You are on page 1of 8

Definition of Utility

Utility is a term used by economists to describe the measurement of "usefulness" that a


consumer obtains from any good. Utility may measure how much one enjoys a movie, or the
sense of security one gets from buying a deadbolt. The utility of any object or circumstance can
be considered. Some examples include the utility from eating an apple, from living in a certain
house, from voting for a specific candidate, from having a given wireless phone plan. In fact,
every decision that an individual makes in their daily life can be viewed as a comparison
between the utility gained from pursuing one option or another. Utility can be seen as a measure
of how much one values a particular good. This depends entirely on the preferences of that
individual, rather than some external, or universal measure. So while an apple and an orange may
give utility values of 5 and 10 respectively to one individual, they may give 1,250 and -180 to
another. These values depend only on how they are valued by the decision makers in each case.
Rationality and Utility
In economics, we usually say that an individual is "rational" if that individual maximizes utility
in their decisions. That is, whenever an individual is to choose between a groups of options, they
are rational if they choose the option that, all else equal, gives the greatest utility. Recalling that
utility includes every element of a decision, this assumption is not particularly difficult to accept.
If, when everything is taken into account, one decision provides the greatest utility, which is
equivalent to meaning that it is the most preferred, then we would expect the individual to take
that most preferred option. This should not necessarily be taken to mean that individuals who fail
to quantify and measure every decision they make are behaving irrationally. Rather, this means
that a rational individual is one who always selects that option that they prefer the most.
The rationality assumption may seem trivial, but it is basic to the study of economics. This
assumption gives a basis for modeling human behavior and decision making. If we could not
assume rationality, it would be impossible to say what, when presented with a set of choices, an
individual would select. The notion of rationality is therefore central to any understanding of
microeconomics.
Measurement
There are no real methods of measuring utility outside of a purely theoretical framework. An
option giving 100 utils has no real interpretation, except that it is preferred to an option giving
50, and is less preferred than an option giving 101. The numbers used to model utility are only
determined in the functional form of the model from which they result. It is meaningless, for
example, to ask "how much utility does this apple give you?" It could only be meaningful to ask,
"Would you prefer an apple or an orange?" in any non-theoretical framework.

One way to measure utility is to give the utility a monetary value.


For example, if I would pay 0.70 for a piece of cake, then we can say the utility is 0.70
If a piece of cake cost 70p, it would make sense to consume 2 pieces.
The first piece gives 100p of utility > than the price of 70p.
The second piece gives a utility equal to the price.

It was recognized that utility could not be measured or observed directly, so instead
economists devised a way to infer underlying relative utilities from observed choice. These
'revealed preferences', as they were named by Paul Samuelson, were revealed e.g. in
people's willingness to pay:
Utility is taken to be correlative to Desire or Want. It has been already argued that
desires cannot be measured directly, but only indirectly, by the outward phenomena
to which they give rise: and that in those cases with which economics is chiefly
concerned the measure is found in the price which a person is willing to pay for the
fulfilment or satisfaction of his desire.

Total Utility
If we could measure utility, total utility would be the number of units of utility that a consumer
gains from consuming a given quantity of a good, service, or activity during a particular time
period. The higher a consumers total utility, the greater that consumers level of satisfaction.

Panel (a) of Figure 7.1 "Total Utility and Marginal Utility Curves" shows the total utility Henry
Higgins obtains from attending movies. In drawing his total utility curve, we are imagining that
he can measure his total utility. The total utility curve shows that when Mr. Higgins attends no
movies during a month, his total utility from attending movies is zero. As he increases the
number of movies he sees, his total utility rises. When he consumes 1 movie, he obtains 36 units
of utility. When he consumes 4 movies, his total utility is 101. He achieves the maximum level
of utility possible, 115, by seeing 6 movies per month. Seeing a seventh movie adds nothing to
his total utility.

Figure 7.1 Total Utility and Marginal Utility Curves

Panel (a) shows Henry Higginss total utility curve for attending movies. It rises as the number
of movies increases, reaching a maximum of 115 units of utility at 6 movies per month. Marginal
utility is shown in Panel (b); it is the slope of the total utility curve. Because the slope of the total
utility curve declines as the number of movies increases, the marginal utility curve is downward
sloping.

Mr. Higginss total utility rises at a decreasing rate. The rate of increase is given by the slope of
the total utility curve, which is reported in Panel (a) of Figure 7.1 "Total Utility and Marginal
Utility Curves" as well. The slope of the curve between 0 movies and 1 movie is 36 because

utility rises by this amount when Mr. Higgins sees his first movie in the month. It is 28 between
1 and 2 movies, 22 between 2 and 3, and so on. The slope between 6 and 7 movies is zero; the
total utility curve between these two quantities is horizontal.
Marginal Utility

The amount by which total utility rises with consumption of an additional unit of a good, service,
or activity, all other things unchanged, is marginal utility. The first movie Mr. Higgins sees
increases his total utility by 36 units. Hence, the marginal utility of the first movie is 36. The
second increases his total utility by 28 units; its marginal utility is 28. The seventh movie does
not increase his total utility; its marginal utility is zero. Notice that in the table marginal utility is
listed between the columns for total utility because, similar to other marginal concepts, marginal
utility is the change in utility as we go from one quantity to the next. Mr. Higginss marginal
utility curve is plotted in Panel (b) of Figure 7.1 "Total Utility and Marginal Utility Curves" The
values for marginal utility are plotted midway between the numbers of movies attended. The
marginal utility curve is downward sloping; it shows that Mr. Higginss marginal utility for
movies declines as he consumes more of them.

Mr. Higginss marginal utility from movies is typical of all goods and services. Suppose that you
are really thirsty and you decide to consume a soft drink. Consuming the drink increases your
utility, probably by a lot. Suppose now you have another. That second drink probably increases
your utility by less than the first. A third would increase your utility by still less. This tendency
of marginal utility to decline beyond some level of consumption during a period is called the law
of diminishing marginal utility. This law implies that all goods and services eventually will have
downward-sloping marginal utility curves. It is the law that lies behind the negatively sloped
marginal benefit curve for consumer choices that we examined in the chapter on markets,
maximizers, and efficiency.

One way to think about this effect is to remember the last time you ate at an all you can eat
cafeteria-style restaurant. Did you eat only one type of food? Did you consume food without
limit? No, because of the law of diminishing marginal utility. As you consumed more of one
kind of food, its marginal utility fell. You reached a point at which the marginal utility of another
dish was greater, and you switched to that. Eventually, there was no food whose marginal utility
was great enough to make it worth eating, and you stopped.

What if the law of diminishing marginal utility did not hold? That is, what would life be like in a
world of constant or increasing marginal utility? In your mind go back to the cafeteria and
imagine that you have rather unusual preferences: Your favorite food is creamed spinach. You
start with that because its marginal utility is highest of all the choices before you in the cafeteria.

As you eat more, however, its marginal utility does not fall; it remains higher than the marginal
utility of any other option. Unless eating more creamed spinach somehow increases your
marginal utility for some other food, you will eat only creamed spinach. And until you have
reached the limit of your bodys capacity (or the restaurant managers patience), you will not
stop. Failure of marginal utility to diminish would thus lead to extraordinary levels of
consumption of a single good to the exclusion of all others. Since we do not observe that
happening, it seems reasonable to assume that marginal utility falls beyond some level of
consumption.
Maximizing Utility

Economists assume that consumers behave in a manner consistent with the maximization of
utility. To see how consumers do that, we will put the marginal decision rule to work. First,
however, we must reckon with the fact that the ability of consumers to purchase goods and
services is limited by their budgets.
The Budget Constraint

The total utility curve in Figure 7.1 "Total Utility and Marginal Utility Curves" shows that Mr.
Higgins achieves the maximum total utility possible from movies when he sees six of them each
month. It is likely that his total utility curves for other goods and services will have much the
same shape, reaching a maximum at some level of consumption. We assume that the goal of each
consumer is to maximize total utility. Does that mean a person will consume each good at a level
that yields the maximum utility possible?

The answer, in general, is no. Our consumption choices are constrained by the income available
to us and by the prices we must pay. Suppose, for example, that Mr. Higgins can spend just $25
per month for entertainment and that the price of going to see a movie is $5. To achieve the
maximum total utility from movies, Mr. Higgins would have to exceed his entertainment budget.
Since we assume that he cannot do that, Mr. Higgins must arrange his consumption so that his
total expenditures do not exceed his budget constraint: a restriction that total spending cannot
exceed the budget available.

Suppose that in addition to movies, Mr. Higgins enjoys concerts, and the average price of a
concert ticket is $10. He must select the number of movies he sees and concerts he attends so
that his monthly spending on the two goods does not exceed his budget.

Individuals may, of course, choose to save or to borrow. When we allow this possibility, we
consider the budget constraint not just for a single period of time but for several periods. For

example, economists often examine budget constraints over a consumers lifetime. A consumer
may in some years save for future consumption and in other years borrow on future income for
present consumption. Whatever the time period, a consumers spending will be constrained by
his or her budget.

To simplify our analysis, we shall assume that a consumers spending in any one period is based
on the budget available in that period. In this analysis consumers neither save nor borrow. We
could extend the analysis to cover several periods and generate the same basic results that we
shall establish using a single period. We will also carry out our analysis by looking at the
consumers choices about buying only two goods. Again, the analysis could be extended to cover
more goods and the basic results would still hold.

Marginal Utility Theory


Marginal Utility theory examines the increase in satisfaction consumers gain from consuming an
extra unit of a good.
Utility is an idea that people get a certain level of satisfaction / happiness / utility from
consuming goods and service.
This utility is not constant. Often we get diminishing marginal utility. The first piece of
chocolate cake gives more utility than the 7th piece.
Quantity (Q)

Total Utility

Marginal Utility

100

100

170

70

190

20

180

-110

140

-4

In the above example, total utility (190) is maximized after just three pieces of chocolate cake.

Ordinal utility
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

Ordinal utility theory states that while the utility of a particular good or service cannot be
measured using a numerical scale bearing economic meaning in and of itself, pairs of alternative
bundles (combinations) of goods can be ordered such that one is considered by an individual to
be worse than, equal to, or better than the other. This contrasts with cardinal utility theory, which
generally treats utility as something whose numerical value is meaningful in its own right. The
concept was first introduced by Pareto in 1906.[1]

Contents

1 Indifference curve mappings


2 Revealed preference
3 Ordinal utility functions
4 See also
5 References
6 External links

Indifference curve mappings


When a large number of bundles of goods are compared, the preferences of the individual can be
seen. This information is usually put together on a graph called an indifference map. One of
these is shown below:

Each indifference curve is a set of points, each representing a combination of quantities of two
goods or services, all of which combinations the consumer is equally satisfied with. The further a
curve is from the origin, the greater is the level of utility. The slope of the curve (the negative of
the marginal rate of substitution of X for Y) at any point shows the rate at which the individual is
willing to trade off good X against good Y maintaining the same level of utility. The curve is
convex to the origin as shown assuming the consumer has a diminishing marginal rate of

substitution. It can be shown that consumer analysis with indifference curves (an ordinal
approach) gives the same results as that based on cardinal utility theory i.e., consumers will
consume at the point where the marginal rate of substitution between any two goods equals the
ratio of the prices of those goods (the equi-marginal principle).

Cardinal utility
From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia

A simple example of two cardinal utility functions of y=2x+3

In economics, a cardinal utility function or scale is a utility index that preserves preference
orderings uniquely up to positive affine transformations.[1][2] Two utility indices are related by an
affine transformation if for every value

of one index u, occurring at quantity

goods bundle being evaluated, the corresponding value


relationship of the form

of the other index v satisfies a

for fixed constants a and b. Thus the utility functions themselves are related by

The two indices differ only with respect to scale and origin.[1]

of the

The idea of Cardinal utility is considered outdated except for specific contexts such as decision
making under risk, utilitarian welfare evaluations, and discounted utilities for intertemporal
evaluations where it is still applied.[3] Elsewhere, such as in general consumer theory, ordinal
utility is preferred.
Expected utility
The expected utility theory deals with the analysis of choices among risky projects with (possibly
multidimensional) outcomes.
The expected utility model was first proposed by Nicholas Bernoulli in 1713 and solved by
Daniel Bernoulli in 1738 as the St. Petersburg paradox. Bernoulli argued that the paradox could
be resolved if decision makers displayed risk aversion and argued for a logarithmic cardinal
utility function.
The first important use of the expected utility theory was that of John von Neumann and Oskar
Morgenstern who used the assumption of expected utility maximization in their formulation of
game theory. Utility as probability of success
Castagnoli and LiCalzi and Bordley and LiCalzi (2000) provided another interpretation for Von
Neumann and Morgenstern's theory. Specifically for any utility function, there exists a
hypothetical reference lottery with the utility of a lottery being its probability of performing no
worse than the reference lottery. Suppose success is defined as getting an outcome no worse than
the outcome of the reference lottery. Then this mathematical equivalence means that maximizing
expected utility is equivalent to maximizing the probability of success. In many contexts, this
makes the concept of utility easier to justify and to apply. For example, a firm's utility might be
the probability of meeting uncertain future customer expectations

Conclusion:
A consumer's utility is hard to measure. However, we can determine it indirectly with consumer
behavior theories, which assume that consumers will strive to maximize their utility. According
to Daniel Bernoulli, for the usual person, utility increased with wealth but at a decreasing rate.
Since consumer demand for utilities does not change dramatically with a change in price, it can
considered as a tool to speculate demand. Utility concept has lot many criticisms too. But as
utility is directly related to consumers taste and satisfaction, this topic demands further research
and exploration.

You might also like