You are on page 1of 4

Frederiek Depoortere

Badiou and Theology


Frederiek Depoortere, Badiou and Theology, Continuum, 2009, 158pp., $2 .95 !p"k#, $%B& 9'805('0)2(21.

*e+ie,ed "y Clayton Cro-kett, .ni+er/ity o0 Central 1rkan/a/


Despite Badiou's professed atheism, there are a number of ways that his philosophy can be related to theology. The value of Depoortere's book is that it is not simply a survey but a constructive engagement with Badiou's thought, centered on his set-theoretic ontology. This value, however, is also a limitation, because Depoortere's overall engagement is somewhat idiosyncratic and incoherent, as I will discuss below. fter an introduction that provides helpful conte!t for reading Badiou in terms of "hristian theology, the rest of the book consists of three fascinating but uneven chapters. The body of the book represents an attempt to articulate, #ustify and defend a proof of $od's e!istence in both traditional Thomistic and modern set-theoretical terms, over against Badiou's atheistic interpretation of set-theoretic ontology. In the introduction, Depoortere defines modernity as %a passion for the new% that has been compromised by the failure of political utopian pro#ects &'(. "hristianity, particularly as seen through contemporary accounts of )aul by *i+ek, Badiou and others, offers %the prospect of a new kind of revolutionary sub#ect% &,(. Badiou's thought is important because it %offers us clues for 'saving' the &"hristian( passion for the new in our post-revolutionary age% &-'(. But this passion for the new and this renewed "hristian sub#ectivity are drawn up into a new proof for the e!istence of $od that takes place in very traditional terms. Depoortere argues that the way for theology to take seriously Badiou's philosophy is to e!plore its usefulness for clarifying our concept of $od, %which no longer has any clearly circumscribed meaning,% so he defaults to the %historical consensus of classical theism% &-.--/(. Badiou claims in his book Saint Paul that )aul gives us a new form of universal sub#ectivity, and this takes the form of an event. Badiou's master-work, Being and Event, develops a mathematical ontology of being 0ua being in order to articulate how an event subtracts from being in a way that cannot be strictly formali1ed. If the event is what offers the promise for a revolutionary sub#ectivity, why does Badiou and Theology ignore the event in favor of a sustained e!position of Badiou's set-theoretic ontology2 Depoortere intervenes into and upon Badiou's ontology in order to shift the terms of the debate from a decision for atheism to a decision for theism, and this is a striking and significant intervention. But the idea of the event completely drops out of the purview of Depoortere's discussion, which is also significant. The ma#ority of this book consists of a constructive philosophical-theological-analytic pro#ect3 what is new is adopting the perspective of set-theoretic ontology to update ristotelian and Thomistic arguments for $od's essence and e!istence. 4et theory as elaborated by "antor replaces ristotelianism in supplying a philosophical ontology to ground a neo-Thomistic theology. This constructive pro#ect is also

problematic, however, because it still relies on fundamentally ristotelian oppositions, mainly that of actual vs. potential, and because it ultimately depends on a leap of faith from the possibility of $od as absolutely infinite to the actuality of this absolute infinite's e!istence. Before e!plaining what is at stake in Depoortere's intervention, and why I think it is ultimately incoherent, I will briefly survey the three chapters that follow the introduction. "hapter ', %5aith and the 6!istence of $od,% lays out definitions and %terminological clarifications% that predetermine the encounter with Badiou's work. Depoortere argues, against many modern humanist understandings, that faith has a supernatural origin and depends on the e!istence of $od to be faith. Depoortere relies strongly on the Summa Theologiae of 0uinas, the statement of 7atican I on Dei Filius, and contemporary 8oman "atholic theologians such as very Dulles for this conclusion. Depoortere wants to resist the possibility of any faith that does not re0uire belief in the e!istence of a traditional theistic $od, and here he agrees with Badiou3 %I want to side with Badiou and hold on to a strong understanding of both religion and faith, an understanding which implies that neither can be true if $od does not e!ist% &.9(. Badiou claims that $od does not e!ist, and therefore religion and faith are impossible. Depoortere takes this challenge seriously, sharpening the edge of the either:or, but he offers an alternative argument that $od does e!ist. Depoortere understands the hermeneutical nature of faith, but he says that this circle is a closed circle, and %the only way to escape from this closed circle is to prove the e!istence of $od without presupposing faith% &.;(. This attempt to prove the e!istence of $od by means of set theory without presupposing sub#ective faith is the implicit thesis of the book, and the payoff of theology's encounter with Badiou. "hapter -, %Badiou on Being,% carefully and clearly lays out the mathematical basis of set theory that informs Badiou's Being and Event. This chapter is e!tremely valuable, because many thinkers concerned with themes of religion and theology avoid the intimidating mathematical formali1ation that predominates in Badiou's masterwork. Depoortere gives us an impressive, sensitive and difficult reading of set theory in general, and Badiou's mathematical ontology in particular. <hat Depoortere makes clear is that Badiou approaches the limits of philosophical speculation and mathematical formali1ation and makes a decision3 in order to e!clude parado!ical sets &sets that are not members of themselves(, Badiou re#ects the idea of the one that would harmoni1e these incompatible sets into any consistent multiplicity. 8ather, by affirming the multiple as multiple, Badiou's ontology %is thus the thinking of 'inconsistent multiplicity'% &9/(. Inconsistent multiplicity cannot be thought as such but provides the %'ungraspable hori1on of being'% &9/(. In order to formali1e or a!iomati1e set theory into a consistent mathematical theory, one must rule out the possibility of parado!ical sets. ccording to Badiou, and affirmed by Depoortere, %this has resulted in a laici1ation or seculari1ation of the infinite in which there is neither need nor place for $od% &9=(. <hy2 Because what ultimately e!ists is being 0ua being, which is inconsistent multiplicity. In order for something to e!ist for us, we must subtract from this original multiplicity and count some multiple as one in order to construct a stable situation of knowledge. The procedure by which one %counts as one% is the void or the null set, which makes it possible to suture presentation to what is presented. The void names the original multiplicity of being, and the link that allows one to present what is ultimately unpresentable. <ithout any overarching one, there can be no $od who e!ists above or beyond the multiplicity in any traditional form.

In order to 'save' $od, Depoortere reverts back to "antor's original presentation of set theory, and his development of the idea of transfinite numbers. "antor relies on the idea of %well-ordered sets% to suggest that we can count numbers higher than infinity, such as infinity plus one, infinity plus two, etc. &;/(. The mathematical manipulation of numbers greater than infinity, or transfinite numbers, involves an understanding of numbers as ordinal &ordering, consecutive( rather than as cardinal &that is, as representing some ob#ective real measurement(. Then the 0uestion arises about the real status of these transfinite numbers3 are they actual infinities or #ust possible infinities2 Do they point toward and are they limited by an absolute infinity, or are they #ust endless2 "antor accepts the a!iom of infinity, which %declares that a limit ordinal e!ists,% or that such transfinite numbers themselves eventually come to an end &;;(. Badiou, on the other hand, re#ects both the a!iom of infinity and the continuum hypothesis that is often associated with it. The continuum hypothesis suggests that numbers are really related in a well-ordered hierarchy, but this hypothesis cannot be proven true or false within the conte!t of the standard >ermelo-5raenken a!iomatici1ation of set theory. 4o this fundamental undecidability provokes a decision3 from Badiou, for the void and against the one as absolute infinity? from "antor, for the absolutely infinite as actually e!isting, which according to Depoortere means the mathematical form of a theological re-instantiation of $od. The final chapter, %Theological 6valuation of Badiou's @ntology,% draws out this distinction between "antor and Badiou and provides a perspective from which to make such a decision concerning the actually e!isting infinite. 5or "antor, inconsistent multiplicity comes at the end, so to speak, at the limit of his mathematical endeavors. There, where the count-as-one fails, one bumps into the absolute. 5or Badiou, in contrast, inconsistency is primary? it is %the nothing that precedes the count-as-one &''=(. Inconsistent multiplicity in mathematical terms means the limit of our understanding, for "antor. "antor decides for $od as the limit of this inconsistent multiplicity based on his assumption that there can be no potential absolutely infinite without it being actual. Badiou cuts off this assumption by beginning with inconsistent multiplicity and claiming that there is no limit. ccording to Depoortere, there is no mathematical solution to this dispute. Aathematics can think a potentially e!isting absolute infinity, but %there is no place for an actually e!isting absolute in mathematics% &'';(. Depoortere is correct to point out that Badiou's claim that set theory necessarily e!cludes the absolute infinite goes too far? it is an interpretation or decision by which Badiou opts for the void as opposed to the absolute infinite. 5urthermore, Depoortere discusses an essay by Benneth 8eynhout, which argues that one can read Badiou's theory of the void in terms of negative theology, where the null set is the sign of Badiou's %hidden $od.% But this negative theological understanding of set theory and Badiou is not sufficient for Depoortere's aims. Depoortere concludes the book with a very condensed argument for a traditional $od understood in set theoretical terms as absolutely infinite by referring to a book by 8udy 8ucker, Infinity and the Mind. 8ucker suggests, by means of the %reflection principle,% that there is a positive connection between transfinite numbers and the absolute infinite. This connection provides Depoortere an opening to declare that we can preserve the traditional knowability and unknowability of $od in modern mathematical terms, and therefore %it remains possible to break out of the closed circle of faith presupposing faith% &'-9(.

There are at least two problems with Depoortere's conclusion. Ce is too smart not to 0ualify the situation of set theory about the infinite and he stresses its indeterminacy. The fact that Badiou opts for the void and for atheism means that it is possible to go back and follow "antor's preference for $od as actually e!isting infinite. The fact that this situation forces a decision, however, is not only problematic in terms of Badiou's ontology? it means that Depoortere is forced back into the closed circle that he was hoping to avoid by offering a proof of $od's e!istence. The decision for $od is at the same time a faithful&l( decision, which means that there is no way out of the hermeneutical circle, at least in terms of how Depoortere constructs it in his book. 4econd, Depoortere relies strongly on the Thomistic and ultimately ristotelian distinction between actual and potential to decide for $od, whereas this traditional opposition may not make as much sense in terms of modern set theory or contemporary philosophy and theology. The most Depoortere is able to gain from his "antorian mathematical set theory is the possibility of an absolute infinite. Ce then falls back on ristotle and 0uinas, as very briefly presented through 8ucker, to argue that the possibility of an absolute infinite implies an actual absolute infinite, and to suggest that the e!istence of transfinite numbers gives us positive knowledge of this actual infinite. But it is clearly a leap of faith to presume that the absolute infinite is reflected in transfinite numbers. 5inally, Depoortere is forced to e0uivocate in terms of this possibility of an absolute infinite, because he needs the absolute infinite to be possible in order to counter Badiou's atheism, but he needs to overcome the limit of this possibility in order to achieve his purpose, which is to prove the actual e!istence of $od, which is the only way to avoid the closed circle of faith. The fact that this book is flawed and cannot achieve what it sets out to do does not diminish its value as a work of theological engagement and theoretical reflection. It does not e!haust the possible or actual relations between theology and Badiou's philosophy, but it is a serious and provocative encounter that is worth much more than the countless surveys and superficial appropriations that generally constitute the genre.

You might also like