You are on page 1of 9

POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1), 5563

The Profession
Teaching and Learning Ontology and
Epistemology in Political Science
Stephen R. Bates* and Laura Jenkins
*University of Edinburgh

University of Birmingham

The teaching and learning of ontology and epistemology is an important element of political
science, as it helps students to appraise, differentiate and choose between competing philosophies,
theories and analytical traditions. Thus, it encourages reflexive learning through the strategies of
inquiry, role taking and benign disruption. However, we argue that there are aspects within the
most prominent introductory material on these meta-theoretical issues which may undermine
these processes. In particular, definitional inaccuracies and a lack of sustained reflection on the
contested nature of the directional relationship between ontology and epistemology tend towards
a prescriptive path dependency and curtail the possibility of reflexive learning. By subjecting this
received knowledge to critical reflection, we hope to overturn these weaknesses and open up a
debate on the teaching and learning of ontology and epistemology.

One repays a teacher badly if one remains only a pupil.


And why, then, should you not pluck at my laurels?
Nietzsche (1961, p. 103).

Introducing complex theories, concepts and issues to students is one of the more
difficult tasks of lecturing and teaching. Theories, concepts and issues must be
rendered accessible, while at the same time remaining accurate. Thus, the necessary
act of simplification, which enables initial understanding, must maintain the possibility of critical engagement, yet not result in any distortion which would misrepresent positions and confuse subsequent learning processes. Moreover, the
simplified version must remain broad and inclusive so as to allow complexity,
nuance and specificity to be reincorporated at a later date. This is especially true
with regard to the meta-theoretical concepts of ontology and epistemology, which
are basic to all research inquiry and in which the complexities are enormous and
controversial, their definitions1 and relationship disputed and their necessity for
political science often not rendered explicit.
In this article, we argue that, despite some very obvious strengths and important
contributions, the dominant literature on ontology and epistemology within political science retains some unacknowledged and problematic assumptions. First, definitional and explanatory short cuts have been taken which do not correspond
closely enough with their original form in philosophy. The result of which is an
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association

56

STEPHEN R. BATES AND LAURA JENKINS

inaccuracy which can cause confusion in the minds of both student and teacher.
Moreover, it raises the possibility of students having to unlearn some of this
introductory information if they go on to study these issues in more detail. Second,
there is a tendency to present, indeed prescribe, a particular directional relationship
between ontology and epistemology as a given, or correct truth, rather than as
dissonant and contested students. This can lead to some philosophical traditions
appearing more problematic than others. Thus, a path dependency emerges which
leads to students choosing positions underpinned by that particular directionality.
Consequently, reflexive learning and the development of critical analysis, the very
activities promoted by an understanding and appreciation of ontology and epistemology, are paradoxically undermined and become stunted at this meta-theoretical
level. In this article, we aim to provide a corrective to some of these shortcomings,
as well as provoke a debate on how best to introduce these complex metatheoretical issues.
The article is structured in four sections. First, we briefly outline why reflexive
learning is important and provide some reasons why ontology and epistemology
should be introduced to students of political science in terms of their facilitation of
this. Second, we introduce the dominant introductory material on ontology and
epistemology within political science. Third, we highlight examples of definitional
inaccuracies and inconsistencies before, fourthly, discussing the lack of engagement
with the debate on ontology and epistemologys relationship and the consequent
impact on the ability to foster reflexive learning.

Reflexive learning, critical analysis and ontology and


epistemology
Within literature on stages of intellectual development, a stress is placed on the
importance of the move from instructional surface learning to deep structure, or
reflexive, learning and independent, critical analysis (see, for example, Bligh, 1982;
Buckler, 2001; Elton, 1992). An instructional surface approach is a regurgitation
and memorisation of key isolated facts without reflection or engagement on the
ideas which inform them (Entwistle, 1997). Moreover, it is informed by the expectation on the part of the student/teacher that the role of the authority is to teach
the right answers (Roberts, 2002, p. 2). In contrast, Steve Buckler suggests that a
reflexive approach to learning involves recognition of the constitutive character
of the conceptual frameworks within which our understandings of the world
subsist { [L]earning about the world involves an element of construction (2001,
p. 73). Taking a reflexive approach to learning is important for two main reasons:
learners develop a theoretically informed, innovative and research-oriented disposition; and teachers learn to cultivate conceptual facility and analytical flexibility
with respect to the presentation of different ideas which figure in their research
(Buckler, 2001, p. 75).
As such, teaching and learning within political science should not be about the
instruction and regurgitation of knowledge. Instead, teaching should mean alerting
students to different ways of thinking. It should provide a non-prescriptive basis
from which students can reflexively engage with the material in order to uncover
relationships, connections and underlying patterns and, consequently, partake in
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

ONTOLOGY AND EPISTEMOLOGY

57

critical analysis (Entwistle, 1997). Engaging in this critical analysis does not constitute an attempt to teach students to be critical theorists, critical realists or a
particular kind of critic, in any theoretical sense. Rather, critical analysis refers to
the crucial capacity to engage with, interrogate and challenge other perspectives.
This allows learners to throw up ambiguities and inconsistencies in received knowledge; critique, revise and, perhaps, reformulate conceptual claims; and, ultimately,
formulate and defend independent arguments.
We believe teaching and learning ontology and epistemology are important in
political science for fostering the processes and strategies of inquiry, role taking and
benign disruption, which enable this reflexive learning. Developing a capacity for
inquiry the ability to ask questions is crucial if students are to interrogate and
challenge the differences between, the assumptions made, and the knowledge
produced by, particular theoretical and analytical traditions. This can be cultivated
by invoking ontological questions concerning the nature of social and political
reality and epistemological questions relating to knowledge and its justification.
Together, these form the foundations upon which contending perspectives are built.
For instance, reflecting on whether there are universal truths helps students to
differentiate, in part, between behaviouralism and post-structuralism.
In general, role-taking experiences are important for intellectual development
because they enable students to critique their own position from the point of view
of another and, concurrently, allow them to comprehend anothers position. An
appreciation of meta-theoretical principles enables students to achieve these outcomes through preventing students from talking past each other. For example,
recognition of the surface realism of rational choice theory by a Marxist allows
them to realise why rational choice theory does not analyse class differences, while,
at the same time, bolstering their understanding of Marxisms focus on structural
inequalities due to an ontology of depth realism.
Finally, benign disruption involves disjunctive experiences that engage a persons
attention { [and] provoke him or her to reconsider, reinterpret or reject prior
assumptions or beliefs (King and Kitchener, 1994, p. 228). Engaging with ontology
and epistemology can lead to a benign disruption of, for example, a rational choice
theorists belief in the predictive capability of political science through highlighting
the open and contingent nature of the social world, or a malestream political
scientists assumptions of objectivity through feminist critique.
In summary, the vital movement towards reflexive learning can be facilitated
through engaging with ontological and epistemological issues, as it enables understanding and adjudication between contending theoretical and analytical traditions.
Many of the differences and disputes between political scientists are more profound
than students often assume, based, as they are, on fundamental meta-theoretical
differences. Learning and teaching ontology and epistemology discloses these philosophical divergences and, thus, can foster reflexive thinking by encouraging students to confront and justify their own ideas, beliefs and positions.

Introductory literature on ontology and epistemology


Probably the most prominent and influential accounts of ontology and epistemology in political science, especially at an introductory undergraduate level, can be
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

58

STEPHEN R. BATES AND LAURA JENKINS

found within the two editions of Theory and Methods in Political Science (TMPS) edited
by David Marsh and Gerry Stoker (1995 and 2002) and Political Analysis by Colin
Hay (2002). Marsh and Stoker are to be commended for virtually doublehandedly introducing the importance of ontological and epistemological reflection
for political science students. This contribution has been reinforced by Hays
endorsement of meta-theoretical engagement. Although not explicit within their
work, Hay and Marsh and Stoker greatly encourage the development of reflexive
learning by imaginatively highlighting issues of the nature and the study of the
political. The significance of these interventions should not be understated, as it
allows students to take a far more sophisticated and involved approach to their
work, as well as providing the premises upon which a pluralistic political science
can be built.
However, this prominent literature contains weaknesses. First, there are a number of
inconsistencies and inaccuracies within explanations of ontological and epistemological positions in TMPS. Second, this literature promotes a view of the ontology/
epistemology relationship as uncontested and unproblematic. Consequently, there
is, perhaps, a tendency towards intellectual gatekeeping which, paradoxically, given
the benefits of reflecting upon these issues, may hinder critical analysis and reflexive
learning. Overall, there is a lack of inquiry and benign disruption at the metatheoretical level, which could result in shaping the preferences of students philosophical positions and, thus, their choice of theoretical traditions.

Inconsistencies and inaccuracies


Ontological and epistemological definitions within TMPS are inconsistent and,
consequently, sometimes inaccurate. For example, Stoker and Marsh assert, ontology is concerned with what we can know about the world and epistemology is
concerned with how we can know it (Stoker and Marsh, 2002, p. 11). These
definitions are, at best, problematic and, at worst, incorrect.2 What exists, which is
an ontological concern, is not necessarily the same as what we can know, which is
an epistemological concern. Yet, as this is an isolated mistake, it can be put down to
a rather glaring and unhelpful editorial error. However, there are more serious
inaccuracies within TMPS which cannot help but confuse.
Perhaps the most prominent of these is the use of the terms foundationalism and
anti-foundationalism. In the chapter entitled A Skin not a Sweater, Marsh and
Paul Furlong refer to both as ontological concepts. They argue, Positivists adhere to
a foundationalist ontology { The realist is also foundationalist in ontological terms
(Marsh and Furlong, 2002, p. 20). Furthermore, referring to the argument that
differences between men and women are socially constructed, Marsh and Furlong
contend that this viewpoint reflects a different ontological position that is antifoundationalism (Marsh and Furlong, 2002, p. 18). This terminology continues
throughout the chapter and highlights the definitional short cuts sometimes taken
by political scientists when they borrow from philosophy. Far more precision needs
to be shown if students are fully to understand and employ ontology and epistemology within political research. Here, the good work carried out by Marsh,
Furlong and Stoker in introducing these concepts is undermined through the
conflation of ontological and epistemological concerns.
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

ONTOLOGY AND EPISTEMOLOGY

59

Even a cursory glance at philosophical dictionaries and introductory texts to


philosophy of (social) science is enough to discover that foundationalism and
anti-foundationalism are epistemological concepts. James Ladyman defines foundationalism as:
In epistemology the theory according to which our justified beliefs fall into two
categories, namely basic beliefs, which are justified independently of all other
beliefs, and non-basic beliefs, which are those that are justified by their inferential relations to basic beliefs (Ladyman, 2002, pp. 265266).
In The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, foundationalism is: The theory that knowledge of the world rests on a foundation of indubitable beliefs from which further
propositions can be inferred to produce a superstructure of known truths (Jones,
1995, p. 289). Consequently, anti-foundationalism is a theory which posits that
there is no one foundation which grounds beliefs and knowledge claims.
This inclusion of epistemological terms when defining ontological positions can be
viewed as part of a broader conflation of ontology/epistemology when Marsh and
Furlong delineate their different meta-theoretical positions. For example, they state
that Realism shares an ontological position with positivism, but, in epistemological
terms, modern realism has more in common with relativism (Marsh and Furlong,
2002, p. 30). There are a number of problems with this statement. First, realism is
an ontological position. It is the contention that there are aspects of the (social as
well as the natural) world that are independent of our knowledge of them. As such,
positivism also has a realist ontology. However, it is a particular type of realism, a
shallow, or surface, realism, rather than the depth realism which characterises the
position outlined by Marsh and Furlong. Second, this meta-theory, which can be
most closely associated with critical realism, does not, in epistemological terms,
have more in common with relativism. Rather, it is relativist at an epistemological
level. Critical realism is underpinned by an epistemic relativity, which asserts that
all beliefs are socially produced, so that all knowledge is transient, and neither
truth-values nor criteria of rationality exist outside historical time (Bhaskar, 1998a,
p. 58). Indeed, central to critical realism is its claim to combine and reconcile
ontological realism, epistemological relativism and judgemental rationality (Bhaskar,
1998b, p. xi).

The directionality of the relationship between ontology


and epistemology
In addition to these definitional weaknesses, there is the important, but unrecognised, issue of the relationship between ontology and epistemology. There appears
to be total agreement on the relationships directionality within these texts. Marsh
and Furlong argue, Ontological and epistemological positions are related, but need
to be separated. To put it crudely, ones ontological position affects, but far from
determines, ones epistemological position (Marsh and Furlong, 2002, p. 18).
Although there are some references to opposing views, Hay also claims:
ontology logically precedes epistemology { we cannot know what we are capable
of knowing (epistemology) until such time as we have settled on (a set of
assumptions about) the nature of the context in which that knowledge must be
acquired (ontology) (Hay, 2006, p. 8).
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

60

STEPHEN R. BATES AND LAURA JENKINS

We do not wish to argue this directionality is wrong. Instead, we wish to argue this
position must be explicitly recognised as a contested perspective, rather than a
given. Within other disciplines, the relationship is often perceived quite differently.
Steve Smith asserts:
ontological claims { without an epistemological warrant is dogma { epistemology
matters because it determines of what we can have knowledge; moreover, it is
not possible to wish it away, or undermine its importance, by arguing, as is
fashionably the case { that ontology is prior to epistemology { I see neither
ontology nor epistemology as prior to the other, but instead see the two of them
as mutually and inextricably interrelated (1996, p. 18).
Furthermore, Derek Gregory contends, Many scholars would now accept that {
ontology is grounded in epistemology (Gregory, 2000, pp. 226227). As Deborah
Dixon and John Paul Jones III similarly assert, from a post-structuralist perspective:
ontological assumptions put the cart before the horse, for any ontology is itself
grounded in an epistemology about how we know what the world is like; in
other words, the analysis of ontology invariably shows it to rest upon epistemological priors that enable claims about the structure of the real world. For
example, the ontological divisions between physical and social phenomena, or
between individual agency and sociospatial structure { [are] the result of an
epistemology that segments reality and experience in order to comprehend them
both. But how do we draw the boundaries of nature, or, for that matter, of the
individual? And when and where did these categories emerge? So much of
geography is predicated upon analyzing variables structured upon such dualisms,
and yet the categories and their derivatives are not natural, in any real sense,
but are the sociohistorical outcomes of representational processes { analysis must
first begin at the epistemological level (Dixon and Jones, 1998, p. 250; see also
2004a and 2004b).
Other strands of post-structuralism3 consciously conflate ontology and epistemology and deny that there are real distinctions between ontology, epistemology, and
value systems (Shusterman, 1998, pp. 126127). Moreover, while not explicitly
denying ontologys priority, Nietzsches and Foucaults genealogical inquiries
operate as a challenge to dominant ontologies, developing from a perspectivism
which suggests that truth is a thing of this world.
There are a number of incommensurable positions on the ontology/epistemology
relationship. As such, the lack of recognition of, and reflection on, alternative
perspectives by Hay and Marsh and Furlong must be seen as problematic from both
philosophical and pedagogical viewpoints. As Foucault (1980) contends, the power
to define the parameters, absence or existence of what constitutes significant
knowledge is profound and ubiquitous. In their efforts to render accessible these
complex meta-theories, Hay and Marsh and Furlong have, perhaps unintentionally,
acted as intellectual gatekeepers in allowing themselves the right to decide the
answer, yet concealing the question by excluding or, at least not fully acknowledging, alternative perspectives. Intellectual gatekeepers possess the ability to limit
access to the knowledge upon which students build. This is in conflict with the
pedagogical task of fostering reflexive learning. As Paulo Freire argues:
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

ONTOLOGY AND EPISTEMOLOGY

61

The fundamental task of the mentor is a liberatory task. It is not to encourage the
mentors goals and aspirations and dreams to be reproduced in the mentees, the
students, but to give rise to the possibility that the students become the owners
of their own history { teachers have to transcend their merely instructive task
and to assume the ethical posture of a mentor who truly believes in the total
autonomy, freedom and development of those he or she mentors (Freire, 1997,
p. 324).
As this quotation suggests, problems can arise from instructing students that
ontology comes first.
This instruction4 may lead to an outcome where students are more prone to support
and defend particular theories, and reject, find contradictions within and fail to
understand others. As this particular directionality would not be recognised by
post-structuralism for example, it becomes difficult to present theoretical traditions
on an even playing field. There is a lack of recognition by Hay and Marsh and
Furlong that the directionality they support is a reflection of their own philosophical positions.
Ultimately, there is something prescriptive about current teaching of ontology and
epistemology in political science. It puts in place a form of path dependency in
which it becomes difficult for students to stop being pupils, in the Nietzchean sense,
and become independent thinkers. Indeed, Jonathan Grix admits, in reference to a
figure adapted from Hay outlining the interrelationship between the building blocks
of research, that he may come across as somewhat prescriptive or, in the words of
one reviewer of this article, it may remind readers of old style methods books of
the 1950s (Grix, 2002, p. 179). If students are encouraged meekly to follow this
directional path, then it may constrain their ability fully to engage and reflect upon
the various philosophies and related theories. The advantages of ontological and
epistemological reflection for the development of reflexive learning are, paradoxically, undermined by a lack of reflection on their relationship.
At present, students are not given the opportunity to make any directional judgements and, as such, their meta-theoretical choices are hindered by the position of
these teachers. Consequently, there is a potential foreclosure of the plurality within
political science that both Hay and Marsh desire.5

Conclusion
Despite some very obvious and important strengths, the dominant literature on
ontology and epistemology in political science does not encourage the full development of reflexive learning. This is due to some inaccuracies and a failure to
present the directionality of the ontology/epistemology relationship as a contested
area of meta-theory.
Ontological and epistemological consideration can facilitate reflexive learning. For
this to flourish further, we must improve the accuracy of definitions, as well as
providing a framework which renders concepts accessible. Moreover, we need to
acknowledge competing perspectives surrounding the directional relationship
between ontology and epistemology in addition to acknowledging the competing
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

62

STEPHEN R. BATES AND LAURA JENKINS

positions within meta-theory. Alerting students to this dissension is particularly


important because it encourages them to challenge assumptions and premises and,
therefore, make up their own minds about what kind of political scientist they are,
rather than blindly following the leader.
The development of such an open and inclusive pedagogical strategy on the subjects
of ontology and epistemology is no easy task and the aim of this article is to move
towards this. However, it is crucial to continue pursuing this end if we are to
develop an environment within which students can take greater ownership of their
own learning and repay their teacher by not remaining a pupil.

Notes
We would like to thank Judi Atkins and three anonymous referees for comments on earlier drafts of this
article. We would also like to thank various members of the critical geography e-mail list for useful
literature suggestions.
1 Although recognising the existence of alternative definitions, we employ the popular Blaikie definitions. Ontology refers to the claims or assumptions that a particular approach to social inquiry makes
about the nature of social reality claims about what exists, what it looks like, what units make it up
and how these units interact with each other (Blaikie, 1993, p. 6). Epistemology is a theory of
knowledge; it presents a view and justification for what can be regarded as knowledge what can be
known, and what criteria such knowledge must satisfy in order to be called knowledge rather than
belief (ibid., p. 7).
2 This is also a problem for other authors writing on this topic (see Grix, 2001, p. 27 and 2002, p. 177).
3 Derrida most notably rejects the concept of ontology due to its operation in a binary and thus
undecidability (see Norrie, 2005).
4 Hay and Marsh and Furlong do not explicitly argue that this directionality should be taught. However,
as the only prominent introductory sources within political science, there is an increased probability
that this directionality will become hegemonic.
5 See Marsh and Smith (2001) and Marsh and Savigny (2004). Moreover, Hay states, it is not my
intention to hide my preference for certain analytical strategies and perspectives over others (2002,
p. 2). In foreclosing the argument on directionality, it could be argued that he goes against this
objective.

References
Bhaskar, R. (1998a), The Possibility of Naturalism, London: Routledge.
Bhaskar, R. (1998b), General Introduction in M. Archer, R. Bhaskar, T. Collier and A. Norrie (eds.),
Critical Realism: Essential Readings, London: Routledge, pp. ixxxiv.
Blaikie, N. (1993), Approaches to Social Inquiry, Cambridge: Polity.
Bligh, D. (1982), Professionalism and Flexibility in Learning, Surrey: SRHE.
Buckler, S, (2001), Reflexivity and the Discipline Specific Context, European Political Science 1(1),
pp. 7077.
Dixon, D. and J.P. Jones III (1998), My Dinner with Derrida, or Spatial Analysis and Poststructuralism do
Lunch, Environment and Planning A 30(2), pp. 247260.
Dixon, D. and J.P. Jones III (2004a), Poststructuralism in J.D. Duncan, N. Johnson and R. Schein (eds.),
A Companion to Cultural Geography, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 79107.
Dixon, D. and J.P. Jones III (2004b), What Next? Environment and Planning A, 36(3), pp. 381390.
Elton, L. (1992), Research, Teaching and Scholarship in an Expanding Higher Education System, Higher
Educational Quarterly 46(3), pp. 252268.
Entwistle, N.J. (1997), Contrasting Perspectives on Learning in F. Marton, D. Hounsell and N.J. Entwistle
(eds.), The Experience of Learning, Edinburgh: Scottish Academic Press.
Foucault, M. (1980), Power/Knowledge, Brighton: Harvester.
Freire, P., J.W. Fraser, D. Macedo, T. McKinnon and W.T. Stokes (1997), Mentoring the Mentor, New York:
Peter Lang.
2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association
POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

ONTOLOGY AND EPISTEMOLOGY

63

Grix, J. (2001), Demystifying Postgraduate Research: From MA to Ph.D., Birmingham: University of Birmingham Press.
Grix, J. (2002), Introducing Students to the Generic Terminology of Social Research, Politics 22(3),
pp. 175186.
Gregory, D. (2000), Epistemology in R.J. Johnston, D. Gregory, G. Pratt and M. Watts (eds.), The
Dictionary of Human Geography, Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 226228.
Hay, C. (2002), Political Analysis, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Hay, C. (2006), Political Ontology in R.E. Goodin and C. Tilly (eds.), Oxford Handbook of Contextual Political
Analysis, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jones, O.R. (1995), Foundationalism in T. Honderich (ed.), The Oxford Companion to Philosophy, Oxford:
Oxford University Press, p. 289.
King, P. and K.S. Kitchener (1994), Developing Reflective Thinking, San Francisco, Cal.: Jossey-Bass.
Ladyman, J. (2002), Understanding Philosophy of Science, London: Routledge.
Marsh, D. and P. Furlong (2002), A Skin, Not a Sweater: Ontology and Epistemology in Political Science
in D. Marsh and G. Stoker (eds.), Theories and Methods in Political Science, Basingstoke: Palgrave,
pp. 1744.
Marsh, D. and H. Savigny (2004), Political Science as a Broad Church: The Search for a Pluralist
Discipline, Politics 24(3), pp. 155168.
Marsh, D. and M. Smith (2001), There is More than One Way to Do Political Science: On Different Ways
to Study Policy Networks, Political Studies 49(3), pp. 528541.
Marsh, D. and G. Stoker (eds.) (1995, 2002), Theories and Methods in Political Science, Basingstoke: Palgrave.
Nietzsche, F. (1961), Thus Spoke Zarathustra, London: Penguin.
Norrie, A. (2005), Theorising Spectrality: Ontology and Ethics in Derrida and Bhaskar, New Formations
56, pp. 96108.
Roberts, K.A. (2002), Ironies of Effective Teaching: Deep Structure Learning and Constructions of the
Classroom, Teaching Sociology, 30(1), pp. 125.
Shusterman, R. (1998), Ravens and Writing-Desks: Sokal and the Two Cultures, Philosophy and Literature
22(1), pp. 119135.
Smith, S. (1996), Positivism and Beyond in S. Smith, K. Booth and M. Zalewski (eds.), International
Theory: Positivism and Beyond, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 1144.

2007 The Authors. Journal compilation 2007 Political Studies Association


POLITICS: 2007 VOL 27(1)

You might also like