You are on page 1of 4

Franoise Chandernagor, "The historian at the mercy of the law"

Libert pour lhistoire, CNRS Editions, 2008


The national narrative, that immense family saga, which for the last hundred and fifty years has underpinned the teaching of history in
France, is in pieces: it has broken apart under the simultaneous opposing pressures of globalization and identity politics, for which it was
expected to justify both the broadest sense of community and the narrowest sectarian loyalties.
Not everyone will mourn its passing. In the days when it was disseminated in schools, enshrined in public monuments, and reaffirmed in
ceremonies of commemoration, this core narrative of national identity was doubtless too generally positive. It was built around the heroes
recognized by the Republic and the most glorious pages of Frances past, back to the ancient Gauls. It obscured all or part of the darker side
of the past, erased differences, downplayed conflicts, and left out the figures whose merits or struggles did not fit neatly into the overall
narrative; the average person was thus as ignorant of Toussaint Louverture as of Henri de La Rochejaquelein, Olympe de Gouges, St.
Bernard of Clairvaux, Jean Cavalier, Jean Chouan, Louise Michel or Esclarmonde of Foix.
However, as simplistic and optimistic as it may seem today, this official narrative had never been forced on academics, scholars,
journalists, or writers, nor on their adult readers: everyone could add to it or challenge it. That option was taken up with a vengeance: the
history of the Revolution, for example, has been a battleground fought over by the historians. But that the political authorities could impose
their version of history through the law that is, by coercion was something nobody could then have imagined. In France, as in other
democracies, no dissident historian risked imprisonment; methods of that sort remained the preserve of totalitarian regimes, whether
Fascist or Communist.
As it began to break apart, the national narrative has gradually opened up a space for the histories of specific groups, which are all the more
charged with emotion because they used to be repressed. Moreover, the individualism that has come to dominate our lives seemed to justify
subjective readings of history. Not only was history no longer that of a single community, but no scholarly authority was seen as having the
power to establish and narrate the truth.
Every vacuum eventually gets filled: seeing this empty space, politicians, sometimes with the support of their clientele of voters, went on
the offensive. Now, in bits and pieces, in schools and at public ceremonies, another history is beginning to be told. That this history focuses
on remorse rather than positive example, and on diversity rather than unity, calls for general discussion. But jurists especially cannot help but
be struck, even disturbed, by the unprecedented character of this development: that is, this new narrative is enshrined in law. It is not only
proposed, taught, and celebrated: it is imposed on every citizen without exception under pain of legal sanction.
By putting itself in the place of both historians and educators, Parliament has, in effect, begun to decide and dictate its conception of the
history of France, and why stop there even of world history as a whole. It does not restrict itself to commemorating events or
authorizing reparations, which would be its proper role; it claims binding force for its own interpretations of the past, has sole power to
describe past events, and forbids disagreement with its decisions. If we are not careful, these dangerous laws will soon have horrified
historians up before a judge at a moments notice.

Rewriting the past


Dangerous laws? First let us not suppose that there are any harmless laws. A law is neither a token measure nor a placebo, even if it may
look like one. Of its nature, a law is a rule, an obligation: it must be observed and applied, and the one who breaks it may, sooner or later, be
brought to justice. The legislature, therefore, should only utilize the law respectfully and carefully.
Unfortunately, it turns out that unlike parliaments in other countries or the Assembly of our own Third and Fourth Republics, since 1958 the
French Parliament has not had the right to vote on resolutions, declarations, proclamations mere words, in short that may be politically
important but are legally neutral. If it wants to console or to please, the Parliament of the Fifth Republic has no choice: it must make use of
the law.
This predicament is here to stay. In late 2007, in fact, the Balladur commission proposed, as part of the institutional reform project, to allow
Parliament to voice its feelings on some subjects by means of a simple resolution. But in April 2008, when the vote on the proposed
reform of the Constitution was taken, the amendment in question was removed. Some feared, and not without reason, a return to the
parliamentary demagoguery of the Fourth Republic: at that period, a government that had secured a majority for the passage of a law could
fall as the result of the concurrent adoption of an opposing resolution. In any case, as a perceptive speaker noted during the debate, now that
we have adopted these bad habits and laws get passed although in other democratic states resolutions would be sufficient for the purpose, no
lobbyist will be satisfied with a mere resolution when a fellow-lobbyist, who got there quicker, can benefit from a real law.
Not a chance of reform in that respect, then. When our Parliament wants to express sympathy, compassion, or legitimate indignation, it will
continue to pass laws, sometimes very brief ones (some are no more than a single line of text), which are often imprecise, usually cobbled
together, but laws all the same, and as such can set judicial machinery in motion.
However, in recent years, for the reason outlined above the collapse of the national narrative one area in which these declarative laws
are most applied is the past, including our rereading of the past in the light of the present and our rewriting of it in modern terms.
It is true that for politicians, intervening in what is dead and gone has many advantages. Aside from the fact that it is easier to change the
past than to improve the future, large sections of the electorate can be satisfied without spending a cent. Politicians also take on the most
desirable of roles, that of a righter of wrongs, at no risk to themselves, since all the criminals to be subdued are long since dead. Criminals
they may indeed be called, since it is chiefly through the use of the concepts of genocide and crime against humanity (at the risk of
attenuating the force of that term) that Parliament is currently undertaking a wholesale revision of world history.
Disentangling good from evil since the dawn of time, condemning all the villains in hindsight, and punishing those who dare to excuse past
misdeeds because they happened long ago who could be upset by this? No one except, once in a while, those who teach or study history.
Or those who read it. Or any citizen who believes in the free expression of opinion, as long as it is not offensive, hateful, or racist.

Five laws and a framework decision


The specific legislation concerning history already passed in France consists of five laws and one European Community framework decision,
which was voted in after being proposed by France.
The first of these laws, the one that the most ink has been spilt over (even though it is not the most poorly worded), is the Gayssot law,
relative to the genocide and other crimes committed by the Nazi leaders who were tried at Nuremberg. It is true that by prohibiting and
penalizing the disputing of the Nuremberg judgments, and of subsequent judgments handed down in France on the same legal basis, Article
9 of this law set a dangerous precedent of principle. Previously, although a final legal judgment had the absolute status of a res judicata
(meaning that no appeal could be made against it), it could still be a topic of debate by historians. With the Gayssot law, however, judgments
for the first time became sacred and untouchable. A new legal category historical truth was implicitly created by introducing into the
1881 law about the press and into the Penal Code a brand-new misdemeanor, dispute (not, as is often supposed, denial, a concept that in any
event would have been more appropriate to the goal in view and legally easier to grasp). This disputing offense can be punished by
imprisonment, and has been on several occasions, but an exact penalty is not defined by the law intended to curb it. This is left entirely to the
discretion of the judge, which has the advantage of being flexible but the disadvantage of being arbitrary.
The other parts of the Gayssot law, which was directed primarily at curbing new forms of anti-Semitism, were well thought out and well
drawn up. But Article 9, although with the best intentions in the world, opened a Pandoras box. It quickly generated intense competition in
the arena of historical memory, which soon led to more legislation and more proposals of a similar kind.
In January 2001, French citizens of Armenian origin obtained the passage of a law recognizing the Armenian genocide of 1915. In May of
that year, Parliament voted the Taubira law which, responding to citizens of the overseas departments in particular, recognized officially that
the Atlantic slave trade was a crime against humanity. Similarly, also in that year, the French government introduced the draft of a
framework decision in the European judicial system, to be legally applicable in all Member States, dealing with the trivialization and
complicity in trivialization (terms even looser than disputing) of any event previously defined by whom, the text does not specify as a
war crime, a crime against humanity, or genocide. In February 2005, the Mekachera law, relative to the gratitude of the nation
toward its repatriated French citizens, asserted the positive role of the French presence overseas and, in terms virtually modeled on those
of the Taubira law, required history teachers and scholars to take this interpretation into account more fully in their work. In October 2006,
the National Assembly adopted the Masse proposal, which extends to the 2001 Armenian law the penalties specified by the Gayssot law for
those who dispute that genocide. On the model of this second Armenian law, a bill was presented to extend the repressive mechanism of
the Gayssot law to the Taubira law as well.
Over the next two or three years, a dozen other bills were filed for consideration by the Assemblies, defining as crimes against humanity or
genocide a number of historical events, both long past and recent, in France and elsewhere. The latest of these focus on the Gypsy
genocide, the Ukrainian genocide of 1932-1933, and the genocide in the Vende of 1793-1794. A Swiss organization has lobbied some
deputies for recognition of the horrible massacre of the Swiss Guards in the Tuileries in 1792, and several organizations are apparently now
working to have the atrocities committed by the Crusaders in Palestine defined as a crime against humanity. And why not go back to 1099?
After all, the Taubira law already covers events that happened in the fifteenth century. In some cases, for instance the war in Algeria,
contradictory bills have been filed, reflecting the clash of histories the crimes against humanity committed against the Algerians (the
suppression of the FLN demonstrations in Paris in 1961) versus the crimes against humanity committed by the Algerians (the assassinations
of pieds-noirs and Harkis in 1962).
As we observe this massive release of collective feelings, it should be remembered that in the case of the Gayssot law Parliament did not
claim to be the sole determiner of historical truth. It did at least draw on an international court, the Nuremberg Tribunal, and on international
agreements, reached in London and incorporated into domestic law, for the proof and the definition of the events that people were to be
forbidden to dispute. But historians all agree that the preliminary investigative work carried out by the judges at Nuremberg was of
extremely high quality. Unfortunately, when legislators intervene or claim the right to intervene in history today, they do so in the absence of
judges, historians, or commissions of inquiry, and go with their gut feelings. This is more troubling.
To complete the picture of the threats historians are facing, we may add that five more bills have been filed, designed to extend automatically
the repressive apparatus of the Gayssot law to anything that in years to come may be recognized by Parliament as a crime against humanity,
no matter when and where it was committed. An automatic extension to the St. Bartholomews Day Massacre well, why not?
This at any rate is what might happen with respect to the EU framework decision, submitted by France in 2001 and brought before the
Council of Ministers of the EU in 2007, then forwarded for an advisory opinion to the European Parliament in Strasbourg. If it were to be
adopted in 2008, during the French presidency of the EU, though without first specifying that the misdemeanor of trivialization should only

apply in the case of genocide or crimes against humanity in recent times (those, for example, condemned by the International Criminal
Court), all the history laws passed by the French Parliament would include, both retroactively and into the future, an automatic provision:
that is, no one would be able to make a move in the field of history without risking three years in prison (which is the specific penalty chosen
by the European judicial authorities). Would France, which initiated this law, then be inclined to agree to the demands of the Baltic
countries? In return for their support, they wanted the Council of Ministers of the EU (which in Europe has the legislative power) to define
the massacres committed in the twentieth century by the Communist regimes as crimes against humanity hence protecting them from being
disputed and trivialized.
Of course the enormity of these various crimes is undeniable. But where should we call a halt? Should this French virus not be prevented
from spreading throughout Europe before it is too late? Surely we should hasten to put an end to this pattern of alternate accusation and selfflagellation, which, under the pretext of prohibiting disagreement about a list of historical events that grows longer every day, has only one
real victim freedom of research and of expression.
Although in January 2006 the President solemnly declared that it is not the job of Parliament to write history, France continues, locally and
globally, to pose as the guardian of world memory and the champion of atonement via the law. France is always ready to confess to sins as
long as they were committed by someone else. Is this an excess of humility? Rather, an excess of self-importance.

The sin of anachronism


This political development is all the more regrettable in that both the form and the content of the history laws already passed are open to
criticism: their form often violates the law, and their content sometimes violates the past.
These laws, it must be said, are not always in accordance with Articles 34 and 37 of the French Constitution. While it is famously said of the
English Parliament that it can do anything except change man to woman, the French Parliament does not have so much power. The 1958
Constitution, approved by 85% of the population, limited its range of activity: anything that is not expressly mentioned in Article 34 as being
within Parliaments purview is out of bounds to the legislature. Is it necessary to point out that Article 34 nowhere mentions educational
curricula, teaching methods, or research programs? All those areas are exclusively the province of government department and the
appropriate administrative bodies (such as program committees).
Parliament knows perfectly well that it is overstepping its limits when it intervenes in these subjects (as in the Taubira law and the
Mekachera law). One has only to read the minutes of the parliamentary debates that preceded the passage of some of these laws. In 2001, for
example, the Garde des Sceaux expressly pointed out to the deputies that they were in breach of Article 37 of the Constitution. Some of them
then took the floor to assert that Since Parliament is elected by universal suffrage, it is sovereign, and can therefore do whatever it likes,
and their fellow-deputies agreed with them. But by law, Parliament is not sovereign, but gets its authority from the sovereign power, that is
to say the people. As such, Parliament is bound by the Constitution, which the people also voted for by universal suffrage. In all
constitutional political systems, the Constitution is above the law. The Constitution establishes the separation of powers, and when one of
those powers ceases to abide by this separation, the freedom of all is threatened.
But as long as the government lacks courage, the deputies can safely violate this ultimate legal authority, since they along with the heads of
the executive power are the only people who can request a decision from the official defenders of the Constitution. Unlike the situation in
the United States, where there is an exception for unconstitutionality, the Constitutional Council cannot be asked to pronounce on a law by
a judge, nor can it pronounce on its own initiative or at the request of a private citizen. At present, laws possibly infringing the Constitution
can only be submitted to the judgment of the Constitutional Council by the President, the Prime Minister, the Presidents of the two
Assemblies, or by sixty deputies. There is no point in nursing the hope that one day sixty deputies will rise up to request that a historical
memory law be referred to the Constitutional Council: all, except the last, were passed unanimously on all sides of the chambers. And
although in 2006 the second bill dealing with the Armenian genocide was only voted through by a hundred deputies, this is because many
others chose to abstain by leaving town early in the week, perhaps because they dared not face the vociferous groups who had planted
themselves in the chambers.
The Constitutional Council has been consulted only once about a history law: the Vanneste amendment, which introduced a reference to
the positive aspects of colonization into Article 4 of the law of February 2005. It immediately had this article revoked, and it is almost
certain that had the first law on the Armenian genocide or the 2001 law on the slave trade and slavery been submitted to the Council, it
would have annulled them, wholly or partly, as unconstitutional. But its opinion was not solicited, nor will it be.

Retroactive legislation
These laws that violate the Constitution also violate the general principles that underpin any law, that is to say, the French Declaration of
Human Rights and in particular its Article 8, which states that no one shall suffer punishment except it be legally inflicted in virtue of a law
passed and promulgated before the commission of the offense which obviously comes to the same thing as prohibiting retroactive laws.
But these history laws are of their very nature retroactive. That is, the law passed on October 12, 2006, which imposes criminal sanctions
on anyone who disputes in any way the application of the concept of genocide to what happened in Armenia in 1915, is not retroactive with
respect to the misdemeanor that it punishes: anyone who might want to dispute this event is on notice that from now on he or she risks
imprisonment. What is retroactive is the actual definition of the crime of genocide.
The concepts of crime against humanity and genocide are recent ones. The word genocide was coined in 1944 by the jurist Raphael
Lemkin to describe the crimes of Nazi Germany. The term crime against humanity was recognized in international law in 1945 by the
military tribunal in Nuremberg, and genocide in 1948 by a UN agreement.
In French criminal law, genocide exists only as one category of crimes against humanity, but the full legal definition adopted is very
detailed, taking up about fifteen lines of text. The concept, though defined analytically and in specific detail, still remains somewhat vague;
the French definition does not correspond exactly to that of the UN, ours being looser, probably for good reason. It is wider than the idea of
extermination based on racial or religious characteristics, by including any extermination based on an arbitrary criterion. To count as
genocide, the other must simply be perceived as other and systematically exterminated for that reason alone. On the French
interpretation, for example, the extermination of the kulaks by Stalin, or of the intellectuals (meaning anyone wearing glasses) by the
Khmer Rouge, would count as genocide a definition which is not altogether a bad one. The EU interpretation, however, as it appears in the
draft of the framework decision under review, is not only narrower than the French one, but also narrower than that of the United Nations,
which counts religiously motivated massacres under the overall rubric of genocide. At the request of the British government which perhaps
feared that they would get into trouble because of Northern Ireland the trivialization of crimes against humanity and genocide, as these are
implicitly defined today by the European Union, will be illegal only if any religious criterion for the persecution is combined with an ethnic
criterion. In Europe, consequently, white Protestants are still allowed to trivialize their maltreatment of white Catholics (and vice versa), in
the same way that black Muslims are allowed to trivialize the abuses they have committed on black Christians as much as they want (and
vice versa?).
It is clear that not only are the legal concepts of genocide and crime against humanity recent ones, but that their very definition is a work in
progress. Would this not be one more reason to enforce them sparingly? This is not, it seems, what our leaders think. Although this new
concept is still developing, they have not hesitated to apply it to a crime committed in the fifteenth century (article 1 of the Taubira law). We
are faced with legislative provisions that apply retroactively over a period of five hundred years an unprecedented situation and that are,
moreover, fundamentally anachronistic. In history, of course, anachronism is the ultimate sin. But how to explain to politicians, who may not
all be fascinated by the discipline of history, that mentalities change over time, that neither sensibilities nor moral values are the same as
they were ten centuries ago? What is obvious to a historian is not so to politicians and the media. Surely an educational effort could be made
here to explain these points, an attempt directed at informing public opinion, something that academics have been very wrong to neglect. But
to get their points across, now that diversity is so fashionable, will they have to phrase their claims for the past in terms of the right to be
different?

Shoddy work
In any case, it is not the perpetrators of crimes against humanity, retroactively (and anachronistically) defined, who are to be punished: they
are long gone! So we are to punish the historians: the French Parliament expressly agreed to do so on October 12, 2006. One deputy who had
the courage to propose an amendment which would exclude academic and scholarly research from being covered by the second law on the
Armenian genocide saw this proposal rejected by his colleagues who thus confessed quite openly that it was precisely academic research
on certain topics that they wished to ban. By rejecting this amendment, they confirmed what the jurists had foreseen: that academics,
scholars, are targeted by these new penal laws.
These dangerous and juridically unsound history laws also fail to go through the normal procedure for the preparation of legislation. As
the bills in question are never government projects but only private bills submitted by deputies, they do not go through the Conseil dEtat,
which might at least edit out their infelicities. However, it can happen that the government is in complete agreement with the parliamentary
proposal, and may even turn out to be its instigator: so why, instead of filing a government bill, does it choose this sleight-of-hand trick
fronted by a deputy or a senator? Precisely to avoid having it examined by the Conseil dEtat, with all the timid objections that its experts in
legal wording might advance.
Some of the texts of these bills were so shoddily prepared that they were not even debated in committee by the internal parliamentary body
charged with technical improvements to the wording of bills. To avoid this standard vetting procedure, some deputies, connected politically
or sympathetically to certain organizations, factions, or pressure groups, took to introducing amendments in open session. This is what
happened with the Vanneste amendment on the teaching of the positive aspects of colonization: it was put on the agenda at the last
moment, so that no jurists could determine its implications before it was adopted as it was, unanimously, we may recall.
That said, this Vanneste amendment which produced such an uproar was, from a juridical point of view, hardly more dangerous than Article
2 of the Taubira law, which required teachers to allocate a consequent place to the history of slavery. Consequent? This word, apparently
used here to mean important, belongs neither to the French language nor the terminology of the law. What would judges decide if they had
to pronounce on it? What is a consequent place? Five minutes? Two hours? A semester?
How can anyone take seriously laws that are so poorly worded? How can anyone abide by them? The second law on the Armenian genocide
was so sloppy that its own author spent the days just before the debate amending it himself all over the place: sometimes he proposed a year
in prison for offenders, sometimes five, and vice versa all completely at random. In the end, he had added so much and crossed out so
much that he had to file a cleanup amendment to restore some order and renumber the whole thing; on the eve of the vote, his proposal
was still a mess. When a law is written in such a slapdash way, who would not be justified in treating it with contempt?

Historians under threat

As well as violating legal standards, these laws can also violate the past. Take the law of May 21, 2001, which, its title says, concerns
slavery and the slave trade. Any jurist would naturally be surprised to hear that more legislation is needed on this question, because since
1926 the slave trade has been a crime punishable under international agreements that are directly applicable in French law, and it is already
defined in our Penal Code (article 212.1) as a crime against humanity. But all of that had to do with present or future crimes. In 2001,
something new came along: the judging of the past.
Should we really judge the past in a court of law, applying our modern legal and moral concepts to it? And if Parliament thinks we should, if
it deems it useful and necessary to legislate, as it has in this case, for the fifteenth century, why does the body of the text include some fine
distinctions that the title of the law does not lead one to expect? Despite its very general title, it turns out, from article 1 onward, that only the
Atlantic slave trade, and the trade in the Indian Ocean that brought Africans to Mauritius and Runion, are considered to be crimes against
humanity. There is no mention nor condemnation of the Arab slave trade and slavery among the Arabs, nor of the slave trade among African
nations themselves, though all of these were extensive and more long-lasting phenomena: in some cases they continued legally within these
nations, if not internationally, up to the 1980s (in Niger and Mali, for example) and even until 2007 (Mauritania has only just adopted a law
which bans slave-owning).
Slavery, a universal crime, is bizarrely reduced by the Taubira law to the slavery imposed by Europeans and the triangular trade. This seems
perfectly reasonable, we might reply, as this is the crime for which the French bear responsibility. That argument might be admissible,
except for the enormous confusion regarding the dates involved. France did not officially participate in the slave trade until the late
seventeenth century, but the period covered by the law includes the fifteenth, sixteenth, and seventeenth centuries. So the crime now being
acknowledged by France began to exist before the French began to commit it. France, standing in for the Turks, had already acknowledged
the Armenian genocide; now it acknowledges in law the sins of the English, the Dutch, and the Portuguese, among others. In including the
fifteenth century in the time-frame, it even acknowledges the Atlantic slave trade in a period before America was discovered!
There is more: In the course of the discussions preparatory to the parliamentary debate, some speakers brought up the enslavement of Native
Americans, saying quite rightly that in South America the European colonists enslaved not only Africans but Indians as well. In support of
this point, a reference to Amerindian slaves was added to one article, which that now says the Atlantic slave trade was a factor in common
for Africans and Amerindians. We have to confess ourselves perplexed at this point: if Carib Indians were transported to Africa, this news
has been kept secret for some time. But that is what the law says happened, if we read it literally. Are we then required under threat of
prosecution to agree that Amerindians were among the victims of the Atlantic slave trade?
If historians are to be hauled before the courts, at least let it be by virtue of laws that are carefully worded and historically accurate, since,
vague as they are, these laws now circumscribe the part of their field that is open to scholars. This at least is how the identity-based
organizations who have taken on the responsibility for enforcing these laws understand the situation. In late 2005, the historian and academic
Olivier Ptr-Grenouilleau, author of a well-received book, Les Traites ngrires, which won the Senate history book award, found himself
taken to court by the Collectif Antillais, Guyanais, Runionnais et Mahorais (Collectifdom) and the Collectif of the sons and daughters of
deported Africans. The lawsuit was based on this claim: In saying that the slave trade spanned thirteen centuries and five continents, M.
Ptr-Grenouilleau revealed a desire to sidestep the unique character of the Atlantic slave trade by adopting a chronological and geographical
scale broader than that defined in law. These are the reasons for the civil and criminal suits that historians are threatened by. For what this
lawsuit clearly asserts is that the law defines the official limits of intellectual activity and that anything outside them is prohibited. In future,
when discussing slavery we are not to speak about anything beyond what the law authorizes, that is to say the European slave trade to the
exclusion of any other.
But speaking about it at all that is to say studying, publishing, and teaching it would still be going too far, to judge by the press release
issued by this same Collectifdom, dated December 15, 2005: The slave trade and slavery are supra-historical phenomena, in that they are
recognized as crimes against humanity. What a clever sleight-of-hand, to be sure: we cannot talk about the Arab slave trade, because to do
so would trivialize the Atlantic slave trade, but we cannot speak of the Atlantic slave trade either, because Parliament, by recognizing it, has
moved it outside history altogether. History has thus become moot. The End of History.
What are French historians to do when they run into a crime against humanity that has been made sacrosanct by a history law? Get out of
the way, and find a different line of work!

Who are the descendants of slaves?


Faced with this reckless legislative campaign, the more sensible judges are in a bind firstly because of the mediocre quality of the texts of
the laws they must implement, but also because of their own ignorance of history, in cases where they are required to prosecute well-known
scholars. Bear in mind that the compulsory law school syllabus includes no courses in general history, nor does that of the National School
of Magistrates. Most judges thus know no more about past ages than todays high school graduate which is to say, not a lot.
Judges are also in a bind because they have no authority to reject lawsuits brought by properly constituted groups. If you bring a complaint to
a prosecutor against your neighbor, it is the prosecutor who decides whether the complaint is serious enough to warrant investigation. But
this does not apply in the case of the history laws. Here the complaints are initiated by organizations, and if one of them brings a suit, the
public prosecutor is only allowed to verify whether it has been legally in existence long enough (five years) to do so but if so, prosecution
must follow. A historian can thus automatically be taken to court, even if the suit is completely frivolous. And, moreover, even if the court in
the end rules against the plaintiff, in the meantime the accused will have been discredited in the media complicity in crimes against
humanity is no laughing matter and an academic career blighted.
We may add that judicial decision-making is often made more difficult by the multiplication of charges and the forms they take. What the
organizations concerned with historical memory can do is more or less extensive depending on the law invoked. The Gayssot law gives them
the power to protect the honor of the Resistance, which is historically specific, and the honor of the deportees, which is also specific
since deportee is a very clearly defined legal category: after the war, there was an administrative census of the deportees, with identity cards
and so on. The Taubira law, in contrast, gave these organizations broader and more imprecise powers: they are allowed to bring suit to
protect the honor of the descendants of slaves. First question: who are the descendants of slaves? It is certainly not a matter of skin color:
if I may be permitted to present myself as an example, I have fair skin, yet I am what those who colonized the islands called an octoroon, a
mestiza descendant (right down to the surname) of a freed slave. Conversely, there are some blacks of African origin whose ancestors owned
slaves. How are we to tell ourselves apart? Second question: for how long will there continue to be descendants of slaves? Slavery was
abolished a hundred and sixty years ago, and today we have reached at least the fifth generation since then. Are we to go on calling ourselves
the descendants of slaves, demanding a special honor, for centuries to come rather like the descendants of the Crusaders under the
Ancien Rgime?
The question is all the more interesting in that in the sphere of the historical memory laws the usual statutes of limitations have been
extended. For example, normally misdemeanors committed by the press have to be brought to court within three months, but in the case of
the history laws this is extended to a year. In civil cases, however, the usual statute of limitations is thirty years, during which it is possible
to demand compensation under the category of moral damage as stated in Article 1382 of the Code: Any act whatever of man, which
causes damage to another, obliges the one by whose fault it occurred, to compensate it. Historians thus have no way of knowing for how
long or when they might be taken to court for something they write today.
Moreover, the litigating organizations can bring suit about the same offense in both the civil and criminal courts at once. Cases become even
more entangled because there are so many single-issue organizations, often created ad hoc to exploit a historical memory law, who operate
unpredictably. This was the case in the Ptr-Grenouilleau affair: when Collectifdom, daunted by the active response of other historians in
his support, withdrew their criminal complaint, other organizations immediately took up the issue, though less raucously, in the civil courts,
one after the other and this harassment, which is all it is, seemed to be endless. The Paris Tribunal de Grande Instance has, we may hope,
put an end to this by fining one of these organizations, the Mouvement pour une nouvelle humanit, for abuse of the system on March 10,
2008. But it is self-evident that this type of harassment, so widely publicized, may lead many scholars to practice self-censorship.

Hereditary crimes
If the more privileged deputies, ministers, journalists, heads of organizations are plunged into such a state of confusion on the issue, how
can we expect the general public to respond to it? It seems to be at a loss, and inclined toward obscurantism. The confusion of terminology in
French law results in a competition for the role of most victimized group; it is the absence of a statute of limitations for a sin that turns it into
a form of sacrilege. The statute of limitations is another legal concept misunderstood by the victims, by the general public, and which is
less excusable by the media. They all view the absence of a statutory time limit on guilt as normal: since time has no beginning or end, the
legal responsibility for a crime and the right to reparations, financial or otherwise, are presumed to last until the end of time. Sins are to be
punished all the way back to the sons of Adam and for all eternity to come.
In this context we need to bring up the meaning and the history of the inclusion of article 213.5 in the French Penal Code. Under the Ancien
Rgime, certain crimes, called imprescriptible, or inalienable, were punishable up to the death of their perpetrators; these included
sacrilege and lse-majest. The Revolution, taking a more modern line, decided that all crimes would have a statute of limitations of
twenty years, meaning twenty years from the date the crime was discovered.
It may be that today, because of longer average life expectancy, this period is too short even in common law. Be that as it may, after the
Franco-German rapprochement of 1963, fearing that the last Nazi war criminals would escape punishment, in 1964 France decided to extend
the period of possible prosecution for crimes against humanity, which had originally been set at twenty years, in line with all other crimes.
But rather than extending it to forty or fifty years, it was decided that these crimes would be imprescriptible, enjoying no statute of
limitations at all. In this case it came to the same thing, since in criminal law being imprescriptible simply means that a crime can be
punished as long as the criminal is alive up until death, but, of course, not after it.
That is not, however, how the term was understood by the general public. Due, no doubt, to a confusion with the political-philosophy
concept of droit imprescriptible or inalienable right, which appears in the French Declaration of Human Rights, in the minds of the
citizenry this penal concept came to lose its proper legal meaning: today, the word imprescriptible applied to a crime is seen as
synonymous with unforgettable or irreparable, and inevitably in due course, hereditary. The punishment of the crime should go on, it
is generally believed, even after the death of the criminal: in short, crime is inherited, passed down from generation to generation, not even
stopping at the third and fourth, as the Bible puts it.
This notion of hereditary crime little by little leads to another one, utterly contrary to enlightened thinking: collective guilt. Since you
cannot put skeletons on trial, and it would be difficult, centuries later, to find the direct descendants of the perpetrators, guilt passes to the
presumed descendants taken collectively, that is, to a whole nation, a present-day nation. By contrast, we may recall that at Nuremberg,
although the crimes judged were of unprecedented atrocity, it was not some eternal Germany that was convicted but twenty-two Nazi

leaders.

Words and deeds


It is clear that this movement has come to take on quasi-religious overtones. We are seeing how sacrilege is constructed: the victim, in
present-day society, has the aura of the sacred. Suddenly the writing of history and academic research finds itself subject to the discretion of
judges and legislators, as it once was by the churchmen of the Sorbonne.
Right-thinking people today go so far as to demand that the law treat speech and action as one, assimilating opinions to acts. Proof of this
return to magical thinking can be found in an article about the second Armenian law published in Le Monde on October 10, 2006, and signed
by ten lawyers. Clearly in favor of this law, they wrote that to dispute the reality of genocide is not simply equivalent to misinterpretation of
a political crime. It is participation in it. They also demanded that any attempt to dispute the genocidal character of an event should be
removed from the special sphere of freedom of the press ... and freedom of expression and repositioned within penal law, along with
other physical acts intended to obstruct justice, and lastly that any contestation of this type be recognized as an offense related to
genocide.
We may note that for centuries the legislature and even the confessional has distinguished mere intention and verbal aggression from
physical aggression. If we were to follow those zealous lawyers, we would find ourselves little by little stepping back into those barbarous
ages when thought was confused with action and a spoken insult was considered as criminal as a dagger-thrust.
*
he only democratic country that has imposed this kind of history laws on its citizens is France; and the declarations of some of its political
figures show that it prides itself on continuing in this direction. On October 12, 2006, a deputy speaking in the Assembly chamber said, We
do not leave medicine to the doctors, so why should we leave history to the historians? This is a mere fallacy, needless to say. True, we do
not leave medicine to the doctors in one sense the government defines, fortunately for us, the conditions under which medicine is
practiced. But we have never seen Parliament replace doctors diagnoses and prescriptions with its own opinions, and we do not line up
outside the Palais Bourbon to be cured of scrofula. Yet what are the deputies currently doing with the past? Replacing the historians
diagnoses with their own. In so doing, they put scholars in the custody of judges: who can say for sure especially with respect to ever
more remote periods and countries where the disputes and trivializations to be prohibited by our new laws will begin and end?
Nothing is more fragile than freedom of expression; nothing is more constantly threatened. A century ago, another set of well-meaning
deputies sought to make insulting the Republic a misdemeanor. Clemenceau, unquestionably a defender of the Republic, got up and said,
My esteemed colleagues: I stand here to urge you to permit people to insult the Republic with impunity. With the best intentions in the
world, you are directly opposing the principle of freedom. For I defy any lawyer to enter this Assembly and tell you by what sign a judge
will recognize that discussion has stopped and insult has begun .... And if nobody knows the answer to that question, I will say that you are
making a law based in arbitrary judgment, not in freedom. Any discussion, even when nothing about it is obviously offensive or hateful,
can be seen as insulting insulting to those whose feelings on a painful subject are wounded, or to those whose political or religious
convictions are affronted. It can be insulting, too, when it is based on fallacious arguments and misinformation. But let us remember that
societies whose citizens live in contented harmony, with no debate and no conflict, are
also societies where there is no freedom.

Franoise Chandernagor
Vice-president, Libert pour lhistoire.

You might also like