTOTLE 384-322


B.C.E.
Mencius 371-288;
Chinese and Confucian Philosopher
Zhuangzi 369-286 Chinese
Philosopher, Daoist
Pyrrho of Elis 365-275; Founder of
Skepticism
Antiochus 350-? Eclectic Philosopher
Epicurus 342-270; Founder of
Epicureanism
Zeno of Citium 336-264; Stoic
Philosopher
Hanfeizi 280-233 Chinese Philosopher,
founder, Legalism

3 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

Looking closely at the timeline, we could make few interesting observations. And
the most important of which is that the famous Greek philosopher Thales was a
contemporary of the historically obscure, but equally interesting figure, Chinese
philosopher Laozi (both are thought to have been menacing other people about their
peculiar ideas around 600-500 B.C.E.). This means that when Philosophy began to
flourish in ancient Greece (around 600-650 B.C.E.), philosophers in the Eastern world
have also started philosophizing about the nature of things, the meaning of their
existence, and their place in the cosmos.

With this in mind, we now begin our exploration of the Ancient Eastern
Philosophical tradition.

4 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

SECTION 3. MAJOR EASTERN PHILOSOPHY AND PHILOSOPHERS FROM THE


ANCIENT PERIOD

Section 3.1. Laozi: The Harmony of Opposites

When the Milesian philosophers (e.g. Thales, Anaximander, etc.) were busily
arguing about the reality of the universe discoverable through understanding its ultimate
stuff (the water versus the four elements), the Eastern sage Laozi (610-575 B.C.E.),
who once worked as a keeper of the archives at the Chinese imperial court (and
became dissatisfied because of corruption), made a debut in China (he started doing
Philosophy at the age of 80!).

Laozi’s interest lies in the study and teaching of the ultimate reality of the
universe, but discoverable by appreciating the essential nature of the Dao (which
literally means the “Way”), as exemplified in Nature (and so, the philosophical
movement Daoism).

Note that Laozi, like the Milesians, observe nature, but unlike these early Greeks,
he observes nature not to find the ultimate stuff of things, but to discover the way
humans should fit in their lives on how nature truly operates. What he discovered is the
fact that nature is full of opposites (life and death, health and sickness, male and
female, wealth and poverty, hot and cold, etc.) but at the same time, nature operates
harmoniously with these oppositions.

Laozi believed that the harmony of opposites, or Tai Chai, is achieved through a
blend of the yin (feminine force) and the yang (masculine force) and this harmony can
be cultivated through creative quietude, an effortless action whose power maintains
equanimity and balance (he calls it Wu Wei). Consistent to this is the foundation of his
teaching (which were recorded in his book, Daodejing), "the violent die a violent death".
Violence opposes the way of living, and whatever opposes life will soon perish.

5 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

The East, as represented by Laozi, thus, first began with an interest of the
practical and of the ethical.

Section 3.2. Gautama: Self-Centeredness Makes Humanity Sick

While Daoist philosophy was making waves of following in China, and while
Pythagoras was teaching his philosophy in Greece, a man named Siddhartha Gautama
(560-480 B.C.E.) was preaching another interesting system of thoughts, and was also
attracting huge followers, in India.

Gautama taught for many years and many conservative Hindus regarded most of
his teachings as heretical. For instance, he questioned the authority of the Brahmins or
the priestly caste or class. According to Buddha, each person can and must strive for
enlightenment through his own efforts. Buddha had also no interest in miracles and
rituals. He taught that there was no quick road to salvation or nirvana. Neither god nor
ritual can bestow salvation. Each person through self-discipline, practice, and
meditation must work for his own salvation.

Though he was extremely "philosophical" in his own way, Buddha had no


patience with philosophical systems or metaphysics. What one does, not what one
believes, is important. When asked about eternity of the world and life after death,
Buddha replied that explaining such things would not solve the problem of human
suffering here and now. Buddha's first sermon at Benares contained the essence of his
message. He taught there the "Four Noble Truths":
(1) Life is suffering (dukkha).
(2) The cause of suffering is self-centered craving (tanha).
(3) In order to bring an end to suffering, one must bring an end to self-
centered craving.

6 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

(4) The way to cease craving is to follow the eightfold way or path.

The fourth in the list includes right views, right intention, right speech, right action, right
livelihood, right effort, right mindfulness, and right concentration.

There are no simple explanations of the Eightfold Way, but some brief comments
might be of help:

7 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

(1) Right views: Though Buddha had little interest in complicated theologies
or doctrines, some beliefs are necessary. Quite simply, right belief is
acceptance of the Four Noble Truths.
(2) Right intention: One must dedicate himself wholeheartedly to
overcoming the dislocation of self-centered craving; one must want this
emancipation more than anything else. One must not let his heart wander
from this path.
(3) Right speech: One must stand guard over his speech, avoid lies and
deceptions, cultivate honesty and truthfulness. One must refrain from
unkind speech.
(4) Right action: One must examine his behavior, determine whether each
action is selfish or self-less. One must practice other-centered rather than
self-centered actions. Moreover, one must obey such precepts as: Do not
kill. Do not steal. Do not lie. Do not be unchaste. Do not drink intoxicants
(ibid.)
(5) Right livelihood: One must not engage in any occupation that opposes or
distracts one from the path. For example, since all life is sacred, one may
not become a butcher, etc.
(6) Right effort: One must pursue the path with the right exertion. On the one
hand, one must strive diligently in order to practice the cultivation of
virtues and the curbing of vices. On the other hand, one must not be
"over-zealous" and run the risk of burning oneself out and abandoning the
way altogether.
(7) Right mindfulness: One must elevate his thoughts, to see things as they
really are beyond the haze of moods and emotions. One must clear up his
mind, clean "the dust off of the mirror." One must rid his mind of self-
centered thoughts, thoughts that separate, and replace them with thoughts
that bind together, that see all beings together. One must make his
concentration objective rather than subjective. One must think in terms of
others as well as oneself. And,

8 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

(8) Right concentration: By so concentrating, all other thoughts and objects


are extinguished. Then, one must extinguish consciousness of even this
one object. In this way, one extinguishes the last flame of grasping
consciousness. This is readiness for nirvana..

Finally, for reasons we previously noted, Buddha did not want to be prayed to or
worshipped, thus it’s a great wonder why the shaven monks pray to Gautama for
salvation. Nevertheless, Sidharta Gautama was the recognized founder of the world’s
third largest religion, Buddhism.

Section 3.3. Confucius: Living the Golden Rule

Sometime after the Buddha has captured the interest of India, Confucius (551-
479 B.C.E.) made his appearance in Chinese Philosophy. Throughout his life, Confucius
was best known as a teacher (he started doing Philosophy at age 30). In fact he was
considered as one among the first professional teachers in the ancient world (not for
any special reasons, but for having the record of the first in Asia to require a
professional fee for teaching his students). Three doctrines of Confucius are particularly
important.

9 | Page
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

The first is benevolence (ren, or jen). Confucius considered benevolence as


something people cultivate within themselves before it can affect their relations with
others. The best way to approach benevolence is in terms of enlightened self-interest,
that is, putting the self in the position of the other and then treating the other
accordingly. Two sayings of Confucius best express this idea: "Do not do to others what
you would not like yourself"; and "Do unto others what you wish to do unto yourself."
(You noted it rightly; Confucius predated Christ’s teaching of the Golden rule for several
couple of centuries). Benevolence means the practice of these two sayings.

The second doctrine concerns the superior man (junzi, or chun-tzu). The superior
man is one who practices benevolence regardless of family background.

Ritual propriety is the third doctrine. Confucius emphasized right behavior in


one's relations; man should act in accordance with propriety. Thus one should behave
ritualistically with the other. Such behavior is called li; it refers to social and aesthetic
norms that guide people in their social relations. Why did Confucius stress the
importance of traditions, customs, and social rituals? Because he believed that they
best provide the social cement that holds the society in tact. Without these practices,
Confucius believe, human societies would dissolve.

Central to the aforesaid doctrines is the doctrine of Confucius concerning Human


nature. He believed that Humans, by nature, are evil: they are egoistic, arrogant,
pleasure-seeker, and glory-seeker. Only through proper education that these nature
could be corrected (and hence, his concept of benevolence could be developed, and
the “superior man” could be molded). The progress of man (in terms of his freedom from
his nature) is the ideals of Confucian theory of “Higher Education”.

10 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

Section 3.4. Mozi: Love in the way that would do for all

Around the peiod when Socrates was attracting many sons of influential families
in Athens, China gave the world another brilliant philosopher (this new comer shares the
same birthyear with Socrates). His name was Mozi (470 – 390 B.C.E.). He introduced
another way of doing philosophy, which scholars today called Mohism. It was a school
of thought that became a bitter opponent of Confucianism and Daoism.

Mo-zi preached his doctrine of “bo-ai”, which could be translated in English as


“universal Love”, which calls for the impartial or equal care for all people. This implies
that we should not give special amount of care or duty towards our parents and family,
but should treat them the way we treat everybody else. When applied in governance,
his doctrine requires rulers to honor all their subjects equally, without special treatment
to their relatives, to the rich, and the good-looking. Mozi believed that when such a
universal love is followed, the strong will not oppress the weak, the eminent will not lord
it over the humble, and the cunning will not deceive the stupid. In exhorting people to be
virtuous for the good that it would do for all, He said:

"Let him who has strength be alert to heIp others; let him who has wealth
endeavor to share it with others: let him who possesses the Way teach
others persuasively. With this, the hungry will be fed, the cold will be
clothed, the disturbed will have peace.... This is procuring abundant life."
(De Barry, 1997)

Unlike Confucius who preached the value of traditions and customs as a


standard for the execution of moral instruction, Mozi advocated judging ideas and
objects through the constant standards of nature and utility. He argued that moral
standards should be measurement-like (e.g. “When X do Y” or “When someone needs
your help, help.”), because it lends itself to reliable application. Traditions are unstable
because they are variable, that is, they differ in different places and times. For instance,
if we don't like its traditions, we can flee from a family, a society, even a kingdom.

11 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

Another related problem is that tradition is not always morally acceptable,


according to Mozi. For instance, we cannot accept the tradition of a tribe that kills and
eats their first born sons (Ibid.). Compare these with the standards of nature, which we
cannot similarly escape, or we cannot similarly refuse to accept. And how does standard
of nature operates? Mozi points out that it is natural for us to "weigh" benefits against
harms. Thus for Mozi, utility, or the preference for benefit, is a natural and reliable
standard for choosing and interpreting traditional practices (this Mohist idea of utility
predates the core idea of John Stuart Mill’s utilitarianism).

Mo-zi has also argued strongly against aggression and war. He claimed that by
not provoking war against other states, a country would be left in peace. Once, a
country is in peace, prosperity follows. Mo-zi believed that war and warfare are mass
murder, they are more of a crime than a single murder. During war the affairs of
government are neglected, the farms lie fallow, and many of the best men are lost.

Mo-zi concludes,

"Such is the injury which warfare inflicts upon men, the harm it brings to
the world. And yet the rulers and officials delight in carrying out such
expeditions. In effect they are taking delight in the injury and extermination
of the people of the world. Are they not perverse?"

Section 3.5. Sunzi: Peace in War

During this period, an immensely influential book on military philosophy, The Art
of War, was published in China. The author was Sunzi, or Sun Tzu (450-380 B.C.E), the
thinker, who is widely considered by Political scholars as the earliest realist in
international relations theory. According to this military-philosopher, knowledge of how to
wage war is of vital importance to the State, “it is a matter of life and death, a road either

12 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

to safety or to ruin.” Hence it is a subject of inquiry which should not be neglected. So,
how should war be conducted according to Sunzi? First, by understanding the nature of
war. And for Sunzi, all warfare is based on deception:

“…when able to attack, we must seem unable; when using our forces, we
must seem inactive; when we are near, we must make the enemy believe
we are far away; when far away, we must make him believe we are near.
Hold out baits to entice the enemy. Feign disorder, and crush him…” (Art
of War, trans. Thomas Cleary, 1991)

This makes the leader of armies, “the arbiter of the people's fate, the man on
whom it depends whether the nation shall be in peace or in peril.”

Sunzi rejects appeals to the supernatural that were becoming popular among
rival groups of philosophers during his time (such as the Daoists and Confucians). For
instance, Sunzi claimed that war is governed by five constant factors, one of which is
“Heaven”. For other thinkers, “Heaven” may imply the supernatural or the divine will –
but for Sunzi, it simply signifies night and day, cold and heat, times and seasons (Ibid.).
His mode of argumentation also moves in the direction of what we recognize
today as "scientific thinking." He avoids unnecessary assumptions, he emphasizes the
importance of observation and proceeds with systematic explanation of his ideas.

3.6. Mencius: The Goodness of Human Nature

Aristotle’s Lyceum had already attracted brilliant minds in and out of Athens when
a disciple of Confucian philosophy became widely known in China. He was Mencius
(371-288 B.C.E.), a philosopher who has been recognized as one of China's greatest
philosophers, second only to Confucius himself. However, unlike Confucius, Mencius

13 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

strongly believed that Human Nature is good, not evil. In his book, Mencius (Yes, the
book was named after his name), Mencius said:

“When left to follow its natural feelings human nature will do good. This is
why I say it is good…The sense of mercy is found in all men; the sense of
shame is found in all men; the sense of respect is found in all men; the
sense of right and wrong is found in all men. The sense of mercy
constitutes humanity; the sense of shame constitutes righteousness; the
sense of respect constitutes decorum (li); the sense of right and wrong
constitutes wisdom. Humanity, righteousness, decorum, and wisdom are
not something instilled into us from without; they are inherent in our
nature. Only we give them no thought. Therefore it is said: 'Seek and you
will find them, neglect and you will lose them.” (De Barry, 1997)

One might wonder, how come man, in the real world, demonstrates more evil in
his dealings then good? Mencius answers: “If it, referring to human nature, becomes
evil, it is not the fault of man's original capability” (Ibid.). The problem is not in man, but
in his society.

A corrupt society corrupts man; an evil society always produces evil citizens
(remember Plato?). But what makes a society corrupt? The answer, for Mencius, is a
corrupt and evil government.

The government must therefore strive to be good and help its citizens to realize
their potential as good persons. But how if the government, by reducing its subjects in
misery, turns them into evil? For Mencius, the people, who are by nature good, need not
tolerate a corrupt government. He believed that the people are the most important in the
state, and thus, if rulers reduce them to poverty and selfishness, the people always
have the right to depose them. He offers an ideal government which he calls “humane
government” – a government that places men of virtue and ability in positions of
responsibility and works to benefit the people. Mencius believed that a country with
such a government would be at peace and free of troubles.

14 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

Another original contribution of Mencius was his unique idea of education. Unlike
Confucius, he did not perceive education as something that should aim at “correcting”
the evil nature of man, but to the “strengthening” of the goodness one could find in the
nature of man.

“Some have these virtues (Humanity, righteousness, decorum, and


wisdom) to a much greater degree than others—twice, five times, and
incalculably more—and that is because those others have not developed
to the fullest extent their original capability.” (ibid.)

The development of these virtues to their original capability in man is the true
goal of education. And this leads us to his concept of equality.

Mencius believed that since virtue is inherent in everyone's nature, therefore


everyone is equal to everyone else, “The sense of mercy is found in all men; the sense
of shame is found in all men; the sense of respect is found in all men; the sense of right
and wrong is found in all men.” The natural goodness found in all men makes them all
equal.

Recall that leading philosophers in Greece, during this period, believed that
everyone is not equal to everyone else (Plato, and even Aristotle, adhered to the idea of
slavery). Thus, if you are the type of person who values equality, always remember that
the first voice, which proclaimed that all men are born equal, came from the East.

3.7. Zhuangzi: Seeking the Great Unity of the World

During the period when many Chinese leaders were mesmerized by Mencius’
brilliance, an equally brilliant, but a rival thinker was emerging in the philosophic scene.
Mencius offered equality among all men, his rival offered freedom.

15 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

His name was Zhuangzi (369-286 B.C.E.) or Chuang-tzu. He was considered,


together with Laozi, the founder of Daoism. Little is known of his life, except that he was
born at Meng in present-day Henan, China. As previously stated, freedom is the
keynote of Zhuangzi's teaching, which stemmed from his unique concept of nature. He
believed that since Dao is the way of nature, which is in constant flux and
transformation (remember Heraclitus?), to be one with nature is to free oneself from all
human bondage and to transcend the phenomenal world. He believed that it is
foolishness to oppose change. One becomes free when we accept change as part of
how things are and drift harmoniously with its tides. This fellow does what he preaches:
when the ruler of Qu offered him premiership, he declined preferring his personal
freedom.

He has also espoused a peculiar idea of how to do philosophy, that is, by not
indulging in too much philosophizing. He thought that knowledge – the object of
Philosophy – is dangerous. He writes,

“There is a limit to our life, but there is no limit to knowledge. To pursue


what is unlimited with what is limited is a perilous thing. When, knowing
this, we still seek to increase our knowledge, we are simply placing
ourselves in peril” (de Bary, 1997).

He also held the view that we cannot decide the truth of our statements with
absolute certainty. This is how he puts his assertion concerning the relativity of truth to
individuals who holds it:

“Suppose that you argue with me. If you beat me, instead of my beating
you, are you necessarily right, and am I necessarily wrong? Or, if I beat
you and not you me, am I necessarily right, and are you necessarily
wrong? Must one of us necessarily be right and the other wrong? Or may
we not both be right or both be wrong? You and I cannot come to a
mutual and common understanding, and others, of course, are all in the
dark. Whom shall I ask to decide this dispute? I may ask someone who

16 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

agrees with you; but since he agrees with you, how can he decide it? I
may ask someone who agrees with me; but since he agrees with me,
how can he decide it? I may ask someone who differs with both you and
me; but since he differs with both you and me, how can he decide it? I
may ask someone who agrees with both you and me; but since he
agrees with both you and me, how can he decide it? Thus, you and I and
the others all would be unable to come to a mutual and common
understanding; shall we wait for still another? (Ibid.)

Like Laozi of Daodejing he also disavowed honor and wealth. Like Parmenides
and the other Eleatics, Zhuangzi also spoke in paradoxical terms and espoused the
concept of a great unity of things through the Tao:

“The possible is possible; the impossible is impossible. The Tao operates


and things follow. Things are what they are called…everything is what it
is, and can be what it can be. There is nothing that is not something, and
there is nothing that cannot be something. Therefore, for instance, a stalk
and a pillar, the ugly and the beautiful, the common and the peculiar, the
deceitful and the strange—by the Tao this great variety are all brought
into a single unity. Division to one is construction to another; construction
to one is destruction to another. Whether in construction or in destruction,
all things are in the end brought into unity…” (Ibid.)

And like The Buddha, and Western thinkers, like Plato, he believed that we all
live in the realm of mere appearances, illusions, or what he calls a dream:

“Those who dream of a merry drinking party may the next morning wail
and weep. Those who dream of wailing and weeping may in the morning
go off gaily to hunt. While they dream they do not know that they are
dreaming. In their dream, they may even try to interpret their dream. Only
when they have awakened do they begin to know that they have
dreamed. By and by comes the great awakening, and then we shall know
that it has all been a great dream. Yet all the while the fools think that
they are awake; this they are sure of. With minute nicety, they
discriminate between princes and grooms” (Ibid.).

And playfully, he puts this dream – reality in another version:

17 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

“Once upon a time, Chuang Chou dreamed that he was a butterfly, a


butterfly fluttering about, enjoying itself. It did not know that it was
Chuang Chou. Suddenly he awoke with a start and he was Chuang Chou
again. But he did not know whether he was Chuang Chou who had
dreamed that he was a butterfly, or whether he was a butterfly dreaming
that he was Chuang Chou” (Ibid.).

It is important to note that Zhuangzi’s brand of philosophy is directed primarily


against the philosophical tradition started by Confucius (which during his time was the
dominant philosophical thought in China).

Section 3.8. HAN FEIZI: RULE WITH AN IRON FIST

The period was third-century B.C.E. China was experiencing domestic problems
as local feudal nobles grew stronger than the king and as powerful warlords constantly
fought among themselves for wealth and territory. It was during this period when
another school of thought in Chinese Philosophy was born. It was called Legalism. Its
founder was Han Feizi (280-233 B.C.E.).

Like Confucius, Han Feizi believed that the nature of man is evil, and goodness
must be acquired. But unlike Confucius, Han Feizi insisted on the need for a
government to demonstrate concrete results rather than to merely follow customs and
tradition. What should be promoted are fear and obedience rather than benevolence
and ritual piety. The goal of governance, according to Han Feizi, is order, peace and
harmony. And the only way to achieve order, he argued, was through strict laws and
harsh punishments, the suppression of civil rights and democratic institutions, rewarding
the obedient and severely punishing the disobedient, equality of all (including the
ministers) before the law, and for the sovereign to subjugate his public officials under
the rule of able men who follows the law. He preached that only a powerful government

18 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

could maintain social order, a weak government is doomed to be destroyed. He thus


urged government leaders to use harsh rule as a means of ending social disorder and
restoring peace and harmony.

Han Feizi also argued for extreme censorship to control dangerous ideas or
ideas that are critical of the government. Anyone who espouses dangerous ideas should
be swiftly terminated, and anything that records these dangerous ideas must be publicly
destroyed (when Han Feizi’s philosophy was officially adopted by the Quin dynasty, this
particular principle of extreme censorship led to the burning of books associated with
Daoism and Confucianism).

Equality before the law is central to the philosophy of Han Feizi, as he


himself proclaimed:

“The law does not fawn on the noble; the string does not yield to the
crooked. Whatever the law applies to, the wise cannot reject nor can the
brave defy. Punishment for fault never skips ministers, reward for good
never misses commoners. Therefore, to correct the faults of the high, to
rebuke the vices of the low, to suppress disorders, to decide against
mistakes, to subdue the arrogant, to straighten the crooked, and to unify
the folkways of the masses, nothing could match the law. … Hence to
govern the state by law is to praise the right and blame the wrong.” (Liao,
1998)

When Han Feizi’s philosophy was officially adopted by the rulers of the Quin
dynaty, they did what the past dynasties failed to do: to tame the unruly local feudal
nobles and powerful warlords, unite their greatly dismembered nation, and built the
Great Wall of China.
However, with the “crushing” success of Legalism came the demise of doing
philosophy in China.

19 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

Legalism has effectively contributed to the retardation of the vigor of


philosophical speculation, which has once characterized the Chinese philosophic
thought.

Section 4. THE PASSING OF THE ANCIENT

Both Eastern and Western Philosophy, of course, have continued to march on


with time, as men persisted to wonder and search for answers. But as time has
changed, so was the condition for doing philosophy.

The emerging social and political conditions of the time did little to encourage
philosophical speculations. Men became precoccupied with the necessities of his
material existence, and found comforts in the once forgotten (and now rediscovered)
dogmatism. Thinkers have begun to measure their philosophical speculations against
the requirements of Religious doctrines.

Although many nameless individuals worked to preserve the philosophic


traditions of what had gone before, there were very few genuine philosophical activities
that could be considered as “high” points for a few centuries to come until the
Rennaisance (1304 C.E.). The primary pre-occupations of the educated were
theological controversies and narrow-minded defenses of traditional doctrine and
practice.
This period in the long and windling history of Philosophy is what we call
Medieval Philosophy. Which, due to the limitation imposed by both space and time for
this present work, is reserved for future discussions.

However, it is hoped that the foregoing is more than sufficient to demonstrate that
both Western and Eastern worlds, not only the former, should be considered as the

20 | P a g e
COMPETENCY PROGRAM IN LOGIC & MORAL PHILOSOPHY – Part 2
Cagayan State University
Office of the Vice-President for Academic Affairs

birthplace of Philosophy. Abstract thought about the ultimate nature of the world and of
human life began to appear in cultures in both worlds, as an urge to move beyond
superstition toward explanation.

This is the reason why the common conception that Philosophy is an “exclusive
product of the Western mind”, and the history of Philosophy is solely the “history of
Western Philosophy”, are both wrong.

21 | P a g e

You might also like