You are on page 1of 83

http://www.law.cornell.

edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DIST. v. DOE


TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [1], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is

1 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [2], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [3] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [4] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [5], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [6], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [7], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [8], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [9] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [10] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [11] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [12], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734
[13]

, 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts).

Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of

2 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [14], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes

3 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [15] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S.

4 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

226 [16], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [17] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [18] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [19] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [20] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[21]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

5 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [22], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [23], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance,

6 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [24] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As

7 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [25], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [26], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [27] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [28] (1971) .1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [29], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [30], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [31], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [32], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [33] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [34] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [35] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [36], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734
[37]

, 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts).

Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is

8 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [38], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for

9 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [39] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of

10 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [40], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [41] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [42] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [43] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [44] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[45]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

11 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [46], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [47], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance,

12 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [48] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As

13 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [49], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [50], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [51] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [52] (1971) .1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [53], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [54], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [55], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [56], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [57] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [58] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [59] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [60], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734
[61]

, 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts).

Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is

14 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [62], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for

15 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [63] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of

16 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [64], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [65] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [66] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [67] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [68] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[69]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

17 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [70], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [71], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance,

18 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [72] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As

19 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [73], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [74], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [75] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [76] (1971) .1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [77], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [78], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [79], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [80], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [81] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [82] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [83] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [84], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734
[85]

, 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts).

Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is

20 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [86], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for

21 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [87] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of

22 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [88], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [89] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [90] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [91] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [92] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[93]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

23 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [94], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [95], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance,

24 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [96] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As

25 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [97], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [98], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [99] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [100] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [101], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [102], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [103], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [104], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [105] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [106] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [107] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [108], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [109], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy

26 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [110], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to

27 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [111] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech

28 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [112], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [113] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [114] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [115] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [116] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[117]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

29 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [118], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v.

30 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [119], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [120] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897).

31 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [121], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [122], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [123] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [124] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [125], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [126], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [127], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [128], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [129] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [130] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [131] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [132], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [133], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts).

32 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also

33 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [134], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [135] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private

34 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [136], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [137] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [138] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [139] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [140] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[141]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time

35 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [142], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority

36 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [143], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [144] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors

37 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [145], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [146], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [147] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [148] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [149], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [150], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [151], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [152], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [153] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [154] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [155] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [156], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s

38 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [157], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o

39 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [158], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [159] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a

40 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [160], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [161] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [162] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [163] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [164] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[165]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the

41 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [166], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617).

42 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [167], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [168] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in

43 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [169], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [170], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [171] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [172] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [173], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [174], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [175], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [176], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon

44 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [177] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [178] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [179] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [180], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [181], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might

45 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [182], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment

46 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [183] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [184], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [185] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [186] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [187] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [188] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment

47 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

[189]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [190], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates

48 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [191], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [192] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting.

49 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [193], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [194], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [195] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [196] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [197], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [198], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [199], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [200],

50 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [201] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [202] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [203] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [204], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [205], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use

51 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [206], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy

52 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [207] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [208], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [209] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [210] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [211] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [212] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in

53 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[213]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [214], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this

54 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [215], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [216] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit
[June 19, 2000]

55 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [217], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [218], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [219] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [220] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [221], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [222], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [223], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch

56 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [224], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [225] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [226] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [227] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [228], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [229], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding

57 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [230], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See

58 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [231] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [232], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [233] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [234] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [235] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U.

59 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

S. 675 [236] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[237]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [238], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with

60 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [239], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [240] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth circuit

61 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [241], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [242], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [243] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [244] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [245], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [246], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal

62 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [247], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [248], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [249] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [250] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [251] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [252], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [253], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3 But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of

63 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [254], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order

64 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [255] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [256], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [257] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [258] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [259] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14.

65 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [260] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[261]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a

school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [262], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100. There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation.

66 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [263], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [264] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

TOP Dissent SANTA FE INDEPENDENT SCHOOL DISTRICT, PETITIONER v. JANE DOE, individually and as next friend for her minor children, JANE and JOHN DOE, et al.

on writ of certiorari to the united states court of appeals for the fth

67 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

circuit
[June 19, 2000]

Chief Justice Rehnquist , with whom Justice Scalia and Justice Thomas join, dissenting. The Court distorts existing precedent to conclude that the school districts student-message program is invalid on its face under the Establishment Clause. But even more disturbing than its holding is the tone of the Courts opinion; it bristles with hostility to all things religious in public life. Neither the holding nor the tone of the opinion is faithful to the meaning of the Establishment Clause, when it is recalled that George Washington himself, at the request of the very Congress which passed the Bill of Rights, proclaimed a day of public thanksgiving and prayer, to be observed by acknowledging with grateful hearts the many and signal favors of Almighty God. Presidential Proclamation, 1 Messages and Papers of the Presidents, 17891897, p. 64 (J. Richardson ed. 1897). We do not learn until late in the Courts opinion that respondents in this case challenged the districts student-message program at football games before it had been put into practice. As the Court explained in United States v. Salerno , 481 U. S. 739 [265], 745 (1987) , the fact that a policy might operate unconstitutionally under some conceivable set of circumstances is insufcient to render it wholly invalid. See also Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [266], 612 (1988) . While there is an exception to this principle in the First Amendment [267] overbreadth context because of our concern that people may refrain from speech out of fear of prosecution, Los Angeles Police Dept. v. United Reporting Publishing Corp. , 528 U. S. ___ (1999), ___ (slip op., at 57), there is no similar justication for Establishment Clause cases. No speech will be chilled by the existence of a government policy that might unconstitutionally endorse religion over nonreligion. Therefore, the question is not whether the districts policy may be applied in violation of the Establishment Clause, but whether it inevitably will be. The Court, venturing into the realm of prophesy, decides that it need not wait for the inevitable and invalidates the districts policy on its face. See ante , at 24. To do so, it applies the most rigid version of the oft-criticized test of Lemon v. Kurtzman , 403 U. S. 602 [268] (1971) . 1 Lemon has had a checkered career in the decisional law of this Court. See, e.g. , Lambs Chapel v. Center Moriches Union Free School Dist., 508 U. S. 384 [269], 398399 (1993) ( Scalia , J., concurring in judgment) (collecting opinions criticizing Lemon ); Wallace v. Jaffree,

68 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

472 U. S. 38 [270], 108114 (1985) ( Rehnquist , J., dissenting) (stating that Lemon s three-part test represents a determined effort to craft a workable rule from a historically faulty doctrine; but the rule can only be as sound as the doctrine it attempts to service (internal quotation marks omitted)); Committee for Public Ed. and Religious Liberty v. Regan, 444 U. S. 646 [271], 671 (1980) ( Stevens , J., dissenting) (deriding the sisyphean task of trying to patch together the blurred, indistinct, and variable barrier described in Lemon ). We have even gone so far as to state that it has never been binding on us. Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [272], 679 (1984) ([W]e have repeatedly emphasized our unwillingness to be conned to any single test or criterion in this sensitive area . In two cases, the Court did not even apply the Lemon test [citing Marsh v. Chambers, 463 U. S. 783 [273] (1983) , and Larson v. Valente, 456 U. S. 228 [274] (1982) ]). Indeed, in Lee v. Weisman, 505 U. S. 577 [275] (1992) , an opinion upon which the Court relies heavily today, we mentioned but did not feel compelled to apply the Lemon test. See also Agostini v. Felton, 521 U. S. 203 [276], 233 (1997) (stating that Lemon s entanglement test is merely an aspect of the inquiry into a statutes effect); Hunt v. McNair, 413 U. S. 734 [277], 741 (1973) (stating that the Lemon factors are no more than helpful signposts). Even if it were appropriate to apply the Lemon test here, the districts student-message policy should not be invalidated on its face. The Court applies Lemon and holds that the policy is invalid on its face because it establishes an improper majoritarian election on religion, and unquestionably has the purpose and creates the perception of encouraging the delivery of prayer at a series of important school events. Ante , at 26. The Courts reliance on each of these conclusions misses the mark. First, the Court misconstrues the nature of the majoritarian election permitted by the policy as being an election on prayer and religion. 2 See ante , at 22, 26. To the contrary, the election permitted by the policy is a two-fold process whereby students vote rst on whether to have a student speaker before football games at all, and second, if the students vote to have such a speaker, on who that speaker will be. App. 104105. It is conceivable that the election could become one in which student candidates campaign on platforms that focus on whether or not they will pray if elected. It is also conceivable that the election could lead to a Christian prayer before 90 percent of the football games. If, upon implementation, the policy operated in this fashion, we would have a record before us to review whether the policy, as applied, violated the Establishment Clause or unduly suppressed minority viewpoints. But it is possible that the students might vote not to have a pregame speaker, in which case there would be no threat of a constitutional violation. It is also possible that the election would not focus on prayer, but on public speaking ability or social popularity. And if student campaigning did begin to focus on prayer, the school might decide to implement reasonable campaign restrictions. 3

69 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

But the Court ignores these possibilities by holding that merely granting the student body the power to elect a speaker that may choose to pray, regardless of the students ultimate use of it, is not acceptable. Ante , at 25. The Court so holds despite that any speech that may occur as a result of the election process here would be private , not government , speech. The elected student, not the government, would choose what to say. Support for the Courts holding cannot be found in any of our cases. And it essentially invalidates all student elections. A newly elected student body president, or even a newly elected prom king or queen, could use opportunities for public speaking to say prayers. Under the Courts view, the mere grant of power to the students to vote for such ofces, in light of the fear that those elected might publicly pray, violates the Establishment Clause. Second, with respect to the policys purpose, the Court holds that the simple enactment of this policy, with the purpose and perception of school endorsement of student prayer, was a constitutional violation. Ante , at 24. But the policy itself has plausible secular purposes: [T]o solemnize the event, to promote good sportsmanship and student safety, and to establish the appropriate environment for the competition. App. 104105. Where a governmental body expresses a plausible secular purpose for an enactment, courts should generally defer to that stated intent. Wallace , supra , at 7475 ( OConnor , J., concurring in judgment); see also Mueller v. Allen, 463 U. S. 388 [278], 394395 (1983) (stressing this Courts reluctance to attribute unconstitutional motives to States, particularly when a plausible secular purpose for the States program may be discerned from the face of the statute). The Court grants no deference toand appears openly hostile towardthe policys stated purposes, and wastes no time in concluding that they are a sham. For example, the Court dismisses the secular purpose of solemnization by claiming that it invites and encourages religious messages. Ante , at 14; Cf. Lynch , 465 U. S, at 693 ( OConnor , J., concurring) (discussing the legitimate secular purposes of solemnizing public occasions). The Court so concludes based on its rather strange view that a religious message is the most obvious means of solemnizing an event. Ante , at 14. But it is easy to think of solemn messages that are not religious in nature, for example urging that a game be fought fairly. And sporting events often begin with a solemn rendition of our national anthem, with its concluding verse And this be our motto: In God is our trust. Under the Courts logic, a public school that sponsors the singing of the national anthem before football games violates the Establishment Clause. Although the Court apparently believes that solemnizing football games is an illegitimate purpose, the voters in the school district seem to disagree. Nothing in the Establishment Clause prevents them from making this choice. 4 The Court bases its conclusion that the true purpose of the policy is to endorse student prayer on its view of the school districts history of Establishment Clause violations and the context in which the policy was written, that is, as the latest step in developing litigation brought as a

70 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

challenge to institutional practices that unquestionably violated the Establishment Clause. Ante , at 16, 17, and 22. But the contextattempted compliance with a District Court order actually demonstrates that the school district was acting diligently to come within the governing constitutional law. The District Court ordered the school district to formulate a policy consistent with Fifth Circuit precedent, which permitted a school district to have a prayer-only policy. See Jones v. Clear Creek Independent School Dist. , 977 F. 2d 963 (CA5 1992). But the school district went further than required by the District Court order and eventually settled on a policy that gave the student speaker a choice to deliver either an invocation or a message. In so doing, the school district exhibited a willingness to comply with, and exceed, Establishment Clause restrictions. Thus, the policy cannot be viewed as having a sectarian purpose. 5 The Court also relies on our decision in Lee v. Weisman , 505 U. S. 577 [279] (1992) , to support its conclusion. In Lee , we concluded that the content of the speech at issue, a graduation prayer given by a rabbi, was directed and controlled by a school ofcial. Id ., at 588. In other words, at issue in Lee was government speech. Here, by contrast, the potential speech at issue, if the policy had been allowed to proceed, would be a message or invocation selected or created by a student. That is, if there were speech at issue here, it would be private speech. The crucial difference between government speech endorsing religion, which the Establishment Clause forbids, and private speech endorsing religion, which the Free Speech and Free Exercise Clauses protect, applies with particular force to the question of endorsement. Board of Ed. of Westside Community Schools (Dist. 66) v. Mergens, 496 U. S. 226 [280], 250 (1990) (plurality opinion) (emphasis in original). Had the policy been put into practice, the students may have chosen a speaker according to wholly secular criterialike good public speaking skills or social popularityand the student speaker may have chosen, on her own accord, to deliver a religious message. Such an application of the policy would likely pass constitutional muster. See Lee , supra , at 630, n. 8 ( Souter , J., concurring) (If the State had chosen its graduation day speakers according to wholly secular criteria, and if one of those speakers (not a state actor) had individually chosen to deliver a religious message, it would be harder to attribute an endorsement of religion to the State). Finally, the Court seems to demand that a government policy be completely neutral as to content or be considered one that endorses religion. See ante , at 14. This is undoubtedly a new requirement, as our Establishment Clause jurisprudence simply does not mandate content neutrality. That concept is found in our First Amendment [281] speech cases and is used as a guide for determining when we apply strict scrutiny. For example, we look to content neutrality in reviewing loudness restrictions imposed on speech in public forums, see Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781 [282] (1989) , and regulations against picketing, see Boos

71 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

v. Barry, 485 U. S. 312 [283] (1988) . The Court seems to think that the fact that the policy is not content neutral somehow controls the Establishment Clause inquiry. See ante , at 14. But even our speech jurisprudence would not require that all public school actions with respect to student speech be content neutral. See, e.g ., Bethel School Dist. No. 403 v. Fraser, 478 U. S. 675 [284] (1986) (allowing the imposition of sanctions against a student speaker who, in nominating a fellow student for elective ofce during an assembly, referred to his candidate in terms of an elaborate sexually explicit metaphor). Schools do not violate the First Amendment
[285]

every time they restrict student speech to certain categories. But under the Courts view, a school policy under which the student body president is to solemnize the graduation ceremony by giving a favorable introduction to the guest speaker would be facially unconstitutional. Solemnization invites and encourages prayer and the policys content limitations prohibit the student body president from giving a solemn, yet non-religious, message like commentary on United States foreign policy. See ante , at 14. The policy at issue here may be applied in an unconstitutional manner, but it will be time enough to invalidate it if that is found to be the case. I would reverse the judgment of the Court of Appeals.

Notes
1 The Court rightly points out that in facial challenges in the Establishment Clause context, we have looked to Lemons three factors to guid[e] [t]he general nature of our inquiry. Ante, at 2223 (internal quotation marks omitted) (citing Bowen v. Kendrick, 487 U. S. 589 [286], 602 (1988) ). In Bowen, we looked to Lemon as such a guide and determined that a federal grant program was not invalid on its face, noting that [i]t has not been the Courts practice, in considering facial challenges to statutes of this kind, to strike them down in anticipation that particular applications may result in unconstitutional use of funds. 487 U. S., at 612 (internal quotation marks omitted). But here the Court, rather than look to Lemon as a guide, applies Lemons factors stringently and ignores Bowens admonition that mere anticipation of unconstitutional applications does not warrant striking a policy on its face. 2 The Court attempts to support its misinterpretation of the nature of the election process by noting that the district stipulated to facts about the most recent election. See ante, at 25, n. 24. Of course, the most recent election was conducted under the previous policya policy that required an elected student speaker to give a pregame invocation. See App. 6566, 99100.

72 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

There has not been an election under the policy at issue here, which expressly allows the student speaker to give a message as opposed to an invocation. 3 The Courts reliance on language regarding the student referendum in Board of Regents of Univ. of Wis. System v. Southworth, 529 U. S. ___ (2000), to support its conclusion with respect to the election process is misplaced. That case primarily concerned free speech, and, more particularly, mandated nancial support of a public forum. But as stated above, if this case were in the as applied context and we were presented with the appropriate record, our language in Southworth could become more applicable. In fact, Southworth itself demonstrates the impropriety of making a decision with respect to the election process without a record of its operation. There we remanded in part for a determination of how the referendum functions. See id., at __ (slip op., at 1617). 4 The Court also determines that the use of the term invocation in the policy is an express endorsement of that type of message over all others. See ante, at 1415. A less cynical view of the policys text is that it permits many types of messages, including invocations. That a policy tolerates religion does not mean that it improperly endorses it. Indeed, as the majority reluctantly admits, the Free Exercise Clause mandates such tolerance. See ante, at 21 ([N]othing in the Constitution as interpreted by this Court prohibits any public school student from voluntarily praying at any time before, during, or after the schoolday); see also Lynch v. Donnelly, 465 U. S. 668 [287], 673 (1984) (Nor does the Constitution require complete separation of church and state; it afrmatively mandates accommodation, not merely tolerance, of all religions, and forbids hostility toward any). 5 Wallace v. Jaffree, 472 U. S. 38 [288] (1985) , is distinguishable on these grounds. There we struck down an Alabama statute that added an express reference to prayer to an existing statute providing a moment of silence for meditation. Id., at 59. Here the school district added a secular alternative to a policy that originally provided only for prayer. More importantly, in Wallace, there was unrebutted evidence that pointed to a wholly religious purpose, id., at 58, and Alabama conceded in the courts below that the purpose of the statute was to make prayer part of daily classroom activity, id., at 7778 (OConnor, J., concurring in judgment). There is no such evidence or concession here.

1. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 2. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 3. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti

73 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

4. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 5. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 6. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 7. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 8. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 9. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 10. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 11. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 12. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 13. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 14. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 15. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 16. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 17. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 18. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 19. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 20. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 21. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 22. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 23. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 24. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 25. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 26. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 27. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 28. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 29. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 30. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 31. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 32. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 33. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 34. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228

74 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

35. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 36. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 37. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 38. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 39. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 40. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 41. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 42. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 43. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 44. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 45. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 46. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 47. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 48. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 49. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 50. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 51. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 52. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 53. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 54. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 55. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 56. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 57. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 58. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 59. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 60. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 61. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 62. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 63. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 64. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 65. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti

75 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

66. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 67. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 68. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 69. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 70. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 71. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 72. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 73. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 74. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 75. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 76. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 77. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 78. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 79. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 80. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 81. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 82. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 83. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 84. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 85. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 86. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 87. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 88. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 89. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 90. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 91. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 92. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 93. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 94. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 95. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 96. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38

76 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

97. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 98. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 99. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 100. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 101. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 102. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 103. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 104. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 105. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 106. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 107. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 108. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 109. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 110. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 111. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 112. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 113. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 114. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 115. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 116. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 117. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 118. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 119. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 120. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 121. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 122. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 123. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 124. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 125. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 126. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 127. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646

77 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

128. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 129. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 130. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 131. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 132. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 133. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 134. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 135. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 136. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 137. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 138. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 139. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 140. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 141. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 142. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 143. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 144. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 145. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 146. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 147. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 148. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 149. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 150. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 151. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 152. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 153. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 154. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 155. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 156. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 157. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 158. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388

78 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

159. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 160. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 161. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 162. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 163. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 164. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 165. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 166. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 167. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 168. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 169. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 170. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 171. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 172. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 173. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 174. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 175. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 176. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 177. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 178. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 179. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 180. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 181. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 182. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 183. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 184. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 185. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 186. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 187. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 188. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 189. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti

79 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

190. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 191. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 192. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 193. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 194. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 195. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 196. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 197. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 198. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 199. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 200. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 201. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 202. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 203. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 204. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 205. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 206. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 207. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 208. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 209. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 210. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 211. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 212. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 213. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 214. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 215. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 216. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 217. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 218. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 219. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 220. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602

80 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

221. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 222. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 223. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 224. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 225. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 226. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 227. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 228. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 229. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 230. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 231. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 232. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 233. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 234. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 235. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 236. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 237. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 238. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 239. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 240. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 241. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 242. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 243. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 244. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 245. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 246. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 247. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 248. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 249. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 250. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 251. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577

81 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

252. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 253. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 254. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 255. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 256. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 257. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 258. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781 259. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 260. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 261. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 262. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 263. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 264. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 265. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/481/739 266. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 267. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 268. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/403/602 269. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/508/384 270. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38 271. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/444/646 272. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 273. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/783 274. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/456/228 275. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 276. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/521/203 277. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/413/734 278. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/463/388 279. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/505/577 280. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/496/226 281. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 282. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/491/781

82 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt/text/530/290

283. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/485/312 284. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/478/675 285. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supct-cgi/get-const?amendmenti 286. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/487/589 287. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/465/668 288. http://www.law.cornell.edu/supremecourt//text/472/38

83 of 83

3/2/14, 1:35 PM

You might also like