You are on page 1of 34

1

Mditation
pascalienne:
Demystification in
Cultural Theory

University of Cambridge
Faculty of Modern and Medieval Languages
Word count: 7,963
Table of contents

Preliminary material
Table of contents 2
2

Preface 3

Introduction 4
Mditation: Pascals dialectical method 7
The object of demystification 11
Qui la ramnera son principe lanantit: Foundation myths? 20
Mditation: the automatic subject 28
Epilogue: conjuncture 31

Bibliography 32











Preface
This dissertation has been formatted according to the most recent Modern Language
Association (MLA) guidelines and the Year Abroad Project Handbook 2015 (YAP)
3

(University of Cambridge, Faculty of Modern and Medieval Languages). In the case of a
conflict, I have followed the YAP.
Except when the fragment number has been previously given (in which case, as usual,
only the relevant page number will be given), references to the Penses contain both the
fragment number and the page number. For example: (fr.94 83) = fragment 94, on page 83, of
the Sellier edition.

























4

Introduction


La dmystification [] nest pas
une opration olympienne
Barthes, Mythologies


If the main two authors involved here are Pascal and Marx, it is because they both attempt to
show that there are obstacles to intelligibility: that is, to rendering reality and especially
social reality intelligible.
The concept of intelligibility has not escaped ideological abuse, however. In the
grand spectacle of le catch (17) where rien nexiste que totalement, the excess of
signification and the luxuries of gesture conspire to produce lintelligibilit parfaite du rel
(23): as Barthes observes, for the crowd at the wrestling match, intelligibility is heightened
to the image of Nature, which balms in full light sans ombre and exists without
contradiction (13).
But intelligibility does not stand for an inevitable component of the human
condition: it is the product of a history (Moriarty Roland 29).
If Pascal were to narrate this history, it would point to the Fall as the ultimate source
of the present distortion in our relation to ourselves and to God. Fragment 94 clarifies this
history: Il y a sans doute des lois naturelles, mais cette belle raison corrompue a tout
corrompu. Here, three temporalities present, past participle, past perfect found,
respectively, the impossibility of certain knowledge (lois naturelles), the corruption of
mans intellectual faculty (corrompue: as quality), and the corruption of all that the faculty
5

relates between itself and the world ever since the Fall (a tout corrompu: as action with
effects enduring to the present). For Pascal, intelligibility has been separated from its original
home; the present but entrenches its alienation from la chre patrie (fr.460 325).
If Marx were to narrate this history, it would account for intelligibility as a social
product, a concrete determination of an individual belonging to a particular form of society
(Theses 199). What are the conditions for intelligibility? The conditions of [mans] material
existence, and these are characterized by the exploitation of one part of society by the other
(Manifesto 21). Two aspects of intelligibility would thereby be emphasised: the rendering
of social life intelligible to those who are exploited; social revolution as the free
development of intelligibility, as the free development of all (23).
No doubt these interpretative histories can be written differently. But for the present
work, and in order to set in motion the aims of this dissertation, we can say: for Pascal and
Marx, intelligibility represents an alienated present (Moriarty Roland 29).

Demystification is inextricably linked to intelligibility. Demystification is a
theoretical tool which seeks to render obscure relations intelligible. Its disclaimer is that
social relations and cultural material are obscure: it seeks not to bring them into full light
the grand spectacle of le monde o lon catch but to reveal the laws, contradictions,
effects, and interests involved in these phenomena. The various texts dealt with in this
dissertation emphasise certain phenomena over others as to the methods and the object of
demystification. Reciprocally, the field of the dissertation will largely widen beyond that of
cultural theory, to theoretical discussion of concepts found in Marx, Pascal, and other
practitioners of demystification. A motivating idea in this work is that of theory and practice
as mutually reinforcing; but one hastens to underline the role of practice as a corrective to
mystificatory philosophizing.
6


All social life is essentially practical. All the mysteries which urge theory into
mysticism find their rational solution in human practice and in the comprehension
of this practice. (Marx Theses 199)

The raison dtre of the two mditations in the dissertation stems from this idea of practice,
but only to the extent that they too practice themselves. To join here with the practice of self-
criticism promoted by Bourdieu, the mditation is that Cartesian moment of personality and
of reflexivity:

ce dessein est pnible et laborieux, et une certaine paresse mentrane
insensiblement dans le train de ma vie ordinaire (Descartes Mditations I 69).
















7

Mditation: Pascals dialectical method

If, for Marx, the philosophers have only interpreted the world differently (Theses 199),
these ways are nonetheless necessarily one-sided. Pascal came to this conclusion regarding
the philosophies of his day: on ne peut tre pyrrhonien sans touffer la nature, on ne peut
tre dogmatiste sans renoncer la raison (fr.164 116). Each position entails abandoning a
certain phenomenon (nature or reason) because it cannot make room for it. In this way, both
positions are one-sided.
As Lebowitz argues, one-sidedness is a major thematic in Marxist thought (vii). In
one way, it is foundational to Marxs method: what is capitalism from the point of view of
Capital? In another, it is a criticism levied at the project: where is the wage-labourer in all
this?
That nineteenth-century socialist discourse promoted the opposition between the
bourgeoisie and the working-class is derived from an idea about one-sidedness and class
struggle. The opposition relates two groups of individuals as bearers and personifications of
their social interests.
1
Workers form unions to keep up the rate of wages (11); the bourgeois
class attempts to lengthen the working day. As Marx and Engels observe in The Communist
Manifesto:

the collisions between individual workmen and individual bourgeois take more and
more the character of collisions between two classes. (11)


1
That the various interests of the proletariat should be progressively equalized is, in my view, contentious.
For this reason, the question of individuals and interests is returned to throughout.
8

One-sidedness both limits and sustains this conflict of interests: sustains, because each
group only promotes its particular set of interests; limits, because neither group can accede to
the perspective of the other. Hence the revolutionary theoretical task: the subject of Capital is
Capital, so as to reveal to the proletariat the perspective of capitalism (Lebowitz, viii). This
is the aim of demystification in the critique of political economy.
We have managed to contextualize the concept of demystification with reference to
the thematic of one-sidedness. Now we shall elaborate a problematic.

What is the object of demystification in this context? Importantly, class struggle is not
self-produced: it is the product of the capitalwage-labour relation, the labour relation unique
to capitalism. Marx develops the concept contradiction to express the inner and necessary
connection or laws which make it prone to crisis (Capital Vol. 3 331). It is thus internal to
this relation and not to class struggle that the contradictions of capitalism are to be located.
To demystify Capital is essentially to reveal these contradictions. Overproduction, for
example, is described as the fundamental contradiction: as the productivity of labour grows,
the consumption of workers cannot keep up (Lebowitz 12). The result is periodic crises,
which can be interpreted as modes of appearance of structural contradictions, contradictions
brought to the surface (Osborne 20).
Pascal, too, has a concept of contradiction. Its sense, however, is rather that of
contestation. The philosophical context of fragment 208 is the argument of universal
consent as a mark of truth (Descotes and Proust 2011). Against this argument, the fragment
reads: Contradiction [read: contestation] est une mauvaise marque de vrit (151). The
criteria of truth and the criteria of contradiction are lexically ordered: the first is not
reducible to the second, it constitutes a qualitatively different ordre (fr.339 229).

9

By what method could one relate both terms: that of contradiction as inner law and
contradiction as contestation? I want to suggest Pascals method of dialectic, since it relates
back to our thematic of one-sidedness. The method, as articulated by Moriarty, is that of

juxtaposing opposing perspectives, each of which enables the perception of some
aspect of reality invisible from the other. They do not themselves, however,
generate a resolution: they need to be resolved and placed in their true
relationship by a revelation external to the process of human reason. But the
opposition prepares us to conceive the need for such a revelation. (Early, n.63
134)

To paraphrase: in the present case the opposing perspectives of the respective concepts of
contradiction are inherently one-sided. Each concept enables the perception of some aspect
of reality invisible from the other:
On the one hand, if for Pascal Contradiction [read: contestation] nest marque de
vrit, Marx can show that contestation can, in a major way, be taken as a source of
truth: since crises are that which periodically reveal the logical and essential
contradictions in the capital-labour relation, and thus are the loci of potential
contestation, in the sense of resistance or revolution.
On the other hand, if for Marx these contradictions, which stem from immanent
laws (332), are not to be confused with their appearance on the surface (337) the
level of crises, which reveal Capitals nature Pascal can radically claim that the
obscurity of social reality does not cease there: a more radical gap between ourselves
and the world is at work, problematizing the attempt of theory to go beyond forms of
appearance.
It is in these precise considerations about truth and resistance, about intelligibility
and social reality that the two concepts of contradiction each render visible some aspect of
reality formerly invisible to the other.
10


To reflect: by deploying a particular method, a problematic has been generated whose
concerns results will be brought to bear on further considerations. This problematic will now
be worked out through considerations of the object of demystification in certain
demystificatory discourses and the kind of problems of intelligibility they raise.
2

















2
Note the underlying assumption of this mditation: the practice of distinguishing concept and method, and
uprooting them, so to speak, from their soils. This is a central theoretical concern. Consider, for example, the
employment of Pascals dialectic method outside of a guaranteed framework of revelation: is the method no
longer fit for use or can it dispose one today to conceive the need for such a revelation (Moriarty,134)?
Compare Iris Murdochs attempt, in The Sovereignty of Good, to transpose prayer as an attitude towards the
Good in ethical and aesthetical life (53-54).
11

The object of demystification

Is the question of demystification one of invisibility? Our presentation of Pascals
dialectical method has been couched in the terms of visibility (a term perceives some aspect
of reality invisible to an opposing term). The couple invisible/visible in fact occupies a
prime place in Marxs philosophical heritage. The difficulty in rendering reality intelligible is
formulated by Kant, for example, in precisely these terms:

lintelligence la plus commune, qui, comme on sait, incline fort toujours
attendre derrire les objets des sens quelque ralit invisible agissant par soi, mais
qui en revanche corrompt cette tendance en se reprsentant immdiatement cet
invisible sous une forme encore sensible, cest--dire en voulant en faire un objet
dintuition, et qui ainsi nen est pas plus avance. (135)

There is a tendency to suppose some kind of law unavailable to perception which acts
behind the objects of the senses: this is corrupted when we present the invisible in a form
amenable to the senses.
But there is more involved than mere sense-perception. Of course, the ralit
invisible, as noumenon, is never available to human perception. Yet the text suggests that the
obstacle is not merely that our knowledge is limited (to phaenomena), but that human
judgments override this by interpreting what is visible as precisely those laws we have no
knowledge of. The obstacle to intelligibility thus lies in the interpretative faculties of the
subject. In this way, demystification would have to respond to a problem more fundamental
than that of visibility: to the level of our judgments.
Some of the terminology of Capital might suggest that Marx merely translates Kants
vocabulary into a critique of political economy: the subject becomes the political
economist, whose concepts are mere translations of the forms of appearance of the capitalist
mode of production, not perceiving the ralit invisible in its laws. This is to some extent
12

correct. However, Marx does not have reference to a transcendental subject as Kant did, and
neither is it a problem merely of interpretation. To employ a term that will subsequently
become clearer, if political economy presents social and economic relations upside-down, it
is because of reality itself.

To demonstrate this, we might have brief recourse to Marxs Critique of Hegels
Doctrine of the State, the subject of which is the constitution of the state on the one hand and
the family and civil society on the other, as according to Hegels Philosophy of Right.
The critique has two points: on the one hand, empirical facts, such as the family and
civil society, are transcended, because Hegel only considers them in so far as they are
dependent on the state; they are denied reality in themselves, because they exist in eternal
necessity to something beyond them. In reality, the family and civil society are the
preconditions of the state; but in speculative philosophy it is the reverse (Marx Early 62).
The state is thus reified, representing the self-sufficient act of the Idea. But, on the other
hand, it is the state that generates empirical form, since this reality [the state] has to
transform itself into real objects in order to exist (Colletti 19). For Marx, this represents an
obvious mystification (70).
The two points of critique are also couched in the logical terms of subject and
predicate. Firstly, Hegel inverts the usual relationship of subject and predicate (where the
universal [is] the predicate of some real object and so [] a category or function of that
object so that now the universal (the state, the Idea) exists in its own right, is self-sufficient
(Colletti, 19). Secondly, Hegel conceives the empirical world as a manifestation or
embodiment of this Idea, and thus a predicate of the predicate, not a predicate of a subject
(Colletti, 19-20). These two positions are distinguished in the Economic and Philosophical
13

Manuscripts as uncritical positivism
3
(deny the empirical world; true reality only in the
Idea) and uncritical idealism (restore the empirical world as manifestation and meaning of
this Idea) (Colletti, 23).
So, the source of mystification in Hegels theory is that it reifies the state into a self-
sufficient substance and transforms the empirical into merely the means by which the state
exists. Interestingly, Marxs subsequent gesture is to explain the failure of political economy
by the same token, since it

[substitutes] for the specific institutions and processes of modern economy
generic or universal categories supposed to be valid for all times and places; then
the former come to be seen as realizations, incarnations of the latter. (27)

As a conceptual tool employed by Marx in his critiques, the subject-predicate
inversion thus employs the fundamental terms of Western logic to show up the mystification
at work in the Hegels Philosophy and classical political economy. This is where the terms
natural/naturalized and historicize/historical enter the picture
4
: the state appears to be
founded on natural, eternal laws undetermined by history, while historical conditions (the
family and civil society) are reduced to its manifestation. Compare Marxs discussion of the
concept of production in the Grundrisse: the aim of political economy is

3
Interestingly, the first position is transposed by Lefebvre into [l]illusion de la transparence (36) one of two
mutual reinforcing illusions which conceal the proposition lespace (social) est un produit (social) (35). For
Lefebvre, there is a problem of intelligibility in the theoretical programme. Demystification in this case, of
philosophical illusions is in this way practically linked to reflexivity.
4
The terms are commonplace in discussions of ideology and in the practice of demystification. Mythologies, for
example, has as its object la mystification qui transforme la culture petite-bourgeoise en nature universelle
(Barthes 7) while for Bourdieu it is lhistoricisation qui permet de neutraliser, au moins dans lordre de la
thorie, les effets de la naturalisation: lhistoricisation represetns the major critical conceptual tool in la
science sociale (262). Eagleton also discusses the terms naturalizing and universalizing (9).
14


to present production [] as distinct from distribution etc., as encased in eternal
natural laws independent of history, at which opportunity bourgeois relations are
then quietly smuggled in as the inviolable natural laws on which society in the
abstract is founded. (The Marx-Engels Reader 255)

Marx elaborates by explaining that political economists will argue that there is no production
possible without an instrument of production [] without stored-up, past labour. Yet, by
identifying capital as an instrument of production, as past labour, they conclude that
capital is a general, eternal relation of nature (224). The mystification is clear.
But the inverted logic involved is grounded not in Hegels discourse, nor in political
economy. Marxs crucial gesture as a response to our point of departure: the question of the
source of upside-down philosophy is to propose that the inverted logic runs through
reality itself. It is no longer a problem of discourse or interpretation. Hegel was simply
translating the current state of affairs:

Hegel should not be blamed for describing the essence of the modern state as it is,
but for identifying what is with the essence of the state. (127)

Political economy likewise, identifies what is with the essence of labour in general, because
reality appears that way to them (in the surface-forms of capitalist economic relations).
It follows that the source of mystification is built into reality: the veil is not added by
bourgeois interpreters of the social life-process, i.e. the process of material production.
5

Instead it belongs to this process, which therefore appears to political economy as what it
really is (Colletti 38). This allows Marx to develop several critiques of the nature of
contemporary social relations. For example, with reference to private property: the reification

5
The idea of a veil in reality is also found in the liturgical theme of the Dieu cach, which inspired toute une
conception du monde at Port-Royal. Sellier cites a letter of Pascal to a certain de Rovannez in October 1656: Il
est demeur cach sous le voile de la nature, qui nous le couvre jusqu lIncarnation. [] Toutes choses sont
des voiles qui couvrent Dieu (28).
15

of private property, as the universal bond of the state (178) and its very constitution, entails
inverting the relationship between man and property:

the state appears as private property, whereas private property should really
appear as the property of the state. Instead of making private property into an
attribute of the body politic, Hegel transforms the body politicinto an attribute
of private property. (180).

Likewise, the state itself is an estrangement and abstraction, a reified body over and above
civil society. The next development is to demonstrate how civil society develops into the
division of society into private interests.
To summarise: Marxs argument is a critique of Hegels inverted logic, whose
mystical character is explained with reference to the reality of the modern state and of civil
society. Mystification is built into reality.

Two issues, relevant to demystification, can be gleamed from our recourse to Marxs
Critique.
Firstly, Hegel is described as the interpreter (151) of the role of legislature in the
modern state. Indeed, his uncritical, mystical method of interpretation is the key both to the
riddle of modern constitutions and also to the mystery of the Hegelian philosophy (149).
Hegel is even described in a singularly aggressive passage as thoroughly contaminated by
the wretched arrogance of Prussian officialdom (196).
The question this gives rise to is the capacity of critique. In this sense, Adornos
problematic of transcendent critique and immanent critique becomes relevant (Bernstein,
18). Now if the critiques position outside the social totality the transcendent critique is
condemned for its lack of inwardness, sympathy and attention to particulars, i.e. to the
specific objects of cultural production, is not the alternative immanent critique, which
16

aims to correspond to reality and to embody the contradictions, pure and uncompromised
in the inner-most structure of the specific content of the object in some way epitomized by
Hegels method itself (18-19)?
The problem is that Marxs concept of consciousness at work here leaves little room
for critique. In distinguishing the two critical positions, Adorno is nuancing this concept on
the theoretical level. A resolution of the immanent and transcendent positions is necessary,
taking the form of the non-position of dialectical criticism (19): The dialectical critic of
culture must both participate in culture and not participate (20). In Adornos terms, then,
demystification would have to work externally of and internally to its object.
As we have seen, it is through a critique of Hegel that Marx is able to point to the
abstraction of property from man, of the state from individuals. This latter abstraction is
expressed in the distinction between political life and civil society mentioned earlier. The
second insight to be gleaned from the Critique is that the nature of the individual in civil
society has changed. This shall now be pursued with reference to contemporary society,
Pascal, and the concept of alienation in both Pascal and Marx.

For Marx, the change in the social nature of individuals is due to the division of civil
societywithin itself into class and social position (147). Civil society does not sustain the
individual as a member of a community, as a communal being as it did previously in the
Middle Ages: there is no substantive good that joins individuals but only private interests that
estrange them (147). Class distinctions which existed before under absolute monarchy
remained political; now, with democracy, they become merely social differences in private
life of no significance in political life (146). Hence why the representative systems that
developed alongside the modern democratic state are contradictory, and in two ways: the
formal contradiction is that the deputies of civil society are not connected it its electors
17

by any instruction or commission; the material contradiction, that there is no public
interest, as Hegel imagines, but only particular interests (194). Class distinctions pertain to
the sphere of civil society and to the sphere of political life. They are thus doubled: as private
interests within civil society with no political meaning (the material), and as an illusory
public interest (the functioning of formal, abstract politics). The individual is thus socially
transformed: the same subject [i.e. woman] is given different meanings, entailing the
creation of a double subject: in Marxs terms, an allegory [has been] foisted on it (149).
There is thus a crisis of form and meaning at the intersection of three characteristics
of individual life: the formal equality as an abstract subject, the material interests which
divide individuals, and political life as disconnected. Marx argues, rather, that it is only by
starting with the essence and true realization (150) of the subject that we can authentically
determine what should be predicated of it. Real form and real meaning (149) would in this
case coincide.
Has Marx committed himself here to an ethical demand: to commence with the
realization of man involving terms like essence and (human) nature and to then see
whether the alleged subjects (the state, private property) are its real predicate[s]? (150)
No answer will be attempted now, but two suggestions can be made.
Firstly, one could interpret the concept of alienation in the sense of a crisis of forms
and meanings. The disjunction between forms and meanings is a source of estrangement and
an interpretative error: it is to interpret an old view of the world in terms of a new one (149).
Hence the dislocation of Hegels interpretative terms: the substantive notion of public
interests (only previously valid) and their referent, civil society as actual estrangement and
internal division.
Perhaps we could interpret Osbornes contemporary account of abstract social and
economic forms in capitalist societies with these terms. Take the notion of collectivity:
18


Collectivity is produced by the interconnectedness of practices, but the broadest
forms of interconnectedness and dependencies that are produced exhibit the
structure of a subject only objectively that is, in separation from both
individual subjects and particular collectivities of labour at the level of states
and beyond. (24, emphasis added)

Moreover, the dominant forms of economic subjectivization such as the constitution of
individuals as constituents of variable capital and consumers of commodities are now
accompanied by forms of financial subjectivization individuals as subjects of loans,
credit-card debt etc. (24, emphasis added). The similarities with Marxs critical vocabulary
(italicized) point to a possible dislocation between the political potential of the concept
collectivity, which has been surpassed (an old view of the world), and the essentially
abstract nature of capitalist societies. This is what alienation would then express. Perhaps
our political and sociological forms and concepts are being surpassed by the experiential
meanings of accelerated subjectivization. Theory can only play catch up if experience is
made to slow down.
The second suggestion is to relate Marxs formulation to Pascal. In fact, I want to
suggest that the problematic is perhaps the reverse, i.e. an inversion of Marxs formulation
with which he condemns Hegel. This would now read: to interpret a new view of the world
in terms of an old one. Since we are dealing with modern political authority, the Discours
sur la condition des grands proposes itself as a pertinent text to discuss this problematic, for
it deals with a contemporary political question for Pascal. The Discours concerns the grounds
of political authority. Addressed to a contemporary noble, it involves these propositions:
there is no lien naturel (230) which attaches the soul and the body of the king to his
condition, and royal authority is [un] tablissement humain. Yet the admiration of the king
by le peuple is founded on a misrecognition of this noblesse as une grandeur relle
(230). This is an illusion since it is only (but nevertheless importantly) a grandeur
19

dtablissement (231). If there is no intrinsic quality to the rulers of this world, then only
an imaginary relation sustains their power: this involves the misperception of an imaginary
quality as essential and natural, whereas authority itself is a historical construction, dictated
in the past which could have [been] imagined quite differently (Moriarty Early 116).
Let us recall the theological context of the Fall: depuis que [lhomme] a perdu le vrai
bien, tout galement peut lui paratre tel (fr.181, 134). I want to suggest that alienation, in
the way we interpreted it via Marx (a crisis of form and meaning), expresses at least to some
extent the fallen subject as Pascal conceives it. It as if the form of the framework which
lhomme inherited from before the Fall has lost its determinations: the justice of earthly,
political authority now appears as mans vrai bien, to fill the gap. And this distortion, to
recall the Discours, is then doubled, due to the misrecognition that founds social reality:
earthly, political authority appears essentialised and ahistorical. Intelligibility itself is
alienated and thus distorted. Only la foi can lead to knowledge of le vrai bien; it would
have to exceed the radical alienation of human intelligibility to do so.

A central disjunction between form and meaning the new political forms of the old
world; the old concepts of the new Fallen world seems to offer itself as a way of conceiving
alienation in relation to intelligibility, the term with introduced this section. An answer
now suggests itself to our initial question why demystification? in relation to Pascal: for
the very reason that political authority foists its own form and meaning on subjects, filling la
marque et la trace toute vide (fr.181 133) with its own distorted content, and exploiting
thereby the central misrecognitions of the social imagination that, in reality, sustains its own
power. In short, a demystifying critique is necessary precisely because God is absent
(Moriarty iek 128).
To the question of how political authority sustains itself we shall now turn.
20

Qui la ramnera son principe lanantit: Foundation myths?

All political authority has an initial act of foundation, and that act is an arbitrary usurpation.
Usurpation was the midwife to Rome, who was born in red blood and fratricide. The thematic
of usurpation is important to several accounts of how political authority founds and
legitimises itself; it is through it that we come to a certain idea about ideology and the role
of demystification. Of course, Romulus killed Remus is a myth in itself, as one of many
ideologies with which the early Romans conceived themselves. In this way, I want to tie
together two threads: the reality of usurpation and the role of ideology, which will form the
node of this reflection on foundations.

The approximation of ideology to myth could seem to say nothing more than that
ideology is a fiction, or a falsehood. This cannot be the case, since ideologies can be true
albeit at the same time fulfilling a particular kind of deceptive or mystifying function within
social life as a whole (Eagleton 7). In this way, a formal study of myths becomes possible:
myths as ides-en-forme.
In Mythologies, Barthes conceives the concept of mythe so as to make sense of how
labus idologique functions (7). As a discipline, la mythologie belongs both to semiology
(concerned with forms) and the ideology (concerned with ideas in history) (219). Conceded
that ideas have an active political force (Eagleton 6), the aim is to study how they function
as mythes to mystify the interests of those who deploy them. This mystification is more
complex than the metaphor of the screen (employed alongside discussions of false
consciousness, for example) would have it (Eagleton 11). Strictly, le mythe ne cache rien:
sa fonction est de dformer, non de faire disparatre (229). Form is motivated in in myth,
21

precisely because it functions to deform its raw material so as to make appear natural the
(historical, social) interests of the class that deploys it.
How does it do so? There are two steps: firstly, an usurpation or superimposition
which is strictly linguistic; secondly, a naturalisation, which relates to the context in which
the myth circulates and relates to wider customs and beliefs.
Barthes uses the terms of Saussurean linguistics to describe the first process. In
language, a signe is composed of a signifiant and a signifi (222). In myth, an initial signe
whose message is literal and practical (for example, that of a Black soldier in the French
army saluting) is usurped and deformed by emptying its sens, leaving a mere forme
(Moriarty 23). This latter functions as the myths signifiant. The concept which fills the
form (as the myths signifi) is historique et intentionnel: it is invested with [une] certaine
connaissance du rel (226). A new signe is thus produced, composed of an emptied forme
(signifiant) and a full concept (signifi). So, in the present example, the literal message of
the photograph of the soldier is emptied and deformed so as to produce a new sign: France as
a great empire faithfully served by black and white alike (and not an oppressive colonial
regime) (Moriarty 23). Barthes describes this transformation of a sens into a forme as a
theft of language; whereas, sil y a une sant du langage, cest larbitraire du signe qui la
fonde (n.7 234). That the signe is arbitrary is the central Saussurean insight; Barthes
reveals that myth usurps this healthy relationship and deforms the relation. Myth is the
parasite of language.
The study is not limited to the discussion of form and concept, because in order to
passer de la smiologie lidologie, that is to expliquer comment [le schma mythique]
rpond lintrt dune socit dfinie, we have to understand how it appears to le lecteur
de mythes (236). This is where the second process, naturalisation, enters the picture. The
myth can employ diverse rhetorical figures to perform it: for example, lidentification,
22

where lautre is ignored, denied, or reduced to the same, or constituted as a kind of
exotisme (Moriarty, 26). The result is immobility and fixity of language and of historically
constituted interests, which take on the appearance of physis, of Nature (exoticism is
grounded on an idea of lhomme as ainsi fait) (261). In this way, myth becomes the perfect
dmarche for bourgeois ideology (251): it can conceal its identity (in concrete terms its
interests) behind an image of Nature, by not naming itself (the process of ex-nomination),
thus enabling the bourgeoisie to maintain its dominance in a different guise (248). The
question of intelligibility is linked with the question of interests: if bourgeois interests appear
natural (because detached from real, social interests) and thus depoliticized in the cultural
material it employs, Barthes offers critical tools for demystifying its products, so as to reveal
the means by which political messages achieve dominance.
The example given by Barthes of ex-nomination is the myth of the nation. The myth
recurs also in Marxs discussion of the So-Called Primitive Accumulation. In the pre-history
of capital (875), it is noted that defenders of the systematic theft of communal property and
the theft of the state domains, which made the way for the capitalist mode of production,
had recourse to the notion of the wealth of the nation, in order to conceal the bloody
methods actually employed (Capital Vol 1, 886). Marxs use of parenthesis and irony
throughout the expos has a similar force to the sarcasm of Barthes semiological analyses:
the former undercuts, the latter demystifies through parody and hyperbole. However, Marx is
comparably less interested in how the notions function, more in its truth-content. For
example: the expropriation of the agricultural population is defended in one passage cited by
Marx as an advantage which the nation should wish for, since there will be a surplus for
manufactures which itself is one of the mines of the nation: after the first use of nation,
Marx inserts the following parenthesis: (to which, of course, the people who have been
converted do not belong) (888). The parenthesis is used here in order to show up the
23

concept of nation as unfounded: it claims to represent a broader set of interests than it
actually does. In short, the central battleground is the narration of the history of Primitive
Accumulation, played out in the chapter between actual history on the one hand and
bourgeois historians on the other (874-875). If the nation serves an ideological end, it is
that the concept it promotes discursively conceals the real interests of those who deploy it.
Both concept and form here are motivs, as Barthes would have it: ideology becomes a matter
of falsehood and myth in discourse.
We might pause here to ask: Does the discursive notion of ideology (ideology as
myth, political message depoliticized) exhaust the experience of domination for subjects in
capitalist society? Though Barthes at least early Barthes refers to the context and
customs which sustain myth and to how they may be read, one might argue that no account is
given of subjectivity: what does it mean to speak of a consammateur du mythe (237)? How
is this subject constructed?
The difficulty underlies the account of the silent compulsion of economic relations
in the same section of Capital:

The advance of capitalist production develops a working class which by
education, tradition and habit looks upon the requirements of that mode of
production as self-evident natural laws. The organization of the capitalist process
of production, once it is fully developed, breaks down all resistance (Marx, 899)

Domination is fundamentally economic: the workers dependence on capital, which springs
from the conditions of production themselves sets the seal on the domination of the
capitalist over the worker. The point here is that the laws of capital appear as natural and its
power guaranteed by the ordinary run of things (899).The same concealment that Barthes
points to in mythe is here built into the very nature of capitalism. Here is in seed form the
idea of false consciousness.
24


Our concepts ideology, usurpation, foundation can thus be related in two ways:
1) Barthes conceives of ideology
6
as myth, which functions via the usurpation
of the signe;
2) Barthes and Marx show ideology as concealing real foundations: the
foundation of social interests and the foundation of capitalist production.
We can relate the remaining pair of terms usurpation and foundation via a
discussion of the contemporary foundational notion of the political (Valentine, 49) as found
in iek. The insight to be gained here is that it offers a critical elaboration of the concept of
false consciousness: in short, by relating the foundation of authority and the amnesia of its
violent origins with mechanisms of belief.

To use a term from iek, the object of Marxs discussion on Primitive Accumulation
was the ideological battle in narrating the origins (the pre-history of capital) (For They
Know Not What They Do, 203). This question of origins for iek is situated within an
extended analysis of the symbolic, which argues that there is an act of concealment inherent
in any field of symbolically structured meaning, because the symbolic order always
presupposes and precedes itself (203). It is the symbolic order which sustains political
authority: but given that we are always-already embarqus, to use the adjective introducing
Pascals pari (fr. 680, 461), in this field of meaning, it is impossible to adopt an external
attitude to it. How, then, can one narrate [its] origins? The problem can be translated,
though not without modification, into phenomenological terms as the attitude naturelle

6
Strictly speaking Barthes use of the word idologie in refers to a particular discipline (Mythologies, 219).
However the present use of ideology is to be taken as a general term, as in Eagletons introduction to Ideology,
which was referenced at the start of this section.
25

which regards the world as allant de soi (Bourdieu, 250). In any case, the common concern
is clear: authority not only conceals its origins, but establishes a field of meaning which one
cannot exit. There is no Archimedean point from which subjects, who do not have the
privilege of retrospective, historical discourse (like Marx), could narrate political authority.
How does authority come to be? Pascals pseudo-historical narrative, or genealogy
as laid out in fragment 668 is insightful in this context (Moriarty, 113). It begins with tous
les hommes voulant dominer, et tous ne le pouvant pas, mais quelques-uns le pouvant, until
a kind of survival of the fittest establishes a precarious peace. Because les matresne
veulent pas que la guerre continue, the submission of the weak must become permanent
(443). Hence, force relies on manipulating the imagination of the conquered, in order to
naturalise itself: peu peu leur pouvoir est apparu comme naturel, et les conventions
juridiques ainsi tablies ont pass pour la justice (Sellier Port-Royal 32).
Arbitrary convention is passed off as justice. At the beginning was violence, but the
permanent establishment of authority requires a kind of amnesia of this primordial
usurpation (Moriarty 129). Il faut la faire regarder comme authentique, ternelle et en
cacher le commencement si on ne veut quelle ne prenne bientt fin (fr.94 85): this is the
insight of fragment 94, from which iek takes his cue. Intriguingly, the fragment articulates
both the narrative about the vrit de lusurpation and a more anthropological description:
the role of la coutume, for example, which exists in all places, derives its power par cette
seule raison quelle est reue (fr. 94, 83). Likewise, la justice is ce qui est tabli (fr.530,
363). In this way, our conclusions concerning political authority in the Discours are now
concretely related to subjective experience, and we have moved from an idea of ideology in
discourse to the subjective mechanisms at work in the constitution of authority. The
appearance of arbitrary conventions as natural and eternal relies on the distorted mechanisms
situated in the human subject.
26

Today, the purest example of this dependence is surely money: it functions only if
there is trust in the social link. [] its worth is purely reflexive, the result of peoples belief
in its worth (iek, ciii-civ). But money has real effects: for the homeless woman who has
none but nevertheless recognises its value, it is the difference between a meal and the shelter
of a department store entrance on the Faubourg St. Antoine.
This is where Bourdieus concept of la double naturalisation has explicative power
(Mditation 260). The legitimacy of the established order is facilitated by the almost
automatic way it functions: there is a double naturalisation qui rsulte de linscription du
social dans les choses et dans les corps (260). This naturalisation is a mechanism by which
the ordre social establishes its sociodice, but functions only to the extent that bodies and
things are inscribed, overridden and penetrated by social relations (262). And this has real
effects: in the order of emotions, for example. If Barthes and Marx considered the myth of the
nation, for example, in relation to discursive ideology and the concealment of real interests,
this is not the whole picture:

cest que la nation, la race ou l identit , comme on dit aujourdhui, est
inscrite dans les choses sous forme de structures objectives, sgrgation de fait,
conomique, spatiale, etc. et dans les corps sous forme de gots et de dgots,
de sympathies et dantipathies, dattractions et de rpulsions, que lon dit parfois,
viscrales. (Bourdieu 260)

The spatial organization of cities, for example, represents a mechanism by which domination
enforces itself; the nation will be inscribed in the articulation of its suburbs, in the
arrangement of communities. Ideology cannot be limited to the order of ideas and action, but
extended to consider conscious and unconscious mechanisms of domination and legitimacy.
This is one of the central insights that Bourdieu reads back into Pascal.

27

The scope of demystification has widened considerably. En filigrane, this section has
aimed to put forward the thesis that as ideology is interpreted anew, so too are the methods of
demystification. We can now make a distinction by resuming in our initial terms: in its
limited sense, the foundation of political authority entails an initial act of usurpation; in a
name other than its own, ideology conceals this act and its real interests. In its broad sense,
foundation is the reality of a variety of mechanisms by which usurpation is forgotten and
ideology penetrates our bodies, daily.


















28

Mditation: the automatic subject

This mditation bears on the constitution of theoretical discourse.
Its inspiration is Marxs analysis of the general formula for capital. This is the
movement M-C-M: the boundless drive for enrichment or buying in order to sell (Capital
Vol. 1 254, 248). In the presentation of the formula, there develops an account of the subjects
involved within the sphere of exchange. The possessor of money is both a concrete person
endowed with consciousness and a will who bears (Trgen) the movement of exchange,
thus becoming capital personified, or simply, a capitalist (254). (To be sure, that capital is
personified means that a social soul can occupy a physical body, or rather, that capitalist
relations condense on individual subjects.
However, the true subject of the relation is strictly neither the capitalist nor capital:
the subject is value:

The money [M, M] and the commodity [C] function only as different modes of
existence of value itself, the money as its general mode of existence, the
commodity as its particular or, so to speak, disguised mode. (Marx 255)

Value is the insidious and sinuous subject which pumps the blood of exchange. To study the
forms of appearance assumed in turn by self-valorizing value leaves us with the elucidation
[] capital is money, capital is commodities; yet in truth [] value is here the subject of a
process which while assuming the form in turn of money and commodities, [] changes its
own magnitude. This occult ability to add value to itself is the kernel of Marxs argument:
it is the source of mystification (255).
Consider further the designation of value as the automatic subject. Value works
beyond human control (automatic) and asserts its identity in the form of money. In the
29

social relationship of exchange the subject is not the capitalist, despite her consciousness and
will; rather, value is the dominant subject of this process (255).
I want to suggest the concept of the automatic subject as a kind of theoretical
manifesto, in the vein of Bourdieus promotion of practical self-criticism: the process of
self-criticism is, as it were, a necessary personal condition for any kind of communication
on ideology (iek Mapping 270).
A concrete example is needed.
In a note to his essay La domination masculine, Bourdieu analyses the philosophical
discourse of Sartre in Ltre et le nant. The passage in discussion is Sartres description of
the female sex as a trou visqueux which is shown to operate via a triad of metaphors: the
hole, and specifically the mouth; viscosity; and the image of the bees sweet death (more
sucre) as it drowns in jam (15). In order to relate the analysis to la domination masculine,
Bourdieu suggests that the foundational oppositions of masculine mythology come to the
surface in objectivized form in the philosophical discourse of Sartre. There is an
objectivation inconsciente de linconscient masculin (15). The fundamental oppositions of
masculine mythology take on des formes, aprs transformation, dans le discours
philosophique. The terminology formes, transformation and the context of Bourdieus
demystification of Sartre could suggest the concept of an automatic subject within
philosophical practice. If value bears forth its own offspring, in Sartres discourse a
phantasme priv is sublimated into an intuition fondamentale du systme philosophique:
philosophical discourse, like value, lays golden eggs (Marx 255).

The point to note in all this is that there is an automatic subject at work as much in
the general formula for capital as in theoretical discourse. Self-criticism would entail a
demystification of discourse to reveal how this subject functions in any given text.
30

Adorno conceived of social research in practice as an important corrective to
philosophical discourse. The construction of interpretive models and categories that
reconstruct its object should be paired with empirical research. This was the double demand
of sociology: reflection on the concept of society and confrontation with facticity (Mller-
Doohm, 284). The double demand is only possible, however, if sociology remains conscious
of its own limits as a particular discipline, i.e. to take up a self-critical position vis--vis its
own categorical and methodological instruments (285). In Bourdieus insistence on the
practice of self-criticism, and in the concept of the automatic subject, there is perhaps a
sketch of how to respond to the demand.
















31

Epilogue: conjuncture

Demystification deals with objects that are obscure. It may be an erreur scolastique to project
this obscurity onto contemporary experiences, as constitutive of life for subjects in capitalist
societies. But, to amend a phrase of Bourdieus: As soon as we think in [the terms of
demystification], it becomes clear that the work of emancipation becomes very difficult
(Mapping Ideology, 270).
The capacity to resistance today runs up against the distortion of individual social
relations. This is borne out by Figaros tirade in Act V, sc. iii of Le Mariage de Figaro. Here
is Figaro, se promenant dans lobscurit. He expresses the failures of his professions, the
burden of censorship, unemployment, and his anger towards the Count for reneging on his
denunciation of seigniorial privilege. Vous vous tes donn la peine de natre, et rien de
plus: with these words, the play might herald the demise of privilege and the rise of a new
system of value (money) in pre-revolutionary society (Pucci, 64). But it is nevertheless an
account of real distortion. Despair is directed at individuals: Quavez vous fait pour tant de
biens! (Beaumarchais, 224). Competition fosters division: chacun pillait autour de moi
(225). Figaro finds it difficult to subsist, perdu dans la foule obscure (224).
Bourdieu has elsewhere noted the discourse of blame in his observations on racism
(La domination masculine, 12). Just as a myth of the nation or race is brought to bear on
individuals by individuals one only has to read the experiences of immigrants so too the
injustices and exploitation under capitalism estrange and distance human beings.

With compassion, the task is to demystify the obscure relations that constitute what
we are, in order to practice, in solidarity, what we ought to be.

32

Bibliography

Works cited
Barthes, Roland. Mythologies. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1957.
Beaumarchais, Pierre Augustin Caron de. Thatre [sic.]: Le barbier de Sville, Le mariage de
Figaro, La mre coupable. Paris: Garnier-Flammarion, 1965.
Bourdieu, Pierre. La domination masculine. Actes de la recherche en sciences sociales. Vol.
84 (September 1990): 2-31.
---. Mditations pascaliennes. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 2003 [1997].
Descartes, Ren. Mditations Mtaphysiques. Paris: Flammarion, Paris, 2011 [1992].
Descotes, Dominique and Proust, Gilles. Les Penses de Blaise Pascal. PRES Clermont
Universit, 2011. Web. 2 Oct. 2014.
Eagleton, Terry. Ideology. London: Longman, 1994.
Kant, Emmanuel. Fondements de la mtaphysique des murs. Trans. Victor Delbos. Paris:
Livre de Poche, 1993.
Lebowitz, Michael A. Beyond Capital: Marxs Political Economy of the Working Class. 2
nd

ed. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan, 2003 [1992].
Lefebvre, Henri. La production de lespace. Paris: ditions anthropos, 1986 [1981, 1974].
Marx, Karl. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy: Volume 1. Trans. Ben Fowkes.
London: Penguin, 1976.
---. Capital: A Critique of Political Economy: Volume 3. Trans. David Fernbach. London:
Penguin, 1981.
---. Early Writings. Trans. Rodney Livingstone and Gregor Benton. London: Penguin, 1971.
---. Theses on Feuerbach in Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich. The German ideology : parts I
& III. London: Lawrence & Wishart, 1939.
33

Marx, Karl and Engels, Friedrich. Manifesto of the Communist Party. The Classics of
Marxism: Volume One. Ed. Wellred Books. London: Wellred Books, 2013.
Moriarty, Michael. iek, religion and ideology. Paragraph 24/2 (July 2001): 125-39.
---. Early Modern French Thought: The Age of Suspicion. Oxford: Oxford University Press,
2003.
---. Roland Barthes. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1991.
Mller-Doohm, Stefan. The Critical Theory of Society as Reflexive Sociology. The
Cambridge Companion to Adorno. Ed. Tom Huhn. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 2004. 279-301.
Murdoch, Iris. The Sovereignty of Good. London: Routledge, 2001, [1971].
Osborne, Peter. A Sudden Topicality: Marx, Nietzsche and the politics of crisis. Radical
Philosophy 160 (Mar-Apr 2010): 19-26.
Pascal. Penses. Paris: Libraire Gnrale Franaise, 2000.
---. De lesprit gomtrique. crits sur la grce et autres textes. Paris: Flammarion, 1985.
Pucci, Suzanne R. The Currency of Exchange in Beaumarchais Mariage de Figaro: From
the Master Trope Synecdoche to Fetish. Eighteenth-Century Studies Vol. 25, No. 1
(Autumn, 1991): 57-84.
Sellier, Philippe. Port-Royal et la littrature II. Paris: Honor Champion diteur, 2012.
Tucker, Robert. C, ed. The Marx-Engels Reader. New York-London: W.W. Norton &
Company, 1972, 1978.
Valentine, Jeremy. Rancire and Contemporary Political Problems. Paragraph 28/1 (March
2005): 46-61.
iek, Slavoj. Mapping Ideology. London: Verso, 1994.
---. For They Know Not What They Do: Enjoyment as a Political Factor. London: Verso,
2008 [1991].
34

Works consulted
Alienation, class struggle, critical theory cultural materialism, cultural studies, false
consciousness, hegemony. Oxford Dictionary of Critical Theory. 1
st
ed. Oxford: OUP,
2010.
Adorno, Theodor. The Culture Industry: Selected Essays on Mass Culture. Ed. J.M.
Bernstein. London: Routledge, 1991.
Barthes, Roland. Essais Critiques. Paris: ditions du Seuil, 1964.
---. Le degr zro de lcriture; suivi de lments de smiologie. Paris: ditions du Seuil,
1964 [1953].
Foucault, Michel. Surveiller et punir: Naissance de la prison. Paris: ditions Gallimard,
1975.
Pascal. Les Provinciales. Paris: ditions Gallimard, 1987.
Prendergast, Christopher. The Order of Mimesis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1986.
Williams, Raymond. The Uses of Cultural Theory. New Left Review I/158 (July-August
1986): 19-31.

You might also like