You are on page 1of 36

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW: A RECONCILIATION

By Anthea Elizabeth Roberts* I. THE PROBLEM OF TRADITIONAL AND MODERN CUSTOM The demise of custom as a source of international law has been widely forecasted.1 This is because both the nature and the relative importance of customs constituent elements are contentious. At the same time, custom has become an increasingly significant source of law in important areas such as human rights obligations.2 Codification conventions, academic commentary, and the case law of the International Court of Justice (the Court) have also contributed to a contemporary resurrection of custom.3 These developments have resulted in two apparently opposing approaches, which I term traditional custom and modern custom. The renaissance of custom requires the articulation of a coherent theory that can accommodate its classic foundations and contemporary developments. This article seeks to provide an enriched theoretical account of custom that incorporates both the traditional and the modern approaches rather than advocating one approach over the other. The Statute of the International Court of Justice describes custom as evidence of a general practice accepted as law.4 Custom is generally considered to have two elements: state practice and opinio juris.5 State practice refers to general and consistent practice by states, while opinio juris means that the practice is followed out of a belief of legal obligation.6 This distinction is problematic because it is difficult to determine what states believe as opposed to what they say. Whether treaties and declarations constitute state practice or opinio juris is also controversial. For the sake of clarity, this article adopts Anthony DAmatos distinction between action (state practice) and statements (opinio juris).7 Thus, actions can form custom only if accompanied by an articulation of the legality of the action.8 Opinio juris
* The research for this article was initially undertaken for my LLB dissertation at the Australian National University and was completed while I was teaching in the universitys Faculty of Law. I wish to thank Professor Hilary Charlesworth for her insightful comments on various drafts of the manuscript. 1 E.g., N. C. H. Dunbar, The Myth of Customary International Law, 1983 AUSTL. Y.B. INTL L. 1; J. Patrick Kelly, The Twilight of Customary International Law, 40 VA. J. INTL L. 449 (2000). 2 THEODOR MERON, HUMAN RIGHTS AND HUMANITARIAN NORMS AS CUSTOMARY LAW (1989). 3 Eduardo Jimnez de Archaga, Custom, in CHANGE AND STABILITY IN INTERNATIONAL LAW-MAKING 1, 23 (Antonio Cassese & Joseph H. H. Weiler eds., 1988) [hereinafter CHANGE AND STABILITY]; W. Michael Reisman, The Cult of Custom in the Late 20th Century, 17 CAL. W. INTL L.J. 133 (1987). 4 INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE STATUTE Art. 38(1)(b) [hereinafter ICJ STATUTE]. 5 North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3, 44 (Feb. 20). 6 RESTATEMENT (THIRD) OF THE FOREIGN RELATIONS LAW OF THE UNITED STATES 102(2) (1987) [hereinafter RESTATEMENT]; IAN BROWNLIE, PRINCIPLES OF PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 411 (5th ed. 1998); MICHAEL BYERS, CUSTOM, POWER, AND THE POWER OF RULES 130 (1999); ANTHONY A. DAMATO, THE CONCEPT OF CUSTOM IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 49 (1971) (citing FRANOIS GNY, MTHODE DINTERPRTATION ET SOURCES EN DROIT PRIV POSITIF 110 (1899)). 7 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 8990, 160. This distinction has been criticized by many commentators, who include certain statements as forms of state practice. RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102; BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 56; Michael Akehurst, Custom as a Source of International Law, 197475 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 1, 2, 35. The distinction is also impliedly inconsistent with some case law of the Court. Fisheries Jurisdiction (UK v. Ice.), Merits, 1974 ICJ REP. 3, 47, 5658, 8188, 11920, 135, 161 ( July 25); North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 4, 3233, 47, 53. 8 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 7475.

757

758

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

concerns statements of belief rather than actual beliefs.9 Further, treaties and declarations represent opinio juris because they are statements about the legality of action, rather than examples of that action.10 As will be demonstrated below, traditional custom and modern custom are generally assumed to be alternatives because the former emphasizes state practice, whereas the latter emphasizes opinio juris.11 What I have termed traditional custom results from general and consistent practice followed by states from a sense of legal obligation.12 It focuses primarily on state practice in the form of interstate interaction and acquiescence. Opinio juris is a secondary consideration invoked to distinguish between legal and nonlegal obligations.13 Traditional custom is evolutionary14 and is identified through an inductive process in which a general custom is derived from specific instances of state practice.15 This approach is evident in S.S. Lotus,16 where the Permanent Court of International Justice inferred a general custom about objective territorial jurisdiction over ships on the high seas from previous instances of state action and acquiescence.17 By contrast, modern custom is derived by a deductive process that begins with general statements of rules rather than particular instances of practice.18 This approach emphasizes opinio juris rather than state practice because it relies primarily on statements rather than actions.19 Modern custom can develop quickly because it is deduced from multilateral treaties and declarations by international fora such as the General Assembly, which can declare existing customs, crystallize emerging customs, and generate new customs.20 Whether these texts become custom depends on factors such as whether they are phrased in declaratory terms, supported by a widespread and representative body of states, and confirmed by state practice.21 A good example of the deductive approach is the Merits decision in Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua.22 The Court paid lip service to the traditional test for custom but derived customs of non-use of force and nonintervention from statements such as General Assembly resolutions.23 The Court did not make a serious inquiry into
Id. at 3539; Akehurst, supra note 7, at 3637. Cf. DAMATO, supra note 6, at 89 (arguing that treaties are actions). But see Akehurst, supra note 7, at 3, 43 (criticizing DAmato for inconsistency). 11 E.g., Ted Stein, Remarks [on customs and treaties], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 12, 13. 12 North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 44; RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102(2). 13 North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 44; Right of Passage over Indian Territory (Port. v. India), Merits, 1960 ICJ REP. 6, 4243 (Apr. 12); Asylum (Colom./Peru), 1950 ICJ REP. 266, 27677 (Nov. 20); S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, at 28 (Sept. 7). 14 The Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. 677, 686 (1900); JAMES BRIERLY, THE LAW OF NATIONS 62 (6th ed. 1963). 15 Delimitation of the Maritime Boundary in the Gulf of Maine Area (Can. v. U.S.), 1984 ICJ REP. 246, 299 (Oct. 12); OSCAR SCHACHTER, INTERNATIONAL LAW IN THEORY AND PRACTICE 3536 (1991); GEORG SCHWARZENBERGER, THE INDUCTIVE APPROACH TO INTERNATIONAL LAW 33 (1965); Georg Schwarzenberger, The Inductive Approach to International Law, 60 HARV. L. REV. 539, 56670 (1947). 16 S.S. Lotus, 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, at 18, 29; see also Nottebohm (Liech. v. Guat.), Second Phase, 1955 ICJ REP. 4, 22 (Apr. 6); S.S. Wimbledon, 1923 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 1, at 25 (Aug. 17). 17 Hiram Chodosh, Neither Treaty nor Custom: The Emergence of Declarative International Law, 26 TEX. INTL L.J. 87, 102 n.70 (1991). 18 Bruno Simma & Philip Alston, The Sources of Human Rights Law: Custom, Jus Cogens, and General Principles, 198889 AUSTL. Y.B. INTL L. 82. 19 Bin Cheng, United Nations Resolutions on Outer Space: Instant International Customary Law? 5 INDIAN J. INTL L. 23 (1965), reprinted in INTERNATIONAL LAW: TEACHING AND PRACTICE 237 (Bin Cheng ed., 1982). 20 North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 44; Eduardo Jimnez de Archaga, Remarks [on general principles and General Assembly resolutions], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 48. 21 Akehurst, supra note 7, at 67; Jonathan I. Charney, Universal International Law, 87 AJIL 529, 54445 (1993). 22 Military and Paramilitary Activities in and Against Nicaragua (Nicar. v. U.S.), Merits, 1986 ICJ REP. 14 ( June 27) [hereinafter Nicaragua]; see also Western Sahara, Advisory Opinion, 1975 ICJ REP. 12, 3037 (Oct. 16); Legal Consequences for States of the Continued Presence of South Africa in Namibia (South West Africa) Notwithstanding Security Council Resolution 276 (1970), Advisory Opinion, 1971 ICJ REP. 16, 3132 ( June 21) [hereinafter Namibia Advisory Opinion]. 23 E.g., Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation Among States in Accordance with the Charter of the United Nations, GA Res. 2625, UN GAOR, 25th Sess., Supp. No. 28,
10 9

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

759

state practice, holding that it was sufficient for conduct to be generally consistent with statements of rules, provided that instances of inconsistent practice had been treated as breaches of the rule concerned rather than as generating a new rule.24 The tests and justifications for traditional and modern custom appear to differ because the former develops slowly through state practice, while the latter can arise rapidly based on opinio juris.25 This difference has spurred considerable discussion over two related issues. First, the legitimacy of traditional and modern custom has been debated at length.26 David Fidler characterizes the various approaches to this issue as the dinosaur, dynamo, and dangerous perspectives.27 The dinosaur approach focuses on traditional custom and argues that massive changes in the international system have rendered it an anachronism. For example, Jonathan Charney claims that the increasing number and diversity of states, as well as the emergence of global problems that are addressed in international fora, makes traditional custom an inappropriate means for developing law.28 The dynamo perspective concentrates on modern custom and embraces it as a progressive source of law that can respond to moral issues and global challenges. For example, Theodor Meron, Richard Lillich, and Lori Bruun argue that modern custom based on declarations by international fora provides an important source of law for human rights obligations.29 Finally, the dangerous perspective views modern custom as a departure from the traditional approach that has created an opportunity for legal and political abuse. Thus, Michael Reisman characterizes the increased dependence on custom as a great leap backwards designed to serve the interests of powerful states.30 Similarly, Arthur Weisburd holds that modern custom often lacks the legitimacy of state consent because it is formed despite little, or conflicting, state practice.31 Second, the divergence between traditional and modern custom has been criticized as undermining the integrity of custom as a source of law. Patrick Kelly argues that custom is an indeterminate and malleable source of law, simply a matter of taste.32 According to DAmato, the modern approach trashes the theoretical foundations of custom by inverting the traditional priority of state practice over opinio juris.33 Sir Robert Jennings insists that most of what we perversely persist in calling customary international law is not only not customary law: it does not even faintly resemble a customary law.34 The phrases modern,
at 121, UN Doc. A/8028 (1970); Conference on Security and Co-operation in Europe, Final Act, Aug. 1, 1975, 73 DEPT ST. BULL. 323 (1975), reprinted in 14 ILM 1292 (1975) [hereinafter Helsinki Accord]. 24 Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 98, para. 186. 25 Georges Abi-Saab, Remarks [on custom and treaties], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 9; Louis Henkin, Human Rights and State Sovereignty, 25 GA. J. INTL L. 37 (1995/96); Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 90; Ted Stein, The Approach of a Different Drummer: The Principle of the Persistent Objector in International Law, 26 HARV. INTL L.J. 457, 457 (1985). 26 Consider, for example, the strong and conflicting responses to the Nicaragua case. Symposium, Appraisals of the ICJs Decision: Nicaragua v. United States (Merits), 81 AJIL 77 (1987). 27 David Fidler, Challenging the Classical Concept of Custom, 1996 GER. Y.B. INTL L. 198, 21631. 28 Charney, supra note 21, at 543. 29 MERON, supra note 2; Lori Bruun, Beyond the 1948 ConventionEmerging Principles of Genocide in Customary International Law, 17 MD. J. INTL L. & TRADE 193, 21617 (1993); Richard B. Lillich, The Growing Importance of Customary International Human Rights Law, 25 GA. J. INTL & COMP. L. 1, 8 (1995/96). 30 Reisman, supra note 3, at 135. 31 Arthur A. Weisburd, Customary International Law: The Problem of Treaties, 21 VAND. J. TRANSNATL L. 1 (1988) [hereinafter Weisburd, Customary IL]. For further discussion, see Anthony A. DAmato, Custom and Treaty: A Response to Professor Arthur A. Weisburd, 21 VAND. J. TRANSNATL L. 459 (1988) [hereinafter DAmato, Response]; Arthur A. Weisburd, A Reply to Professor Anthony A. DAmato, id. at 473; Anthony A. DAmato, A Brief Rejoinder, id. at 489. 32 Kelly, supra note 1, at 451. 33 Anthony A. DAmato, Trashing Customary International Law, 81 AJIL 101 (1987). 34 Robert Y. Jennings, The Identification of International Law, in INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 19, at 3, 5; see also North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3, 224 (Feb. 20) (Srensen, J. ad hoc, dissenting); Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 83.

760

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

new,35 contemporary,36 and instant37 custom appear inherently contradictory and obscure the real basis for forming this law. Hilary Charlesworth contends that modern custom can be rationalized only by dispensing with the traditional rhetoric of custom.38 Bruno Simma and Philip Alston argue that the modern approach has created an identity crisis39 for custom and would be better understood as a general principle of international law.40 Likewise, Charney, Daniel Bodansky, and Hiram Chodosh conclude that modern custom is really a new species of universal declaratory law because it is based on authoritative statements about practice rather than observable regularities of behavior.41 Both the legitimacy and the integrity of traditional and modern custom have received considerable attention and polarized positions are evident. However, few commentators have transcended these debates by attempting to provide an overall theory of custom. Frederic Kirgis rationalizes the divergence in custom by analyzing the requirements of state practice and opinio juris on a sliding scale.42 At one end, highly consistent state practice can establish a customary rule without requiring opinio juris. However, as the frequency and consistency of state practice decline, a stronger showing of opinio juris will be required. Kirgis argues that the exact trade-off between state practice and opinio juris will depend on the importance of the activity in question and the reasonableness of the rule involved.43 Simma and Alston claim that this approach reinterprets the concept of custom so as to produce the right answers.44 However, John Tasioulas argues that the sliding scale can be rationalized on the basis of Ronald Dworkins interpretive theory of law, which balances a description of what the law has been with normative considerations about what the law should be. This perspective shows why the Court may be less exacting in requiring state practice and opinio juris in cases that deal with important moral issues. This article builds on the work of Kirgis and Tasioulas and offers a defense of custom by seeking to reconcile the traditional and modern approaches. Part II analyzes the competing values of descriptive accuracy and normative appeal that are used to justify international law. These values characterize traditional and modern custom, respectively, because of their inductive and deductive methodologies and facilitative and moral content. Part III examines custom on a sliding scale and rejects this interpretive approach because it does not accurately describe the process of finding custom and would create customs that are apologies for power or utopian and unachievable.45 Part IV presents an alternative vision of Dworkins interpretive theory of law applied to custom, which incorporates the justifications of descriptive accuracy and normative appeal and seeks to balance them in a Rawlsian reflective equilibrium.46 Part V outlines the advantages of the reflective interpretive approach over the sliding-scale methodology. Rearticulating the theoretical founda35 Curtis A. Bradley & Jack L. Goldsmith, Customary International Law as Federal Common Law: A Critique of the Modern Position, 110 HARV. L. REV. 815, 838 (1997); Kelly, supra note 1, at 454 n.20, 484. 36 Stein, supra note 11, at 12. 37 Bin Cheng, in INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 19, at 249. 38 Hilary C. M. Charlesworth, Customary International Law and the Nicaragua Case, 198487 AUSTL. Y.B. INTL L. 1. 39 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 88, 96. 40 Id. at 10206; see also ICJ STATUTE Art. 38(1)(c). 41 Daniel Bodansky, Customary (and Not So Customary) International Environmental Law, 3 IND. J. GLOBAL LEGAL STUD. 105, 11619 (1995); Charney, supra note 21, at 543, 54647; Chodosh, supra note 17. 42 Frederic L. Kirgis, Jr., Custom on a Sliding Scale, 81 AJIL 146 (1987); John Tasioulas, In Defence of Relative Normativity: Communitarian Values and the Nicaragua Case, 16 OXFORD J. LEGAL STUD. 85 (1996). 43 Kirgis, supra note 42, at 149. 44 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 83. 45 For an explanation of the phrases apology for power and utopian and unachievable, see MARTTI KOSKENNIEMI, FROM APOLOGY TO UTOPIA: THE STRUCTURE OF INTERNATIONAL LEGAL ARGUMENT 2 (1989). 46 RONALD DWORKIN, LAWS EMPIRE (1986); JOHN RAWLS, A THEORY OF JUSTICE 20 (1972).

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

761

tions of custom in this more principled and flexible fashion will provide international actors with a coherent theory for applying custom. It will also help to justify the traditional and modern approaches to custom as two aspects of a single source of law, rather than characterize one approach as illegitimate and the choice between them as undermining the integrity of custom. II. THE DESCRIPTIVE AND NORMATIVE APPROACHES TO CUSTOM Descriptive Accuracy and Normative Appeal H. L. A. Hart and R. M. Hare distinguish between descriptive and prescriptive statements and laws.47 Descriptive laws can be discovered by observation and reasoning because they are statements about what the practice has been. By contrast, prescriptive laws are not determined primarily by observations of fact because they state demands about what the practice should or ought to be. Legal rules are always prescriptive because they make demands about how people and states should behave. However, their prescriptive nature can be justified by what the practice has been and/or what the practice should be. A law is primarily descriptive if it conforms to the premise: the law is what the practice has been. A law is primarily normative if it is formulated on the assumption: the law is what the practice ought to be. What the law is (prescription) can be justified by what the practice has been (description) or what the practice ought to be (normativity). Thus, we should distinguish between what the practice has been, what the law is, and what the practice ought to be: has/is/ought (description/ prescription/normativity). These distinctions, however, are often confused in two ways. First, some theorists mistakenly amalgamate descriptive and prescriptive considerations. By aligning the distinction between description and normativity with the positivist is/ ought dichotomy, which distinguishes between what the law is and what the law should be, they conflate the has/is/ought structure with the is/ought dichotomy. This is misguided because it merges descriptive and prescriptive elements by fusing considerations of what the practice has been with considerations of what the law is. Moving from has to is involves some level of law creation because it requires the formulation of an abstract rule from actual practice, despite the existence of silences, ambiguities, and contradictions in that practice.48 Determining what the law is from what the practice has been relies heavily on the choice of characteristics under which precedents are classified and the degree of abstraction employed.49 Description and prescription are not coextensive because one reflects practice (description) and the other directs practice (prescription). Second, prescriptive and normative rules are often confused because both express an imperative to act. Prescriptive laws express a legal imperative to act (you should do x because x is legally required), while normative rules express a moral imperative to act (you should do x because x is morally required). Many laws embody both a legal and a moral imperative, for example, the prohibition of murder. However, the two considerations are distinct because laws may be prescriptive but not normative; thus, traffic regulations are legally required but often morally indifferent. Likewise, a rule may be normative but not prescriptive; for example, adultery may be considered morally wrong, but it is not illegal in Western societies. Hence,
47 H. L. A. HART, THE CONCEPT OF LAW 183 (1961); R. M. HARE, MORAL THINKING, ch. 4 (1981); R. M. HARE, THE LANGUAGE OF MORALS (1952). 48 The same issue arises with codification of international law. CHARLES DE VISSCHER, THEORY AND REALITY IN PUBLIC INTERNATIONAL LAW 39 (P. E. Corbett trans., rev. ed. 1968); Hersch Lauterpacht, Codification and Development of International Law, 49 AJIL 16 (1955); Oscar Schachter, Recent Trends in International Law Making, 198889 AUSTL. Y.B. INTL L. 1, 23; Julius Stone, The Vocation of the International Law Commission, 57 COLUM. L. REV. 16, 1819 (1957). 49 Ulrich Fastenrath, Relative Normativity in International Law, 4 EUR. J. INTL L. 305, 31619 (1993).

762

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

what the law is (prescription) can be justified by what the practice should be (normativity), but the two considerations are not always coextensive. The values of descriptive accuracy and normative appeal provide important, and sometimes competing, justifications for international law. Descriptive accuracy (which focuses on what the practice has been) is valuable in justifying the content of international law because laws should correspond to reality.50 Laws must bear some relation to practice if they are to regulate conduct effectively, because laws that set unrealistic standards are likely to be disobeyed and ultimately forgotten. This consideration particularly applies to decentralized systems of law, such as international law, where traditional enforcement mechanisms are unavailable or underdeveloped.51 Descriptive accuracy is also essential to predictive power52 because a theory that accurately describes practice enables more reliable predictions of future state behavior.53 The alternative justification for international law provided by normative appeal (which focuses on what the practice ought to be) involves procedural and substantive aspects. First, procedural normativity requires that the process for forming laws be transparent, so that states are aware of the real basis for forming customs and can regulate their actions accordingly.54 It also entails an opportunity for states to participate in law formation and have their positions considered.55 Legal rules are more likely to engender respect in a decentralized system, possibly even when the outcome is less favorable, if they result from a process perceived as legitimate.56 Second, substantive normativity requires that laws be coherent and that their content be morally good or at least neutral, depending on their subject matter. Claims about morality are contentious because it remains unclear whether morality is objective or culturally relative. By morality, I am referring to commonly held subjective values about actions that are right and wrong, which a representative majority of states has recognized in treaties and declarations.57 The justifications for traditional and modern custom align with description and normativity, respectively, in keeping with the methodologies that characterize each approach. Descriptive accuracy and normative appeal respectively represent inductive and deductive methods of justification.58 Martti Koskenniemi argues that the inductive pattern privileges description over normativity, while the deductive pattern does the reverse.59 Traditional custom is closely associated with descriptive accuracy because norms are constructed primarily from state practiceworking from practice to theory.60 Reliance on state practice provides continuity with past actions and reliable predictions of future actions. It
50 Bin Cheng, Custom: The Future of General State Practice in a Divided World, in THE STRUCTURE AND PROCESS OF INTERNATIONAL LAW: ESSAYS IN LEGAL PHILOSOPHY, DOCTRINE, AND THEORY 513, 539 (Ronald St. J. Macdonald & Douglas M. Johnston eds., 1983). 51 Bodansky, supra note 41, at 11619. 52 Jerome Frank, Law and the Modern Mind, in LLOYDS INTRODUCTION TO JURISPRUDENCE 679 (Michael Freeman ed., 6th ed. 1994); Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of Law, 10 HARV. L. REV. 457, 457 (189697); Karl Llewellyn, Some Realism About Realism, 44 HARV. L. REV. 1222 (1931). 53 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 89. 54 Bin Cheng, supra note 50, at 539; Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 27. 55 THOMAS R. TYLER, WHY PEOPLE OBEY THE LAW 17073 (1990); Kelly, supra note 1, at 51718, 53031; Stephen Machura, Introduction: Procedural Justice, Law and Policy, 19 MICH. J. INTL L. 345, 35354 (1998). 56 TYLER, supra note 55, at 163, 17073, 17578; Thomas M. Franck, Legitimacy in the International System, 82 AJIL 705, 706 (1988); Kelly, supra note 1, at 531; Machura, supra note 55, at 35354. 57 These values are intersubjective, i.e., values commonly held by a group of subjects, in this case states. Jan Narveson, Inter-subjective, in THE OXFORD COMPANION TO PHILOSOPHY 414 (Ted Honderich ed., 1995) [hereinafter OXFORD COMPANION]. 58 See also ascending and descending methods of justification. WALTER ULLMANN, LAW AND POLITICS IN THE MIDDLE AGES 3031 (1975). 59 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 41. 60 North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3 (Feb. 20); RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102(2).

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

763

results in practical and achievable customs that can actually regulate state conduct. By contrast, modern custom demonstrates a predilection for substantive normativity rather than descriptive accuracy. Modern custom derives norms primarily from abstract statements of opinio jurisworking from theory to practice. Whereas state practice is clearly descriptive, opinio juris is inherently ambiguous in nature because statements can represent lex lata (what the law is, a descriptive characteristic) or lex ferenda (what the law should be, a normative characteristic). The Court has held that only statements of lex lata can contribute to the formation of custom.61 However, modern custom seems to be based on normative statements of lex ferenda cloaked as lex lata, for three reasons. First, attempts to distinguish lex lata and lex ferenda often rely on differentiating between codification and progressive development of the law.62 Codification means formulating and systematizing rules that already exist in the form of practice accepted as law (lex lata), while progressive development is an overtly political act concerned with formulations of what the law should be (lex ferenda).63 However, even though codification is meant to be scientific, not political,64 formulating a general rule from actual practice necessarily entails some level of law creation. Codification involves legal judgments because it seeks to form a coherent rule in the face of inconsistent practice, which requires some crystallization of lex ferenda. Second, it is difficult to distinguish between codification and progressive development by examining the language of treaties and declarations and their travaux prparatoires.65 For example, treaties and resolutions might form customs when expressed in obligatory language, such as must, rather than aspirational terms, such as should.66 However, the Court has relied on resolutions couched in both mandatory and nonmandatory language.67 Further, mandatory language is still ambiguous because it can represent a moral, treaty, or customary obligation. Thus, whether a declaration or treaty provides a statement of what the customary law is or should be cannot be determined by reference to mandatory or permissive words alone. Finally, treaties and resolutions often use mandatory language to prescribe a model of conduct and provide a catalyst for the development of modern custom.68 Treaties and declarations do not merely photograph or declare the current state of practice on moral issues. Rather, they often reflect a deliberate ambiguity between actual and desired practice, designed to develop the law and to stretch the consensus on the text as far as possible.69 For example, some rights set out in the Universal Declaration of Human Rights of 1948 are expressed in mandatory terms and have achieved customary status even though infringements are widespread, often gross and generally tolerated by the international community.70 As a result, modern custom often represents progressive development of the law masked as codification by phrasing lex ferenda as lex lata.71
North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 3, 38. MARK VILLIGER, CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW AND TREATIES: A MANUAL ON THE THEORY AND PRACTICE OF THE INTERRELATION OF SOURCES 102 (2d ed. 1997); R. R. Baxter, Multilateral Treaties as Evidence of Customary International Law, 196566 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 275, 286. 63 ICJ STATUTE Art. 15. 64 Schachter, supra note 48, at 2. 65 Akehurst, supra note 7, at 4547. 66 For example, the range of terms in the Manila Declaration on the Peaceful Settlement of International Disputes, GA Res. 37/10 (Nov. 14, 1982). See also Luigi Condorelli, Remarks [on lex lata and lex ferenda], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 79. 67 E.g., Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 107, paras. 20304 (citing Declaration on Principles of International Law Concerning Friendly Relations and Co-operation Among States in Accordance with the Charter of the United Nations, supra note 23; Helsinki Accord, supra note 23). 68 Jimnez de Archaga, supra note 20; Alain Pellet, The Normative Dilemma: Will and Consent in International LawMaking, 198889 AUSTL. Y.B. INTL L. 22, 35. 69 MERON, supra note 2, at 4344. 70 SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 335. 71 MERON, supra note 2, at 42.
62 61

764

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

Thus, state practice is descriptive, while opinio juris can be descriptive or normative. Traditional custom and modern custom are primarily justified by descriptive accuracy and normative appeal, respectively, because of their emphasis on state practice and normative opinio juris. Facilitative and Moral Customs The best balance between the justifications of descriptive accuracy and normative appeal depends on the facilitative or moral content of the custom involved. International laws are ranged on a spectrum between facilitative and moral rules.72 At one extreme, there are completely facilitative rules, which promote coexistence and cooperation but do not deal with substantive moral issues (such as that ships must pass on the left). Next come primarily facilitative rules that regulate interaction but also give rise to some moral considerations (such as the fair distribution of resources in a continental shelf). Moving to the middle, one finds rules that involve important facilitative and moral considerations (such as environmental rules). Toward the other extreme, the laws are primarily moral rather than facilitative (such as some human rights obligations) and peremptory rules that prohibit actions whether or not they affect coexistence and cooperation (such as jus cogens laws prohibiting genocide). While it is possible for a law to facilitate interaction between states and also have a strong moral content (such as the prohibition on the use of force), laws often tend more toward one or the other end of the spectrum. Facilitative customs are more descriptive than normative because they turn a description of actual practice into a prescriptive requirement for future action.73 Moral customs are more normative than descriptive because they prescribe future action based on normative evaluations of ideal practice. Traditional customs primarily facilitate coexistence and cooperation between sovereign states without having a peremptory moral character; for example, the law on diplomatic immunity.74 State practice is dominant in establishing traditional facilitative customs because these rules turn empirical descriptions of past practice into prescriptive requirements for future practice.75 However, international law has expanded since 1945 to include many moral 76 issues such as human rights,77 the use of force,78 and environmental protection.79 Louis Henkin characterizes this development as a move from state values to human values, and from a liberal state system to a welfare system.80 State practice is less important in forming modern customs because these customs prescribe ideal standards of conduct rather than describe existing practice.81 For example, the customary prohibition on torture expresses a moral abhorrence of torture rather than an accurate description of state practice.82
HART, supra note 47, at 225. HANS KELSEN, PRINCIPLES OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 30708, 418 (1952). 74 Kelly, supra note 1, at 47980. 75 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 89. 76 By morality, I am again referring to commonly held subjective values about actions that are right and wrong, and have been recognized by a representative majority of states in treaties and declarations. While these values are often called normative, I call them moral so as not to confuse the distinction between descriptive/ normative justifications and facilitative/moral content. I use the term normative to describe a statement about what the practice should be, rather than to reflect the inherent moral content of a rule. 77 Bruun, supra note 29, at 21617; Lillich, supra note 29, at 8. 78 E.g., Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. 14. 79 Bodansky, supra note 41. 80 Henkin, supra note 25, at 3435. 81 SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 11; FERNANDO R. TESN, HUMANITARIAN INTERVENTION: AN INQUIRY INTO LAW AND MORALITY 14 (1988); Theodor Meron, On a Hierarchy of International Human Rights, 80 AJIL 1, 1920 (1986); Oscar Schachter, Entangled Treaty and Custom, in INTERNATIONAL LAW AT A TIME OF PERPLEXITY 717, 73334 (Yoram Dinstein ed., 1989). 82 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 702.
73 72

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

765

The moral content of modern custom explains the strong tendency to discount the importance of contrary state practice in the modern approach. Irregularities in description can undermine a descriptive law, but a normative law may be broken and remain a law because it is not premised on descriptive accuracy. For example, jus cogens norms prohibit fundamentally immoral conduct and cannot be undermined by treaty arrangement or inconsistent state practice.83 Since the subject matter of modern customs is not morally neutral, the international community is not willing to accept any norm established by state practice.84 Modern custom involves an almost teleological approach, whereby some examples of state practice are used to justify a chosen norm, rather than deriving norms from state practice. As noted above, this approach was evident in the Nicaragua case, where the Court held it sufficient for the conduct of states to be generally consistent with statements of rules, provided that contrary state practice had generally been treated as breaches of that rule, not as indications of the recognition of a new rule.85 Thus, the importance of descriptive accuracy varies according to the facilitative or moral content of the rule involved. The relative importance of procedural and substantive normativity also varies between facilitative and moral customs. These two types of normativity are reminiscent of Dworkins distinction between fair institutions (procedural normativity) and just outcomes (substantive normativity).86 The two concepts are related in international law because unfair institutions that concentrate power in the hands of a few states are less likely to produce just outcomes as judged by the majority of states. They are also independently important because inadequacies in either procedural or substantive normativity will diminish respect for asserted customs and reduce their ability to effect compliance. However, their relative importance varies in accordance with the customs concerned. As primarily facilitative rules do not deal with substantive moral issues, it suffices for them to be procedurally normative and substantively neutral. For example, traffic regulations should be enacted by a fair process but do not need to be substantively normative because they generally facilitate interaction rather than deal with substantive moral issues. Ideally, rules that deal with moral issues should be procedurally and substantively normative, but the international community may allow the substantive morality of some customs to outweigh defects in their process. For example, the substantive morality of jus cogens norms outweighs the procedural right of sovereign states to become persistent objectors to them.87 The relative importance of substantive and procedural normativity links to criticisms of modern custom as creating quasi legislation on the basis of declarations and treaties.88 Declarations of international fora are formally nonbinding, while states can determine whether, and to what extent, they wish to be bound by treaties.89 By contrast, custom is generally binding except for the limited and contentious persistent objector rule.90 Transforming
83 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, opened for signature May 23, 1969, Art. 53, 1155 UNTS 331; see also RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102 cmt. k; DAVID HARRIS, CASES AND MATERIALS ON INTERNATIONAL LAW 42, 835 (5th ed. 1998); H. W. A. THIRLWAY, INTERNATIONAL CUSTOMARY LAW AND CODIFICATION 110 (1972); Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 4; cf. ANTONIO CASSESE, INTERNATIONAL LAW IN A DIVIDED WORLD 179 (1989). 84 SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 11; see also Schachter, supra note 81, at 73334. 85 Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 98, para. 186. 86 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 177. 87 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102 cmt. k; THIRLWAY, supra note 83, at 110; Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 4; cf. CASSESE, supra note 83, at 179. 88 Henkin, supra note 25, at 37; Fred L. Morrison, Legal Issues in the Nicaragua Opinion, 81 AJIL 160, 162 (1987). 89 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 83, Art. 26; Schachter, supra note 81, at 72728. 90 According to the persistent objector rule, states that have persistently objected during the emergence of a custom are not bound by it. Gerald Fitzmaurice, The General Principles of International Law Considered from the Standpoint of the Rules of Law, 92 RECUEIL DES COURS 1, 4950 (1957 II); Stein, supra note 25, at 457. However, the International Court of Justice has endorsed the persistent objector rule only twice, and arguably both times in obiter dicta. Fisheries case (UK v. Nor.), 1951 ICJ REP.116, 131 (Dec. 18); Asylum (Colom./Peru), 1950 ICJ REP. 266, 27778 (Nov. 20); see also Nuclear Tests (Austl. v. Fr.), 1974 ICJ REP. 253, 28693 (Dec. 20) (Gross, J., sep. op.). Further, a state cannot be a persistent objector to jus cogens rules and theorists have generally concluded that the

766

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

declarations and treaties into custom changes their nature because customs can bind nonparties to treaties and declarations91 and are not affected by reservations92 or denunciation.93 Thus, Prosper Weil argues that the requirements of treaties have not been frontally assaulted but cunningly outflanked.94 However, the emphasis on community consensus over individual state consent in modern custom reflects the priority of substantive normativity over procedural normativity in important moral issues. Modern custom evinces a desire to create general international laws that can bind all states on important moral issues.95 According to Kirgis, The alternative would be an international legal order containing ominous silenceswhere treaty commitments cannot be foundconcerning the ways in which states impose their wills on other states or on individuals.96 The international community discounts the importance of dissenting states and contrary state practice because it is not prepared to recognize exceptions to the maintenance of certain fundamental values. Recognizing exceptions to such rules would shock the conscience of mankind97 and be contrary to elementary considerations of humanity.98 The substantive normativity of modern custom can therefore be used to justify a reduced focus on procedural normativity and descriptive accuracy. The importance of descriptive accuracy and normative appeal, and procedural and substantive normativity, varies according to the facilitative and moral content of traditional and modern custom. The reduced focus on state practice in the modern approach is explained by its use to create generally binding laws on important moral issues. Apology and Utopia Descriptive accuracy and normative appeal provide important bases for justifying international law. While facilitative and moral rules respectively tend more toward descriptive accuracy and normative appeal, neither value is sufficient to justify all international laws. According to Koskenniemi, international law mediates between the competing tendencies of apology (description) and utopia (normativity). A law which would lack distance from State behaviour, will or interest would amount to a non-normative apology, a mere sociological description. A law which would base itself on principles which are unrelated to State behaviour, will or interest would seem utopian, incapable of demonstrating its own content in any reliable way.99 The conflicting values of description and normativity, and their respective risks of being an apology for power or utopian and unachievable, represent the fundamental tension in legal argument.100 Theorists oscillate between these two extremes and each position remains open to challenge from the opposite perspective.101 Thus, international legal argument is
practical application of the rule is limited. BYERS, supra note 6, at 181; DAMATO, supra note 6, at 18799, 23363; Jonathan I. Charney, The Persistent Objector Rule and the Development of Customary International Law, 1986 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 1, 1116. 91 It may also discourage states from voting for aspirational instruments. Thomas M. Franck, Some Observations on the ICJs Procedural and Substantive Innovations, 81 AJIL 116, 119 (1987). 92 Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 11314, paras. 21718; MERON, supra note 2, at 67, 27; Pierre Imbert, Reservations and Human Rights Conventions, 6 HUM. RTS. REV. 28 (1981); Schachter, supra note 81, at 72728. 93 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 83, Art. 43. 94 Prosper Weil, Towards Relative Normativity in International Law? 77 AJIL 413, 438 (1983). 95 CASSESE, supra note 83, at 31, 110, 398; Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 13; Tasioulas, supra note 42, at 11617. 96 Kirgis, supra note 42, at 148. 97 Reservations to the Convention on the Prevention and Punishment of the Crime of Genocide, Advisory Opinion, 1951 ICJ REP. 15, 23 (May 28). 98 Corfu Channel case (UK v. Alb.), Merits, 1949 ICJ REP. 4, 22 (Apr. 9). 99 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 2. 100 BYERS, supra note 6, at 49. 101 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 42.

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

767

always dynamic. David Kennedy argues that [e]ither international law has been too far from politics and must move closer to become effective, or it has become dangerously intermingled with politics and must assert its autonomy to remain potent.102 The dynamic between description and normativity represents the deep doctrinal schizophrenia of law,103 or a disciplinary hamster wheel from which theorists appear unable to escape.104 While the justifications for traditional and modern custom mainly align with descriptive accuracy and normative appeal, neither approach is completely descriptive or normative because both recognize the importance of state practice and opinio juris to varying degrees. However, as the two approaches to custom tend toward opposite ends of the theoretical spectrum, the strongest criticisms of each come from the counterstandpoint. Traditional custom embodies the value of descriptive accuracy but the risk of apologism, so that one of the main criticisms of traditional custom is that it lacks democratic legitimacy (a normative criticism). By contrast, modern custom is normatively appealing but risks creating utopian rules, so it is criticized for producing norms that are divorced from reality (a descriptive criticism). The critiques of traditional and modern custom rest on this basis. A critique of traditional custom. Traditional custom lacks procedural normativity. The process of custom formation is inherently uncertain, with no clear guide to the amount, duration, frequency, and continuity of state practice required to form a custom.105 The unwritten nature of traditional custom makes its content inherently insecure, while requiring repeated practice is too clumsy and slow106 to accommodate the fast-paced evolution of law.107 Traditional custom is meant to be based on general and consistent state practice, but selective analysis inheres in this approach because of the impossibility of thoroughly analyzing the practice of almost two hundred states.108 This selectivity results in a democratic deficit109 because most customs are found to exist on the basis of practice by fewer than a dozen states.110 For example, the finding of a custom of neutrality of international canals in the Wimbledon case was based on the Suez and Panama Canal Treaties alone.111 If norms are based primarily on actions,112 then only states with the ability to act can form and reject customs.113 States might participate directly by making statements114 or indirectly if inaction amounts to acquiescence.115 However, all states must then have perfect knowledge of state practice, unlimited resources to respond, and the awareness that failure to respond will have legal consequences, all of which is patently not so.116 Thus, a majority of states rarely participate in the creation of customs that limit their sovereignty.117
David Kennedy, When Renewal Repeats: Thinking Against the Box, 32 N.Y.U. J. INTL L. & POL. 335, 355 (2000). DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 271. 104 Kennedy, supra note 102, at 407. 105 BYERS, supra note 6, at 15662; DAMATO, supra note 6, at 5666. 106 WOLFGANG FRIEDMANN, THE CHANGING STRUCTURE OF INTERNATIONAL LAW 122 (1964). 107 Fidler, supra note 27, at 216. 108 Charney, supra note 21, at 537; Fidler, supra note 27, at 203, 217. 109 Kelly, supra note 1, at 519. 110 Charney, supra note 21, at 537; Chodosh, supra note 17, at 102; Oscar Schachter, New Custom: Power, Opinio Juris and Contrary Practice, in THEORY OF INTERNATIONAL LAW AT THE THRESHOLD OF THE 21ST CENTURY: ESSAYS IN HONOUR OF KRZYSZTOF SKUBISZEWSKI 531, 536 ( Jerzy Makarczyk ed., 1996); Weisburd, supra note 31, at 6. 111 S.S. Wimbledon, 1923 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 1, at 25 (Aug. 17); see also Chodosh, supra note 17, at 102 n.69; Kelly, supra note 1, at 470 n.93. 112 E.g., DAMATO, supra note 6, at 7487; W. Michael Reisman, International Incidents: Introduction to a New Genre in the Study of International Law, 10 YALE J. INTL L. 1, 14 (1984). 113 BYERS, supra note 6, at 37. 114 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 9697. 115 KAROL WOLFKE, CUSTOM IN PRESENT INTERNATIONAL LAW 135 (2d ed. 1993); Akehurst, supra note 7, at 37; I. C. MacGibbon, The Scope of Acquiescence in International Law, 1954 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 143, 14546 [hereinafter MacGibbon, Acquiescence I ]; I. C. MacGibbon, Customary International Law and Acquiescence, 1957 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 115, 138 [hereinafter MacGibbon, Acquiescence II ]. 116 Kelly, supra note 1, at 522. 117 Id. at 519.
103 102

768

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

These procedural inadequacies have also led to problems regarding the substantive normativity of traditional custom. New, developing, and socialist states have objected to customs as having been created by wealthy European and imperialist powers.118 Instead of being apolitical, traditional custom is arguably hegemonic, ideologically biased, and a legitimating force for the political and economic status quo. For example, new states are bound by existing customs even though they did not participate in their formation.119 The legal fiction of free and equal states also masks the reality of extreme variations of de facto power.120 Powerful states wield disproportionate and often decisive influence in determining the content and application of custom.121 Further, courts tend to focus primarily on Western state practice.122 For example, the Permanent Court cited decisive precedents in the Lotus case based on actions by only six Western states.123 Recently, some international lawyers have predicted that NATOs intervention in Kosovo will establish a right to unilateral humanitarian intervention, despite protests by China, India, and the Russian Federation.124 Procedural inadequacies also give rise to substantive unfairness. For example, Mohammed Bedjaoui argues that the freedom of the high seas was developed to meet the needs of wealthy states with large fleets rather than the interests of states whose shores were approached.125 Its undemocratic nature allows traditional custom to become an apology for exercises of power by strong Western nations.126 The resulting sense of injustice diminishes respect for traditional custom, as well as its pull toward compliance. A critique of modern custom. Modern custom demonstrates strengths and weaknesses in procedural normativity. Reliance on statements accelerates the formation of custom,127 which allows it to regulate global, as opposed to regional or national, issues in a timely manner.128 Deriving customs primarily from treaties and declarations, rather than state practice, is potentially more democratic because it involves practically all states. Most states can participate in the negotiation and ratification of treaties and declarations of international fora, such as the United Nations General Assembly. The notion of sovereign equality (one state, one vote) helps to level the playing field between developed and developing countries. While formal equality cannot remedy all inequalities in power, international fora provide less powerful states with a cost-efficient means of expressing their views.129 However, allowing a majority of states to bind a minority does not sit well with the notion of state sovereignty. Further, the precise criteria for forming modern custom have not been clearly articulated in cases such as Nicaragua, where the Court still claimed to be applying the traditional test.130 It is also not clear that states know that treaties will become customary law, or that they wish
118 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102(2); LOUIS HENKIN, HOW NATIONS BEHAVE 121 (2d ed. 1979); Fidler, supra note 27, at 21314, 218; B. Graefrath, Remarks [on custom and treaties], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 19, 1920; Schachter, supra note 81, at 721. 119 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 19193; Akehurst, supra note 7, at 27. 120 Tasioulas, supra note 42, at 123. 121 MOHAMMED BEDJAOUI, TOWARD A NEW INTERNATIONAL ECONOMIC ORDER 5152 (1979); DE VISSCHER, supra note 48, at 149; SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 6. 122 Kelly, supra note 1, at 469. 123 S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, at 29 (Sept. 7); see also Chodosh, supra note 17, at 102 n.70; Weisburd, Customary IL, supra note 31, at 6. 124 E.g., Antonio Cassese, Ex iniuria ius oritur: Are We Moving Towards International Legitimation of Forcible Humanitarian Countermeasures in the World Community? 10 EUR. J. INTL L. 23 (1999); Jonathan I. Charney, Anticipatory Humanitarian Intervention in Kosovo, 93 AJIL 834, 83537 (1999). 125 BEDJAOUI, supra note 121, at 136. 126 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 355. 127 Bradley & Goldsmith, supra note 35, at 840 n.167. 128 Charney, supra note 21, at 543; cf. Right of Passage over Indian Territory (Port. v. India), Merits, 1960 ICJ REP. 6, 39 (Apr. 12) (on regional customs). 129 Right of Passage over Indian Territory, 1960 ICJ REP. at 37. 130 Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 27.

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

769

them to,131 though this may be changing. Likewise, votes in the General Assembly usually receive little media scrutiny and are generally not intended to make law.132 For example, the General Assembly resolution on torture133 was adopted unanimously, while a much smaller number of states ratified the Convention Against Torture134 and others entered significant reservations to it.135 On the substantive normative level, modern custom provides coherent statements of law on moral issues such as human rights, but it has been criticized for normative chauvinism.136 For example, some decry human rights obligations as reflecting a Western tendency to give primacy to individual rights over communal or group needs.137 Similarly, the conclusions of the Restatement (Third) of the Foreign Relations Law of the United States about customary human rights correlate with civil and political rights enshrined in the U.S. Bill of Rights,138 but omit economic, social, and cultural rights not protected by those provisions.139 Treaties and international fora are harder to charge with Western ideological hegemony because developing nations have been in the majority since the 1950s.140 However, as resolutions and treaties do not automatically become customary law,141 the practice of powerful states arguably determines which ones are so transformed.142 The greatest criticism of modern custom is that it is descriptively inaccurate because it reflects ideal, rather than actual, standards of conduct.143 The normative nature of modern custom leads to an enormous gap between asserted customs and state practice. For example, customary international law prohibits torture, yet torture is endemic.144 A similar criticism is made of the emptiness of jus cogens norms, which are often flouted in practice.145 These laws lack efficacy because states have not internalized them as standards of behavior to guide their actions and judge the behavior of others.146 The regulatory function of modern custom is doubtful because it appears merely to set up aspirational aims rather than realistic requirements about action. For example, while many Asian and African states have accepted human rights treaty obligations, the Tunis declaration by forty-two African states in 1992 and the Bangkok declaration by thirty-four Asian states in 1993 suggest that the majority of nonWestern states view asserted human rights customs as aspirational goals rather than enforceFranck, supra note 91, at 119; I. C. MacGibbon, Means for the Identification of International Law, in INTERsupra note 19, at 10, 13; Pellet, supra note 68, at 31. 132 Dean Rusk, A Comment on Filartiga v. Pena-Irala, 11 GA. J. INTL & COMP. L. 311 (1981); Phillip R. Trimble, A Revisionist View of Customary International Law, 33 UCLA L. REV. 655, 680 n.60 (1986). 133 Resolution Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman, or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, GA Res. 46, UN GAOR, 39th Sess., Supp. No. 51, at 197, UN Doc. A/39/51 (1984). 134 Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman, or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, Dec. 10, 1984, 1465 UNTS 85, 23 ILM 1027 (1984), as modified 24 ILM 535 (1985). 135 For example, the United States. U.S. Reservations, Declarations, and Understandings, Convention Against Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman, or Degrading Treatment or Punishment, 136 CONG. REC. S17,486 (daily ed. Oct. 27, 1990). 136 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 94. 137 Rhoda E. Howard, Dignity, Community, and Human Rights, in HUMAN RIGHTS IN A CROSS-CULTURAL PERSPECTIVE 81 (Abdullahi Ahmed An-Naim ed., 1992); see also Kelly, supra note 1, at 466, 491; cf. Lawrence Friedman, Borders: On the Emerging Sociology of Transnational Law, 32 STAN. J. INTL L. 65, 8385 (1996). 138 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 702. 139 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 9495. 140 BEDJAOUI, supra note 121, at 141. 141 See pt. I supra; see also Charney, supra note 110, at 547; cf. DAMATO, supra note 6, at 104, 110, 164. 142 Kelly, supra note 1, at 52021. 143 Bodansky, supra note 41, at 11011; James S. Watson, Legal Theory, Efficacy and Validity in the Development of Human Rights Norms in International Law, U. ILL. L.F. 609, 61013, 641 (1979). 144 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 702; Fidler, supra note 27, at 227 n.129; Rosalyn Higgins, Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It, in INTERNATIONAL HUMAN RIGHTS IN CONTEXT 232 (Henry J. Steiner & Philip Alston eds., 2d ed. 2000). 145 Arthur A. Weisburd, The Emptiness of the Concept of Jus Cogens, as Illustrated by the War in Bosnia-Herzegovina, 17 MICH. J. INTL L. 49 (1995). 146 HART, supra note 47, at 8691.
NATIONAL LAW,
131

770

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

able obligations.147 Some theorists characterize modern customs as soft laws or sublegal obligations that do not amount to law.148 Indeed, norms that are honored in the breach do not yield reliable predictions of future conduct and are likely to bring themselves, and possibly custom as a whole, into disrepute.149 The dynamic relationship between apology and utopia. The advantages and disadvantages of traditional and modern custom are dynamic because criticisms of traditional custom tend to correspond to advantages of modern custom and vice versa. An improvement in normative appeal will often correspond to a decline in descriptive accuracy, while an enhancement of descriptive accuracy will often result in a deterioration of normative appeal. Whereas some rules are descriptively accurate and normatively appealing, the two justifications often have a relationship of inverse proportionality. For example, relying on declarations by international fora is potentially more democratic than relying on the actions of powerful states (a normative improvement in modern custom), but since these declarations are supported by a majority of states rather than a predominance of power, they are less likely to be enforced in practice (a descriptive deterioration from traditional custom).150 Similarly, the relationship between procedural and substantive normativity is also dynamic. For example, one could bind all states on important moral issues (a substantive normative advantage), but doing so would bind some states without their consent (a procedural normative problem).151 Thus, the values of description and normativity represent the fundamental tension in legal argument152 and both approaches remain open to challenge from the opposite perspective.153 As seen, international law reveals a dynamic tension between descriptive accuracy and normative appeal. Traditional custom has descriptive strengths but lacks democratic legitimacy, while modern custom deals with substantive moral issues but produces laws that do not reflect reality. This tension leads to the issue of whether the two approaches can be reconciled in a single interpretive theory. III. CUSTOM ON AN INTERPRETIVE SLIDING SCALE The divergence between the traditional and modern approaches to custom has been criticized as making custom indeterminate and malleable.154 This part analyzes one attempt at reconciling them by applying Dworkins interpretive theory of law to custom on a sliding scale. Law as Interpretation: Dworkin Dworkin argues that legal decisions aim at reformulating past decisions and practice in the most coherent and morally attractive way, consistent with the facts of legal history. Dworkin outlines three steps in the interpretive process: preinterpretation, interpretation, and postinterpretation.155 In the preinterpretive stage, the rules and facts that form the practice to be interpreted are identified. The term preinterpretation is somewhat misleading because the collection of
147 Report of the Regional Meeting for Africa of the World Conference on Human Rights, UN Doc. A/ CONF.157/AFRM/14, at 1 (1992); Report of the Regional Meeting for Asia of the World Conference on Human Rights, UN Doc. A/CONF.157/ASRM/8, at 3 (1993). 148 Weil, supra note 94, at 415. 149 Jonathan I. Charney, Customary International Law in the Nicaragua Case Judgment on the Merits, 1988 HAGUE Y.B. INTL L. 16, 24. 150 BEDJAOUI, supra note 121, at 14144. 151 Fidler, supra note 27, at 22022, 22425. 152 BYERS, supra note 6, at 49. 153 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 42. 154 Kelly, supra note 1, at 451. 155 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 66.

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

771

data is theory dependent.156 Consequently, this stage requires a high degree of consensus to provide a common focus for interpretation.157 In the interpretive stage, the interpreter formulates a general explanation for the main elements of the practice. This explanation is called the dimension of fit and it imposes a rough threshold requirement that accepts an interpretation as eligible only if the raw data of legal practice adequately support it.158 There can be three outcomes at this stage: no eligible interpretations, if every possible interpretation is inconsistent with the bulk of raw material available; easy cases, when there is only one eligible interpretation; and hard cases, where a range of eligible interpretations result because the tests are unsettled or the practice conflicting. Postinterpretation only becomes relevant in hard cases, where interpreters must choose the best eligible interpretation according to the dimension of substance.159 The best interpretation is the one that makes the practice appear in the best light, judged according to the substantive aspirations of the legal system. This criterion involves consideration of moral and political ideals, as well as higher-order convictions about how these ideals should be prioritized when they conflict.160 The interpretive stage is backward looking and descriptive, while the postinterpretive stage is forward looking and normative. Dworkins interpretive theory of law combines a descriptive historical investigation about what the law has been (fit) with a normative moral inquiry about what it should be (substance).161 According to Dworkin: propositions of law are not simply descriptive of legal history in a straightforward way, nor are they simply evaluative in some way divorced from legal history. They are interpretive of legal history, which combines elements of both description and evaluation but is different from both.162 What, however, is the relationship between fit and substance? Dworkin originally proposed a lexical ordering between them,163 but in Laws Empire he revised the relationship. Fit provides a rough threshold criterion.164 Interpretations need not fit every aspect of the existing practice, but they must fit enough for the interpreter to be interpreting that practice, not inventing a new one.165 On the other hand, if there are multiple eligible interpretations, then fit and substance must be balanced against each other.166 Thus, any inadequacies of fit will count against an interpretation at the substantive stage because an interpretation is pro tanto more satisfactory if it shows less damage to integrity than its rival.167 Similarly, defects of fit may be compensated . . . if the principles of that interpretation are particularly attractive.168 The interpreter must therefore balance the relative strengths of fit and substance in different interpretations to determine the best interpretation. Dworkin likens this process to multiple authors writing consecutive chapters in a chain novel. Each author must contribute a chapter that provides sufficient continuity with the earlier chapters
Id. Id. at 6566. 158 Id. at 255. 159 Id. at 256. 160 Id. 161 Ronald Dworkin, Law and Morals, Natural Law, and Legal Positivism, in OXFORD COMPANION, supra note 57, at 473, 47374, 606, 60607, and 476, 47677, respectively; Ronald Dworkin, Law as Interpretation, 60 TEX. L. REV. 527, 528 (1982) [hereinafter Dworkin, Interpretation]. 162 Dworkin, Interpretation, supra note 161, at 528. 163 RONALD DWORKIN, TAKING RIGHTS SERIOUSLY 34041 (3d ed. 1981); RONALD DWORKIN, Is There Really No Right Answer in Hard Cases? in A MATTER OF PRINCIPLE 143 (1985). 164 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 25557. 165 Id. at 66. 166 John Finnis, On Reason and Authority in Laws Empire, 6 LAW & PHIL. 357, 37374 (1987). 167 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 24647. 168 Id. at 257.
157 156

772

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

(fit) and develops the book in the best way (substance).169 However, Dworkin details no method for weighing fit and substance other than the metaphor balance.170 Hence, anyone using Dworkins interpretive theory must correctly identify fit and substance and develop a working theory about how to balance them. Custom on a Sliding Scale: Kirgis and Tasioulas The international legal system is decentralized, resulting in multiple interpreters of custom. The existence and content of custom is usually determined by states and academics, though the Court remains the ultimate arbiter in some cases.171 These interpreters are meant to determine customs on the basis of state practice and opinio juris.172 However, the traditional and modern forms of custom both appear to emphasize one element at the expense of the other. Kirgis argues that the two approaches can be understood by viewing state practice and opinio juris as interchangeable along a sliding scale:173 On the sliding scale, very frequent, consistent state practice establishes a customary rule without much (or any) affirmative showing of an opinio juris, so long as it is not negated by evidence of non-normative intent. As the frequency and consistency of the practice decline in any series of cases, a stronger showing of an opinio juris is required. At the other end of the scale, a clearly demonstrated opinio juris establishes a customary rule without much (or any) affirmative showing [of state practice].174 Yet when will a custom be formed on the basis only of state practice or opinio juris, instead of requiring both elements? According to Kirgis, the answer depends on the importance of the activity in question and the reasonableness of the rule involved. If an activity is not very destructive, then the Court will be more exacting in requiring both state practice and opinio juris to form a custom. By contrast, Kirgis states, [t]he more destabilizing or morally distasteful the activityfor example, the offensive use of force or the deprivation of fundamental human rightsthe more readily international decision makers will substitute one element for the other, provided that the asserted restrictive rule seems reasonable.175 The sliding scale has been criticized as reinterpreting the concept of customary law to ensure that it provides the right answers.176 Tasioulas, however, claims that the sliding scale can be rationalized by means of Dworkins interpretive theory of law. While Dworkin is primarily concerned with interpreting previous case law, custom is principally concerned with interpreting the raw data of state practice and opinio juris. At the level of fit, the Court must attempt to formulate eligible interpretations that can explain the raw data of state practice and opinio juris. If there is little or no state practice or opinio juris, there will be no eligible interpretations. In easy cases, there will be strong state practice and opinio juris, which will produce only one eligible interpretation. In hard cases, there will be inconsistent levels of state practice and opinio juris, giving rise to multiple eligible interpretations. For example, high state practice and low opinio juris may indicate that torture is permitted, and low state practice and high opinio juris may indicate that torture is prohibited. Two eligible interpretations result, one permitting torture and the other prohibiting it. To determine
Id. at 22832. Finnis, supra note 166, at 374. 171 Bodansky, supra note 41. 172 ICJ STATUTE Art. 38(1)(b); North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3, 44 (Feb. 20). 173 See Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. 14; Namibia Advisory Opinion, 1971 ICJ REP. 16; Corfu Channel case (UK v. Alb.), Merits, 1949 ICJ REP. 4, 34 (Apr. 9). 174 Kirgis, supra note 42, at 149. 175 Id. 176 Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 83.
170 169

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

773

the best interpretation in these cases, Tasioulas argues that the Court must balance the dimensions of fit and substance on a sliding scale. Thus, an interpretation may be the best, even though it fares poorly on the dimension of fit (for example, because it has strong opinio juris but weak state practice), if the norm possesses very strong substantive appeal.177 By contrast, the Court will be more exacting in requiring both elements in the absence of strong substantive considerations.178 A Critique of Custom on a Sliding Scale Although Tasioulas does not articulate this, his interpretive theory of custom actually involves two sliding scales. The first weighs state practice and opinio juris against each other at the level of fit to create eligible interpretations. If there are multiple eligible interpretations, the best interpretation is determined by employing a second sliding scale to balance the dimensions of fit and substance. While interpretation is less mechanical in practice, these stages should be differentiated to demonstrate why custom should not be analyzed on a sliding scale. Criticism one: apology and utopia. The first sliding scale allows inadequacies in state practice to be compensated for by strong opinio juris and vice versa. However, this procedure paves the way for normative criticism because it allows the strength of one element to outweigh deficiencies in the other. Finding traditional custom on the strength of state practice alone allows it to become an apology for state power.179 Similarly, deducing modern custom purely from opinio juris can create utopian laws that cannot regulate reality. Arguably, interpretations are prevented from lapsing into apology and utopia because the second sliding scale balances deficiencies in fit against the strength of the dimension of substance. But this argument fails for two reasons. First, the dimension of substance becomes relevant only if there is more than one eligible interpretation. Thus, a custom may be the only eligible interpretation on the basis of strong state practice without any reference to its procedural or substantive normativity. In this case, custom would become an apology for exercises of power. Second, the sliding scale allows strong opinio juris to create an eligible interpretation at the dimension of fit, which is then weighed according to the second sliding scale for its substantive appeal. However, opinio juris is often an expression of lex ferenda, so that the two sliding scales would allow modern custom to be formed by normative considerations of lex ferenda at the level of fit and substance. In this case, utopian customs could be produced without any guarantee of the descriptive accuracy associated with fit and state practice. Criticism two: asymmetrical application. Kirgis and Tasioulas claim that the more morally distasteful an activity, the more readily the Court will substitute opinio juris for state practice and vice versa.180 This works for modern custom, where there is strong opinio juris but weak state practice, for example in the Nicaragua case. However, the Court seems willing to find traditional custom, where there is strong state practice and weak opinio juris, without considering whether the activity is morally distasteful, for example in S.S. Wimbledon.181 Thus, it is wrong to conclude that the stronger the substantive considerations involved, the more likely the Court is to substitute one element for the other. Instead, questions of substance seem likely to arise in situations where the problems with fit concern a lack of affirming state practice rather than a lack of opinio juris.
Tasioulas, supra note 42, at 113. E.g., North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. 3. 179 KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 2. 180 Kirgis, supra note 42, at 149. 181 S.S. Wimbledon, 1923 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 1, at 25 (Aug. 17); see also North Sea Continental Shelf, 1969 ICJ REP. at 231 (Lachs, J., dissenting); id. at 241, 24647 (Srensen, J. ad hoc, dissenting); Nottebohm case (Liech. v. Guat.), Second Phase, 1955 ICJ REP. 4, 22 (Apr. 6).
178 177

774

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

Employing a sliding scale between fit and substance does not adequately describe the process of finding custom because it applies asymmetrically to traditional and modern custom. It does so for two reasons. First, the second sliding scale is employed only if more than one interpretation meets the threshold requirement of fit.182 Traditional custom fares well on fit because it focuses on state practice, which is descriptively accurate. Modern custom fares less well on fit because opinio juris often cloaks lex ferenda as lex lata and thus lacks descriptive accuracy. Modern custom also involves practice that is hard to identify and evaluate, such as intrastate action and inaction. Consequently, traditional custom is more likely than modern custom to result in only one eligible interpretation, often removing the need for substantive considerations and a second sliding scale. Second, the importance of substantive considerations also varies according to the facilitative and moral content of traditional and modern custom. Traditional customs are often facilitative, so that even when there is a deficiency in fit owing to insufficient opinio juris, the postinterpretive stage has little application because the rules do not involve substantive moral issues. Traditional customs should still be procedurally normative, but this aspect does not provide a strong dimension of substance. By contrast, modern customs often have a strongly moral content. Thus, modern custom involves strong substantive considerations about what the law should be, as well as respect for procedural normativity to ensure that all nations are able to express their views about what substantive aims should be pursued. For these reasons, modern custom is more likely than traditional custom to give rise to a strong dimension of substance and a second sliding scale. IV. CUSTOM AS A REFLECTIVE INTERPRETIVE CONCEPT Dworkins interpretive theory of law incorporates the values of fit (description) and substance (normativity) but does not provide a mechanism for balancing them. Analyzing custom on a sliding scale is flawed because it misconceives the nature of fit and substance and risks creating customs that are apologies for power or utopian and unachievable. This part presents an alternative vision of Dworkins interpretive theory as applied to custom, which re-conceptualizes the nature of fit and substance and balances them in a Rawlsian reflective equilibrium. The Theory of Custom as a Reflective Interpretive Concept Preinterpretation. At the preinterpretation stage, the relevant data for interpretation are identified. For custom, these are generally assumed to be state practice and opinio juris. However, the collection of data is theory dependent and our interpretive approach is limited by the assumptions we make at this stage.183 Focusing exclusively on state practice and opinio juris is theory dependent because it reflects a statist approach to international law. It is generally assumed that states, acting individually or collectively in intergovernmental organizations, are the only relevant actors in the formation of custom.184 Nevertheless, nonstate actors also affect the determination and development of custom in various ways.185 First, judicial decisions and writings by publicists can be used as a subsidiary means of determining international law.186 Though not formal sources of law, they may provide
DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 24647, 25557. Id. 184 John King Gamble & Charlotte Ku, New Actors and New Technologies: Center Stage for NGOs? 31 LAW & POLY INTL BUS. 221, 24344 (2000). 185 Karsten Nowrot, Legal Consequences of Globalization: The Status of Non-Governmental Organizations Under International Law, 6 IND. J. GLOBAL LEGAL STUD. 579, 595 (1999); Peter J. Spiro, New Global Potentates: Nongovernmental Organizations and the Unregulated Marketplace, 18 CARDOZO L. REV. 957, 95960 (1996). 186 ICJ STATUTE Art. 38(1)(d).
183 182

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

775

authoritative evidence of the state of the law. In practice, however, judicial decisions can also have a formative effect on custom by crystallizing emerging rules and thus influencing state behavior.187 Moreover, academics often cite the work of other writers as evidence of the existence and content of custom instead of thoroughly analyzing state practice. Yet how judicial decisions and academic writings could be incorporated into an interpretive analysis of custom is unclear. For example, Dworkin includes judicial decisions in the dimension of fit when interpreting domestic law, but this may be inappropriate in international law, which lacks a doctrine of precedent.188 Custom is also concerned with interpreting past practice, rather than past case law, and judicial decisions do not always accurately describe practice.189 Second, nonstate actors such as nongovernmental organizations and corporations often have an impact on custom. They have an indirect effect by influencing state behavior and statements through actions such as lobbying and calling boycotts.190 They have assisted in setting the agenda for international conferences and participated in the negotiation and drafting of treaties and resolutions.191 Nongovernmental organizations help to articulate emerging customs and monitor state compliance with international law by investigating and publicizing breaches of the law in areas such as human rights and environmental protection.192 Isabelle Gunning has also argued that nonstate actors should be granted a direct role in the formation of custom,193 though this proposal is controversial because it may give these actors power without accountability.194 The present and potentially increasing role of nonstate actors in the development of custom is undertheorized and beyond the scope of this paper. Nevertheless, it is an important issue and further analysis of it may change our perception of custom in the future. Identifying the dimension of fit. According to Dworkin, a successful interpretation must not only fit but also justify the practice it interprets.195 An interpretive theory of custom combines descriptive accuracy (fit) with normative considerations (substance).196 Questions of fit and description are both backward looking, analyzing the extent to which a decision accords with past practice. Normativity and questions of substance are both forward looking, involving moral and political considerations relevant to what the law should be. This characterization has important implications for properly identifying fit and substance. Tasioulas argues that state practice and opinio juris are both relevant to the dimension of fit. However, the main function of fit is to ensure that interpretations are descriptively accurate. State practice is integral to fit because of its descriptive accuracy, but opinio juris is problematic because statements are descriptive when they express lex lata and normative when they express lex ferenda. Ideally, one should be able to distinguish between lex lata (fit) and lex ferenda (substance). However, as demonstrated above, it is often not possible to distinguish between the two by looking at the language or travaux prparatoires of treaties and decSee examples in BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 1925. ICJ STATUTE Art. 59; see also BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 2021. 189 For example, torture was held to be against customary international law but remains common throughout the world. Filartiga v. Pena-Irala, 630 F.2d 876 (1980). 190 For example, consumer boycotts were called on French products over French nuclear testing. Protests Hurt Wines Sales, N.Y. TIMES, Dec. 25, 1995, 1, at 58. Similarly, many U.S. corporations terminated their presence in South Africa in protest over apartheid well before they were required to do so by federal laws. Kevin P. Lewis, Dealing with South Africa: The Constitutionality of State and Local Divestment Legislation, 61 TUL. L. REV. 469 (1987). 191 For example, the International Committee of the Red Cross played a pivotal role in the initiation and negotiation of the Ottawa convention banning land mines. Kenneth Anderson, The Ottawa Convention Banning Landmines, the Role of International Non-Governmental Organizations and the Idea of International Civil Society, 11 EUR. J. INTL L. 91 (2000). 192 Nowrot, supra note 185, at 59698. 193 Isabelle R. Gunning, Modernizing Customary International Law: The Challenge of Human Rights, 31 VA. J. INTL L. 211, 22734 (1991). 194 Spiro, supra note 185, at 96267. 195 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 285. 196 Id.
188 187

776

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

larations. Thus, strong opinio juris cannot provide an eligible interpretation in the absence of state practice because that would not be descriptively accurate. Instead, statements of opinio juris should be relevant to interpretation in two ways. First, state practice must be accompanied by some articulation of legality so as to distinguish between legal and social obligations.197 For example, giving aid to developing countries probably could not form a customary obligation (even though it is supported by state practice and involves strong substantive considerations) because states have never articulated it as a legal obligation. Second, strong opinio juris is relevant at the level of substance because it represents lex ferenda considerations about what the law should be. Thus, a declaration or treaty adopted by a representative majority of states will provide a strong dimension of substance. Dworkins theory envisages fit as providing a rough threshold for interpretations.198 As we have seen, there are three possible outcomes at this stage. When there is no eligible interpretation, there will be no custom and the legality of action will be determined according to the Lotus principle, which states that [r]estrictions upon the independence of States cannot therefore be presumed.199 Second, when there is only one eligible interpretation because of the uniformity of the practice, there will be no doubt about the existence of a custom, such as customs on diplomatic immunity. Finally, when there are multiple eligible interpretations, one must weigh the dimensions of fit and substance to determine the best interpretation. I contend that because of its superior descriptive accuracy, traditional custom will fare well on fit and is more likely than modern custom to result in only one eligible interpretation. However, modern custom can still pass the threshold of fit by allowing for multiple eligible interpretations if we adopt a more nuanced approach to state practice in two ways. First, state practice is not an automatic operation but is open to interpretation.200 The sliding scale assumes that there must be a trade-off between state practice and opinio juris because they are fixed and irreconcilable quantities. However, inconsistent state practice can be interpreted as a breach of an existing custom or a seed for a new custom,201 which is a particularly important consideration in modern customs such as human rights obligations, where breaches seem reasonably common and widespread.202 Contrary state practice does not necessarily undermine an eligible interpretation but, rather, may create multiple eligible interpretations. For example, NATOs intervention in Kosovo could be interpreted as a breach of an existing customary prohibition on intervention or as the seed for a new custom allowing unilateral humanitarian intervention.203 Thus, modern custom can produce multiple eligible interpretations of state practice without needing to employ a sliding scale between state practice and opinio juris.
GNY, in DAMATO, supra note 6, at 49. DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 24647, 25557. 199 S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, at 18 (Sept. 7). The Court affirmed this principle in Legality of the Threat or Use of Nuclear Weapons, Advisory Opinion, 1996 ICJ REP. 226, 238, para. 20 ( July 8). These decisions establish a residual negative principle, which provides that in the case of a non liquet (an absence of law), whatever is not prohibited in international law is permitted. Daniel Bodansky, Non Liquet and the Incompleteness of International Law, in INTERNATIONAL LAW, THE INTERNATIONAL COURT OF JUSTICE AND NUCLEAR WEAPONS 153 (Laurence Boisson de Chazournes & Philippe Sands eds., 1999); Ole Spiermann, Lotus and the Double Structure of International Legal Argument, in id. at 131; Julius Stone, Non Liquet and the Function of Law in the International Community, 1959 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 124, 135. 200 Martti Koskenniemi, The Pull of the Mainstream, 88 MICH. L. REV. 1946, 1952 (1990); Fastenrath, supra note 49, at 31617. 201 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 9798. 202 SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 335. 203 See The Fluid Nature of Custom, infra p. 784.
198 197

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

777

Second, modern custom is more likely to yield eligible interpretations if we broaden our understanding of state practice beyond the traditional forms of interstate interaction and acquiescence. The atrocities of World War II, the globalization of trade, and improvements in communications have all diminished the importance of state boundaries.204 International law now covers many intrastate issues such as the human rights obligations, which largely protect citizens from their own governments.205 These intrastate issues give rise to little or no interaction between states.206 In its stead, we need to broaden our understanding of state practice to include consideration of intrastate action (not just interstate interaction), obligations being observed (not just obligations being breached), and reasons for a lack of protest over breaches (other than acquiescence in the legality of those breaches). State practice should include intrastate practice rather than just interstate interaction because of the changing subject matter of international law. Patterns of domestic practice, such as decisions of domestic courts, are recognized as relevant forms of state practice.207 Internal breaches of human rights obligations are often characterized as instances of contrary state practice.208 Yet there is little corresponding focus on governments respect for human rights obligations as positive instances of state practice. For one thing, adequate evidence of internal compliance with human rights obligations may be hard to obtain.209 Breaches are sensational and likely to attract attention, but that should not be allowed to obscure a general pattern of less publicized observance.210 The observance of many human rights is also difficult to measure because they are negative rights, which means that they place limitations on state action rather than impose a positive duty on states to act. Observance by inaction, in the form of not violating rights, is inherently ambiguous because it may result from an obligation (prohibitive norm) or discretion (permissive norm);211 or from domestic or treaty obligations rather than custom.212 However, even though intrastate action and inaction may be difficult to identify and evaluate, they are still important forms of state practice in modern international law. Breaches of intrastate obligations are also likely to result in inaction by other states because states do not usually protest violations unless they affect their rights or the rights of their nationals. According to the theory of acquiescence, opinio juris in favor of the legality of action can be inferred if states fail to protest when faced with an infringement of their rights.213 Some intrastate obligations, such as fundamental human rights obligations, can theoretically be enforced by any state because they are owed erga omnes.214 Thus, Karol Wolfke and Weisburd claim that inaction over intrastate breaches amounts to acquiescence, which undermines the customary status of these obligations because rules that are not enforced
Richard A. Falk, Kosovo, World Order, and the Future of International Law, 93 AJIL 847, 853 (1999). Charney, supra note 21, at 543; Henkin, supra note 25, at 36. 206 LOUIS HENKIN, INTERNATIONAL LAW: POLITICS AND VALUES 18081 (1995); Bradley & Goldsmith, supra note 35, at 84041; Henkin, supra note 25, at 38; Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 99. 207 E.g., Filartiga v. Pena-Irala, 630 F.2d 876 (1980); The Paquete Habana, 175 U.S. 677 (1900); see also M. O. Chibundu, Making Customary International Law Through Municipal Adjudication: A Structural Inquiry, 39 VA. J. INTL L. 1069 (1999). 208 Chodosh, supra note 17, at 121; Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 90100; Watson, supra note 143, at 60912; Arthur A. Weisburd, The Effect of Treaties and Other Formal International Acts on the Customary Law of Human Rights, 25 GA. J. INTL & COMP. L. 99, 129 (1995/96); Weisburd, Customary IL, supra note 31, at 41. 209 Schachter, supra note 48, at 10. 210 MERON, supra note 2, at 61. 211 S.S. Lotus (Fr. v. Turk.), 1927 PCIJ (ser. A) No. 10, at 28 (Sept. 7). The Court affirmed this principle in North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3, 44 (Feb. 20); see also Simma & Alston, supra note 18, at 99100, 104. 212 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 62, 63; Akehurst, supra note 7, at 4347. 213 Akehurst, supra note 7, at 37; MacGibbon, Acquiescence I, supra note 115, at 14546; MacGibbon, Acquiescence II, supra note 115, at 138. 214 Barcelona Traction, Light & Power Co. (Belg. v. Spain), Second Phase, 1970 ICJ REP. 3, 31 (Feb. 5).
205 204

778

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

are not legal rules.215 However, horizontal enforcement of intrastate obligations is unlikely to work in practice because the right of enforcement (which belongs to states) is divorced from the interest being protected (which belongs to individuals).216 Silence in the absence of an obligation to speak should not necessarily imply consent.217 Many plausible explanations can be made for a failure to protest intrastate breaches other than belief in the legality of the action, including lack of knowledge, political and economic self-interest, and realization of the futility of action.218 The lack of protest over intrastate breaches should not necessarily imply acquiescence in the legality of those breaches. Therefore, a lack of protest may also give rise to multiple interpretations. In summary, an interpretation is only eligible if it passes the dimension of fit, which examines whether the interpretation accurately describes the raw data of practice. Although traditional customs are likely to form eligible interpretations because of their focus on state practice, modern custom can also pass the threshold of fit if state practice includes intrastate action and inaction and we recognize that conflicting practice can give rise to multiple eligible interpretations. Identifying the dimension of substance. The dimension of substance requires a moral and political theory of international law, which is problematic because moral and political ideals vary among states.219 Kirgis refers to strong moral issues but does not provide a theory for determining morality in international law. Tasioulas limits his discussion of substantive aims to the coexistence and cooperation of states, which does not account for many modern aims of international law such as human rights. I contend that the dimension of substance should include both procedural and substantive normative considerations about whether the content of custom is substantively moral and whether it is derived by a legitimate process. By moral, I am again referring to commonly held subjective values about right and wrong that have been adopted by a representative majority of states in treaties and declarations. This concept includes substantive aims, such as the protection of human rights and the environment, as well as higher-order convictions about how these substantive aims should be prioritized when they compete.220 For example, how should conflicts between human rights and state sovereignty be resolved in humanitarian intervention? Statements of opinio juris will often be relevant at the level of substance because they are normative statements about what the law is or should be.221 Allowing the dimension of substance to include procedural and substantive normative considerations helps to justify the importance of this dimension. Substantive normativity has been criticized for confusing law and politics,222 and obliterating the distinction between discovering and inventing the law.223 While this issue is beyond the scope of this article, it merits a brief comment. First, substantive considerations become relevant only if the threshold of fit has been passed and they are weighed against fit.224 Thus, considerations of lex ferenda need not be eliminated, because they are relevant to the development of the law and will not form a custom in the absence of adequate state practice at the level of fit. Second, the dimension of fit
WOLFKE, supra note 115, at 135; Weisburd, supra note 208, at 10709; see also Akehurst, supra note 7, at 39. Henkin, supra note 25, at 41. 217 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 19293; Kelly, supra note 1, at 522. 218 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 6870; Charney, supra note 21, at 53638. 219 Kevin T. Jackson, Global Rights and Regional Jurisprudence, 12 LAW & PHIL. 157, 15859 (1993). 220 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 256. 221 Christine Chinkin, The Challenge of Soft Law: Development and Change in International Law, 38 INTL & COMP. L.Q. 850, 861, 865 (1989); Fastenrath, supra note 49, at 323. 222 Holmes, supra note 52, at 45962; Martti Koskenniemi, The Police in the TempleOrder, Justice and the UN: A Dialectical View, 6 EUR. J. INTL L. 325 (1995). 223 Kelly, supra note 1, at 458; Kennedy, supra note 102, at 347. 224 DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 24647, 25557.
216 215

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

779

is also interpretive and political, rather than mechanical.225 The collection and interpretation of data is theory dependent and biased by assumptions.226 Fit also represents a form of ideological nostalgia227 because it demonstrates a conservative political preference for the past and the status quo.228 Third, the substantive moral principles relied upon result from statements of opinio juris, rather than abstract moral considerations, so they have been given sufficient expression in legal form.229 They have also been formulated by a majority of states rather than judges,230 which provides procedural normativity and helps to prevent criticism of Western ideological bias.231 Finally, self-consciously value-based adjudication can also increase determinacy and accountability by making the reasons for a decision explicit.232 Balancing Fit and Substance: A Reflective Methodology Applying Dworkins interpretive theory to custom is useful because it incorporates description (fit) and normativity (substance) into a single approach. If there are multiple eligible interpretations, the best interpretation is the one that most coherently explains the dimensions of fit and substance.233 Coherence, which Dworkin calls integrity, is an important value in international law.234 Interpretations should aim for coherence by mediating between fit and substance in the same way as Rawls mediates between intuitions and moral principles in ethical theories.235 Instead of prioritizing one value above the other, Rawls advocates revising our interpretation of practice and principles, back and forth, until we have done everything possible to render our interpretation coherent and justified from both ends.236 Rawls calls this a reflective equilibrium.237 To illustrate this process in moral theory, consider the moral principle that killing another person is wrong. This principle generally coincides with our intuitive judgments, but there are exceptions. For example, we may intuitively feel that someone who kills in self-defense is not guilty of murder. Instead of arbitrarily rejecting this intuition or creating an unprincipled exception to the general rule, a reflective equilibrium seeks to provide the most coherent explanation of both positions. Killing in self-defense is not as morally culpable as murder because it lacks a mental fault element. Accordingly, we could amend our general principle to provide that killing another person is wrong if it is intentional. However, what if the killing was unintentional but reckless? We could amend our intuition to provide that killing in self-defense may be morally justifiable when it is a proportionate response to a perceived threat. If it is a disproportionate response, then the killing is not morally justified,
Id. at 257. Stanley Fish, Working on the Chain Gang: Interpretation in Law and Literature, 60 TEX. L. REV. 551, 559 (1982); Stanley Fish, Wrong Again, 62 TEX. L. REV. 299, 306 (1983). 227 Richard A. Falk, Presentation [on the extent of ideological neutrality of international law and international lawyers], in CHANGE AND STABILITY, supra note 3, at 137, 137. 228 BEDJAOUI, supra note 121, at 13637. 229 South West Africa (Eth. v. S. Afr.; Liber. v. S. Afr.), Second Phase, 1966 ICJ REP. 6, 34 ( July 18); cf. Christian Tomuschat, Obligations Arising for States Without or Against Their Will, 241 RECUEIL DES COURS 195, 303 (1993 IV). 230 Kennedy, supra note 102, at 407. 231 BEDJAOUI, supra note 121, at 141. While developing states hold the majority of power, these norms may still be criticized for allowing the majority to bind the minority. 232 KARL N. LLEWELLYN, THE COMMON LAW TRADITION: DECIDING APPEALS 3545 (1960). 233 See also coherentism in epistemology. NICHOLAS EVERITT & ALEC FISHER, MODERN EPISTEMOLOGY 10207 (1995). 234 THOMAS M. FRANCK, FAIRNESS IN INTERNATIONAL LAW AND INSTITUTIONS 38 (1995); THOMAS M. FRANCK, THE POWER OF LEGITIMACY AMONG NATIONS 150 (1990); Franck, supra note 56, at 73536. 235 RAWLS, supra note 46, at 20; John Rawls, Outline of a Decision Procedure for Ethics, 60 PHIL. REV. 177 (1951); see also DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 66 n.17. I am not arguing that the international system is akin to Rawlss concept of the original position; rather, that his notion of a reflective equilibrium can be used more generally to reconcile inductive and deductive methodologies. 236 RAWLS, supra note 46, at 21. 237 Id. at 1920.
226 225

780

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

though it may be less morally culpable than murder. This circumstance may provide a partial defense to murder, such as provocation, which would reduce a conviction from murder to manslaughter. Thus, killing another person is wrong if it is intentional or reckless, subject to a complete defense of self-defense or a partial defense of provocation. This process of revising both our intuitions and our moral principles and testing them against each other continues until the two correspond in a reflective equilibrium. Rawls does not detail a method for determining which end of the spectrum should be revised to achieve equilibrium.238 Instead of striking an unprincipled compromise, one could draw an analogy with scientific method, which also seeks to reconcile observations with abstract justifications.239 Scientists develop hypotheses inductively based on observed phenomena and then test these hypotheses deductively against interpretations of experimental results in a two-way harmonizing process, modifying the theory or practical conditions until the theory coherently explains observed reality. This process involves mediating between radical empiricism (which emphasizes the raw facts of experience as primary) and rationalism (which gives preference to the importance of scientific theory in interpreting facts).240 If a general principle conflicts with particular experimental results, then either the general rule should be modified to explain those results or the practical conditions for the experiment should be revised to ensure that accurate results are obtained. In accordance with this method, a widely supported principle might be modified if there are isolated counterexamples, whereas a weakly supported theory should be rejected if the contrary data are overwhelming. However, conflicting data should never be discounted as irrelevant because what is currently understood as a breach of, or an exception to, an existing theory may later form the basis of a new theory. To illustrate this scientific approach, consider the competing explanations of planetary motion. The Aristotelian geocentric view of the universe (that the sun and planets revolve around the earth) was discarded in the face of overwhelming contrary observations. This theory was replaced by the Copernican heliocentric theory of planetary motion (that the planets revolve around the sun). However, the Copernican theory also fails to explain many practical observations about the movement of the planets. Instead of modifying the general theory, these exceptions have been rationalized by examining the many disturbances that obscure the pure case, such as tidal friction, atmospheric refraction, and instrument error. Thus, a weakly supported theory was discarded in the face of considerable conflicting data, whereas a widely supported theory has been upheld despite some contrary data, because those data could be better explained in other ways. Nevertheless, the conflicting information is still relevant for future interpretations because it may in time support a new theory. For example, Galileos theory of the circular planetary orbits was useful to explain the general movement of the planets but could not explain some observed irregularities in their orbits. Instead of discarding these irregularities as irrelevant, they were later explained by embracing Keplers model of elliptical orbits. Thus, the best explanation of practice and principles will vary in light of new state practice, opinio juris, and moral considerations. While custom and moral theories involve very different considerations, a Rawlsian reflective approach can be used more generally to reconcile the inductive and deductive methodologies that are common to both.241 The dimension of fit and the theory of moral intuitionism are both inductive because they seek to infer a general rule from particular instances of practice. The dimension of substance is similar to moral principles because both deduce norms about practice from abstract statements of principles. Instead of prioritizing
238 G. R. Grice, Moral Theories and Received Opinion, 52 ARISTOTELIAN SOCY PROC. 1 (Supp. 1978); R. M. Hare, A Critical Study of John Rawls A Theory of Justice, 23 PHIL. Q. 144, 14455 (1973). 239 ROBIN ATTFIELD, ENVIRONMENTAL PHILOSOPHY AND PROSPECTS 92 (1994); RAWLS, supra note 46, at 20. 240 Paul K. Feyerabend, History of Philosophy of Science, in OXFORD COMPANION, supra note 57, at 806, 80607. 241 RAWLS, supra note 46, at 20 n.7; see also NELSON GOODMAN, FACT, FICTION, AND FORECAST 6568 (4th ed. 1983).

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

781

one value above the other, we should revise our interpretation of practice and principles until the two approaches are coherent and justified from both ends in a reflective equilibrium. While Dworkin argues that the best interpretation is objectively determinable,242 I believe that subjectivity is inherent in interpreting raw data. However, the reflective process provides some guidelines for reconciling practice and principles rather than allowing one element to override the other. It also explains why the best interpretation of practice and principles will change over time in light of new data or theories. Practical Application of the Reflective Interpretive Concept A reflective equilibrium requires revising our interpretations of practice (fit) and principles (substance) to find the most coherent explanation of both dimensions in the case of multiple eligible interpretations. This section explores how the reflective interpretive approach applies to two practical problems in custom, first, by applying it to the spectrum of facilitative and modern customs, and second, by using it to explain the fluid nature of custom. This analysis demonstrates that the reflective interpretive approach is dynamic, varying over time and according to the nature of the custom involved. The spectrum of facilitative and moral customs. The best balance between fit and substance will depend on the relative strength of the practice and principles in the custom involved. This is because the best interpretation of a custom usually leans toward the stronger element (practice or principles) as providing the greatest consistency with both elements. Traditional facilitative customs will result in a more descriptive equilibrium because they do not involve strong issues of principle. By contrast, modern customs with a strong moral content require a more normative equilibrium because they involve important issues of principle. Other customs, such as environmental protection, may involve strong normative and descriptive considerations, requiring a more even balance of fit and substance. Thus, traditional and modern customs exist on a facilitative-moral spectrum, which explains the asymmetrical application of fit and substance to them. To illustrate this spectrum, let us consider torture. State practice is ambiguous because some states torture their citizens with minimal protest by other states, while other states do not engage in torture. Further, most states have accepted declarations against torture (opinio juris). This situation produces at least two eligible interpretations. First, torture is permitted, which explains instances of torture and the frequent lack of protests (acquiescence). Other states refrain from torturing citizens out of choice rather than obligation, while the statements of opinio juris represent lex ferenda because they do not accord with practice. Second, torture is prohibited because many states refrain from torturing people out of a sense of obligation and most states have formally accepted that torture is illegal. Instances of torture breach the rule and may fail to provoke a response because of diplomatic, economic, and political constraints on other states. These two plausible interpretations demonstrate that state practice and opinio juris are not fixed considerations but are open to interpretation. As there is more than one eligible interpretation, the dimension of substance becomes relevant to determining the best interpretation. At this stage, lex ferenda statements about the immorality of torture carry important weight in representing what states believe the law should be. As a result, the most coherent explanation of fit and substance would probably be that torture is illegal. To illustrate the other end of the spectrum, consider a facilitative custom that all ships should pass on the left. A survey of practice may determine that ships usually pass on the left but often pass on the right as well. One would need to consider whether passing on the left or right corresponds to particular regions or states and whether either alternative results in protests by states. Further, this practice can only form a custom if there are statements that
242

DWORKIN, supra note 46, at 23940.

782

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

passing on the left or right is a legal obligation, not just a social practice (opinio juris). If ships usually pass on the left, this usage may provide the only eligible interpretation without any consideration of the dimension of substance. Alternatively, if the practice is more equivocal, it may produce several eligible interpretations. For example: all ships must pass on the left; all ships must pass on the right; all ships must pass on the left (general custom) except in particular regions where they pass on the right (a special custom); or all ships should pass on the left, but some states are persistent objectors and may pass on the right. As there are multiple eligible interpretations, one should consider their merits in light of the dimension of substance. While having a custom to determine how ships should pass makes an important contribution to coexistence and cooperation, it does not involve substantive moral issues. Thus, as the custom is facilitative, it will be determined primarily by which eligible interpretation best satisfies fit. In this case, the custom would be that all ships should pass on the left. The middle of the spectrum is occupied by laws that facilitate coexistence and involve moral considerations, such as an environmental duty to prevent transboundary harm. To determine eligible interpretations, we need to consider the following: actions (including actual examples of transboundary pollution); inaction (including instances of states refraining from, or attempting to limit, transboundary pollution); statements articulating the legality or illegality of transboundary harm (to determine whether it is a legal, rather than a merely social, issue); and examples of protests to or acquiescence in instances of transboundary harm by other states. These considerations give rise to at least two eligible interpretations. First, there is a customary norm prohibiting transboundary pollution, which explains why most states refrain from causing interstate pollution most of the time and why instances of pollution are often met with protests.243 Second, there is a permissive customary norm allowing transboundary pollution, which explains why pollutants regularly travel across international borders, provoking little or no reaction by other states.244 Statements of opinio juris (asserting that there should be a legal right to pollute or a legal obligation not to pollute) are mainly relevant at the dimension of substance because they represent what the practice should be, not necessarily what it has been. These statements generally support the view that states are, or should be, under a duty to prevent transboundary harm.245 For example, Principle 21 of the Stockholm Declaration provides that states have the responsibility to ensure that activities within their jurisdiction or control do not cause damage to the environment of other States or of areas beyond the limits of national jurisdiction.246 Thus, the best interpretation of practice and principles probably leans in favor of a prohibition on transboundary harm. However, as this outcome is more finely balanced than the previous examples, it is more likely to be contentious and open to change.247
243 PATRICIA W. BIRNIE & ALAN E. BOYLE, INTERNATIONAL LAW AND THE ENVIRONMENT 89 (1992); Pierre-Marie Dupuy, Overview of the Existing Customary Legal Regime Regarding International Pollution, in INTERNATIONAL LAW AND POLLUTION 61 (Daniel B. Magraw ed., 1991); Rdiger Wolfrum, Purposes and Principles of International Environmental Law, 1990 GER. Y.B. INTL L. 308, 309. 244 Bodansky, supra note 41, at 11013 (noting that transboundary pollution seems to be the rule rather than the exception and that customary environmental norms seem to be based on statements rather than regularities in behavior); Oscar Schachter, The Emergence of International Environmental Law, 44 J. INTL AFF. 457, 46263 (1991) (noting that there is only fragmentary evidence of state practice and opinio juris to support international environmental principles). 245 E.g., Convention on Long-Range Transboundary Air Pollution, Nov. 13, 1979, TIAS No. 10,541, 1302 UNTS 217; Co-operation in the Field of Environment Concerning Natural Resources Shared by Two or More States, GA Res. 3129, UN GAOR, 28th Sess., Supp. No. 30, at 48, UN Doc. A/9030 (1973); OECD Council Recommendation C(74)224, Nov. 14, 1974, tit. B(2), reprinted in ORGANISATION FOR ECONOMIC CO-OPERATION AND DEVELOPMENT, OECD AND THE ENVIRONMENT 142 (1986). See generally Bodansky, supra note 41, at 11012, 11415. 246 Stockholm Declaration on the Human Environment, Princ. 21, REPORT OF THE UNITED NATIONS CONFERENCE ON THE HUMAN ENVIRONMENT 3, UN Doc. A/CONF.48/14/Rev.1 (1972), reprinted in 11 ILM 1416 (1972). This principle was reiterated (in slightly modified form) in Rio Declaration on Environment and Development, UN Doc. A/CONF.151/5/Rev.1 (1992), reprinted in 31 ILM 874 (1992). 247 BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 28586.

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

783

These examples illustrate that the best balance between fit and substance varies according to the relative strength of the practice and principles involved. Strong substantive considerations may compensate for a relatively weak fit, while equivocal substantive considerations will require a finer balance between fit and substance. For example, the moral considerations involved in environmental pollution are strong but not as compelling as the moral imperative against torture. Consequently, a customary environmental norm will require greater conformity with state practice, and is more likely to be undermined by conflicting practice, than a customary prohibition on torture. As Schachter argues: [I]nternational rules are not all equal. Some are more important than others because they express deeply-held and widely shared convictions as to the unacceptability of the prohibited conduct. . . . Contrary and inconsistent practice would not and should not defeat their claims as customary law.248 The relative normativity of customs may help to explain the peremptory nature of jus cogens norms. The Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties defines jus cogens norms as laws accepted and recognised by the international community of states as a whole . . . from which no derogation is permitted and which can be modified only by a subsequent norm of general international law having the same character.249 Examples of jus cogens norms include the prohibitions on the use of force250 and genocide.251 Scholars disagree over whether peremptory norms are part of customary international law. Lauri Hannikainen and Ian Brownlie argue that custom is a suitable source for peremptory norms because it serves as a vehicle for generally binding international law on important moral issues.252 By contrast, Weil takes issue with the concept of jus cogens rules, arguing that they are not truly customary because they can be asserted despite a lack of state practice and consent by states.253 It is unclear whether rules of jus cogens can be analyzed according to a reflective interpretive approach for the same reasons that it is unclear whether they are truly customary rules. On the one hand, these norms are supported by extremely strong substantive considerations, which are likely to outweigh contrary practice and deficiencies in fit. The substantive morality of jus cogens norms may also outweigh the procedural normativity of allowing states to become persistent objectors to them.254 In addition, jus cogens norms are supported by widespread state practice in the form of inaction. For example, most states do not engage in officially recognized torture most of the time. Breaches may be sensational and well reported, but that should not be allowed to eclipse a general pattern of less publicized observance.255 The significance of contrary state practice may also be discounted because offending states usually base their denials of having breached the law on the facts, rather than on claims of invalidity of the law itself.256 A states resort to factual or legal exceptions to justify a prima facie breach of a rule has the effect of confirming the general rule, rather than undermining it or creating an exception to it.257
Schachter, supra note 48, at 11 (citation omitted); see also Schachter, supra note 81, at 73334. Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 83, Art. 53. 250 CASSESE, supra note 83, at 147. 251 Malcolm N. Shaw, Genocide in International Law, in INTERNATIONAL LAW AT A TIME OF PERPLEXITY, supra note 81, at 797. 252 BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 51417; LAURI HANNIKAINEN, PEREMPTORY NORMS ( JUS COGENS) IN INTERNATIONAL LAW 22642 (1988). 253 Weil, supra note 94, at 427. 254 RESTATEMENT, supra note 6, 102 cmt. k ; THIRLWAY, supra note 83, at 110; Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 4; cf. CASSESE, supra note 83, at 179. 255 MERON, supra note 2, at 61. 256 E.g., Human Rights Commission, Report of the Special Rapporteur on Torture and Other Cruel, Inhuman and Degrading Treatment or Punishment, UN Doc. E/CN.4/1988/17, at 23 (1988); see also SCHACHTER, supra note 15, at 338; DAmato, Response, supra note 31, at 469. 257 Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 98, para. 186; see also ANTONIO CASSESE, VIOLENCE AND LAW IN THE MODERN AGE 3539 (S. J. K. Greenleaves trans., 1988); HENKIN, supra note 118, at 70; MERON, supra note 2, at 60 (citing Jonathan I. Charney, The Power of the Executive Branch of the United States Government to Violate Customary International Law, 80 AJIL 913, 916 (1986)); Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 21.
249 248

784

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

On the other hand, jus cogens norms do not seem to require any conformity of practice, which means they could exist even without any eligible interpretations of practice for support. Weil has thus criticized the theory of jus cogens for forcing states to accept the supernormativity of rules they were perhaps not even prepared to recognize as ordinary norms.258 Rules of jus cogens also do not admit of persistent objectors, which undermines the consensual basis of custom. For example, South Africa was not recognized as a persistent objector to the prohibition on apartheid.259 Finally, the concept of jus cogens seems to discount the importance of contrary practice, treaties, and declarations unless they also form a rule of jus cogens. This factor denies the possibility that conflicting practice could form a new custom, no matter how widespread the practice, and seems to assume an answer to the interpretive process before it is applied, rather than using the process to determine whether a custom exists. Thus, jus cogens norms are more static and less open to change than other types of custom. The Fluid Nature of Custom Customs can generally change and harden over time because custom is a fluid source of law. The content of custom is not fixed; it can develop and change in light of new circumstances. The formation and modification of custom is an uncertain process because international law lacks an authoritative guide as to the amount, duration, frequency, and repetition of state practice required to develop or change a custom.260 Using Harts terminology, custom would be a primitive source of law because it lacks clear rules of change. Instead, custom develops through a slow process of growth, whereby courses of conduct once thought optional become first habitual or usual, and then obligatory, and the converse process of decay, when deviations, once severely dealt with, are first tolerated and then pass unnoticed.261 One reason for the difficulty of identifying the formation and change of custom is the radical decentralization of the international system. States are both legislators and subjects of international law, which explains why DAmato argues that every breach of a customary law contains the seed for a new legality.262 In one sense, the action is a breach because the state is judged as a subject of international law; in another sense, the action is a seed for a new law because the state acts as a legislator of international law.263 However, whether a custom develops or changes depends not only on the actions of some states but also on the reactions of other states. This is because states are also both legislators and enforcers of international law. Thus, a breach will effectively repeal or modify an existing custom only if other states emulate the breach or acquiesce in its legality.264 The reflective interpretive approach is useful in explaining the fluid nature of custom. Just as customs can develop and change in light of new circumstances, so a reflective equilibrium is not stable because the best explanation of practice and principles must be reevaluated in light of new state practice, opinio juris, and moral considerations.265 The best balance between practice and principles must be regularly reassessed. Consequently, conflicting data should never be discounted as irrelevant because they may significantly affect future interpretations. What is now an exception to, or a breach of, an accepted rule may later become integral to the explanation of a new general rule. According to DAmato:
Weil, supra note 94, at 427. BYERS, supra note 6, at 183; Jimnez de Archaga, supra note 3, at 27. 260 BYERS, supra note 6, at 15662; DAMATO, supra note 6, at 5666. 261 HART, supra note 47, at 90. 262 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 9798. 263 Weisburd, Customary IL, supra note 31, at 3031. 264 North Sea Continental Shelf (FRG/Den.; FRG/Neth.), 1969 ICJ REP. 3, 44 (Feb. 20); id. at 23031 (Lachs, J., dissenting); Akehurst, supra note 7, at 37; Weisburd, supra note 208, at 107. 265 RAWLS, supra note 46, at 20.
259 258

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

785

When a state violates an existing rule of customary international law, it undoubtedly is guilty of an illegal act, but the illegal act itself becomes a disconfirmatory instance of the underlying rule. The next state will find it somewhat easier to disobey the rule, until eventually a new line of conduct will replace the original rule by a new rule.266 The number of disconfirmatory acts that are required before the breach of an old rule will constitute the basis for a new rule depends on the extent of previous practice and the importance of the moral principles involved. Moral customs, and in particular jus cogens norms, are unlikely to be undermined by contrary practice. Furthermore, well-established customs will demonstrate relative resistance to change because new state practice or opinio juris must be weighed against a wealth of previous contrary practice.267 However, a custom can change quickly in the face of very strong state practice or opinio juris, particularly if the rule was uncertain or still developing.268 Recent practice may also carry proportionately greater weight than past practice in determining the present or future state of custom. Customs can develop or change in light of the recognition of new moral considerations in international law. For example, the customary prohibition against genocide stemmed from the recognition of human rights as a substantive aim of international law after World War II. Likewise, currently nonbinding aspirations may harden into legally binding custom in the future. For example, DAmato and Sudhir Chopra have argued that whales may have an emerging right to life under customary international law.269 Thus, the content of custom can change in view of new practice and principles in international law. The fluidity of custom is demonstrated by the present debate over whether NATOs intervention in Kosovo has formed the basis for an emerging customary right to unilateral humanitarian intervention. In the Nicaragua case, the Court found a general customary prohibition on intervention in other states but held that [r]eliance by a State on a novel right or an unprecedented exception to the principle might, if shared in principle by other States, tend towards a modification of customary international law.270 Whether states have successfully created an exception to the general custom of nonintervention will depend in part on whether they justified their conduct by reference to a new right of intervention or a new exception to the principle of its prohibition.271 It will also depend on whether the action provokes protest by other states or is emulated or met with acquiescence. However, if a state prima facie breaches a custom but defends its conduct by appealing to exceptions or justification contained within the rule itself, then whether or not the States conduct is in fact justifiable on that basis, the significance of that attitude is to confirm rather than to weaken the rule.272 Most commentators have concluded that NATOs intervention in Kosovo was illegal under existing international law.273 For example, Charney finds it indisputable that NATOs intervention violated the United Nations Charter and international law.274 However, the precedential status of the intervention is more contentious. Simma argues that NATOs intervention should not become a precedent because of the exceptional factual circumstances in Kosovo, the insistence by participating states such as France and Germany that the intervention did not form a precedent, and the detrimental impact of allowing an isolated
DAMATO, supra note 6, at 97. BYERS, supra note 6, at 15759. 268 Bin Cheng, in INTERNATIONAL LAW, supra note 19, at 249. 269 Anthony A. DAmato & Sudhir K. Chopra, Whales: Their Emerging Right to Life, 85 AJIL 21 (1991). 270 Nicaragua, 1986 ICJ REP. at 109, para. 207. 271 Id. 272 Id. at 98, para. 186. 273 E.g., Charney, supra note 124, at 834; Louis Henkin, Kosovo and the Law of Humanitarian Intervention, 93 AJIL 824, 82425 (1999). 274 Charney, supra note 124, at 834.
267 266

786

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

breach of collective security to become a general rule for unilateral action.275 By contrast, Antonio Cassese argues that NATOs action may support an emerging custom allowing the use of forcible countermeasures to impede a state from committing large-scale atrocities within its own territory, in circumstances where the Security Council is incapable of responding to the crisis.276 I submit that these conflicting arguments can be understood by employing a reflective interpretive approach. To determine eligible interpretations of fit, one must primarily consider the state practice respecting unilateral humanitarian intervention. Opponents of the norm focus on the lack of explicit authorization of NATOs action by the Security Council and the likelihood that China or Russia would have vetoed any resolution supporting intervention. The intervention also provoked significant protests by China, India, Namibia, Belarus, and the Russian Federation,277 which undermines its ability to form a custom. Prominent members of NATO, including France and Germany, insisted that the intervention did not constitute a precedent for a general right to unilateral humanitarian intervention.278 In pleadings for the case brought by the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia against ten NATO members in 1999, only Belgium expressly mentioned humanitarian intervention as a possible legal justification for action.279 Thus, the intervening states did not attempt to justify their intervention on the basis of a new exception to the general prohibition on intervention.280 States have also repeatedly abstained from invoking the right of humanitarian intervention where there were grounds for doing so, including Indias intervention in East Pakistan in 1971, Vietnams invasion of Kampuchea in 1978, and Tanzanias intervention in Uganda in 1979.281 These states justified their interventions on other grounds, such as self-defense, which suggests that they did not believe that unilateral humanitarian intervention was accepted in international law.282 However, states will generally resort to factual or legal exceptions rather than openly admit they have breached a law, even if they wish to change it.283 The absence of intervention in potentially analogous situations involving, for example, the Kurds in Turkey, the Chechens in Russia, and the Tibetans in China may also suggest that states did not believe that unilateral humanitarian intervention was permitted under international law. By contrast, proponents of an emerging norm argue that NATO had authority to act because the Security Council had defined the situation in Kosovo as a threat to peace and security in the region.284 The lack of condemnation of NATOs intervention by the Security Council and most other states also indicates a general acquiescence in its legality. For example, a draft resolution condemning NATOs use of force was rejected by a vote of 12 to
275 Bruno Simma, NATO, the UN and the Use of Force: Legal Aspects, 10 EUR. J. INTL L. 1 (1999), at <http:// www.ejil.org/journal/index.html> (visited Oct. 1, 2001). 276 Cassese, supra note 124. 277 The draft resolution condemning NATOs use of force, UN Doc. S/1999/328, was sponsored by Belarus, India, and the Russian Federation and supported by China, Namibia, and the Russian Federation in the Security Council. 278 For example, German Foreign Minister Kinkel stated, The decision of NATO [on air strikes against the Federal Republic of Yugoslavia] must not become a precedent. Deutscher Bundestag, Plenarprotokoll 13/248, at 23,129 (Oct. 16, 1998), quoted in Simma, supra note 275. 279 Some states focused exclusively on the preliminary issue of jurisdiction; others, including Germany, argued that the intervention represented a justifiable exception to the normal rules. The United States focused on the humanitarian catastrophe, the acute threat to security of neighboring states, the serious violation of humanitarian law, and the resolutions of the Security Council but did not expressly argue for a right to unilateral humanitarian intervention. Oral pleadings (Yugo. v. U.S. et al.), 1999 ICJ Pleadings (Legality of Use of Force), at <http://www.icj-cij.org>. 280 Charney, supra note 124, at 83637. 281 C. Gray, After the Ceasefire: Iraq, the Security Council and the Use of Force, 1994 BRIT. Y.B. INTL L. 135, 162; Dino Kritsiotis, Reappraising Policy Objections to Humanitarian Intervention, 19 MICH. J. INTL L. 1005, 1014 (1998). 282 Charney, supra note 124, at 83639. 283 CASSESE, supra note 257, at 3539; MERON, supra note 2, at 60 (citing Charney, supra note 257); HENKIN, supra note 118, at 70; Charlesworth, supra note 38, at 21. 284 SC Res. 1203 (Oct. 24, 1998); see also SC Res. 1199 (Sept. 23, 1998); SC Res. 1160 (Mar. 31, 1998).

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

787

3 in the Security Council,285 and no state requested an immediate meeting of the General Assembly to condemn the intervention. Precedents can also be found for humanitarian intervention without explicit authorization by the Security Council, such as the action by the United States, France, and Great Britain in Iraq in 1991. Moreover, the interventions in Iraq and Kosovo provide more modern, and thus potentially more weighty, precedents than the counterexamples from the 1970s. Contrary examples of states seeking Security Council approval before intervening in other situations could represent a politically prudent course of action, rather than a necessary element of legality. Further, the failure of states to intervene in previous humanitarian crises represents discretionary nonaction, rather than obligatory negative practice or acquiescence, because a custom allowing intervention is a permissive right rather than an obligatory duty.286 The range of eligible interpretations brings the dimension of substance into play to help determine the best interpretation in light of the substantive aims of international law. Unilateral humanitarian intervention involves the conflicting substantive considerations of state sovereignty (which would support a duty of nonintervention) and humanitarian aims (which would support a right to intervention). Prohibitions on intervention and the use of force appear to be peremptory norms of international law.287 Some humanitarian considerations, such as the prohibition on genocide, have also achieved jus cogens status.288 The dimension of substance must include consideration of how the substantive aims of international law should be prioritized when they conflict. While state sovereignty has traditionally been accorded primary importance in international law, arguably the international community is increasingly recognizing exceptions to this principle in extreme humanitarian crises.289 Thus, which principle will prevail when the two conflict depends on the extremity of the humanitarian crisis in question. The dimension of substance also requires consideration of the procedural normativity of unilateral intervention. Critics of unilateral intervention argue that it is open to abuse and likely to result in selective and self-interested action.290 Proponents argue that selective application is inherent in the concept of rights rather than duties, that selective intervention may be better than no intervention, and that it is unrealistic to expect states to intervene only when they are completely disinterested.291 Some of the objections may also be met by clearly identifying the conditions for intervention so as to provide safeguards against abuse, rather than creating a blanket prohibition on intervention. Further, the alternatives to unilateral intervention, which are no intervention and collective intervention,292 should be taken into account. Collective intervention, approved by the Security Council, is arguably less partisan and less open to abuse than unilateral intervention. However, the legitimacy of the Security Council itself is questionable because it comprises only fifteen states and the five permanent members all have the power of veto. Thus, collective action may not enjoy the advantages of procedural normativity. Collective action may also not be possible even in the face of extreme violations of human rights such as genocide. In such cases, unilateral intervention may be justified on the basis that the importance of the substantive moral issues involved outweighs deficiencies in procedural normativity.293
See supra note 277. This distinction is made by DAMATO, supra note 6, at 6163, though not with respect to unilateral humanitarian intervention. 287 BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 515; CASSESE, supra note 83, at 147. 288 BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 515; Shaw, supra note 251. 289 Kritsiotis, supra note 281, at 104046. 290 Christine M. Chinkin, Kosovo: A Good or Bad War? 93 AJIL 841, 847 (1999). 291 Kritsiotis, supra note 281, at 102039. 292 Henkin, supra note 273, at 82425. 293 Ruth Wedgwood, NATOs Campaign in Yugoslavia, 93 AJIL 828, 833 (1999).
286 285

788

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

In applying the reflective equilibrium, we need to consider which explanation most coherently explains the competing conceptions of practice and principles outlined above. There are two eligible interpretations of custom, one prohibiting unilateral humanitarian intervention and one permitting it. Since the first interpretation more adequately explains the raw data of practice to date, the second interpretation would only be preferred if supported by a strong dimension of substance. Substantively, the principles of state sovereignty and nonintervention generally prevail, except in cases of extreme human rights violations such as genocide. From a procedural perspective, collective intervention is usually preferable to unilateral intervention, though the latter may be justified if the Security Council is paralyzed by the veto power. Thus, the dimension of substance provides equivocal support for both interpretations, which varies according to the circumstances of the case. The present state of practice and principles probably leads to the conclusion that unilateral humanitarian intervention is not currently recognized as an exception to the principle of nonintervention. However, a narrow right to unilateral humanitarian intervention may be emerging in exceptional circumstances where there are gross violations of human rights, peaceful avenues for settling the dispute have been exhausted, the veto power has rendered the Security Council incapable of taking coercive action, the action is undertaken by a group of states with the support (or at least the nonopposition) of the majority of states, and the armed force is used exclusively to stop the atrocities.294 Whether this emerging norm is transformed into a binding custom will depend on future developments in the practice and principles of international law. Thus, the reflective interpretive approach can be used to demonstrate the fluid nature of custom as a source of law. V. THE ADVANTAGES OF A REFLECTIVE INTERPRETIVE APPROACH The contemporary interest in custom as a source of international law poses a challenge to articulate a coherent theory of custom. This is a difficult exercise because the traditional and modern approaches to custom appear to be opposed, with traditional custom emphasizing state practice and modern custom emphasizing opinio juris. The divergence between the descriptive and normative approaches of traditional and modern custom causes problems because the tests and justifications for traditional custom do not apply to modern custom and vice versa. Instead of advocating the rival merits and legitimacy of either approach, this article has sought to build an enriched theoretical account of custom that analyzes the competing justifications for traditional and modern custom and accommodates both approaches in a consistent interpretive theory. This reconciliation provides a methodology for assessing asserted customs. After gathering evidence of state practice and opinio juris, one must apply the threshold criterion of fit to determine if there are any eligible interpretations that adequately explain the raw data of practice. Fit provides continuity and descriptive accuracy, so that state practice will assume primary importance at this stage. However, state practice is open to interpretation and should include intrastate action and inaction, not just interstate interaction and acquiescence. Some articulation of legality is needed to differentiate between legal custom and social practice. If there is no eligible interpretation, then there is no custom. If there is one eligible interpretation, then the custom is clear. If there are multiple eligible interpretations, then one must weigh the dimensions of fit and substance to determine the best interpretation. Strong statements of opinio juris become relevant at this third stage because they represent normative considerations about what the law should be. The best interpretation is the one that most coherently explains fit and substance, which varies according to the facilitative or
294

Cassese, supra note 124; Charney, supra note 124, at 83639; Wedgwood, supra note 293, at 828.

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

789

moral content of the custom involved. Primarily facilitative customs do not involve strong substantive considerations and thus will be determined principally by fit. Primarily moral customs give rise to strong procedural and substantive normative considerations, which must be balanced against deficiencies in fit. Custom is also a fluid source of law, which causes the point of equilibrium to vary over time in light of new state practice, opinio juris, and moral considerations. Consequently, the reflective interpretive approach results in a more sophisticated understanding of fit and substance and constitutes a more nuanced method for reconciling them than the sliding scale in various ways. First, the reflective interpretive approach recognizes that the role of the dimension of fit is to provide descriptive accuracy. Questions of fit and descriptive accuracy are both backward looking because they focus on whether a custom is supported by past practice. Tasioulas claims that strong statements of opinio juris can form the basis of eligible interpretations at the dimension of fit. Similarly, Michael Akehurst has argued that state practice should include paper practice in the form of statements, declarations, and resolutions.295 I have demonstrated that this approach is not feasible because statements often fuse lex lata and lex ferenda and thus lack descriptive accuracy. However, one can still form eligible interpretations of traditional and modern custom by considering the open-textured nature of practice. State practice should also include consideration of intrastate action (not just interstate interaction), obligations being observed (not just obligations being breached), and reasons for a lack of protest over breaches (other than acquiescence in the legality of those breaches). These forms of practice reflect the changing subject matter of international law to include intrastate issues and are descriptively accurate because they focus on action and inaction. Second, I have outlined a dimension of substance that embodies both substantive and procedural normativity. Kirgis refers to strong moral issues but does not provide a theory for determining them. Tasioulas deliberately limits his discussion of the substantive aims of international law to coexistence and cooperation. By contrast, my approach provides a more expansive understanding of the substantive aims of international law, which includes recognized moral aims (such as the protection of human rights) that do not necessarily affect coexistence and cooperation. Substantive aims are frequently criticized as being subjective value judgments that serve as a vehicle for normative chauvinism. For this reason, I have defined moral issues as commonly held subjective values about right and wrong that have been adopted by a representative majority of states in treaties and declarations. This approach has several advantages. Focusing on commonly held, or intersubjective, values avoids the need to consider whether moral values can be objectively determined and it explains why these values can change over time. It also denotes an agreed set of values rather than requiring interpreters to determine what they believe the substantive aims of international law should be. It builds the concept of procedural normativity into the dimension of substance because these values have been accepted by a majority of states, which helps prevent accusations of Western ideological bias. Finally, while these statements may include lex lata and lex ferenda, the dimension of fit already provides a threshold test to determine if a custom is adequately supported by practice. Third, I have suggested a more nuanced approach to balancing fit and substance than the crude sliding scale. Finding traditional custom on the strength of state practice and fit alone allows it to become an apology for state power.296 Similarly, deducing modern custom purely from opinio juris and substance can create utopian laws that cannot regulate reality. Thus, the sliding scale can allow one element completely to outweigh the other. While a reflective equilibrium will lean toward the stronger value, it avoids extremes of apology and utopia.
295 296

Akehurst, supra note 7, at 53. KOSKENNIEMI, supra note 45, at 2.

790

THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF INTERNATIONAL LAW

[Vol. 95:757

The strength of fit and state practice in traditional customs must still be balanced against their substantive deficiencies, such as a lack of procedural normativity. Similarly, modern customs must be supported by state practice because they must pass the threshold of fit and deficiencies in their fit may still outweigh their moral content.297 A lower standard of practice may be tolerated for customs with a strong moral content because violations of ideal standards are expected.298 However, while occasional breaches may not nullify their legal character, massive, grave, and persistent violations will.299 The only exceptions are jus cogens norms, which by definition cannot be undermined by contrary practice unless that practice creates another rule of jus cogens.300 Fourth, Kirgis and Tasioulas argue that the more morally distasteful an activity, the more readily the Court will substitute opinio juris for state practice and vice versa. However, I have explained that substantive considerations apply asymmetrically to traditional and modern customs because of their facilitative and moral content. This reasoning results in a better explanation of when, and on what basis, traditional and modern customs will be formed. It also means that, to the extent that the reflective equilibrium can still be criticized for apology and utopia, these criticisms are less compelling because they apply to facilitative and moral customs, respectively. Criticizing a facilitative custom for being an exercise of power is not problematic because it does not concern substantive moral issues. Instead, these customs are akin to domestic traffic rules. If developing states wish to challenge a traditional custom, they can enact declarations in international fora, as they did on whether there should be an international minimum standard of compensation for expropriation301 or a national treatment standard.302 Similarly, modern customs that set up ideal standards about moral issues are expected to be somewhat utopian. Meron argues that the international community is willing to accept gradual or partial compliance as fulfilling the requirements for forming moral customs.303 Alasdair MacIntyre argues that the charge of utopianism is made by the deliberately shortsighted who congratulate themselves upon the limits of their vision.304 While hard law that is always enforced may be preferable to soft law, the choice in areas such as human rights is often between soft law and no law.305 Giving these aspirations some legal force may be preferable to giving them no legal status, because they can be enforced in extreme situations such as apartheid in South Africa306 and their legal status may harden over time.307 Finally, the reflective equilibrium can be used to explain the fluid nature of customary international law. The sliding scale assumes that state practice and opinio juris are fixed and irreconcilable quantities that must be traded off against each other to form eligible interpretations of custom. However, I have demonstrated that state practice is open textured and capable of being interpreted in various ways. For example, contrary state practice can be analyzed as a breach of an old rule or as the seed of a new rule. Finding the best interMERON, supra note 2, at 4445. Id. at 44; Schachter, supra note 110, at 539; Schachter, supra note 81, at 735. 299 MERON, supra note 2, at 58. 300 Vienna Convention on the Law of Treaties, supra note 83, Art. 53. 301 Supported by Resolution on Permanent Sovereignty over Natural Resources, GA Res. 1803, UN GAOR, 17th Sess., Supp. No. 17, at 15, UN Doc. A/5217 (1962). See also BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 52729, 53538. 302 Supported by Charter of Economic Rights and Duties of States, GA Res. 3281, UN GAOR, 29th Sess., Supp. No. 30, at 50, UN Doc. A/9030 (1974). See also BROWNLIE, supra note 6, at 52627, 538. 303 MERON, supra note 2, at 44. 304 ALASDAIR MACINTYRE, THREE RIVAL VERSIONS OF MORAL ENQUIRY: ENCYCLOPAEDIA, GENEALOGY, AND TRADITION 234 (1990); see also Tasioulas, supra note 42, at 127. 305 Condorelli, supra note 66, at 81; Pellet, supra note 68, at 47. 306 DAMATO, supra note 6, at 89; Henkin, supra note 25, at 39, 42. 307 Chinkin, supra note 221, at 85758.
298 297

2001]

TRADITIONAL AND MODERN APPROACHES TO CUSTOMARY INTERNATIONAL LAW

791

pretation of practice and principles requires one to determine the most coherent explanation of state practice and opinio juris, rather than simply giving preference to one and discounting the other. For this reason, conflicting state practice should never be discounted as irrelevant to interpretation, because it may contain the seed for a new custom. It also clarifies how customs change over time in light of new state practice, opinio juris, and moral considerations. The reflective interpretive approach rearticulates the theoretical foundations of custom in a more principled and flexible fashion. Instead of debating the relative merits and legitimacy of traditional and modern custom, this interpretive theory seeks to justify and reconcile the two approaches and, in so doing, offers a coherent theory of custom that helps to defend its integrity as a source of international law.

You might also like