You are on page 1of 38

chapter 8

Theology and Logology


1979

The main purpose of this long essay is to dene, illustrate, apply, and defend logology pretty much against all comers. Theology is used as a comparison and
contrast to logology and is the central concern of the essay, as it was, say, in The
Rhetoric of Religion (1961). This essay is probably the most complete on the subject of logology, how it works, what its basic assumptions are, and why it should
be taken seriously as a way of dealing with words (symbolic action) and the human
condition (which includes the realm of motion). It is a summing-up essay, which
means that there is quite a lot of repetition of material that appears in other essays
before and after this one. Burke had nished this essay by the fall of 1977 when he
came to Chicago for talks at the National Humanities Institute at the University of
Chicago, where I was a fellow. The institute typed the essay for him, and he had
made all of his corrections by the spring of 1978, when he returned to Chicago to
give a series of talks at Northwestern University that was arranged by Lee Grifn,
and featured Burkes latest denition of humans as bodies that learn language.
Nothing is more basic to late (post 1970) logology than this denition, which
replaces his old one, symbol-using animals. As Burke liked to say, you can
spin everything else from it, and he did. A distinctive human trait now becomes the intrinsic inherited species trait: the ability to learn a language, any language from the thousands that are spoken worldwide. All normal human beings have this ability to understand and speak a language, and, with training, to
read and write it. One learns the language of the tribe more or less automatically
if one is socialized and grows up where the language is spoken. No other living
species that we know of has this ability, perhaps because no others have a neural network complex enough to accomplish the feats of memory required to
learn, and learn how to use, thousands upon thousand of words in hearing,
speaking, reading, and writing. Prodigious feats of memory are characteristic of
humans in their relationship to language.
Burke is not really so interested in these feats of memory as he is in the fact
that the ability to learn and use a language is ubiquitous in humans and that language (symbolic action) has a logic (logologic?) of its own that affects every part
of our lives, the more so since the advent of the age of print technology and, later,
of radio, television, and computers. Logology is the study of words, and words
about words. Burke likes to point out that even reality is not real, rather than,
say, nature or some other nonverbal subject until it has been turned into words,
and major events (spring, love, marriage) are not complete until we have a song
or poem to go with them. We literally see with words and name everything we
see to incorporate it into the verbal realm so that we can refer to it when it is not
present and make appropriate use of it. The illiterate Indians of the Amazon
jungle have named and learned how to use hundreds of natural substances for
172

173

Theology and Logology

medicinal and other purposes. The Eskimos have a huge number of words for
every kind of snow. The Plains Indians had a language more complex than
Greek. Print technology gave us the world of books, which many of us still inhabit. We may yearn for an unmediated experience of the natural world (Burkes
realm of motion) but it is impossible, no matter what the ecocritics and ecologists tell us. We have no images that are not tainted with words. Dogs may smell
their way through the world, but we talk our way through itand beyond it.
In these matters, Burke is absolutely correct in his relentless insistence that the
way to knowledge and understanding of what it means to be human is through
words, in all of their many forms and permutations. In and through words; beyond words he once wrote. But beyond words there is nothing. God after all is
nothing but a word in logology. It is hard to imagine what could be beyond
words in logology, except nothing. Maybe a pure, powerful musical experience,
such as Beethovens last piano concerto might give us an experience beyond
words, though the second music critics or conductors or players begin to discuss
it, they have brought it into the realm of words because they have no other way
to get it out of the pure musical state it is in when we hear it.
I seem to be far aeld, but Im not. Burkes example of the air conditioner in
the movie theater is meant to illustrate how mind affects body, or what the
rhetorical properties of a lm can do. The body that learns language is also the
body that suffers from itwhat you see in the theater is nothing but images;
what you hear is nothing but words and whatever sound effects and music are
part of the movie. There is nothing real about it except that it is happening to you
as you internalize what is on the screen and what is coming from the speakers.
As Burke points out, no one is really being killed, tortured, burned, buried alive,
raped, or having an orgasm up there. There are no real bullghts in Hemingways
novels, nor is there any actual violence in Faulkners novels. However, the power
of words (and of images on the screen) is so great, and the connection between
words outside the head and words inside the head is so extensive and the neural
network is so complex that the whole body is affected by what it sees and hears.
In spite of the fact that we know it is not real, what we read and see on the screen
can make us shout, weep, laugh, close our eyes, even leave the theater or TV to
avoid any more of that experience. This interactive relationship is the eld of logology: the nature of words (symbolic action), what words can do to us, how
words behave, what we can do to and with words as bodies that learn language.
No mind without body, Burke says over and over again in discussing the realm
of symbolic action. Even inside the head, language is an embodiment and the
brain is a clutter of words. There may be 50,000 to 100,000 in there. The only
escape seems to occur when we dream, which is often wordless.
This is Burkes realm. If I go on, Ill get lost in it, lost in words about words,
lost in the logological trap. Once in there (say, in a text) how can you ever get
back out except by using more words about words? Artists painted abstract pictures and left them untitled to escape the tyranny of words. But even to call it
Untitled is to rely on words again.

***

174

Logology

foreword
There is the possibility of confusion, in connection with my use of the
term logology. Though I shall constantly be encountering occasions
where theology (as words about God) and logology (as words about
words) overlap, particularly as when logology was taken literally to
mean the Doctrine of the Logos (the reference to Christ as the Word
in the Gospel of John), in my discussion I shall be stressing the secular
meaning of the term.
Technically, each term could treat the other as of narrower scope. For
logology in the secular sense could class all sorts of isms and ologies
and many other kinds of utterance, including itself, as modes of verbal
behavior. And theology would certainly look upon any such theorizing as far less comprehensive in scope than theologys concern with the
relations between the human, word-using animal and the realm of the
supernatural.
Professor J. Hillis Miller, most notably in his essay on The Linguistic Moment in The Wreck of the Deutschland (The New Criticism and
After, edited by Thomas Daniel Young [Charlottesville: University Press
of Virginia, 1976], pp. 4760), has expertly discussed Hopkinss way of
fusing a fascination with words in general and a devotion to Christ as the
creative Logos. And when elsewhere he refers to the peculiarly precarious Feuerbachian pose which says, in effect, All the afrmations of
Christianity are true, but not as the believers believe, I thought of the
kabbalists who said that biblical references to God as though he had a
human body are not gurative; they are literal. But only God knows how
to interpret their literal meaningand the nearest we can come is by understanding them as gures of speech.
Our bodies are gestated and born in wordlessnessand out of such a
state grows the doctrinal (that is, the verbal, the scriptural even). Themselves speechless, they help us learn to speak.

i
We have heard much talk of a birth trauma, the shock of a fetus in being exiled from an Edenic realm in which it had ourished but which its
own stage of growth had begun to transform from a circle of protection
into a circle of connement. With its rst outcry after parturition it is
started on its pilgrimage as a separate organism, its sensations, its feelings of pleasure and pain, being immediately its own and none others.

Theology and Logology

175

We assume that such immediate experiences of a particular physiological organism are like the experiences of similar other organisms. But at
least they are far from identical in the sense that your pleasures and pains
are exclusively yours, and no one elses.
Whether or not the organisms radical change of condition at birth is
a trauma, a wound that leaves a deep scar, we do know that under ordinary favorable conditions the organism begins to ourish, and even so
much so that in later life the vague memories of its early years can assume an Edenic quality, presumably the material out of which myths
about a primal Golden Age can take form. And this is the stage of life
during which the infant (that is, literally the speechless human organism) learns the rudiments of an aptitude which, to our knowledge, distinguishes us from all other earthly beings: namely, language (or, more
broadly, familiarity with arbitrary, conventional symbol-systems in generalinsofar as traditions of dance, music, sculpture, painting, and so
on are also modes of such symbolic action).
But the kind of arbitrary conventional symbol-system that infants acquire in learning a tribal language differs from the other media in at least
this notable respect: It is the one best equipped to talk about itself, about
other media, and even about the vast world of motion that is wholly outside all symbol-systems, that was going on long before our particular
kind of symbol-using animal ever came into existence, that is the necessary ground of our animal existence, and that can go on eternally without us.
Rousseau tells us that our kind was born free. But that formula can
be misleading in its implications. Every infant emerges from organic infancy (speechlessness) into language during a period of total subjectionsubjection to the ministrations of higher powers, the familial
adults with whom it comes to be in what Martin Buber would call an IThou relationship. Under favorable conditions these powers are benign; sometimes they are malign; or there is an ambiguous area, inasmuch as ministrations that the powers conceive of as well-intentioned
may be interpreted otherwise by the maturing infant, since its condition
does not enable it to clearly recognize the limitations imposed upon the
higher powers which the infant conceives of as all-powerful.
The rst cry of the infant had been a purely reex action. But as the
aptitude for symbolic action develops, the child acquires a way of transforming this purely reex response into the rudiments of communication. In effect, the cry becomes a call, a way of summoning the higher
powers by supplication. In out-and-out language, it becomes a way of

176

Logology

saying Please. There we see emerging the profound relationship between religion and prayer. The Wailing Wall is not a cry of despair. The
Wailing Wall is a cry of hope. It is not the cry of Hell, as with Dantes
line, Abandon all hope, ye who enter here. The cries of Hell are eternally hopeless. But the prayers of religion are in their essence as with the
infants cries, which had become transformed from a condition of
sheerly reex expression into a plea, the very essence of prayer.
I would consider these paragraphs a logological observation about the
cradle of theology. Theology is words about God; logology is words
about words. Logology cant talk about God. It can only talk about
words for God. Logology can make no statement at all about the afterlife and the related concept of the supernatural. Logology cant either afrm or deny the existence of God. Atheism is as far from the realm
of logology as is the most orthodox of fundamentalist religions. All logology is equipped to do is discuss human relations in terms of our nature as the typically symbol-using animal. In that regard, without pronouncing about either the truth or falsity of theological doctrine,
logology does lay great emphasis upon the thought that theology, in
purely formal respects, serves as a kind of verbal grace that perfects
nature. It rounds things out, even if such fulllment happened to be
but the verbal or doctrinal completing of the pattern that the infant naturally experiences when rst learning language, and its modes of supplication in an I-Thou (familial) relationship with higher powers.
Logology involves only empirical considerations about our nature as
the symbol-using animal. But for that very reason it is fascinated by the
genius of theology; and all the more so because, through so much of our
past, theologians have been among the profoundest of our inventors in
the ways of symbolic action. Also, everywhere logology turns, it nds
more evidences of the close connection between speech and theologic
doctrine. Saint Paul tells us, for instance, that faith comes from hearing
[ex auditu], which in the last analysis amounts to saying that theology
is exactly what it calls itself etymologically, an ology. The story of
Creation in Genesis is an account of successive verbal ats (and God
said). And in the New Testament the Gospel of John tells us that in the
beginning was the Logos.
But these issues dont stop with such obvious cases as that. In my essay on Terministic Screens (Language as Symbolic Action [Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1973], pp. 4447), after having noted how
the nature of our terms affects the nature of our observations, by directing our attention in one way rather than another (hence many of the ob-

Theology and Logology

177

servations are but implications of the particular terminology in terms of


which the observations are made [46]), I turned to the formula which
Anselm had developed at great length from Isaiah 7:9 (nisi credideritis,
non intelligetis): Believe, that you may understand (crede, ut intelligas).
It is my claim that the injunction Believe, that you may understand,
has a fundamental application to the purely secular problem of terministic screens.
The logological, or terministic counterpart of Believe in the
formula would be: Pick some particular nomenclature, some one terministic screen. And for That you may understand, the counterpart
would be: That you may proceed to track down the kinds of observation implicit in the terminology you have chosen, whether your choice of
terms was deliberate or spontaneous. (47)
Or, in my The Rhetoric of Religion (On Words and the Word: Sixth
Analogy [1961; reprint edition, Berkeley and Los Angeles: University
of California Press, 1970], pp. 29ff) I have tried to show how the relation between the name and the thing named would be the Power (equals
the Father); the name would be the Wisdom (equals the Son, which the
Father generates in the sense that the thing named calls for its name);
and the two together spirate Love (equals the Holy Spirit, in the sense
that there is the perfect correspondence between the thing and its name,
and the perfect term for such correspondence or communion between
the terms would be Love).
And as for Perfection itself, the theological idea of God as the ens
perfectissimum has a striking logological analogue in the astoundingly
many ways in which terminologies set up particular conditions for the
tracking down of implications. The whole Marxist dialectic, for instance,
is so designed as to foretell fulllment in what logology would class as a
Utopian perfection, a dialectic so perfect that it is to inevitably culminate in the abolition of itself (with the withering away of the state, a
state of the political state that may be quite dubious, but that can make
claims to inevitability if we substitute for the state of the body politic the
analogous state of the human body).
In more restricted ways, the tracking down of implications towards
various perfections manifests itself in our many technological nomenclatures, each of which suggests to its particular votaries further steps
in that same direction. Such expansionist ambitions are near-innite in
their purely visionary scope; but though they have no inner principle
of self-limitation, their range of ideal development is restricted by the
ways in which they interfere with one another, including academic

178

Logology

problems to do with the allocation of funds among the various departments.


This logological principle of perfection (which I would call entelechial, restricting the Aristotelian concept of the entelechy to the
realm of nomenclature, symbolicity) can also be seen to operate in areas which we do not ordinarily associate with the idea of perfection, except in such loose usages as perfect fool or perfect villain. But its
powers along that line are terrifying. It showed up repeatedly in theological charges of heresy, in which the heretics were nearly always saddled with the same list of hateful vices. And in our day the Nazis did the
most outrageous job with perfection in that sense by the thoroughness
of their charges against the Jew. It takes very little inducement for us to
begin perfecting the characters of our opponents by the gratuitous imputation of unseemly motives. Thus, all told, in my logological denition
of humankind, I put a high rating on my clause rotten with perfection.
Satan was as perfect an entelechy in one sense as Christ was in another.
Doubtless Machiavelli was thinking along those lines when he told his
prince that, whereas one should be wary of hiring mercenaries, the way
to get the best ghters is make the war a holy war.
Language is one vast menagerie of implicationsand with each channel of such there are the makings of a corresponding fulllment proper
to its kind, a perfection in germ. For the logological study of dialectic
teaches us that there are two quite different ways of introducing the entelechial principle of perfection, thus:
1. There is the thing, bread.
2. There is the corresponding word, bread.
3. Language being such as it is, with no trouble at all I can make up
the expression, perfect bread.
4. We may disagree as to which bread could properly be called
perfect.
5. A mean man, or a dyspeptic, or a philosopher might even deny
that in this world there can be such a thing as perfect bread.
6. Nevertheless, theologians can speak of God as the ens perfectissimumand the expression perfect bread is a secular counterpart of such dialectical resources.
7. Nay more. Even if there is no such thing as perfect bread in
actuality, I can consider bread from the standpoint of perfect
bread in principle.

Theology and Logology

179

8. Here is some perfect bread; or


9. As compared with perfect bread, this bread I am offering you
is a dismal substitute; or
10. I can assure you that, humble as it is, this bread represents
perfect bread in principle. (It stands for the spirit of perfect
bread.) (Kenneth Burke, Dramatism and Development [Barre,
Massachusetts: Clark University Press, 1972], p. 59; appendix
to essay on Archetype and Entelechy.)
But the question of the relation between logology and theology also
requires that we look in another direction, namely, the question of the
relation between logology and behaviorism. A handy way to introduce
this issue is by reference to a passage in my review of Denis Donoghues
recently published admirable collection of essays, The Sovereign Ghost:
Studies in Imagination (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1976):
On going back over Coleridges Biographia Literaria, I ran across a
footnote in which with regard to the desynonymizing of the terms
imagination and fancy, he says: insofar as any such distinctions
become accepted, language itself does as it were think for us. It is a
chance remark which the structuralists would make much more of than
would either Coleridge or Donoghue. (The Sovereign Ghost by Denis
Donoghue, The New Republic 177 [September 10, 1977]: 3031)

In effect Coleridge is saying that words are doing what the theologian
would say that the mind is doing, an interesting twist inasmuch as Coleridge, in his day, was known much better for works like his theological Aids to Reexion than as a literary critic, though his works generally
had a theological cast. Yet in passing, Coleridge there hit upon a quite
strategic substitution, since the immediate context of situation in which
words are learned is the realm of nonsymbolic motion, whereas mind
is more readily associated with an ultimate supernatural ground beyond
the realm of physical and physiological motion.
Logology here is in an intermediate position between theology and behaviorism (which monistically acknowledges no qualitative difference
between a human organisms verbal and nonverbal behavior). Logology
is as dualistic in its way as theology is, since the logological distinction
between symbolic action and nonsymbolic motion is as polar as theologys distinctions between mind and body, or spirit and matter. Logology holds that persons act, whereas things but move, or are
moved. And personality in the human sense depends upon the ability

180

Logology

and opportunity to acquire an arbitrary, conventional symbol-system


such as a tribal, familial language.
However, logology need not be driven to a mentalist position when
in controversy with a behaviorist. Indeed, seizing upon a behaviorist
term, logology needs but point to the empirical distinction between verbal behavior (which logology would call symbolic action) and molecular behavior (which logology would call nonsymbolic physiologic
motion).
To adapt some comments from Western Speech (summer 1968), I
read somewhere that, when thrillers are shown in movie houses, the airconditioning plant must be accelerated, owing to the audiences increased rate of respiration, and so forth, in response to the excitement of
the ction. The ction is in the realm of symbolic action, with which
the air-conditioning plant has no relation whatever. The air conditioners behavior is in the realm of nonsymbolic motion, which relates
directly to the physical conditions produced in the theater by the bodys
nonsymbolic molecular motions correlative with the symbol-using organisms responses to the story (which as a story is wholly in the realm
of symbolism, though the sights and sounds of the story, in their role as
mere uninterpreted vibrations, are but in the realm of motion). For in the
empirical realm, no symbolic action is possible without a grounding in
motion, as words on the screen cant even be words unless they can be
seen or heard.
But logology would hold that their symbolic dimension cannot be
monistically reduced to the order of physical motion alone. Whatever the
mutation whereby our prehistoric ancestors acquired their aptitude with
symbolicity, from then on the human animal was a composite organism,
be the duality conceived in theological terms of mind and body, or in logological terms of symbolic action and nonsymbolic physiological motion. The principle of individuation was in the body, with the immediacy of its sensations. The realm of symbolism, with its many modes of
identication (family relationships, geology, history, politics, religious
doctrine, and so on), shaped the public aspects of human awareness and
personality.

ii
With Coleridges passing remark that, if a new distinction becomes generally established, in effect the corresponding words think for us, we are
at the very center of logological inquiry: the close but indeterminate re-

Theology and Logology

181

lationship between substitution and duplication. There is obvious duplication in the very fact that we have verbal parallels for nonverbal things,
processes, and relationships. There is substitution inasmuch as, given the
thing bread and the word bread, the person who asked for bread with
the proper symbol (the word for bread in that particular language) might
be given instead another symbol, the money with which to buy it. One
could spend a lifetime doing nothing more than tracking down the intricately interwoven manifestations of these two principles, which are
perhaps more accurately discussed not just as aspects, but as the very
essence, of language. For present purposes, let us cite a few such aspects
at random:
First, there are the extensions of language by analogy, what Jeremy
Bentham called ctions, a term that itself is probably a metaphorical
extension of the expression legal ctions. Terms that have a quite literal meaning as applied to physical conditions can be adapted guratively to subject matter that does not admit of such usage. For instance,
if we speak of one object as being at a certain distance from another,
our statement can be strictly literal, capable of verication by measuring
the distance. But if we speak of one persons views as being distant
from anothers, we are employing a ction which admits of no such
literal physical test. Or, in saying that a certain leaning object has an inclination of thirty degrees, we are using the term literally, in contrast
with the statement that a person has an inclination to do such-andsuch. In this connection Bentham observes that our entire vocabularies
of psychology and ethics are made up of such ctive duplicates, without which we could not talk about such matters at all. Go to the etymological origins of all such terms, and you will spot the literal images implicit in such ideas.
The relation between our sensory experience as individual speechless
physical organisms and the vast public context of symbolicity we acquire
as social beings sets up the endlessly complex conditions for such duplication as is revealed in the spontaneous use of terms for the weather as
a nomenclature for states of mind, or attitudes. And one can
glimpse how a whole magic world of human relations might develop
from that mode of duplication whereby, as one pious person fearsomely
plants a crop, another (an expert in the lore of mythic counterparts) collaborates by contributing his skill to the process, in scrupulously performing the necessary attendant ritual of a planting song (necessary
because, man being the symbol-using animal, the realm of nonsymbolic
natural motion is not completely humanized until reduced to terms of

182

Logology

symbolicity; hence spring calls for a spring song, harvest for a harvest
song; marriage, death, changes of status, and so on similarly attain their
completion when thus ritually paralleled).
The resources of duplication and substitution are revealed most
clearly of all in such mathematical operations as the use of the symbol ,
instead of 3.1416, or the internal relationships whereby 2 plus 2 can be
the same as 4 times 1. And surely mathematics began with that primal
substitution whereby, in making three marks to stand for three apples,
one also had a sign that would stand for three of anything, whereupon
ones symbol had advanced to a higher level of generalization whereby
the number itself could be operated on in its own right, without reference to any particular numbered things.
On inspecting more closely this aspect of what we might call the duplication-substitution complex, we come upon a similar usage that, at
rst glance, might seem of a quite different sort. Insofar as some particular ritual is ceremonially repeated in identical fashion on different occasions (which would also include annual seasonal occurrences, since no
two situations are identical) in effect the ritual acts as a mode of classication that abstracts from any particular occasion, just as numbers become abstracted from any one particular instance of their use. Thus, a
marriage rite is an institution whereby all sorts of couples are
processed in identical fashion. It is not like a situation where John and
Mary are consulting a marriage counselor about their particular problems. Rather, it is individualized only insofar as there is a blank space to
be lled with whatever proper names are to be included under that head
this time.
The ubiquitous resources of substitution probably attain their profoundest theological embodiment in the doctrines and rites of vicarious
sacrice. I plan to discuss later the distinctions between theological and
logological concerns with the principle of sacrice. But let us now consider the astounding thoroughness (even to the edge of paradox) with
which Christian theology developed the logological principle of substitution. Of all victims that were ever offered as redemption for the guilt
of others, surely Christ was conceived as the most perfect such substitute,
even to the extent of being perfectly abhorrent, as bearer of the worlds
sinfulness. Thus Luther said:
All the prophets saw that Christ would be the greatest brigand of all, the
greatest adulterer, thief, profaner of temples, blasphemer, and so on, that
there would never be a greater in all the world. . . . God sent his only
begotten Son into the world, and laid all sins upon him, saying: You are to

Theology and Logology

183

be Peter the denier, Paul the persecutor, blasphemer, and wild beast, David
the adulterer, you are to be the sinner who ate the apple in the Garden of
Eden, you are to be the crucied thief, you are to be the person who
commits all the sins in the world. (I translate from Leon Chestov,
Kierkegaard et la philosophie existentielle [Paris: Vrin, 1948].)

Thus, in terms of the specically Christian logology, the most perfect divine Logos also became the perfect end, in serving as the substitute vessel for the guilt of all.
With regard to the vexing issue of the relation between words and
mind (whereby some nomenclatures would substitute words for
mind, as per the tangential remark we have cited from Coleridge), before moving on to other aspects of our subject we should consider J. Hillis
Millers ingenious and penetrating essay The Linguistic Moment in The
Wreck of the Deutschland. This essay is particularly relevant since
Hopkinss exceptional involvement in strictly logological concerns is so
strikingly interwoven with the most poignant of theological devotions.
Miller here notes three apparently incompatible theories of poetry . . .
each brilliantly worked out in theory and exemplied in practice:
Poetry may be the representation of the interlocked chiming of created
things in their relation to the Creation. This chiming makes the pied beauty
of nature. Poetry may explore or express the solitary adventures of the self
in its wrestles with God or in its fall into the abyss outside God. Poetry may
explore the intricate relationships among words. These three seemingly
diverse theories of poetry are harmonized by the application to them all of a
linguistic model. This model is based on the idea that all words rhyme
because they are ultimately derived from the same Logos. Nature is words,
expression, news of God (Sermons, 129), and God has inscribed himself in
nature. The structure of nature in its relation to God is like the structure of
language in relation to the Logos, the divine Word; and Christ is the Logos
of nature, as of words. (4748)

Coleridge, when commenting on how words can think for us, and
noting that the two words imagination and fancy (the one from the
Latin, the other from the Greek) were often used synonymously, proposed to desynonymize them, so that they would have different meanings. But Hopkins proceeded in the other direction; he let the word Logos think for him by refusing to distinguish between its secular meaning
as a word for word and its meaning in Christian theology, where the
New Testament word for Christ was the Word. Hopkinss thinking
could not possibly have been as it was had those early sectaries, the Alogians, succeeded in their attempts to exclude the Gospel of John and

184

Logology

Revelations from the Christian canon because in both texts Christ was
referred to as the Logos.
Saint Augustine had in effect desynonymized the two usages by explicitly referring to his conversion from his career as a pagan rhetorician (a
peddler of words, venditor verborum) to a preacher of the Christian
Word. But he had also Christianized the very beginning of the Old Testament by noting that Gods successive acts of Creation had been done
through the Word (when he had said, Let there be . . .)and thus in
effect the Creation was done by the Fathers Word, which was the Son.
Miller begins his essay: By linguistic moment I mean the moment
when language as such, the means of representation in literature, becomes a matter to be interrogated, explored, thematized in itself (47).
While his engrossing study of what B. F. Skinner might call Hopkinss
verbal behavior is essentially logological, the very fact of Hopkinss refusal to desynonymize the two usages keeps the study of the linguistic moment constantly infused with the theological implications of
Hopkinss poetics.
As might be expected, variations on the theme of duplication and
repetition are plentiful; even talk of a primal bifurcation is a signal
to look for ways of tying the issue in with the distinction between speechless nonsymbolic physiological motion (analogous to the traditional
terms, matter or body) and the publicly infused realm of symbolic
action (analogous to the traditional terms, spirit or mind). In this
connection Miller has a footnote which succinctly bears upon polar
aspects of the human being as a dualistic, composite individual, in
contrast with the monistic assumptions of behaviorism, which denies
any qualitative distinction between verbal behavior and nonverbal behavior (in brief, it thinks by refusing to desynonymize the term behavior). Referring to an admirable passage in Hopkinss commentary
on The Spiritual Exercises of Saint Ignatius, Miller quotes:
And this [my isolation] is much more true when we consider the mind;
when I consider my selfbeing, my consciousness and feeling of myself,
that taste of myself, of I and me above and in all things, which is more
distinctive than the taste of ale or alum, more distinctive than the smell
of walnutleaf or camphor, and is incommunicable by any means to
another man. (47)

In my view of logological dualism (which Hopkins comes close to replacing with a monism exactly the reverse of the behaviorists, insofar as
Hopkins would reduce everything to terms of the universal Logos) the

Theology and Logology

185

linguistic moment proclaimed by that resonant sentence implicitly


pronounces the principle of inscape in what are essentially problematical terms. The selfhood of a Catholic priest must obviously be
grounded in Catholic doctrine, which is necessarily spiritual, on the
side of what logology would call public symbolicity. But he expresses
the sense of his separate identity in terms of immediate sensation, which
is in the realm of the individuals sheer physiology.
True, poets have traditionally used the terminology of sensation to
give the feel of the internal immediacy that Hopkins aims to suggest. And
there is no good reason for denying poets such a time-honored rhetorical device. I am but pointing out that the essential polarity or duality of
the human condition is not actually bridged (it cant be) but is stylistically denied. The mode of expression is thus in effect a linguistic element that represses an explicit statement of the case. Whereupon the
return of the repressed reveals itself in the person of Hopkins himself
as the wreck with which the poem starts out (signicant timing!) by
being explicitly and exclusively concerned.
The rst ve stanzas are in the form of an I-Thou prayer. Forty lines
in all, there are nineteen cognates of the rst-person pronoun, fourteen
of the second. The second half of the rst part is transitional, in that the
pronouns move farther off (rst-person plural and third-person singular). The second part, two-thirds of the poem, is built explicitly around
the wreck of the Deutschland, a pied name if there ever was one (O
Deutschland, double a desperate name!as the home of both the nun
Gertrude, Christs lily, and the beast, Luther). With regard to the
poem as a structure, we could say that it transforms the pied nature
of the poets personal problems into the grander interwoven ambivalences of sinking and salvation.
At the end of the essay Miller adds a footnote:
Kenneth Burke, in remarks about this paper after its presentation at the
Ransom Symposium at Kenyon College in April of 1975, argued that I
should add something about the multiple meaning of the word wreck in the
title. The poem, he said, is about Hopkinss wreck. This was a powerful plea
to relate the linguistic complexities, or tensions, back to their subjective
counterparts. Much is at stake here. That the poem is a deeply personal
document there can be no doubt. Its linguistic tensions are lived, not mere
verbal play in the negative sense. . . . In The Wreck of the Deutschland
Hopkins is speaking of his own wreck. . . . The danger in Burkes suggestion, however, is, as always, the possibility of a psychologizing reduction,
the making of literature into no more than a reection or representation of
something psychic which precedes it and which could exist without it. . . .

186

Logology

Subjectivity, I am arguing, with all its intensities, is more a result than an


origin. To set it rst, to make an explanatory principle of it, is, as Nietzsche
says, a metalepsis, putting late before early, effect before cause. (5960n)

I wrote Miller, calling attention to the closing paragraph of an essay by


me concerning Keatss Ode on a Grecian Urn (Symbolic Action in a
Poem by Keats, A Grammar of Motives [1945; reprint edition, Berkeley
and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1969], pp. 44763). In
that essay I had noted respects in which traces of the symptoms of the disease he was to die of manifested themselves. But I added this qualication:
We may contrast this discussion with explanations such as a materialist of
the Kretschmer school might offer. I refer to accounts of motivation that
might treat disease as cause and poem as effect. In such accounts, the
disease would not be passive, but wholly active; and what we have called
the mental action would be wholly passive, hardly more than an epiphenomenon, a mere symptom of the disease quite as are the fever and the chill
themselves. Such accounts would give us no conception of the essential
matter here, the intense linguistic activity. (46268)

In that last paragraph, I wrote Miller, At least I say Im not doing


exactly what you say I am doing. Then I added: However, Ill meet
you halfway. I think the relation between the physiology of disease and
the symbolic action of poetry can be of the vicious circle sort. Ones poetizing, in the very act of transcending hints got from the bodys passions,
can roundabout reinforce the ravages of such sufferings. I had in mind
here such a reexive process (I guess current cant would call it feedback) as the role of psychogenic asthma in Prousts search for essence
by the remembrance of things past.1

iii
Let us now list some cases the discussion of which might most directly
help us inquire, by comparison and contrast, into words about the divine, the supernatural (theology), and words about words (logology), including words for the divine and supernatural, whether or not there be
such a realm, which theologies have words for.
Since theology in our tradition is so clearly grounded in the relation
between the Old Testament and the New, lets begin logologically from
there. The formula of the Christian theologians was stated thus: Novum
Testamentum in Vetere latet, Vetus in Novo patet. How translate it exactly? The New Testament was latent in the Old Testament. The Old

Theology and Logology

187

Testament becomes patent in the New Testament. Or The implications of the Old Testament became explicitly manifest in the New Testament. It was a way of both letting the Jews in and keeping them out,
unless they became converted or, like an old Testament patriarch, each
had been an anima naturaliter Christiana; I forget whether Socrates was
adjudged such, but his association with the symbolic action of Platonism
might well include him, for his Hellenic contribution to the cult of Logos that the early Alogian Christians wanted to rule out.
In any case, the Christian theology, with regard to the relation between Old Testament and New Testament, would see in the Old Testament many stories about characters that were conceived as what they
were only insofar as they were types of Christ. Indeed, the Jewish tribe
itself, in its Exodus from Egypt, was but a type of Christ. Thus its Jewish identity was, in effect (in principle), being viewed not as that of a tribe
in its own right, but as an emergent stage of the Christian future.
Exactly, then, what does logology, as a purely secular cult of the Logos, do with that particular localization of dialectical resources? Obviously, the Old Testament story of Abraham and Isaac (telling of how the
father, in obedience to Gods Law, would consent to sacrice even his
most beloved person, his son) can be conceived of as incipiently, prophetically a type of the New Testament story of an all-powerful Father, the
very soul of justice, who actually does fulll the pattern, in completing
the sacrice of his most precious person, his only begotten Son. And logology looks upon both stories as variations on the theme of sacrice.
In my early scattered readings among mediaeval texts, I found a sentence that fascinated me. It was probably a rule of some monastic order,
I dont know which. And though I have lost track of the original, I still
incline to go on repeating my translation, which is as resonant as I could
make it: If any one have any thing of which he is especially fond, let it
be taken from him. There is even the ironic possibility that I got the
Latin somewhere from Remy de Gourmont, a nonbeliever if there ever
was one; and he taught me to appreciate, in a kind of twisted nostalgia,
the forlorn fragmentary beauty of such accents. The fantastically materialistic George Santayanas gallant Realm of Spirit is also in that
groove.
But the main consideration, from the standpoint of logology, is the
fact that, however variously theologians may treat of the relation between the Old Testament and the New Testament, they have in common
the theological stress upon the principle of sacrice. As viewed from the
standpoint of logology, even the most primitive offering of animals on

188

Logology

the altar can be equated with the Crucixion of Christ insofar as any and
all such rites embody the principle of sacrice (which, given the ubiquitous logological resources of substitution, turns out to be synonymous
with vicarious sacrice).
As viewed logologically, the theological story of the Creation and the
Fall (in the opening chapter of Genesis) would be summed up thus:
The story of Creation, in representing the principle of Order, necessarily introduced a principle of Division, classifying some things as distinct from other things. In this purely technical sense, Creation itself was
a kind of Fall, inasmuch as it divided the principle of Unity into parts,
each of which has a nature of its own, regardless of how they might in
principle be unied. (As seen from this point of view, even a project
for unication implies a grammatical gerundive, a to-be-unied.)
Thus, viewed from the other side, the orderly principle of Division is seen
to contain implicitly the possibility of Divisiveness.
The possibility of Divisiveness calls for a Law against Divisiveness.
(In a world set up by the creative word, how keep Division from becoming Divisive except by a word, a Law, that says, Dont do whatever
would disrupt the Order?) So the story includes a dont that, stories
of that sort being what they are, stands for the sheer principle of Law,
as the negative aspect of Order. But implicit in the idea of Dont there
is the possibility of Disobedience. One says, Do or Dont only to
such kinds of entities as can be able to respond (that is, can have the responsibility) by in effect saying, Yes or No (that is, being obedient
or disobedient).
But Saint Pauls theology was quite in keeping with logology when he
said that the Law made sin, as Bentham was to say that the Law makes
crime. However, note that, in introducing, via Law, the possibility of
Disobedience, one has by implication introduced the principle of Temptation (the incentive, however originating, to fall afoul of the Law).
Where, then, locate the origin of that Temptation, as bets the nature
of narrative (story, myth)?
At this point, the implications of terms for Law and Order surface by
translation into terms of role. These are two kinds of priority. There
is logical priority in the sense of rst premise, second premise, conclusion. Or in the sense that the name for a class of particulars is prior to
any particular included under that head, quite as the term table already anticipates the inclusion of countless particular objects that
dont even yet exist. Or there is temporal priority in the sequence
yesterday-today-tomorrow.

Theology and Logology

189

As a result of this doubling, one can state matters of principle (that is,
rsts or beginnings) in terms of either logical or temporal priority.
(Hence in my Rhetoric of Religion I put major emphasis upon the etymological fact that both the Greek and Latin words for principle
[arch and principium] refer to priority in both the logical and temporal
senses of the term.) I said somewhere (I think in my Grammar of Motives, but I cant locate it) that a Spinozistic translation of the rst words
in the Vulgate Bible, In principio Deus creavit, would be not in the
beginning God created, but in principle God created For his basic
equation, Deus sive Natura, amounts exactly to that, since he would
never associate the words God and nature in terms of a temporal
priority whereby God came rst in time. Though such equating of
God and nature was pantheistic, hence anathema, in its sheer design it
resembled the thinking of those Orthodox Christians who attacked Arianism by insisting that the priority of Father to Son was not in any
sense temporal. We here confront a purely logological kind of priority,
as we might well say that the number 1 is prior to any other number,
but only in principle; for no number in time is prior to any other,
since an internal relationship among numbers is nontemporal. Before
numbers were, 3 was less than 4 and more than 2, though we can go
from one such to another. And logologically we confront an analogous
situation with regard to the narrative or mythic translation of nontemporal implications among terms into terms of story, as with the narrative ways of stating the principles of Order in the rst three chapters
of Genesis, under primal conditions involving an audience for whom
the poetic ways of story came rst; however, such expressions were later
to be sophisticated by the traumatic step from poetry and mythology
to criticism and critically mature theology.
The Old Testament begins in its way quite as the New Testament
Gospel of John begins in its, with pronouncements that overlap upon
these two kinds of priority. Genesis tells the story of the divine words
informative power. John tells the story of the Logos, a Hellenistic stress
upon the word that a Judaizing sect among the emergent Christian
doctrinarians had unsuccessfully attempted to exclude from the canon.
Hence, though the term in English seems to have begun by reference to
the Logos in the Gospel of John (a usage that is ambiguously implicit in
these present shuttlings between theology and logology), both the Book
of Genesis and the Gospel of John present their cases in terms of story.
And we now take on from there.
Logologically, we confront the fact that, given the uid relation between

190

Logology

logical and temporal priority, the logical rstness of principles, when


stated in the ways of story (mythos), as with the opening chapters of
Genesis, calls for translation into terms of temporal priority. Thus the
narrative way of saying what Saint Paul had in mind when saying that
the Law made sin and Bentham when he said that the Law made crime
was to say that the rst human being sinned against the rst Law decreed
by the rst and foremost Law-giver.
The principle of the Law, implicit in the principle of Order, is identical with an astounding seiendes Unding that human language has added
to nature, the negative (a purely linguistic invention unknown to the
world of sheer wordless motion, which can be but what it positively is).
Thus, implicit in the legal negative, the thou shalt not of the Law
(which, the story of Beginnings tell us, was born with the creation of
worldly order) is the possibility that its negativity can be extended to the
negating of negativity. There is thus the responsibility of being able to
say no to a thou-shalt-not.
But the tactics of narrative personalizing (in effect a kind of substitution that represents a principle in terms of a prince) raise a problem local to that particular mode of representation itself. If this kind of rst
is to represent the possibility of disobedience that is implicit in the decreeing of a Law, where did the temptation to disobedience come
from? Up to this point, we have been trying to show that a logological
analysis of the case would coincide with a theological presentation, in
that theology has said implicitly what logology says explicitly; namely,
the conditions of the Fall were inherent in the conditions of the Creation,
since the Divisiveness of Order was reinforced by the divisive possibility
of saying either Yes or No to the primal Law of that Order.
However, the sheer psychology of personality is such that an act of
disobedience is but the culminating stage of an inclination to disobey, a
guilty disobedient attitude. And where did that prior step, the emergent
temptation to disobey, originate? Here theologys concern with the
sources of such an attitude introduces a causal chain that turns out to involve a quite different provenance.
Eve was the immediate temptress. But she had been tempted by the
serpent. But the serpent was not entelechially perfect enough to be the
starting place for so comprehensive, so universal (so catholic) a theological summation. The principle of substitution gets perfect embodiment here in that the serpent becomes in turn the surrogate for Satan,
the supernatural tempter beyond which no further personal source of
temptation need be imagined, since his personality and his role as ulti-

Theology and Logology

191

mate tempter were identical, in such total consistency that this supreme
light-bearing angel was the most thorough victim of his own vocation.

iv
In his epic, Paradise Lost, Milton turns that story into a further story. Beginning with theologys search for the grandest personalized source of
temptation, Milton reverses the mode of derivation as we have traced it
logologically. Thus, whereas logologically the story of the revolt in
Heaven would be derived from motivational ambiguities whereby the
eventuality of the Fall was implicit in the conditions of the Creation, Miltons theological route would proceed from the revolt in Heaven to the
Fall, and consequent expulsion from the Garden.
Although there are many respects in which logology and theology are
analogous (respects in which the two usages, words about words and
words about the Logos, can go along in parallel) there are also the many
occasions when, as we have here been noting, they will unfold a series of
interrelated terms in exactly the reverse order. A good example is a creation myth that I learned of from Malinowski (compare Language as
Symbolic Action, pp. 36465n).
According to this myth, the tribe is descended from a race of supernatural ancestors (in this case, subterranean ancestors, since their original ancestors were thought to have lived underground). These mythic ancestors
had a social order identical with the social order of the tribe now. When
they came to the surface, they preserved the same social order, which has
been handed down from then to now. In this case, obviously, whereas conditions now are mythologically derived from imputed primal conditions
then, logologically the mythic imputing of such primal conditions
then would be derived from the nature of conditions now. (I hope later
to discuss respects in which we might distinguish between mythology and
theology; but in a case of this sort they are analogous with regard to their
difference from logological derivation. And they have the advantage of
providing much simpler examples, at least as usually reported. Also, their
polytheistic aspect makes them much easier to rationalize than the ways
of the single all-powerful personal God of monotheistic theology, who tolerates so much that seems to us intolerable. Since logology makes no judgment at all about the truth or falsity of theologic doctrine, its only task is
to study how, given the nature of symbolism, such modes of placement are
logologically derivable from the nature of symbolic action.)
Logologically considered, the issue may be reduced to the matter of

192

Logology

the negative, another aspect of the condition that arose in the story of the
Creation when God introduced the thou shalt not of the Law. Implicit
in the negative is the possibility of polar terms which bear a timeless relationship to each other. This relationship is timeless in the sense that
although, with polar terms like order and disorder, each implies the
other, their relationship doesnt involve a temporal step from one to the
other. But the supernatural realm of eternity is timeless. And Heaven was
the realm of timeless perfect order. But inasmuch as the genius of the
negative makes such terms as order and perfection polar, so far as
such terms were concerned they contained the timeless implication of
their contrasting term. Also, there are two kinds of polar negative: the
propositional (is, isnt), the hortatory (do, dont). And they tend to
lose their initial distinctness.
Myth, story, narrative makes it possible to transform this timeless relation between polar terms into a temporal sequence. That is, myth can
tell of a step from either one to the other. Thus, with regard to the perfection of Heaven outside of time, the resources of narrative made it possible to carry out the implications of polar terms such as order and
perfection by such stories as the revolt of Lucifer in Heaven. And the
timeless nature of such polarity is maintained eternally in the unending
establishment of Heaven and Hell, the one all Yes, the other all No.
Polytheistic myths didnt have the acute problems with this terministic situation that monistic theology has. Joseph Fontenroses volume
Python: A Study of Delphic Myth and Its Origins (New York: Biblo &
Tannen, 1959; which I use as the basis of my essay Myth, Poetry, and
Philosophy, reprinted in my Language as Symbolic Action), takes as its
point of departure the myth of the combat between Apollo and Python,
then extends the discussion to two main types in general. There is a late
type, concerning a struggle between an older god and a new god,
with the new god triumphing and founding a cult. But this is said to be
derived from an earlier type, concerning a struggle between a dragon and
a sky-god, with the sky-god triumphing.
In such cases, the principle of negation in polar terms can accommodate itself easily to such stories of personal combat. Also, the timeless nature of the negative in such terms can be preserved, since the vanquished
combatant, though slain, is yet somehow still surviving, like Typhon
buried by Zeus beneath Sicily and fuming through Aetna, with the constant threat that he may again rise in revolt. Or the two may reign in succession, the vanquished principle taking over periodically, for a season.
Or under certain conditions the opposition can be translated into terms

Theology and Logology

193

more like cooperation, with both powers or principles being necessary


to make a world, whereby the principle becomes itself a species of order,
too. Even the kingdom of Darkness is not just a rebellion against Light,
but has its own modes of organization. Polytheistic mythology could
thus readily accommodate temples to rival gods, for there was general
agreement that all such powers should be propitiated. And the meaner
they were, the more reason there was to appease them with cult.
In transforming these resources of polytheistic myth, monistic theology
encounters many serious embarrassments. And some years back, when I
happened to be dealing with some of my logological speculations in a seminar at Drew University, William Empsons polemical volume Miltons
God (London: Chatto & Windus, 1965) came along. Obviously, Empson
had decided to play the role of a very bad boy. But what interested me in
the book was the fact that its quarrels with Miltons theology would serve
so well to help point up my neutral concerns with logology.
As judged from the logological point of view, there is no combat
among terms. In my Rhetoric of Religion, the Cycle of Terms Implicit
in the Idea of Order is a set of mutually interrelated terms which simply imply one another. Though terms can confront each other as antithetically as reward and punishment, nothing happens until they
are given functions in an irreversible, personalized narrative. Terms like
disorder, temptation, disobedience come to life when Adam is
assigned the role of personally representing the principle of sin, and Satan is assigned the role of ultimate tempter. God has the role of setting
up the Order and giving the critical negative order, so terministically necessary before a Fall can even be possible.
There is no one strict way to select the cycle of terms for such a
chart. In general, the ones I suggest are quite characteristic of the theological tradition for the discussion of which I am offering a pragmatically
designed pattern (with, behind it or within it, thoughts on the strategic
interwoven difference between temporal priority and logical priority, the
distinction itself being logological).
The interesting twist involves the way in which supernatural timelessness parallels logological timelessness, with both becoming mythologized (that is, translated into terms of a temporally irreversible story,
along with an ambiguity whereby history can be viewed as both in time
and in principle, for instance when Christs Crucixion is both said to
have happened historically once, and to be going on still, in principle).
Thus, quite as Orthodox Christian theology would condemn Arianism
because it treated the Sons coming after the Father in a temporal sequence,

194

Logology

whereas the Fathers priority was but such in principle, so logology would
point out that there can be no temporal priority between two such terms.
The very relationship that makes a son a son is, by the same token, the
relationship that makes a father a father. Thus, in effect, the Father can
but generate the Son in principle.
Looking upon both mythology and theology as involved in the problem of translating supernatural timeless relationships into terms of
temporal sequence, logology tentatively views monotheism as in various
ways struggling to perfect the simpler rationales of polytheism while
still deeply involved in the same ultimate motivational quandaries. But
logology approaches the matter this way: If you talk about local or tribal
divinities, you are on the slope of polytheism. If, instead, you talk about
the divine in general, lo! you are on the slope of monotheism. (On pp.
4069 of my Language as Symbolic Action, in the article I have mentioned on Myth, Poetry, and Philosophy, I list several ways in which
polytheism verbally behaved in this situation. And I do think that on
page 408, with regard to my point about the divine, I stumbled into a
real surprise, though my inadequacies as a scholar make me fear that
something may have gone wrong with my Greek.)
In any case, logology quotes this passage from a letter of Saint Ambrose:
The devil had reduced the human race to a perpetual captivity, a cruel
usury laid on a guilty inheritance whose debt-burdened progenitor had
transmitted it to his posterity by a succession drained by usury. The Lord
Jesus came; He offered His own death as a ransom for the death of all; He
shed His own Blood for the blood of all. (Drawn up by His Eminence Peter
Cardinal Gasparri, The Catholic Catechism, translated by Reverend Hugh
Pope [New York: P. J. Kennedy & Sons], p. 291)

Logology tends to see in such statements vestiges of the transitional


stage from polytheism to monotheism when the pagan gods were viewed
not as mere gments of the imagination but as actually existent demons.
You pay such high ransom only to someone who has terric power over
you, not to someone to whom you needed but to say, Be gone for
good, and hed be gone for good. Logology leaves it for the scruples of
theology to work out exactly why that damned nuisance has to be put
up with, by an all-powerful Ordainer of all Order. Logologys only contribution to the cause is the reminder that, to our knowledge, the Law,
be it Saint Pauls kind or Benthams, is the owering of that humanly, humanely, humanistically, and brutally inhumanely ingenious addition to
wordless nature, the negative, without which a gure like Satan would

Theology and Logology

195

be logologically impossible, as also it would be impossible to put next to


a live wire a sign saying: Danger, dont touch. Could even Heaven be
possible, if not dened by reference to its polar contradictory, Hell? I
have quoted from Fritz Mauthners Wrterbuch der Philosophie: Die
Bejahung ist erst die Verneinung einer Verneinung (Language as Symbolic Action, A Dramatistic View of the Origins of Language and Postscripts on the Negative, p. 419). On the same page, from Dictionnaire
des Sciences Philosophiques: Le nant nest quun mot, but think what
it has looked like, with being grounded in non-being.
But lets sample a few of the problems that turn up with Miltons theological treatment of some logological situations:
Praise is a basic freedom of speech. There is great exhilaration in
being able to praise, since praise is on the same slope as love. But what
of God, as the august recipient of praise? Is He to be a veritable glutton
for attery, with jealous signs of a Jehovah complex?
However, the principle of hierarchy so intrinsic to Order, and formally perfected in the orders of Thrones, Dominations, Princedoms,
Virtues, Powers, could work well in one notable respect. For thus Satans
revolt could be treated as motivation for the obedient revolt of the angels immediately under him. They were loyal to their local leader.
If God in His omnipotence lets the battle rage indecisively for quite
some time whereas He could have stopped it the moment it began, there
arises the question whether He is as powerful as He is supposed to be,
or is cruel. Yet if Milton disposed of the problem from the start, where
would the epic be? Under the conditions of polytheism the ght can go
on; Fontenrose codies the stages that can be protracted ad libitum; for
both combatants are mighty powers in conict. But under monotheism
there is but one power whose word is power in the absolute, except for
the one logological embarrassment that, implicit in polar terms, there is
a timeless principle of negativity which not only warns against the wiles
of Satan, but creates the need for Satan. The dragging out of the battle is
not a theological matter. As The Iliad shows, thats the only way you can
write an epic.
Empson seizes upon the notion of the Fortunate Fall as a way of indicting the Father on the ground that it proves Adams Fall to have been
in the cards from the start and thus to have involved the collusion of
God. But as regards the logology of the case, Adams fall was in the cards
from the start in the sense that his task, as the rst man, was to represent the principle of disobedience that was implicit in the possibility of
saying no to the rst thou shalt not. The only way for the story aspect

196

Logology

of theology to say that the Law made sin is by translating the statement
of such principles into temporal terms. Theologically, as a private person, Adam didnt have to sin. But logologically, if he hadnt, the whole
rationale of the Bible would have been in ruins. By the logologic of the
case, he had a task to perform that only the rst man could be principled enough to perform. Eve couldnt do it. She could but serve as a
temptress. For it was a patriarchal culture, and such original sin could
only be established through the male line.
There was a Patripassian heresy that thought of the one God as offering himself for the redemption of mankind. But the Trinitarian relation between Father and Son allows for a divine self-sacrice without Patripassianism. Empson considers the same grammar without benet of
logology but in his bad-boy method thus: What Milton is thinking has
to be: God couldnt have been satised by torturing himself to death, not
if I know God; you could never have bought him off with that money;
he could only have been satised by torturing someone else to death.
There is quite a bit more of such discussion in the pages Words Anent
Logology I sent to the members of the class by way of a post mortem
on our seminar, later published in Perspectives in Literary Symbolism,
edited by Joseph Strelka (University Park: Pennsylvania State University
Press, 1968, pp. 7282). But this should be enough to indicate the relation between theology and logology as revealed by Empsons somewhat
naively nonlogological treatment of Miltons theological narrative.

v
A somewhat oversimplied pattern might serve best to indicate the drift
of these speculations. Ideally postulate a tribe of pronouncedly homogeneous nature. Its cultural identity has developed under relatively autonomous conditions. That is, its contacts with other tribes have been
minimal, so that its institutions have taken shape predominantly in response to the local material circumstances on which it depends for its
livelihood.
The tribes poetry and myths would thus emerge out of situations with
which the members of the tribe had become familiar in their gradual
transformation from wholly dependent speechless organisms, through
successive institutionally inuenced stages along the way to maturity and
death, a major aspect of such institutions being the role of the tribal language in shaping the sense of individual and group identity. In this connection I would place great stress upon the notion that, though the tribes

Theology and Logology

197

language and myths were largely the work of adult experiences, usages,
and imaginings, they retained the vestiges of their magical origins. Important among these would be the childs experiences as living among
higher powers. The proportion of child to adult would thus be mythologically duplicated in the proportion of adult to supernatural beings,
in a realm also associated with the idea of death (a frequent synonym for
which, thanks to the genius of the negative, is immortality).
The closeness of the relation between poetry and mythology is clearly
attested by the long tradition of Western literary interest in myths of
the Greeks. Myths are grounded in beliefs. And beliefs are myths to
whoever doesnt believe them. And the step from poetry to criticism
takes over to the extent that the conditions under which our hypothetical tribes body of poetry and mythology took form have become notably altered.
One can imagine various such inducements. The tribes internal development may have introduced new problems (as with the heightening
of social inequities). Climatic changes or invasion may cause migration.
The tribe may become much more closely associated with some other
tribe (by becoming a colony of some imperial power, for instance, or by
becoming an imperial power itself). And insofar as the voice of criticism
replaces the era of poetry, there is a corresponding step from mythology
to theology. At least such is the obvious case with regard to both Jewish
and Christian theology, which developed controversially (as monotheism versus pagan polytheism), and with tense involvement in problems
of empire that radically modied the possibilities of purely internal
tribal development. But theology as I would place it still does tie in
closely with the aspect of mythology that shared the poetic sense of origins in the experiences of childhood, even to the stage when the speechless human organism was but getting the rst inklings of the ways with
verbal utterance.
Also, its quite likely that a development purely internal to the medium
can favor a great stress upon criticism. The incentives to criticism increase
with the invention of writing, and its doubtful whether criticism could
ever realize its fullest potentialities without the acutely anatomical kind
of observation that the written version of a work makes possible. At least,
after our long reliance on the written or printed text, our reliance on the
record has probably hobbled our memory to the point that, whereas a
grounding in primitive illiteracy is in all likelihood the best condition for
poetry, criticism must write things down, the better to check on all the
subtleties of interrelationships among the parts of a text. Yet, although in

198

Logology

that respect logology is always much more at home with a text than not,
it must constantly admonish itself regarding the limitations of a text as the
adequate presentation of a symbolic act, and as instructions for the reader
to reenact it. In comparison with a well-edited musical score, for instance,
the literary text when considered as instructions for performance is seen
to be quite decient. And think how impoverished the text of a drama is,
when viewed as instructions for the reader to reenact it in his imagination.
But what then, in sum, is logology, in relation to poetry, criticism,
mythology, theology, and the possible relation that they all have to the
realm of nonsymbolic motion in which all such forms of symbolic action
are empirically grounded? (That is to say, regardless of whether theology
is right or wrong, it is propounded by biological organisms that can
themselves propound anything only so long as they are physically alive,
hence capable of motion.) Whatever a theologian may be in some supernatural realm, empirically he cant be a theologian except insofar as his
symbolizings are enacted through the medium of a bodyand logology
begins (and also necessarily ends) with questions about his nature thus.
Logology relates to all ologies in asking, as its rst question, What
all is going on, when someone says or reads a sentence? There are some
things going on, with relation to the specic subject matter of the sentence. And behind or beyond or within that, there are the kinds of
processes and relationships that are involved in the saying or understanding of any sentence. That approach to the subject in general sets up
logologys rst question, which necessarily puts the logologer on the uncomfortable fringes of all the answers to all specic questions. It must
start from the fact that logologys rst question is a variant of the prime
Socratic question, the questioning of itself, and of its relation to nature
(whereby it becomes the purely technical analogue of the theologians
grace that perfects but does not abolish the realm of natures
speechlessness).
Even at the risk of resorting somewhat to the mythical, lets end by
surveying the eld thus, as it looks in terms of logology:
First, although in many respects the speculations of logology bring us
much closer to behaviorism than is naturally the case with inquiries
into the nature of the word, there is one total, unyielding opposition. Behaviorism is essentially monistic, in assuming that the difference between
verbal behavior and nonverbal behavior (logology would call it a distinction between symbolic action and nonsymbolic motion) is but a manner of degree. But logology is dualistically vowed to the assumption that
we here confront a difference in kind. Hence, it puts primary stress upon

Theology and Logology

199

duplication, polarity, negation (and countless variations of such) as


the very soul of logological inquiry.
And where do such modes of duplication come from? In our nature
as sheerly physiological organisms there is the bisymmetry of the body,
there are the modes of reciprocating motion (systole and diastole of the
heart, the rhythm of respiration, the alternations and compensatory balances of walking). And in a vague way the gist of what Newton summed
up in his third Law of motion, To every action there is always an equal
and opposite reaction, is experienced to the extent that an organism
must sense the difference in alterity between pushing a reed and colliding with a stone.
But a whole further realm of duplication arises from the nature of discourse as a reection of the nonlinguistic situations in which the human organisms prowess with language is acquired. This is the kind of
duplication that shows up most obviously in the critical difference between a physical thing and its corresponding name.
Further, by the nature of language such parallels (completed in the
relation between spring and a spring song, or between the physical
process of planting and a ritual designed to accompany such a process)
inevitably give rise to a vast realm of duplication due to the fact that
analogy is implicit in the application of the same terms when referring
to different situationsand all actual situations are different insofar as
no two such situations are identical in their details. Such idealization,
at the very roots of the classifying function intrinsic to the repeated application of the same terms to different conditions (a property of speech
without which no natural language could take form or be learned), itself
involves an endlessly repeatable act of duplication.
This analogical aspect of language thus sets up possibilities of further
development in its own right, making for the ctive range of identications and implications and substitutions which add up to the vast complexities of the world as we know it. It becomes a realm in its own right
and essentially anthropocentric, in being verbally amplied by our
isms and ologies and mathematical reductions (all instances par excellence of specically human inventions in the realm of symbolic action).
Such resources can become so highly developed out of themselves, by
analogical extension and the duplication of such analogies in corresponding material implements and techniques, that the process of duplication can become paradoxically reversed, as in Platos theory of imitation. By this twist things are said to imitate the ideas (logology
would call them the class names) which we apply to them, hence in

200

Logology

terms of which we can be said to conceive of them. Here stating thoughts


of essence in terms of quasi-temporal priority, Platonism concluded
that the ideas or forms (that is, the class names) for the particular
existent things of our empirical, everyday world must have been experienced in a supernatural realm prior to their imperfect imitation that
we see all about us.
As viewed logologically, such forms are prior in the sense that
the name for any class of objects can be viewed as logically prior to
the particulars classed under that head. And any particular can be called
an imperfect instance of that class name, because such a word (and its
idea) is not a thing, but a blank to be lled out by a denition, which
wouldnt be a thing in that sense. Yet no particular thing could perfectly
represent the denition. To take Platos example: There is not one bed
which you could point to and say, Thats bed. Nor could any of the
countless other beds, variously different in their particulars from one another, and many of them not even made yet, be selected as the bed. You
could say, Thats a bed, but not just bed or the bed. Incidentally,
though you could thus use an indenite article, Plato couldnt; for there
is no such grammatical particle in his Greek.
That impinges upon another realm of speculation in which logology
is properly much interested. Consider the scholastic formula Nihil in intellectu quod non prius in sensu. There is nothing in the realm of understanding which did not begin in the realm of the senses. Obviously, we
are there involved in the ambiguous relation between images and
ideas which directly bears upon the analogical factor operating in the
modes of duplication.
To that formula, Leibniz added, nisi intellectus ipse, except the understanding itself. The strictly logological equivalent of that addition
would be a concern with respects in which the given structure of a language (such as its particular grammar, or even such sheer accidental
afnities as similarity in sound between particular words in a given idiom) sets up conditions intrinsic to the medium whereby we dont just
think with a language, but the language can in effect think for us. Much
has already been done along those lines, and much can still be done. Basically, I take it, the study of words as words in context asks us to ask
how they equate with one another, how they imply one another, and
how they become transformed.
There are contexts in the sense that a whole text is the context for any
part of the text. There are contexts in the sense of whatever background, historical, geographical, personal, local, or universal, might be

Theology and Logology

201

conceived of as the scene to which the symbolic act of the author as agent
explicitly or implicitly refers, over and above the nature of the texts
sheerly internal relationships.
But now let us consider again the behaviorist angle. On the issue
which I am to discuss here, dont fail to consult a truly admirable article, Explanation, Teleology, and Operant Behaviorism: A Study of the
Experimental Analysis of Purposive Behavior, by Jon D. Ringen, Philosophy of Science, 43 (1976): 22353. Though I doubt whether I quite
use it the way it was intended, it is so methodologically scrupulous a performance, its accuracy speaks for itself.
There is operant conditioning and there is respondent conditioning. Pavlovs (or Watsons) was of decidedly a respondent sort. The experimental animal responds by salivating when you give it a sniff of meat.
Test its response quantitatively by checking its ow of saliva. Then, after
having by repetition established the association between the sniff of meat
and the ringing of a bell, ring the bell without the sniff of meat, and check
on the amount of salivation as a response thus conditioned.
B. F. Skinner experimented with an additional test. Give an animal a
goal, set up some simple condition whereby, if it pecks at a certain form
(or color) or presses a lever, it operates a mechanism that releases a bit of
food. Having been systematically starved to about four-fths of its natural weight, it does whatever it can in the need for food. The laboratory
conditions are so set up that there are few things it can do. As the result
of its random motions, it learns to repeat the pressing or pecking operation that is most congruent with its natural endowment. And conditions are so set up that this operation procures it food. The kind of instrumental purpose it thus acquires is called an instance of molar
behavior. And such methods of control can be employed by the experimenter to teach the animal quite specialized modes of behavior, as compared with its natural repertoire for getting food. At the same time, of
course, there is a kind of molecular behavior going on in the animal,
the purely physiological correlates of bodily motion such as Pavlov was
studying in his technique for measuring the degree of salivation with
which his dogs responded to his respondent mode of conditioning.
It is my notion that logologys interest in questions of human molar
responses would primarily involve considerations of rhetoric and legislation (as with matters of penal law and taxation). But whereas humanistic studies usually show little interest in questions of molecular behavior, logology must stress this subject since it bears so directly upon
the possible correlations between physiological nonsymbolic motion and

202

Logology

symbolic action along the lines we touched upon in our reference to the
air-conditioning plant that had to use proportionately more energy
when a more exciting motion picture was being shown (which is to say,
when the audiovisual motions of the lm were being interpreted by the
audience in terms of symbolic actions for which the correlative nonsymbolic motions of their bodies put a proportionately greater burden
upon the air-conditioning mechanism, which could have no direct response to the lm itself as a sequence of motions, but which its sensors
were designed to register, as translated from the lms motions by the audiences actions, which were in turn reected as correlative bodily motions). I have deliberately left that sentence in its present unwieldy condition, the better to suggest the underlying problematics of such
logological concerns, though it is obvious that modern technology is developing at a high rate the resources for such clinical inquiries into the
molecular bodily motions that accompany our ways with symbolic action (apparently including even inquiries into corresponding routines of
self-control).
When considering such mythic gures as the Worm Ouroboros, the
Amphisbaena, or the world conceived as a mighty Hermaphrodite, one
might plausibly derive them from designs purely internal to the resources
of symbolicity. For instance, even the range of meanings in the Greek
preposition amphi is enough to suggest how the thought of such aroundness and aboutness might be mythologized (made narrative) in the image of a creature that went both forwards and backwards. The mutuality of ways in which terms imply one another might well suggest the
circular analogy of a creature with its own tail in its mouth (the design
here, long before there were dictionaries, suggesting what does characterize the nature of a dictionary, as a wholly self-contained universe of
discourse, a kind of circularity in the way all the terms circle back
upon one another). And when the principle of polarity becomes localized in terms of the sexes, it follows as a standard resource of dialectic
that such a quasi-antithesis can be resolved by the most obvious corresponding term for synthesis.
Logology does tentatively entertain the likelihood that such imaginings may have a grounding in physiologically still existent vestiges of our
ancestral evolutionary past. However, even if there may happen to be
such survivals from our preverbal past, and should they still be manifesting traces of themselves in some of the verbalizing animals most eschatological myths, logology builds on the assumption that the differentiating modes of sensation as immediately experienced by us animals

Theology and Logology

203

now contribute most to the imagery out of which a complex texture of


concepts and ideals can be developed by the resources of analogy intrinsic to the nature of terms.
By the adjective intrinsic here is not necessarily meant a power
of language. The same property can as accurately be called a mere limitation of language, a limitation due to the fact that we cannot apply the
same expression to two situations without to some extent introducing
the principle of analogy, metaphor, ction as a creative resource in
its own right.
Logology tentatively assumes that, quite as physically grounded hermaphroditic tendencies are clearly indicated in many actual instances
of such synthesis, so such mythic gures as the primal worm feeding
on itself may be a response to physiological conditions (prior even to our
uterine stage) still vestigially within us, and acting as a source of imagery.
Though one may doubt whether such possibilities may ever yield much
in the way of further discoveries, I mention them simply to indicate the
range of inquiry which would be involved in the study of the human animals nonsymbolic molecular behavior underlying the eld of symbolic action.
A more rewarding kind of inquiry along these lines might concern the
possibility that the socially morbid featuring of criminality, violence,
sadism, terror, and the like (many aspects of which show up in folk tales
for children) may have a double origin. As a social phenomenon (thus
wholly in the realm of symbolic action) the astoundingly large number of
mercenaries (writers, actors, and the various kinds of experts employed
in the purely technological aspects of such behavior) are obviously producing commodities that are designed to attract ideally a maximum number of viewers as a means of establishing as large a marketplace as possible where the experts in sales promotion can best recommend their
clients products.
The social morbidity of such art is greatly aggravated by the nature
of current TV realism, in which there is no appreciable difference between a merely simulated act of violence and a real one (which would be
the equivalent of saying that there is no appreciable difference between
the artistic imitation of suffering in Greek tragedy and the actual brutalities witnessed by the mobs who attended the gladiatorial contests in
decadent Rome).
Apologists for the protable selling of such wares will point to the
high degree of violence in, say, the greatest plays of Shakespeare. They
make no mention of the fact that the quality of the diction introduces a

204

Logology

notably different dimension. And as a matter of fact, writers for the current market operate in a eld which, by the very nature of contemporary
realism (or naturalism) as addressed to both eye and ear, wholly obliterates the distinction between real and simulated happenings, a confusion so natural to the medium that strictly scientic depictions of
moon-shots and the like must specically keep admonishing their public
when they are not recording an instrument in motion but are merely simulating such.
If one must be so scrupulously specic in keeping that distinction
clear, what then of a child who watches quasi-real killings time after
time, with no warnings that the simulations appeal to a childs imaginativeness in a way whereby, after a few years of such fare, that child has
been through all those experiences. The incidents have become
moral in the most etymologically accurate sense of the term, that is,
customary. In that medium, such modes of conduct have become established as the norm, and the child has been educated to think of
human relations in such terms.
Recall the case of the lawyer who recently tried to get his young defendant declared innocent because the boy had been greatly inuenced
by the depictions of violence on the tube. I doubt whether even a
Clarence Darrow could have used that defense successfully, if only because there is such a vast investment in the depiction of violence. Yet I
personally go along with those who believe that entertainment, as so
conceived, does function as a morbid kind of education. But the pressures of the market are such that the suppliers of commodities for that
market must sacrice a lot when cutting down on violence and hoppedup sex, either of which can be a substitute for the other except when attacks are directed with equal insistence against both. For any radical
elimination of them both would leave a void that other forms of symbolic action are not equipped to ll.
But how far should we go when asking what is the source of such appeal in these modes of substitution, depicting criminal Christs whose
mission it is to take on the burden of our guilt, suffer their imitated
passions in our behalf (as is also the case of real victims, offered for
the entertainment, fascination even, I mean for that inferior species of the
tragic pleasure we get from digesting the literal news of each days
crime and disaster)?
Might not the search for such sources of appeal lead us back to a kind
of purely physiological frustration? I do not refer to ways whereby imag-

Theology and Logology

205

inary substitutes help us compensate by fantasies that fulll our


wishes for dominance, sexual gratication, or vengeance, and like wishes
that are both stimulated and repressed by factors in the social order. I
have in mind a more paradoxical kind of frustration; namely, if human
bodies have been selectively disciplined through countless years of prehistory to endure certain purely physical kinds of strain, might the conditions of civilization frustrate the direct expression of such aptitudes as
get developed by, and inherited from, the conditions that prevailed prior
to the conditions of civilization?
To illustrate by an oversimplied anecdote, a spirited youth, living almost aimlessly in a modern slum, encounters kinds of frustration that a
young healthy Eskimo, at a time before Western civilization had contributed so greatly to the deterioration of his tribal culture, could not
have had the slightest notion of. The physicality of his purposes would
have been clear. They would have been developed by traditions that also
developed his ability to undergo the kinds of effort and corresponding
strain indigenous to such a mode of livelihood. The conditions of his situation would also have selectively developed the physical and attitudinal resources consistent with the purposes that the needs for survival under those conditions called for.
Insofar as such an endowment was developed in answer to the challenge that the conditions themselves helped dene, is there not a frustration of the aptitudes that are, as it were, inborn in the very genetic
endowment of a species thus selectively trained, their bodies thus having had bred into them whatever abilities to perform are by the same
token needs to so perform? After all, I am but saying that inbred in
birds there is the ability to y; and insofar as that ability is not given expression, they are frustrated, in their very nature repressed.
Viewed thus, the spirited youth who becomes a delinquent, might
more accurately be thought of as seeking the moral equivalent of war.
But wars are largely social constructs, thus motivated by disorders in the
realm of symbolicity; and we are here asking about a possible reduction
to the realm of sheer nonsymbolic, physiological motion. The kinds of
strain or conict that are being assumed here, and that the organisms
genetic endowment needs to express if it is not to be frustrated,
would be wholly in the realm of motion. One gets glimpses of such a
motive in athletic efforts (now invariably corrupted from the very start
by their tie-in with modes of decadent symbolicity known as professional sports). They are grounded in an asceticism of training, training

206

Logology

to undergo (and thus express) the potentialities of the physiological organism to endure strain, potentialities that would otherwise be denied
expression.
In an early book (1935; Permanence and Change, second revised edition [Los Altos, California: Hermes Publications, 1954]), I exercised
considerably about a corresponding moral conict that characterized Nietzsches cult of tragedy, and that I related also to a salient aspect of his
style, its restless hankering after perspectives by incongruity, in the
service of an Umwerthung aller Werthe. In summing things up some four
decades later, I nd that related speculations should be recalled. Recalling them, I might sum up the whole logological situation thus:
There is (1) the principle of polarity with regard to the qualitative distinction between symbolic action and nonsymbolic motion. This is the
prime source of duplication, insofar as the experiences of bodily sensation shape the materials which language draws upon as the source of its
ctions, in the realm of symbolicity. Within the realm of symbolicity
itself there is (2) the kind of polarity that the negative adds to nonsymbolic nature. It itself splits into the propositional (is-is not) pair and the
hortatory (do-do not) pair. In the realm of the body as a sheerly nonsymbolic physical organism there is (3) the polarity of the distinction between the need for struggle (in the effort to attain the means of livelihood) and the rewards of relaxation (when a hunger has been sated). In
a highly complex social structure the resources of symbolicity are such
that the sheer physiology of such a distinction becomes greatly confused
by symbolic factors (property relationships, for instance). But we have
tried to indicate why we assume that it can function quite paradoxically
as a motive. (Leisure, for instance, can function as a mode of psychological unemployment, with twists whereby people can make work for
themselves by inventing confused purposes and relationships.)
Formal symbolic structures might be reduced to three terministic relationships: equations (identications), implications, transformations.
For instance, if some particular ism or ology or personality type or
location or whatever is explicitly or implicitly presented as desirable or
undesirable, it would be identied with corresponding valuesand
such would be equations. Implications would gure insofar as one
term explicitly or implicitly involved a cycle or family of terms, as the
idea of order implies a companion-term, disorder, or implicit in the
idea of an act is the idea of an agent who performs the act. By
transformations would be meant what would be the from-what,
through-what, to-what developments in a symbolic structure. Such

Theology and Logology

207

unfoldings (from potentiality to actualization via a peripety of some


sort) can be either narrative or purely conceptual or both. The question
of transformations necessarily impinges upon the shifting choices between temporal, narrative priority (yesterday/today/tomorrow) and logical priority (the syllogistic rst premise/second premise/conclusion designor the dialectical notion of a class name as prior to any
particulars that can be classed under that head).
In this connection, the route from logology to theology is via a logological criticism of Platos mythology because it assigns to his ideal forms
a realm narratively prior to their mode of classication as in effect general names for worldly particulars included under those various ideal
heads. Such a procedure would be called the temporizing of essence,
in that it does mythologize (that is, translate into terms of story) a verbal resource of classication that has no temporal dimension.
Since eternity is also a kind of nontemporality, the conditions are
present whereby the timelessness of the supernatural realm after death
(by extension involving a realm prior to all wordly existence) ambiguously overlaps upon the purely technical sense of timelessness in the logological sense of polar terms timelessly implying each other. And inasmuch as theology necessarily uses narrative terms with regard to the
emergence of time out of timelessness, logologys business is to discuss
such embarrassments that survive, even after theology has critically gone
beyond mythology.
But looking in the other direction, whereas logology is vowed by sheer
denition to be much concerned with the molecular behavior of the
body (thereby going along radically with behaviorist inquiries), logology
must insist categorically upon a polar distinction between verbal and
nonverbal behavior, in contrast with the behaviorists notion that they
are there concerned with but a difference of degree. Logologys distinction between the symbolic and nonsymbolic realms is at least as absolute
as any distinction between mind and body, though it has a notably
different way of getting there. In fact, the distinction is as basic as that
between bread and the word bread. Or as the distinction between the
sea as a mother symbol and the sea as the physical body of saltwater
it is, vastly a sloshing-around.
With regard to the logological distinction between symbolic action
and nonsymbolic motion, it makes no difference whether the human animal thinks with language, or thought and symbolicity are identical. In either case, insofar as the speechless human organism acquires
familiarity with a tribal language there arises a duality of motivational

208

Logology

realms whereby the human animals way with symbols is not reducible
to terms of its correlative molecular behavior.
But when I read of hermeneutic experts who congratulate themselves
that the traditional Cartesian split between subject and object, thought
and extension, is being avoided, I would note that there are two quite different ways of considering any such development. If Descartess dualism
is attacked as a psychology of consciousness, it is in trouble. But we
should not let any reservations regarding the Cartesian formulation of
the dualism serve as a device by implication to discredit the dualistic
principle itself. For if we do so, we are in effect implying monism either
by smuggling in undeclared vestiges of idealism, or by willy-nilly subscribing to the materialistic oversimplication of behaviorism. But logologys dramatistic (or dialectical) view of language as symbolic action is in its very essence realisticand such a view is necessarily
dualistic, since man is the typically symbol-using animal, and the linguistic invention of the negative is enough in itself to build a dualism,
even beyond the other two polarities we also included in our summation.
At least as a tentative working principle, logology holds to the notion
that the relations between poetry and mythology (and thence via criticism and writing to theology, plus wholly secular offshoots or disrelated
growths, if there are such) must in all likelihood embody imaginative
traces intrinsic to any symbolic (that is, human) medium in its own right,
along with traces of the formative experiences undergone while the human animal is gradually acquiring familiarity with the medium (such as
its initiation in the ways of a tribal language). And such traces of the inceptive are all the more likely to be still with us since experiences of that
sort are not a matter merely of a human organisms infantile past, but
are ever born anew. For language is innately innovative. No one could
go on making his words mean the same, even if he expended his best efforts to make them stay put.

notes
This essay was rst published in The Kenyon Review 1 (winter 1979): 15185.
1. Any such possible relationship between personal tensions and their use as
material for intense linguistic activity (to be analyzed and admired in its own
terms) might gure thus. But there are special, purely logological, incentives for
such a relationship between poetic activity and psychological passion. On various occasions (particularly the essay, The First Three Chapters of Genesis, in
my Rhetoric of Religion [1961]) I have discussed the process whereby the effort
to characterize conditions now turns into a story of origins then, often a

Theology and Logology

209

purely mythic past. This endeavor can come to tie in with purely psychological motives in such cases as, for instance, a poets inclination to dwell regressively on thoughts of early years actual or imaginary vestigial memories of infancy. Thus Wallace Stevenss puzzlements about the rst idea seem to me an
attempt, by an act of the imagination, to recover a sense of what things must
have seemed like to a child before things became codied by names, or even colored by the assumption that anything unnamed was potentially namable.
Incidentally, with regard to Keatss ode (which I take to envision a kind of
art-heaven, a theological heaven romantically aestheticized), by my interpretation, the transforming of his diseases bodily symptoms (fever and chill) into
imaginal counterparts within the conditions of the ction would be a poetic embodiment of the orthodox religious promise that the true believers would regain
their puried bodies in heaven. That is, the symptoms would have their transcendent counterparts in poetic diction as indicated in my analysis.
I review these various considerations because the discussion of them offers a
good opportunity to at least indicate humanistic concern (the admonition to
know ourselves) that I take to be involved in the logological distinction between the human organisms realm of nonsymbolic motion and the kind of
self it naturally acquires through its protracted, informative trafc with the
(learned) public modes of symbolic action.

You might also like