You are on page 1of 20

Logic and Sortal Incorrectness Author(s): Merrie Bergmann Source: The Review of Metaphysics, Vol. 31, No. 1 (Sep.

, 1977), pp. 61-79 Published by: Philosophy Education Society Inc. Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20127017 . Accessed: 01/03/2014 09:19
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Philosophy Education Society Inc. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Review of Metaphysics.

http://www.jstor.org

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

LOGICAND SORTAL INCORRECTNESS*


MERRIE BERGMANN

sortally incorrect statement


mistake), in which nomenon in natural in its simplest the subject of sortal

(non-significant statement,

category

as a statement be characterized form, may are mismatched. The and predicate phe arises both as follows. an extension Any and be assigned predicate a sortal

incorrectness may

language

range. The extension of a predicate is the collection of all those entities of which the predicate is true, while the sortal range con sists of all those entities to which the predicate is significantly ap of plicable. When the entity designated by the subject-expression an atomic statement (a predication) falls outside of the predicate's sortal range, the statement is sortally incorrect. The following
are typical examples of sortally incorrect statements.

(1) The theory of relativity

is blue (Drange);

and "Socrates is a prime number" (Pap); "Quadruplicity drinks pro crastination" (Russell); "This stone is thinking about Vienna"
(Carnap). (1), for instance, is sortally incorrect because the pred

icate "is blue" is not significantly applicable to abstract entities. The theory of relativity is not the sort of thing that could be blue. A wealth of literature has been devoted to the problem of de
veloping ments.1 correct semantic of sortally incorrect state analysis adequate0 is clear, motivation albeit in controversial: sortally an unusual statements to exhibit when behavior appear The other two statements senses in of negation incorrect logically complex are distinguishable statements. statements. when In this the an

with coupled For instance, operation

is applied

to sortally

paper,

of the 1976 Dissertation essay prize-winning Essay Education sponsored Competition Inc., by The Philosophy Society, of The Review publisher of Metaphysics. 1 recent are: J. N. Three with extensive articles, bibliographies, "A for Semantics Martin, Many-Valued Mistakes," Category Synthese, 31 (1975), pp. 63-83; R. Routley, "The Need for Nonsense," Australasian Journal 47 (1969), pp. 367-384; "A and R. H. Thomason, of Philosophy, Semantic Theory of Sortal Incorrectness," Journal of Philosophical Logic, 1 (1972), pp. 209-258.

This

is the

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

62 I shall sortally the of the "correct"

MERRIE BERGMANN
reopen incorrect question statements. semantic analysis of

I are in order. under the rubric few preliminary remarks First, a I intend to exclude related incorrect statements" closely "sortally statements which be of called may "type-errors." Type variety as being errors are statements if treated true or false, may which, A lead to semantic paradoxes. Examples include: "What I am now

saying is false"; "The term 'heterological' is heterological" (Grelling). Unlike type-errors, the statements which I call "sortally incorrect"
do ments choose from not may to type Second, lead to semantic state incorrect paradoxes. Sortally I be odd or deviant, but not paradoxical. For this reason as a phenomenon examine sortal distinct incorrectness incorrectness. I am treating sortally incorrect statements as seman

R. H. Thomason has shown that treating these tically deviant. statements as syntactically deviant leads to the following prob
lem.2 Let us suppose that sortally of incorrect statements are syn

tactically
have say been that

deviant?that
coupled statement (1)

is, the expressions


combines

within

the statements

in violation

rules. Then we may syntactic an "abstract" subject-expression

("the theory of relativity") with a "concrete" predicate ("is blue"), in violation of the implicit grammatical rule that "concrete" predi
cates can expressions. be meaningfully Now consider combined the only with "concrete" subject following statement:

(2)What

I am thinking of is blue.

If I am thinking of the sky, then the statement is sortally correct and true. But consider the occasion on which I utter (2) while On this occasion, (2) would thinking of the theory of relativity.
appear to be sortally incorrect. But then sortal incorrectness cannot

be a purely syntactical matter; the reference of the expression "what I am thinking of" is the crucial factor in evaluating the sortal status
2

in the The grammatical rule suggested below p. 212. Thomason, is an example of a linguist's "subcategorization" rule. See N. Chomsky, Mass.: M.I.T. of the Theory of Syntax 1965), Aspects Press, (Cambridge, pp. 148-160. text

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS of (2). In the interest of a unified approach,


as a semantic phenomenon.

63 I shall treat all sortal

incorrectness

II

classical The by now classic defense of bivalent logic?indeed, bivalent logic?as being fully equipped to handle sortally incorrect statements is given by Quine:
. . . there has been a concern among to declare mean philosophers as 'This stone is such rather than trivially false, predications ingless, drinks procrastina (Carnap) and 'Quadruplicity thinking about Vienna' tion' (Russell). Here we witness sometimes revul just a spontaneous a remote project of cutting sion against silly sentences and sometimes down to something like empirical size. But meaningful language since the philosophers who would build such categorial fences are not generally to banish from language all falsehoods resolved of mathe I fail to see much benefit matics and like absurdities, in the partial exclusions for the forms concerned would that they do undertake; remain still quite under control if admitted like self-contradic rather, if one likes). Tolerance of the tions, as false (and false by meaning, ... source of simplicity is a major in theory; and in the don't cares it counts double, instance present sparing us as it does both the and the of them.3 of settling categories respecting The suggestion seems simple enough: the once the deviant statements

have been admitted


simply assign

into the language (as syntactically well-formed),


statements value false.4 I shall assume

to these

for the moment that it is atomic sortally incorrect statements which should be assigned the value false. Once we have made this assign
ment to the sortally The incorrect statements, they are no more obnoxious as

than contradictions
guage. any over, then may

that have
will or

likewise been admitted


the same play set of sentences role and

into the lan


More are

expressions sentence inconsistent truth-functions over

in deductions no more. statements truth-functions

atomic

defined?because simply be used.

incorrect sortally the classical exactly

V. O. Quine, Word and Object (Cambridge, Mass.: M.I.T. Press, to which Quine aludes here is taken 1960), p. 229. The "meaninglessness" to be a result of syntactic non-well-formedness. 4 This is an extension of the Fregean of allowing the signifi method or sortal range, of a predicate to include everything that can cance-range, count as an object. See especially in P. T. Geach "Function and Concept," and M. Black and eds.), the Philosophical Translations (trans, from (London: Basil Blackwell, of Gottlob Frege Writings 1970), pp. 33ff.

3 W.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

64

MERRIE BERGMANN One objection against any bivalent theory dealing with
statements If these

sortal

incorrectness are

is that

just meaningless either

incorrect sortally or non-significant.

aren't false; they are to statements

be admitted
assigned

into a semantically
wo truth-value

interpreted

system

they should be
systems) or a

(e.g.,

in supervaluational

truth-value other than those designated


(e.g., in many-valued But ingless" semantic the mere is not claim sufficient Along which empirically statements systems). that sortally to warrant Quinean are at

as the truest and the falsest


statements are "mean

incorrect

approach.

a departure from the classical we may lines, stipulate simply

that the classical value false


call incorrect, sortally to contradictions and sense in which such

applies to those statements


any rate not false statements. are "meaningless,"

which we

as well as true, There may be a but that need

not preclude us from developing a semantic theory in which they are simply treated as being false. Brushing this objection aside, then, it seems that the conse quences of any bivalent approach should be the decisive factors in accepting or rejecting it. R. Routley offers the following problem:
... a theory which simply reclassified non-significant as inconsistent: since false would be quickly discredited a sentence of definition, is, nonsignificant by negation be for some sentence p both p and ~p would nificant, theory.5 as sentences the classical also non-sig false in the

That is, if "Quadruplicity drinks procrastination" is sortally incorrect On the then so is "Quadruplicity does not drink procrastination." of the latter is the that classical the former, negation assumption
and the are to be designated statements incorrect sortally inconsistent. is rendered classical system that Note that in this quote, Routley makes an important as false, assump

tion: that the classical negation of a sortally incorrect statement is itself sortally incorrect. But if the Quinean theory treats sortally
incorrect sary atomic statements of sortal usual, as false, condition as incorrectness, and will produce a neces falsehood thus, making classical may simply negation a true statement from a false

function

one. No

reference

is made
of any

in the definition
the statement distinction

of classical

negation
other than between

to any semantic its truth-value.

aspect Thus,

upon operated that may be drawn

5 Routley,

p. 368.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS
atomic sortally negation incorrect statements and other non-true statements

65

is obscured; Quine has indicated that this was his intention.


The which Routley has in mind is not classical nega of ex

tion, but internal negation.6


external predicates

The distinction

between

internal and

can be seen most clearly negation by an examination such as "un-" or "dis-." with For prefixes negating

ample, from the nontruth of (3) The theory of relativity it can be inferred that (4) It is not the case that the theory of relativity
in classical music,

is interested

in classical music,

is interested

but not that (5) The theory of relativity is uninterested in classical music.

(4) and (5) may be said to express, respectively, the external nega tion and the internal negation of (3). In statement (4), the prefix "it is not the case that" is interpreted as denying the truth of the subsequent statement, while in the case (5) something more seems to be at stake. The assertion appears to entail that the theory of
can have dispositions?a clear relatively a of negation, that takes then, sortally another incorrect statement. sortally absurdity. incorrect It is this statement sort into

The distinction between


the The

these two modes

of negation

is tied to

of a predicate's sortal concept semantic of sortally deviance the have restricted

of applicability). (or range range can be ex incorrect statements

plained with reference


of language the

to the claim that (at least) certain predicates


sortal ranges; they The are not sig of

nificantly applicable to everything which can be picked out (referred


to) by true?that subject-expressions is, the predicate's of the language. sortal range to which

a predicate

includes both those things of which


extension?and those

the predicate
things

is

the predicate could otherwise be significantly applied. The problem with negation, then, is that on one reading (inter nal negation) the negation of a predication can be taken as indicat falls outside of the ing that the denotation of the subject-expression
6

The distinction between to Aristotle, Prior Analytics,

internal I, 46.

and external

negation

may

be traced

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

66 predicate's reading, the extension internal but within negation

MERRIEBERGMANN
sortal the predicate's a of incorrect sortally On this range. can statement

not be true. But if bivalent logics only admit of classical negation, then internal negation is not expressible in those languages. Classical
negation discredits statements yields true statements from sortally evaluate incorrect statements

when the latter are treated as being false, and for this reason Routley
semantic as false. approaches which sortally incorrect

But it is not clear that Quine's position cannot be saved. Note that the examples of sortally incorrect statements given by Quine are atomic; these statements are to be admitted into the theory
as falsehoods. The question of the truth-values of non-atomic sortally in Word

incorrect statements may


statement, from Quine's

still be left open.


discussion

Consider

the following
terms

of non-denoting

and Object:
and coped with, such truth-value per gaps can be admitted a But they values. truth of three like best logic by something haps are that promise no as complications remain an irksome complication, in understanding. gain issue merely that these various perplexities Let it not be supposed is neither between what is false and what from a pedantic distinction two cate those would be true nor false. gained by pooling Nothing under gories under the head of the false; for they are distinguished, of the negations contains in that the one category whatever names, of none of its all its members the other contains the negations while Even
members.7

The point to be noted is that the negation which Quine is considering


internal here, semantics. It is the negation, apparent at would not be truth-functional over a bivalent

non-truth-functionality

of

internal

negation the dis

that has led to the most


for, it is claimed, least

serious
three

criticism of bivalent
are needed

approaches; claims that

values

to make

tinction between

internal and external negation.

Routley

. . . forces in . . . the addition of the limited [internal ] negation models. Con 3-valued to at least the theories of up terpretations a sort of not is discerned the falsity; just non-significance sequently be split off as a for short?can falsity?nonsense non-significance third value.8

Once

this third value

truth-functionally

is admitted, internal negation can operate (taking the third value into the third value). The

7 p. 177. 8Quine, p. 378. Routley,

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS

67

sortally incorrect statements problem is not in deciding whether should be called false, but rather in deciding how many values the (It seems that underlying logic, if truth-functional, must have. Quine and Routley would not be in disagreement on this point.)

Ill
Within
for internal

a three-valued
and external

(truth-functional)
negation are:

semantics,

the matrices

~A T F N
internal

A T F N
external

F T N
negation

F T T
negation

The two matrices may be related by the use of the Bochvar-Frege horizontal h:9 hA T F N T F F

-A is defined as ~hA. With respect to the matrices for negation, the third value may indifferently be interpreted as signifying non
truth signifying The incorrectness). "it is true that. or as semantic internal deviance negation Then case, (in the present incorrect of a sortally the external sortal state

ment
read:

is both nontrue and sortally incorrect.


..."

The horizontal may be


negation of any

statement A may
sortally ?A, -A incorrect, involves

be read: "It is not true that A."


-A no is both derivative true and non-deviant?for affirmation

Where

A
unlike sortal

is

concerning

applicability. But adopting a three-valued semantics has an additional con sequence: the binary logical connectives must be redefined over
9

see H. G. Herzberger, "Truth For a discussion of this connective, in R. L. Martin and Modality in Semantically Closed Languages," (ed.), The Paradox Press, 1970), pp. 25-46. of the Liar (New Haven: Yale University

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

68 the three values.10 matrices is normal by that alternatives normal are varieties

MERRIE BERGMANN
Many for two I shall of these possible; A con of disjunction. statement which gov have

consider nective erned

just connective

in case whenever has immediate

a compound components

been assigned classical values (T or F), the compound statement itself is assigned the value itwould be assigned by the corresponding
classical matrix. Normality is a minimal concession to classical logic;

it means
been given affect

in the present
to sortally the

case that although semantic recognition has


incorrect statements (by means of assigning

the third value to these),


not guage. As nectives Note as operations that in any the on

the admission
the non-deviant

of these

statements
of the

will
lan

statements normal

three-valued

logic with

connectives, to normal The con prin

all tautologies
far are

(with value T designated)


remaining other concerned, statement assignments principles

are classical tautologies.


of values may be invoked.

ciple of purity yields Bochvar's


is that any compound

"internal" disjunction11; the principle


one of whose components is assigned

the value N will

itself be assigned

the value N:

AvB T F N
the assignment Letting is semantically deviant, the

I T T T N

F T F N

N N N N
mean of the that the statement

of A7 to a statement

of purity principle acceptance is de statement to saying amounts that if any part of a compound a as whole is the viant compound meaningless), (nonsignificant, This is the most natural rendered deviant. interpretation thereby case. of A7 in the present

Against
where the 10 F.

the principle
components

of purity,

it may
are

be objected
that only

that even
one is as

of a statement

such

an internal negation avoids this problem Sommers by making "Pre his a See on bivalent semantics. and predicates, retaining operation in America in M. Black (Ithaca: Cornell (ed.), Philosophy dicability," I develop semantics The alternative Press, 1967), pp. 262-281. University is defined over all in Section IV is likewise bivalent, but internal negation statements of the language. 11 and its Application D. A. Bochvar, "On a 3-Valued Logical Calculus Matematicheskii Sbornik to the Analysis of Contradictions," n.s., 4 (1938), pp. 287-308.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS
signed warrant a classical the value, this one

69
to be sufficient may assignment Take value to the compound. is of whose immediate components logic, the compound statement

as an example the assigned

assignment a disjunction, value T.

of a classical one

In classical

would be assigned the other disjunct.


tives should have

the value T regardless of the value assigned to The principle of uniformity states that connec
matrices: whenever a given Kleene's row (or column) dis

uniform

of a matrix
F, the value junction

has the same entry for both the value T and the value
N will also have that entry. "strong" to this principle:12

conforms

AvB T F

IT T T

F T F

N T N
value the N latter in this case is non appears

N
The most natural truth, rather as interpretation than deviance. shown by the

IT N N
of the In following fact reading

anomalous,

example.13

(6) Either

today is Friday or today is less than ten.

When the disjunction is interpreted as Kleene's strong connective, (6) will be assigned the value T on Friday and A7 on every other day of the IfN signifies deviance, this will mean that the statement is week. deviant on every day of the week but Friday. Each of the two interpretations of the third value is plausible
as applied statements. to sortally incorrect atomic seems it that for disjunction is chosen, however, When a decision the matrix between

the two interpretations


valued sortal approach incorrectness.14 12 S. is R.

is forced.
H. The

A recent alternative

to the three

Thomason's approach

for system supervaluational from truth-functional diverges

van to Metamathematics Introduction (Toronto: Kleene, 332-340. Nostrand, 1952), pp. 13 is from but related point, The example, together with a different p. 238. Thomason, 14 here that Martin I should mention contains an alterna Thomason. on H. "two-dimensional" G. based tive semantic Herzberger's analysis of Truth," Journal "Dimensions methods. (See H. G. Herzberger, of 2 [1973], The methodology is 535-556.) pp. Logic, Philosophical own a semantics I of similar have (Sect. my invaluable; analysis given in a forth and which will be presented dissertation IV) in my Ph.D. C.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

70 in the rejection systems sible valuations. The propositional language tive connectives. Define of truth-functionality scheme is roughly with

MERRIEBERGMANN
with as to admis respect Let L be a follows. as primi function

and negation taken disjunction a partial valuation p: p is a partial

with the atomic statements of L in its domain, and the set of classical The partial function is defined for all and values in its range.
only members language. Let of the class a complete of sortally valuation correct atomic statements of the classical v generated by p be any =

valuation
where A

over the statements


is a sortally correct

of L,
atomic

subject
statement,

to the constraint
p(A) v(A).

that
Let

V(p) be the class of all complete the super valuation s(p) generated = T iff = T for v(A) s(p)(A) = F iff = F for v(A) s(p)(A) s(p)(A)
Hence
value.

valuations generated by p. by p is defined as follows: all v e V(p) allv G V(p)

Then

is undefined
sortally

otherwise.
atomic statement is assigned a truth

no

incorrect

Let us say that a logical connective is truth-functional just in case the truth-values (or lack thereof) of the immediate components of a compound governed by that connective wholly determine the value (or lack thereof) of the compound. A logical system is truth-functional
are truth-functional with all of its connectives when respect exactly seen can be of the system. It to the admissible valuations by examina are the supervaluations where tion that a supervaluational system the admissible valuations is non-truth-functional.15 The divorce from of generating for the method is important, the set that exactly above guarantees

truth-functionality described valuations

super of classi

cal tautologies will be tautologies over the supervaluations (with T and entailment coincides with the classical relation. designated), is (The proof straightforward). The virtue of the supervaluational approach lies in this fact.
Neither tems. of these For results will, example: coupling in general, hold the three-valued for three-valued for matrices sys internal

I and Two-Dimensional But article, Logic." "Presupposition coming is based on certain will not consider Martin's work here, for his analysis in this section. I am arguing which intuitions 15 against will both be and s(p)(~C) if C is sortally incorrect, s(p)(C) E.g., = T. is undefined, undefined. But while s(p)(CvC) C) s(p)(Cv~

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS
negation "internal" together is a proper and Bochvar's "internal" it Mw); disjunction and Kleene's comprise of classical we obtain Bochvar's

71

(call system with internal negation subset of the class

disjunction "strong" Kleene's system "strong"

(call itMs).

Taking T as designated,

the class of tautologies


tautologies, and the

inMw
entail

ment relation is a proper subrelation of the classical. Taking both T andN as designated, the sets of tautologies coincide, but the entail
ment The relation same Yet ofMw results the is still a proper hold for Ms.16 subrelation of classical entailment.

supervaluational

concession

to classical

logic

seems

to be

too strong. Note that the results for statement (6) inM s hold also for the supervaluational system. (The statement is true on Friday and
receives no truth-value on other days of the week.) So here absence

of truth-value should be interpreted as signifying nontruth, than deviance. But why should the statement

rather

(7) Either the theory of relativity is interested in classical music or the theory of relativity is uninterested in classical music be true, if neither disjunct is true? Because the statement has the form of a classical tautology, it will be true on the supervaluational
approach even when the negation is interpreted as internal negation.

I fail to see the virtue in retaining the set of classical tautologies, if this is the result. Thomason has shown how to define external
negation statement over the supervaluations; and it seems correct that the

(8) Either the theory of relativity is interested in classical music or it is not the case that the theory of relativity is interested
in classical music

should be considered true. But this because the second disjunct (which involves external negation) is itself true. What we have here is a conflict of intuitions. Three different
criteria may be used for choosing the non-bivalent dyadic connectives,

and each has some intuitive plausibility. First, sortal deviance may be said to be contagious: statements such as (6)would be judged odd on sortal grounds by many native English speakers, and odd on any day
of the week. Second, uniformity is a plausible characteristic; al

though (6) is odd it also appears to be true by virtue of the first disjunct
16 For proofs, consult Chapter Two of my Ph.D. dissertation.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

72

MERRIE BERGMANN

(on Fridays). Third, classical tautologies expressible by statements such as (8) seem true?despite the apparent nontruth of their counter
parts containing internal negation?in this case, statement (7). Note

once again that the interpretation of the third value as indicating deviance in the case ofMw is the most plausible interpretation, while in the case ofMs and the supervaluational approach, the third value
and truth-value gaps are most plausibly interpreted as indicating nontruth.

But here is the key to the conflict: in all three systems, the sortal incorrectness of a statement has been held semantically identi fiable through the statement's truth-value. When this identification
is made, seems problems to be true squeeze is rendered out somewhere: either a statement which nontrue deviance (Mw), or a statement's a passion In the next sec for truth. in the

is obscured

semantically

through

tion, I shall present a logical system inwhich the definitions of truth


value and sortal theory incorrectness and reflected semantic are separated, but both dealt with in the accompanying language.

IV

My proposal is to build a logical system inwhich R. H. Thomason's


refinement basis, lying in the of B. C. van Fraassen's has only two not and which semantic ordinary "logical space" serves truth-values.17 Because will be as a semantic of the under

structure, sense.

all connectives

truth-functional

Let the language Lc have the following primitive


For
Pn

vocabulary:
predicates

each
i p ,r 2

integer
n p y . . .

n, a finite
,r m n

number

of n-adic

(Iwould prefer to restrict the number n to something smallish, but leave it open for generality. At any rate, for any number
n, the number m of n-adic ax,a<?, and Individual Logical constants connectives predicates . . . may be zero.)

punctuation:

-, D,

y,

(, ).

I will later introduce defined connectives. defined recursively:


If for some n, tu . . . , tn are then Ptxt2 n-adic

The statements

of Lc are
is an

predicate,

constants individual . . . tn is a statement.

and P

17 Thomason; Nous, Predicates,"

and B. C. van Fraassen, 1 (1967), pp. 161-179.

"Meaning

Relations

Among

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS
If A and B are statements, then -A, yA, and A D B are

73
state

ments. That's all.

The basis for the semantics will be a logical space S. S is a non empty set, which we may assume to be the collection of all entities which occur in at least one possible world. (I assume that the domains
of all possible worlds are disjoint. However, non-disjoint domains

may be assumed, provided that each possible entity is included in the extension/sortal range of a given predicate in one world if and only if it is included in that extension/sortal range in every possible world of which it is a member.) The meaning, or intension, of a predicate determines a class of possible entities to which the predicate could I truly apply; or the meaning is that class of possible entities.18 because the if idea is here that those entities say "could," possible
were actual existent entities, the predicate would be true of them.19

Likewise, the sortal range of a predicate includes those possible indi viduals of which the predicate is significant, or sortally correct. Any predicate's intension will be included in its sortal range; the possible entities of which P could be true must be part of P's sortal range. Letting S be the logical space for Lc, define a sortal specification R on S: R is a function defined over the predicates of Lc. For each n-ary predicate P, R (P) is an ordered pair of subsets of Sn, such that the first member of the pair is included in the second. The first member of R(P), P's intension, will be denoted by [RKP)]; the second, P's sortal range, by [R2(P) J. Let refbe a function (reference function) defined over the individual constants of Lc: for arbitrary constant a, ref(a) E S. We may think of ref(a) as the individual
denoted by a. Let M = (R, ref) be a model relative to the sortal

specification R on S.
18 Van Fraassen's com have this ontological theory does not ostensibly But I believe that ontological commitment does squeeze out some so rather as nebulous than leaving intents entities where; only being in the theory, I prefer simply to think of logical space in such a represented can be identified with the intents of the predicates. way that its regions Van Fraassen's account com alternative of logical space is, of course, below. patible 19with the formal apparatus developed I am here taking the sense of predicates, as we ordinarily use them, to be existence-entailing. It is because of this existence-entailment that I say that possible in the logical space would entities be such-and-such of the actual world). See also H. S. Leonard, (as members if they existed and Predicates," Philo "Essences, Attributes, of the American Proceedings 37 (1964), pp. 25-51. sophical Association,

mitment.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

74 Sortal cause ternal on

MERRIEBERGMANN
specifications logical space of distinguishing a bivalent language. a reasonable?be provide between internal and ex The internal negation of a

explanatory?means within negation

predication involves a derivative affirmation that the denotation of of the predication lies within the predicate's the subject-expression sortal range. in classical "The theory of relativity is uninterested music" is true if: it is not true that the theory of relativity is interested in classical music, and it is true that the theory of relativity is the sort External nega of thing that could be interested in classical music. So where Pa is a tion does not involve this derivative affirmation.
statement duce "~" of Lc, as and "~" stands for internal ?Pa a defined connective), (I will later intro negation will be true exactly when

That is, the referent of a is within P's R\P). refia) E ?2(P) sortal range but excluded from P's intension. Thus, if ref(a)
E R2(P), exactly one of Pa, ?Pa will be true and the other false. On

the other hand, if ref(a) ? R2(P), then both statements will be false. The external negation of a predication is defined only with respect
to the predicate's intension?viz., Pa is true if and only if Pa is

false (iff ref(a) & RKP)).


Given the previous comments, a necessary condition for the truth

of Pa or ?Pa is that ref(a) E R2(P). This means that ?Pa is true iff Pa is false and Pa is sortally correct. Carrying this idea a bit further, ' ifwe had in the language for each statement B a statement B which
is sortally that B says to range over definition then we correct, ?B all statements: could is true extend iff B the is false above andB'

is true.
B tions

This will be the function of the operation y?yB


correct. Now we may turn to a definition

will mean:
of the valua

is sortally for Lc.

A bivalent valuation for Lc with fixed S is defined as follows. For each model M on S, v is the bivalent valuation generated by M iff for every statement A of Lc, v(A) E {T,F}; and the following con
ditions are met:

= T iff . . . , (9) v(P?% . . . td (refitj, ref(td) E R*(Pfl = T = T iff = F or v(B) v(A) (10) v(A DB) = F = (11) v(-A) Tiffv(A) . . . , refit,)) E R2(P2(P, . . . ii) = T iff (ref(tt), (12) viyPfa

(13) viyiA 3B)) = T iff v(yA) = v(yB) = T

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS (14) v(y-A) (15) v(yyA)


Note that

75

= T = T.
connective, in the following sense (noted

= If we let A by van Fraassen). | |R {ref: A is true in (R,ref)}, we find that |-A \Rand \A D B |Rare functions, respectively, of |A |R, no corresponding function for yA and |J5 |Rand A | |R. There is | |R.
The operation bivalent theory. is non-truth-functional, and allows us to develop a

"y" is an unusual

The connectives definable inLc may be divided into four groups,


as follows.20

(16a) A composite limited connective


a statement whose truth-value

is a connective which forms


depends on both the truth

value and sortal status of its immediate substatement(s), and whose sortal status depends on the sortal status of its
immediate substatement(s).

(b)

A simple limited connective


statement whose truth-value

is a connective which forms a


depends of its on the truth-value of

its immediate
depends ment(s). on the

substatement(s)
sortal status

and whose
immediate

sortal status
substate

(c)

A composite unlimited
forms a statement whose

connective
truth-value

is a connective which
depends on the sortal

status of its immediate substatement(s),


(d) sortally A simple unlimited a statement whose correct. connective truth-value

and which is always


which forms

is a connective depends on the

truth-value

of its immediate
sortally Let me "-" now correct. some

substatement(s),
of the connectives It forms

and which

is always

is a simple

classify unlimited

connective.

of Lc. The a statement

negation is which

always sortally correct (14), and which is true iff the statement negated is false (11). "It is not the case that the theory of relativity
20 comes from A. Pap, The terminology "limited" and "unlimited" Mind 59 and n.s., (1960), p. 54. "Types Meaninglessness," Pap uses these terms to distinguish modes between of negation, where "limited" is internal negation, and "unlimited" is external nega negation negation
tion.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

76 is blue" is true and the

MERRIEBERGMANN
sortally correct, despite sortal status of the

imbedded statement.
ternal

The sortal status is due to the function of ex


(or semantic) sortal status is a simple by the connective; of the statement limited "D" connective.

as a "sortally negation opaque" statement formed does not receive the The of a connective statement "D"

upon. operated truth-value The

governed

is determined

classically (10). But the statement is sortally incorrect if either of its immediate components is sortally incorrect (13). Thus, "If today is less than ten, then today is Friday" is both true and sortally incorrect
on Friday.

Internal negation
nectives.

is defined with -A
have

the aid of the following

con

(17) 1A =?tAD
As consequence, we

(18) v(lA) = Ti??v?A) = F


(19) v(y 14)
"~l" is a simple

v(yA),
negation.

limited

(20) A&B =df HAD where

IB)f Then internal negation is

"&" is simple limited conjunction.


(21) -A =d{ lA&yA. is a composite limited

Internal

negation

connective,

for

(22) v(-A)

= T = F and = T iff v(A) v(yA) = (23) v(y-A) v(yA).


"y" is a composite unlimited connective. The truth-value

Finally,

of a statement governed by this connective depends only upon the sortal status of the immediate substatement ((12)-(14)), and the statement formed is always sortally correct (15). "y" is also "sortally
opaque," or a semantic operator.

The way inwhich models have been defined allows for the intro duction of two modes of semantic entailment and of validity.21 The
second correspond to logical, or universal, relations; the first are more

21 This

distinction

is drawn

in Thomason,

pp. 233 ff.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS
restricted. A set of statements T sortally entails a statement

77
A

relative to R, T |hR A, if: for every model M relative to R, if the bivalent valuation v generated by M is such that v(B) = T for all then v(A) = T also. A statement A is sortally valid relative PET, to R if $ h | RA. A set of statements T logically entails a statement A, r | \-A, if: for every logical space S and sortal specification R thereon, r |hR A. A. A statement A is logically valid if 4> \\behind the of intuitions and conflict Mw Ms is resolved by Thus,
status. and sortal The present truth-value system may separating in to various Note first that if classical also be related, ways, logic. statement correct for some model M, then the is sortally every atomic

simple limited and composite limited versions of any connectives will have identical truth-conditions on that model. (This is readily veri fiable.) Moreover, the truth-conditions for the simple limited con
nectives are identical with the classical truth-conditions. So on the

hypothesis, the resultant system would differ from classical logic only in the addition of a primitive "verum" operation y :v(yA) = T for allA.
Of correct. true") as (24) TA =??--A. course, So not define all models the simple will make unlimited statement every 'T" connective (read: sortally "is

We may replace every atomic statement A by TA, and define the connectives as in Lc (note that the clause (12) is then inoperative). The resultant system is then classical with the addition of the verum operation. That is, the simple limited and composite limited connec
tives again changeable Note collapse. salva veritate; that for TA and A are that not for it is possible in general inter some v and A,

v(yTA)

= T and = F. v(yA)

V A full quantificational system Lq may also be defined along the same lines. The vocabulary of Lq includes, in addition to the vocabu lary of Lc, the following:
Individual Possible Dyadic Logical variables individual predicate symbol xu x2, . . . wu w2, . . . variables "="

"V."

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

78

MERRIEBERGMANN of

The terms of Lq include the individual constants and both varieties variables. The formulas are defined recursively:
If for some n, tu . . . ,tn are terms and P is an n-adic predicate, . . . tn is a formula. then Pti If ii, t2 are terms then tx = t2 is a formula. are formulas, If A andP then -A, y A, and A D B are formulas.

If A

is a formula and z is a variable (Vz)A is a formula.


of Lq are exactly those

(of either variety),


in which

then

The occurs

statements free.

formulas

no variable

Let S (a non-empty
sortal specification on S, the

set) be the logical space for Lq.


as defined for Lc. Where D

Let R be a
is some non

empty subset of S, letD be the domain for L q. We will assume that D


normally represents set of actual individuals. Let ref be a func

tion defined over the individual constants of Lq: for arbitrary constant = a, ref (a) E D. Let M (R,D, ref) be a model relative to the sortal specification R on S. The definition of the bivalent valuations generated by the model is twofold, since we have introduced quantification. First, let an over on M d the terms of be any function defined assignment function = ref (a), Lq with range S, such that for any individual constant a, d(a) and for any individual variable x, d(x) E D. Relative to each assign ment function d, a satisfaction function sd is defined for the model M:
for every variable formula of either A, sd(A) E {T,F}, and (where t j is a term, and y is a variety)

. . . , . . . ?i) = T iff (26) sd(P^ d(t?) E ?HPj1) (diU), = T = T iff = F or (27) sd(A D B) sd(B) sd(A) = F = Tiff*d(A) (28)sd(-A) = = = (29) sait, d(t2) t2) T iff d(ix) = T iff = T for all sd, (A) (30) sd((Vi/)A) assignment functions on are as same d' M which d except possibly in the value of the

d(y)
(31) s?(y(Pfli (32) sd(y(A Di)) = T (33)sd(y-A) . . . , . td) = T iff (?(ij, dtfi)) E ?W) = = T = T iff sd(yA) sd(yB)

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

SORTAL INCORRECTNESS (34) s^yt^t,) = T

79

= T iff = T for all d' defined as in s* (yA) (30) (35) sd(y(Vy)A) = T. (36) sd(yyA) Finally, define the bivalent valuation v generated by M on S as: for = T for all satisfaction functions = T iff any statement A, v(A) sd(A) = F. The two modes of entailment and sd on M; otherwise, v(A)
validity are defined as earlier.

The reason for the introduction of two varieties of variables is that sortal specifications are then reflected in the language. Since individual variables range only over the domain in the logical space, the relations on the space determined by sortal specifications may not
be adequately reflected In general, bles. the in a language containing of D may be cardinality varia only individual smaller than that of S.

Suppose, then, that for some monadic predicates P and Q, R2(P) C R2(Q). Suppose also that for some D c M, [R2(Q) R2(P)]nD = (?>. Then for the individual variable x, the statement (\/x)(-yPx D -yQx), as well as (\fx)(yPx D yQx), will be true in that model. That
is, as far as the members of the domain are concerned, the sortal

ranges of P and Q seem to be identical. But they are not. The pos sible individual variables come into play here: ifw is a possible indi vidual variable, then (Vw)(-yPw D -yQw) is not true in the model.
Other relations in the sortal specification are also thus expressible. to R, and y

Let P and Q be monadic predicates, w a possible


R a sortal specification on a space S,Ia model

individual variable,
relative

the valuation generated (37) R2(P) (38) R2(P) (39) R2{P)


and so on.22

by M. Then = T. n R2(Q) = <f> iftv((4w) (yPw&yQw)) = = = T. R2(Q) i??v((4w)(yPw yQw)) v yQw)) = T, U R2(Q) = S ffiv(Qtw)(yPw Dartmouth

College.

22 as part of my Ph.D. in this essay were developed The ideas contained "A Presuppositional dissertation of Uni Semantic Theory Categories," I should like to acknowledge of Toronto, 1976. my debt to my versity dissertation Dr. B. C. van Fraassen, and advisor, Dr. H. G. supervisor, Herzberger.

This content downloaded from 128.214.2.137 on Sat, 1 Mar 2014 09:19:49 AM All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

You might also like