You are on page 1of 14

Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy

Philosophy in Chile
First published Thu Apr 2, 2015
Philosophy in Chile, as in the rest of Latin America, has been an academic pursuit ever since the
conquest and settlement of the New World by Spain and Portugal in the early sixteenth century. Very few
philosophers ventured beyond the walls of academic or religious institutions (usually one and the same)
during the entire colonial period, which ended in most Spanish American countries (the exceptions being
Cuba and Puerto Rico) in the early nineteenth century. Even after Independence, philosophy remained a
fundamentally academic endeavor. Chile, in contrast to other nations in the region, has shown remarkable
institutional continuity, with the exception of the years of military rule in the last quarter of the twentieth
century.
The academic context in which the discipline developed, however, has not prevented philosophers from
engaging in social and political activities, and, especially, in debates concerning the history, culture and
direction of the emerging nations. Philosophers have been important political figures since the early
republic as well as leaders in the university reform processes that have taken place during the countrys
modern history. During the period of military rule (19731990) several became important opponents of
the regime. A concern for politics, in fact, has dominated the agenda of philosophers, including those
who have denounced the encroachment of politics in the discipline.
The centrality of politics, even in cases of direct involvement in it, has not distracted philosophers from
their essential commitment to exploring different philosophical (predominantly European) schools, some
specific fields within the discipline, such as logic and metaphysics, and some thematic concerns like the
role of religion in a secular state, the impact of modernity on self and society, and the role of universities
in the development of nationhood. Chilean philosophy is characterized by a constant tension between
academic pursuits solely informed by developments within the discipline, and critical outlooks that
demand a closer philosophical engagement with politics and society.
1. Colonial Background
2. Independence and Nationhood: The Formative Years
3. The Era of Positivism
4. The Reaction Against Positivism.
5. The Reception and Critique of Philosophical Professionalism
6. The Period of Military Rule
Bibliography
Primary Sources
Secondary Sources
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. Colonial Background

While one cannot speak properly of a Chilean philosophy until the former colony achieved its
independence from Spain in February 1818, it would not be appropriate to ignore the activities of several
philosophers during the Spanish colonial period. Philosophical activity made a first appearance with the
teachings of Cristbal de Valdespino in the Dominican convent in Santiago in 1595, spread quickly to
other secondary schools in the seventeenth century, and picked up momentum with the creation of the
Royal University of San Felipe in 1758. Prominent scholars during this time, and up to the early
nineteenth century include clergymen Alonso Briseo, Miguel de Vias, Manuel Ovalle, and Manuel
Antonio Talavera, all of whom wrote significant philosophical treatises mostly within the scholastic
tradition. The expulsion of the Jesuits in 1767 meant that several talented authors, including Miguel de
Olivares, Felipe Gmez de Vidaurre, Juan Ignacio Molina and Manuel Lacunza, published their works
elsewhere. The main difference between the two traditions resides in that the former cultivated
philosophy as an instrument to address theological questions whereas the latter were more oriented to
practical concerns, such as understanding the conditions of the New World, and were therefore less
interested in theological questions. Lay authors who covered some philosophical themes reflecting the
concerns of the Enlightenment during the late colonial period included Manuel de Salas and Juan Egaa,
who served as bridges to the post-independence period.
But it is with the foundation of Chile as an independent republic that Chilean philosophy began to be
cultivated in a systematic manner within institutions of higher education entrusted with a deliberate
national purpose. Five major periods characterize the history of the discipline: the formative years from
Independence through 1865; the ascendancy and decline of Positivism from 1865 through 1920; the antipositivist reaction from 1920 to 1950; the rise and critique of professionalization from 1950 to 1973, and
the fate of philosophy under military rule, from 1973 to 1990. These periods coincide roughly with the
major stages in the development of philosophy in other countries in the region. The period since 1990,
when Chile returned to democratic rule, is much more difficult to trace and define. And yet, the main
foundations of the discipline have not changed in any substantial way.

2. Independence and Nationhood: The Formative Years


Philosophers in the immediate post-independence period, and up to the arrival of Positivism in the 1860s,
had to confront the complexities of the changing relations between Church and State. The independence
struggle which pitted Chileans against Chileans had been a struggle against arbitrary and unstable
colonial rule, not against the Catholic Church. On the contrary, the Church was seen as an indispensable
ally in the building of new republican institutions. Hence, all Chilean constitutional documents in the
nineteenth century proclaimed Catholicism as the official religion of the State. As a result, public
institutions, including educational institutions, had to conform to Catholic doctrine. Because most
philosophers were believers this limitation did not necessarily mean a problem. But as philosophers they
were compelled to examine doctrines and schools that were secular or even antagonistic to Catholicism.
In such cases they discussed the doctrines but suppressed that which could be seen as beyond the pale of
the Catholic Church. As a result, a thinker like David Hume could be commented upon but in the end
heavily criticized because of his skepticism. A school such a French Idologie could be discussed, but
again deprived of its most materialistic edges. The outlet for philosophical production was by and large
the secondary school textbook, which had to be approved by the appropriate governmental mechanisms,
and this usually meant applying Catholic Church criteria for the philosophically permissible and the
theologically acceptable. There was no room for openly anti-Catholic tracts such as Francisco Bilbaos
Sociabilidad chilena (1844, collected in 1866), which ended up burnt for blasphemy and immorality.
Philosophers still found ways to be true to their discipline, and yet recognize the constraints imposed by

Catholicism as the official religion of the State. Perhaps the best example is the work of Andrs Bello
(17811865), who explored a wide range of philosophical sources, especially those of the Scottish
Enlightenment. However, he never questioned the importance of religion in general, and Catholicism in
particular. His Filosofa del entendimiento was published posthumously in 1881, but substantial parts of
this work appeared in the 1840s.
Bellos Filosofa shows an important acquaintance, and much agreement, with the work of Thomas Reid,
Thomas Brown, and Dugald Stewart. Bellos main emphasis in this work was the acquisition of ideas,
which he considered the central endeavor of the discipline. His work was divided in two parts, namely,
psychology and logic. For Bello, philosophys task was the appropriate understanding of the origin of
ideas, and the guiding of human actions. In the process, Bello engaged the thought of John Locke and
George Berkeley seriously, although by no means uncritically. The impact of Bellos philosophical work
was limited at first, but it spread rapidly to other countries in the region in the twentieth century, and
became one of the few works by a Latin American philosopher to be fully translated into English (1984).
And yet, perhaps the most important, in the sense of the most widely used philosophical text in Chile was
the Curso de filosofa moderna by Ramn Briseo (18141910), published in two volumes in 184546.
Compared to Bellos contribution, Briseos work was far more partial to Catholicism, and thus had an
easy entry into the curricula of public and private schools. Multiple editions appeared during the
remainder of the nineteenth century. Briseos partiality to an idea of philosophy closely linked to
religion is evident in his coverage of ethics and natural law, where he argued that the practice of religion
was the most important duty of a human being, and concluded that any philosophy that does not lead to
the conclusions of Christianity is dangerous and false (1846: 216). While Andrs Bello did not entirely
disagree with the religious emphasis of the work, he objected to the poor coverage of logic, which in
Briseos treatment was limited to deductive logic. Hence it can be observed that the larger polemic
concerning the role of religion was manifest in the choice of subfields for the teaching of the discipline.
Although philosophy developed in an academic context in the post independence period, and helped
define the mission of the University of Chile when it was founded in 1842 (Andrs Bello crafted the
statutes of the institution and became its Rector for the next 23 years), other philosophers brought the
discipline closer to political action. The most important example is Jos Victorino Lastarria (18171888)
who advocated the elimination of the colonial legacies still embedded in the Church, and in authoritarian
practices that prevented free individual initiative and expression. Be it through his congressional seat, his
role as founder of the Liberal Party (1849), or his copious writings, Lastarria promoted the main tenets of
liberalism and articulated a coherent philosophy of history firmly based on Enlightenment thought. Other
thinkers who contributed to the development of liberal views in Chile included the Argentine exiles
Domingo Faustino Sarmiento (18111888) and Juan Bautista Alberdi (18191884), who presented their
ideas in various widely circulated writings, some of them of a philosophical nature, and through vigorous
polemics in the press.

3. The Era of Positivism


As elsewhere in Latin America, Positivism in Chile had a significant impact in a number of areas,
including philosophy. The arrival of Positivism coincided with the rising tide of anticlericalism in Chile
from the 1860s and the 1880s, but its influence was not restricted to attacks against the Church. Indeed, it
had a profound influence in education, contributing to a substantial transformation of the curriculum at
the secondary and higher education levels. Initially, however, it was a timely weapon against the
influence of the Church in Chilean society.

The fundamental appeal of Positivism was through its notion of progress. Based on Auguste Comtes
work, Positivism allowed anticlerical thinkers to dismiss the theological stage as a primitive state in the
evolution of humanity, one that would inevitably be superseded by the metaphysic and scientific
stages. The political implications and uses of this evolutionary view were obvious: to advance to the
highest level, Chileans needed to leave behind the religious influence of the Catholic Church. As
articulated by the leading early proponent of Positivism, Jos Victorino Lastarria, who abandoned his
liberal commitments (for being based on abstract, or metaphysical, principles), science could address
the problems of Chilean society in the most effective way. Others heeded the call, and concentrated on
such important priorities as education. The liberal historian Diego Barros Arana had done much in this
regard through reforms of the curriculum at the Instituto Nacional, as did Miguel Luis Amuntegui, who,
in his role as Minister of Education, in 1879 formally introduced the teaching of science in public
schools. But the most significant positivist figure was Valentn Letelier (18521919), whose Filosofa de
la educacin (1927 [1891]) served as the basis for a profound reorientation of philosophical studies in
Chile. In his view, the theological and metaphysical emphases that had dominated Chilean education
since independence had done little to unify the country around a core of shared beliefs. In his view, only
the certainties of science could do that. The instrument for achieving this higher stage was logic, which
he successfully introduced in the educational plan of 1893, at the expense of ethics and theodicy.
Consistent with this emphasis, Juan Serapio Lois (18441913) published the most complete treatment of
logic from a Comtean perspective, the Elementos de filosofa positiva (19061908), applying logical
analysis to the methodology of a range of sciences.
Philosophy under the influence of Letelier acquired a scientific character, with a special emphasis on
experimental psychology that would ultimately provoke a reaction among thinkers dissatisfied with the
local unresponsiveness to new currents of thought emerging in Europe and the United States. Positivism,
however, did help in consolidating the study of philosophy at both the higher level (through the Instituto
Pedaggico at the Universidad de Chile), and at secondary schools, where it was an obligatory subject of
study.
Although it was less influential, it is important to point out that there was another branch of Positivism
represented by the brothers Juan Enrique (18521927) and Jorge Lagarrigue (18541894), who embraced
the religious ideas of the late Auguste Comte and brought the Religion of Humanity to Chile. Although
this variety of Positivism survived well into the twentieth century, it left little influence in the field of
philosophy. Politically, it was aligned with the presidentialist and allegedly authoritarian administration
of Jos Manuel Balmaceda, who was defeated in the Civil War of 1891. As in the case of Comtes
support of Louis Bonaparte, the Lagarrigue brothers brand of positivism came to be associated with
authoritarianism.

4. The Reaction Against Positivism.


The revolt against Positivism in Chile was led by Enrique Molina (18711964), a graduate of the
Positivist-inspired Pedagogical Institute at the University of Chile. Molina found the study of philosophy
stagnant, and considered the emphasis on science stifling. He initially shared the schools emphasis on a
scientific approach to the teaching of several disciplines, including philosophy. However, after
encountering the work of William James and, especially, Henri Bergson, Molina launched a philosophical
campaign to establish metaphysics as the most important field within the discipline. In his view, the
positivist concept of progress had come to mean material, and specifically technological, progress. In
his most important philosophical work, De lo espiritual en la vida humana (1937), Molina argued that
science and technology had done little to advance human happiness. Therefore, an emphasis on the life of

the spirit (though not in a religious sense) deserved to become the central endeavor of the discipline as
well as its main contribution to society. He developed a hierarchy of values where those of a spiritual
nature reigned over crass materialistic concerns.
Molinas argument was by no means devoid of a political edge. He argued that after Positivism Marxism
had become the main conduit for the spread of materialistic concerns. In the Chile of the middle decades
of the twentieth century, Marxism had indeed made major inroads into the country, and Molina was part
of a generation of philosophers who were alarmed by the threat represented by Marxist ideology. His
response was the advancement of philosophical views that placed metaphysics at the top of a hierarchy of
fields. He then set out to reorient the study of philosophy in the country through his writings and
institutional activities, including the rectorship of the University of Concepcin, which he founded in
1919.
In disciplinary terms, Molinas arguments found resonance among Catholic thinkers like Clarence
Finlayson (19131954), and the more secularly inclined Jorge Millas (19171982), whose Idea de la
individualidad (1943) was entirely free of any ties to Positivism, emphasizing instead individual liberty
as the principal concern of the discipline. Although Millas retained a high level of political engagement
throughout his career, he viewed individual liberty as a higher stage of human existence beyond the
externalities of society and politics.
The institutional expression of such views was a succession of changes in the philosophy curriculum that
incorporated new authors and new schools of thought such as phenomenology, existentialism, and neoThomism. In 1929, Pedro Len Loyola created a Center for Philosophical Studies at the University of
Chile, and in 1931 a major university reform placed the Pedagogical Institute, the home of philosophical
studies, at the more academically oriented Faculty of Philosophy. Philosophy was also taught at the
Universidad de Concepcin and at the Catholic University of Chile (founded in 1888). The latter
institution created an Academy of Philosophy in 1923, and a Pedagogical School in 1943 where courses
on ontology, theodicy and ethics were offered. By 1950, it added courses on epistemology, metaphysics
and aesthetics. Increased philosophical activity translated into the creation of the Chilean Society of
Philosophy (Sociedad Chilena de Filosofa) in 1948, and the launching of the Revista de Filosofa the
next year. The outbreak of the Spanish Civil War and the Second World War meant that several
philosophers arrived in Chile as refugees in the 1940s, adding to the increased variety of philosophical
concerns.
Despite the diversity, the main consensus among Chilean philosophers was that the discipline was
autonomous, especially from politics. Individual philosophers could and did have political commitments,
but they all agreed that the field was a highly specialized academic endeavor. They entered the phase that
Argentine philosopher Francisco Romero named philosophical normalcy, which was characterized by
university-level positions, publications in specialized journals, international conferences, teaching stints
in foreign institutions and, above all, a strong divide separating academic philosophical activity from
social and political concerns.

5. The Reception and Critique of Philosophical Professionalism


The philosophical model established in reaction to Positivism blossomed in the 1950s as a result of the
activities of the Chilean Society of Philosophy, the regular publication of the Revista de Filosofa, and
the internationalization of the philosophical community. The society was recognized by the InterAmerican Federation of Philosophical Societies, the Institut International de Philosophie, and the

Fedration International des Socits de Philosophie. Foreign faculty taught regularly at the major
philosophy departments in the country, and in 1956 the first international congress of the Inter-American
Society of Philosophy took place in Santiago, featuring such prominent figures as Miguel Reale, Eduardo
Nicol, Risieri Frondizi, Francisco Romero, Jos Gaos and Jos Ferrater Mora. Presenters in the fields of
logic, philosophy of science and theory of knowledge included Willard Van Orman Quine, Roderick
Chisholm, Mario Bunge, Francisco Mir Quesada, and Juan David Garca Bacca. The local philosophical
community could celebrate with pride the effectiveness with which the discipline had become a
recognized professional endeavor both nationally and internationally.
Initially, a new generation of philosophers embraced the high international standards of philosophical
work proclaimed by the Chilean philosophical community. In addition to Jorge Millas, new names
appeared steadily in publications and other professional venues: Flix Schwartzmann (19132014),
Marco Antonio Allendes (19252000), Humberto Giannini (19272014), Juan de Dios Vial Larran
(1924), Gastn Gmez Lasa (1926), and Juan Rivano (19262015). However, not all thought that the
professional model was the only, or indeed the most appropriate for the conditions of Chile at the time.
Some had come from diverse disciplinary backgrounds or interests, and therefore became skeptical of a
model of philosophical activity that appeared to be excessively subservient to international (mainly
European) currents, and perhaps even irrelevant for the country. Juan Rivano, in particular, developed a
devastating critique of the levels of abstraction he found in the philosophical community, and questioned
the distance of his colleagues from the concerns of the nation. Coming from the field of logic, he
questioned the lack of consistency in the usage by his colleagues of several key philosophical concepts.
He also introduced the work of British neo-Hegelians such as Francis H. Bradley and Harold Joachim,
but soon moved to the study of Hegel and Marx in such works as Entre Hegel y Marx (1962) and Desde
la religin al humanismo (1965). He advocated a type of philosophical work that was both critical of
social and economic conditions, and more responsive to the complex changes taking place in Chile and
Latin America.
The wider philosophical community rejected the claims of Rivano and dismissed his call for bringing the
discipline in line with the needs of the nation. They not only reinforced the foundations of philosophical
professionalism but also proceeded to develop a spirited defense of a university model that sheltered the
work of professionals from the demands of the larger society. The rapid expansion of the electorate, the
emergence of strong parties of the Left, and the expansion of higher education enrollments all introduced
pressures for university reform which the defenders of philosophical professionalism resisted. In terms of
philosophical schools, they continued to engage phenomenological themes, and particularly the work of
Martin Heidegger. The critique of modernity was the dominant theme among philosophers in their
specialized work.
The most articulate voice from the professionalist camp came from Jorge Millas who, following the
Spanish philosopher Jos Ortega y Gasset, was a strong critic of mass society. In such works as Ensayos
sobre la historia espiritual de Occidente (1960) and El desafo espiritual de la sociedad de masas (1962),
Millas reiterated the claim that spirituality occupied a higher place than materialism, and especially
Marxism, in the concerns of the discipline. What was new in the context of the 1960s was the connection
he made between the aims of the discipline and those of the university: both had the obligation to resist
the pressures of mass society. Others who followed this line of argument, like Flix Martnez Bonati
(1929), and Juan de Dios Vial Larran, emphasized the role of the university in forming an intellectual
elite inspired by the higher aims of philosophy. They anticipated, in many ways, the arguments of Allan
Bloom in The Closing of the American Mind (1987).
Such debates on the nature of higher education and the responsibility of philosophers merged with

political competition inside the most important universities of the country. Philosophers who claimed to
be apolitical or who opposed the encroachment of politics in university campuses paradoxically became a
part of openly political debates. Significant university reforms were introduced in the latter half of the
1960s but the debates on the nature of higher education and the aims of philosophy did not diminish.
What did diminish was the level of philosophical production, which dropped consistently through the
years of the Salvador Allende administration (19701973). The Revista de Filosofa ceased publication
in 1970, classes were frequently interrupted, and books of a philosophical nature were reduced to a
trickle. Perhaps the most important exceptions are to be found in a handful of philosophers, especially
Jorge Millas, whose two-volume Idea de la filosofa was published in 1970. The philosophical
community was deeply divided as a result of political turmoil and disputes over the aims of the
university.

6. The Period of Military Rule


The military coup of September 11, 1973 led by General Augusto Pinochet was followed by sixteen and
a half years of dictatorship. The proclaimed intent of the coup was to reestablish order after the chaotic
years of the Allende administration. Within a few years, however, it was obvious that the regime intended
to transform Chilean society and politics, closing the Congress, banning political parties, especially those
of the Left, and introducing a new Constitution in 1980. In the area of higher education, the military
regime reversed years of university autonomy and intervened directly in the administration of the
principal universities of the country: it appointed as Rectors military officers on active duty, closed
several schools and faculties, and purged academics and students perceived to be dissidents or potential
opponents. The military as an institution did not act alone, as it counted on a significant number of
civilian supporters.
The Department of Philosophy at the University of Chile was perhaps the hardest hit among philosophy
departments in the nation. As the flagship public university, with a history going back to 1842, the
University of Chile was from the start of the military regime the target of severe and continuous
repression. Critics like Juan Rivano were arrested and sent into exile while others, like Edison Otero
(1946), were dismissed without charges. The military placed the University of Chile first under the aegis
of the Air Force and subsequently (1976) the Army. But instead of relying on those professionals who
had opposed university reform, like Jorge Millas, Humberto Giannini, or Gastn Gmez Lasa, it placed
largely unknown though sympathetic philosophers in key academic and administrative positions. As a
result, professional philosophers became increasingly alienated from the regime and some turned into
vocal opponents.
Perhaps the most important example is that of Jorge Millas. Initially he was hopeful that the military
would indeed seek to realize his ideal view of the university as a home of reflection and reason. By 1976,
however, his hopes had turned into disillusion: Millas attacked the military intervention of the
universities, declaring that there was no improvement from the politicization of higher education in the
1960s and early 1970s; the university had become an institution under surveillance (1981: 84). His
own philosophical work paid increasing attention to the theme of violence, as he demonstrated in La
violencia y sus mscaras (1978), co-authored with critical philosopher Edison Otero, a collaboration that
signaled a rapprochement between the two historical philosophical traditions in the country. Isolated and
increasingly alienated by government censorship, Millas retreated to the southern Universidad Austral in
Valdivia, where he was initially welcomed but soon removed (1980) for his increasingly public and vocal
criticisms of the regime. In one of his last works, Idea de la Universidad (1981), he renewed his life-long
commitment to the university as the site of scholarship and reflection, and reiterated his critique of

military intervention. Silenced, isolated and ill, he died at the age of 65 in 1982.
Other philosophers were not as vocal as Millas, but were clearly unhappy with the military handling of
both the universities and the nation. Established philosophers like Humberto Giannini and Gastn Gmez
Lasa concentrated on their philosophical work, and on occasion made pronouncements that could be seen
as critical. But the environment of repression was not conducive to the dialogue and free inquiry that they
felt the field required. Exiled philosophers like Juan Rivano were even less able to find national outlets
for their opinions. He was banned from the country and unable to return until after the plebiscite of 1988.
That was the turning point that unleashed the transition to democracy that culminated with the
presidential elections of 1989, and the inauguration of the Patricio Aylwin administration in 1990.
The balance of the period is negative for the philosophers involved except for those who occupied the
positions of those persecuted under military rule and who remained in their posts even after the
restoration of democracy. Still, an important change took place as a result of the years of dictatorship:
those philosophers who were hostile to politics now fully embraced the value of democracy with all its
implications for accommodating different points of view. As a result of the hostile climate present at the
universities, many migrated to independent research centers and thus entered into dialogue with scholars
from other disciplines. Philosophers were thus able to break away from the separation of philosophy and
politics that characterized the foundations of the field in the twentieth century.
Another important element to emerge from the period of military rule, and perhaps even before, is the
number of philosophers who moved abroad in response to political turmoil, like Roberto Torretti (1930)
and Carla Cordua (1925), or because of outright persecution as in the case of Juan Rivano and Renato
Cristi (1941). There is a significant philosophical production that must be included in a longer-term
examination of the history of the field in Chile. There are others of a younger generation who were
trained abroad and whose work upon returning to the country started to have an impact in the field. Time
will tell when a clearly defined new period can be added for an extended examination of the history of
Chilean philosophy.

Bibliography
Primary Sources
Alberdi, Juan Bautista, 1900, Ideas para presidir la confeccin del curso de filosofa contempornea, in
Escritos pstumos de Juan Bautista Alberdi, (Volume 15), Buenos Aires: Imprenta Juan Bautista
Alberdi.
Allendes, Marco Antonio, 1980, La imaginacin creadora en la ciencia y el arte, Atenea: Revista de
Ciencia, Arte y Literatura, 442: 3744.
, 1965, Relacin entre religin y filosofa en el pensamiento hind, Anales de la Universidad de
Chile, 135: 131152.
Bello, Andrs, 1881 [1981], Filosofa del entendimiento y otros escritos filosficos, in, 1981, Obras
completas, (Volume 3), Caracas: Fundacin La Casa de Bello.
, 1984, Philosophy of the Understanding, trans. by O. Carlos Stoetzer, Washington, D.C.: General
Secretariat, Organization of American States.
Bilbao, Francisco, 1866, Obras completas de Francisco Bilbao, Manuel Bilbao (ed.), Buenos Aires:
Imprenta de Buenos Aires.
Briseo, Ramn, 18451846, Curso de filosofa moderna, para el uso de los colegios hispanoamericanos, y particularmente para el de los de Chile: extractado de las obras de filosofa que

gozan actualmente de celebridad, Volumes 12, Valparaso: Imprenta del Mercurio.


Egaa, Juan, 1827, Tractatus de re logica, metaphisica, et morali pro filiis et alumnis Instituti nacionalis
Jacobo politanae erudiendis J.E., Santiago: Raimundo Rengifo.
Finlayson, Clarence, 1969, Antologa, Toms MacHale (ed.), Santiago: Editorial Andrs Bello.
Frei Montalva, Eduardo, 1946, La poltica y el espritu, Santiago: Editorial del Pacfico, 2nd edition.
Giannini, Humberto, 1965, Reflexiones acerca de la convivencia humana, Santiago: Facultad de Filosofa
y Educacin, Universidad de Chile.
, 1968, El mito de la autenticidad, Santiago: Ediciones de la Universidad de Chile.
, 1981, Desde las palabras, Santiago: Ediciones Nueva Universidad.
, 1982, Tiempo y espacio en Aristteles y Kant, Santiago: Editorial Andrs Bello.
, 1987, La reflexin cotidiana: Hacia una arqueologa de la experiencia, Santiago: Editorial
Universitaria.
Gmez Lasa, Gastn, 1978a, Platn: El periplo dialgico, Valdivia: Ediciones de la Universidad Austral
de Chile.
, 1978b, Platn: Aporas dialgicas, Valdivia: Universidad Austral de Chile.
, 1979, Platn: Primera agona, Valdivia: Departamento de Extensin Acadmica, Universidad
Austral de Chile.
, 1980a, La institucin del dilogo filosfico, Valdivia: Universidad Austral de Chile.
, 1980b, El expediente de Scrates, Valdivia: Universidad Austral de Chile, 1980.
, 2011, El periplo de la metafsica, Santiago: Ediciones Universidad Diego Portales.
Lagarrigue, Jorge, 1875, La filosofa positiva, Revista Chilena, 2: 632645.
, 1879, Una conversin a la Religin de la Humanidad, Revista Chilena, 14: 228246.
Lagarrigue, Juan Enrique, 1926, La Religin de la Humanidad, Santiago: Fundacin Juan Enrique
Lagarrigue, 5th edition.
Lastarria, Jos Victorino, 1875, Lecciones de poltica positiva, Paris: Librera de A. Bouret e Hijo.
, 1885, Recuerdos literarios. Datos de la historia literaria de la Amrica espaola y del progreso
intelectual de Chile, Santiago: Librera de M. Servat, 2nd edition.
, 18431844, Investigaciones sobre la influencia social de la conquista i del sistema colonial de los
espaoles en Chile, Anales de la Universidad de Chile, 1: 199271.
Letelier, Valentn, 1895, La lucha por la cultura: Miscelnea de artculos polticos y estudios
pedaggicos, Santiago: Imprenta y Encuadernacin Barcelona.
, 1927 [1891], Filosofa de la educacin, Buenos Aires: Cabaut, 2nd edition.
Lois, Juan Serapio, 19061908, Elementos de filosofa positiva, Copiap: Imprenta de la Tribuna, 2nd
edition.
Loyola, Pedro Len, 1954, Una oposicin fundamental en el pensamiento moderno: Causalidad y
evolucin, Santiago: Editorial Jurdica de Chle.
Mann, Wilhelm, 1915, El espritu general y los ramos de la enseanza filosfica en el Liceo, Anales de
la Universidad de Chile, 137: 643707.
Marn, Ventura, 18341835, Elementos de la filosofa del espritu humano escritos por Ventura Marn
para el uso de los alumnos del Instituto Nacional de Chile, Santiago: Imprenta de la Independencia.
Martnez Bonati, Flix, 1965, La situacin universitaria, Santiago: Prensas de la Editorial Universitaria.
, 1960, La misin humanstica y social de nuestra universidad, Anales de la Universidad de Chile,
119: 114137.
Millas, Jorge, 1943, Idea de la individualidad, Santiago: Prensas de la Universidad de Chile.
, 1960, Ensayos sobre la historia espiritual de Occidente, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1962, El desafio espiritual de la sociedad de masas, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1963, Discurso sobre la universidad y su reforma, Anales de la Universidad de Chile, 127: 249
261.

, 1970, Idea de la filosofa, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.


, 1981, Idea y defensa de la universidad, Santiago: Editorial del Pacfico; Coedicin Corporacin de
Promocin Universitaria.
Millas, Jorge and Edison Otero, 1978, La violencia y sus mscaras, Santiago: Ediciones Aconcagua.
Molina, Enrique, 1914, Filosofa americana: Ensayos, Paris: Casa Editorial Garnier Hermanos.
, 1921, De California a Harvard: Estudio sobre universidades norteamericanas y algunos problemas
nuestros, Santiago: Sociedad Imprenta y Litografa Universo.
, 1925, Dos filsofos contemporneos: GuyauBergson, Santiago: Editorial Nascimento.
, 1942, Confesin filosfica y llamado de superacin a la Amrica hispana, Santiago: Editorial
Nascimento.
, 1945, Discursos universitarios, Santiago: Editorial Nascimento.
, 1947 [1937], De lo espiritual en la vida humana, Santiago: Editorial Nascimento, 2nd edition.
Mora, Jos Joaqun de, 1832, Cursos de lgica y tica segn la escuela de Edimburgo, Lima: Imprenta
de Jos Masas.
Otero, Edison, 1979, Los signos de la violencia, Santiago: Editorial Aconcagua.
, 1982, El pensador en la caverna, Estudios Sociales, 31(1): 79108.
, 1985, Los derechos de la inteligencia, Santiago: Instituto Chileno de Estudios Humansticos.
, 1986, Reivindicacin de la filosofa, Estudios Sociales, 48(2): 195200.
, 1986, Los filsofos y el poder: Un anecdotario, Estudios Sociales, 50(4): 4756.
Otero, Edison and Ricardo Lpez, 1989, Pedagoga del terror: Un ensayo sobre la tortura, Santiago:
Editorial Atena.
Oyarzn, Luis, 1967, Temas de la cultura chilena, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
Rivano, Juan, 1962, Entre Hegel y Marx: una meditacin ante los nuevos horizontes del humanismo,
Santiago: Comisin Central de Publicaciones de la Universidad de Chile.
, 1964, Curso de lgica antigua y moderna, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1965, Desde la religin al humanismo, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1965, El punto de vista de la miseria, Santiago: Facultad de Filosofa y Educacin, Universidad de
Chile.
, 1966, Contra sofistas, Santiago: Encuadernadora Hispano-Suiza.
, 1969, Cultura de la servidumbre: Mitologa de importacin, Santiago: Editorial Santiago.
, 1985, Lgica elemental, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria, 2nd edition.
, 1986a, Perspectivas sobre la metfora, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1986b, Globalizacin y estrategias lgicas, Cuadernos Americanos, 265(2): 7285.
, 1987, Mitos: Su funcin social y cultural, Santiago: Pehun.
Schwartzmann, Flix, 1950, El sentimiento de lo humano en Amrica; ensayo de antropologa filosfica,
(Volume 1), Santiago: Universidad de Chile.
, 1953, El sentimiento de lo humano en Amrica; antropologa de la convivencia, (Volume 2)
Santiago: Universidad de Chile.
, 1967, Teora de la expresin, Santiago: Ediciones de la Universidad de Chile.
Stahl, Gerold, 1964, Elementos de metalgica y metamatemticas, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
Torretti, Roberto, 1967, Manuel Kant: Estudio sobre los fundamentos de la filosofa crtica, Santiago:
Ediciones de la Universidad de Chile. 2nd edition, 2005.
, 2006, Estudios filosficos, 19571987, Santiago: Ediciones Universidad Diego Portales.
, 2007, Estudios filosficos, 19862006, Santiago: Ediciones Universidad Diego Portales.
Varas, Jos Miguel, 1828, Lecciones elementales de moral, Santiago: Imprenta de la Independencia.
Varas, Jos Miguel and Ventura Marn, 1830, Elementos de ideologa, Santiago: Imprenta de la
Independencia.
Vial Larran, Juan de Dios, 1965, Idea de la universidad, in La universidad en tiempos de cambio,

Santiago: Editorial del Pacfico, pp. 712.


, 1971, Metafsica cartesiana, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1979, Tres ideas de la filosofa y una teora, Santiago: Facultad de Ciencias Fsicas y Matemticas,
Universidad de Chile.
, 1980, La filosofa de Aristteles como teologa del acto, Santiago: Editorial Universitaria.
, 1987, Una ciencia del ser, Santiago: Ediciones Universidad Catlica.

Secondary Sources
Abelln, Jos Luis, 1967, Filosofa espaola en Amrica, 19361966, Madrid: Ediciones Guadarrama.
Ardao, Arturo, 1986, Andrs Bello, filsofo, Caracas: Biblioteca de la Academia Nacional de la Historia.
, 1963, Assimilation and Transformation of Positivism in Latin America, Journal of the History of
Ideas, 24(4): 515522.
Astorquiza, Fernando (ed.), 1982, Bio-Bibliografa de la filosofa en Chile desde el siglo XVI hasta 1980,
Santiago: Universidad de ChileInstituto Profesional de Santiago.
(ed.), 1985, Bio-Bliblografa de la filosofa en Chile desde 1980 hasta 1984, Santiago: Universidad
de Chile-Instituto Profesional de Santiago.
Atria, Manuel, 1970, El pensamiento metafsico de Clarence Finalyson, Mapocho, 23: 7182.
Bader, Thomas, 1970, Early Positivistic Thought and Ideological Conflict in Chile, The Americas,
26(February): 376393.
Bazn, Armando, 1954, Vida y obra del maestro Enrique Molina, Santiago: Editorial Nascimento.
Bloom, Allan, 1987, The Closing of the American Mind: How Higher Education Has Failed Democracy
and Impoverished the Souls of Todays Students, New York: Simon & Schuster.
Collier, Simon, 1967, Ideas and Politics of Chilean Independence, 18081833, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Cristi, Renato, 1975, El gesto filosfico de Lastarria, Teora, 56(December): 314.
Cristi, Renato y Carlos Ruiz, 1981, Hacia una moral de mercado?, Mensaje, 30(June): 244.
Da Costa Leiva, Miguel, 1978, El pensamiento filosfico de Enrique Molina, Ph.D. Dissertation,
Universidad Complutense de Madrid.
Donoso, Ricardo, 1946, Las ideas polticas en Chile, (Coleccin Tierra Firme), Mexico: Fondo de
Cultura Econmica.
, 1964, El Instituto Pedaggico: Tres generaciones de maestros, Journal of Inter-American Studies,
6(January): 516.
Echeverra Yez, Jos R., 1965, La enseanza de la filosofa en la universidad hispanoamericana,
Washington, D.C.: Unin Panamericana.
Escobar, Roberto, 1970, Clarence Finlayson: el filsofo que regres del silencio, Revista
Interamericana de Bibliografa, 20(4): 459463.
, 1976, La filosofa en Chile, Santiago: Universidad Tcnica del Estado.
Frondizi, Risieri, 1948, Hay una filosofa Iberoamericana? Realidad, 3: 158170.
Frondizi, Risieri and Jorge J. E. Gracia, 1975, El hombre y los valores en la filosofa lainoamericana del
siglo XX, Mexico: Fondo de Cultura Econmica.
Fuentealba H., Leonardo, 1959, Filosofa de la historia en Letelier, Revista Chilena de la Historia y
Geografa, 127(January-December): 313351.
Gngora, Mario, 1986, Ensayo histrico sobre la nocin de Estado en Chile en los siglos XIX y XX,
Santiago: Editorial Universitaria, 2nd edition.
Gracia, Jorge J. E. (ed.), 1986, Latin American Philosophy in the Twentieth Century: Man, Values, and
the Search for Philosophical Identity, Buffalo, N.Y.: Prometheus Books.

, 1984, Philosophical Analysis in Latin America, History of Philosophy Quarterly, 1(1): 111122.
Gracia, Jorge J. E. and Ivn Jaksic, 1984, The Problem of Philosophical Identity in Latin America,
Inter-American Review of Bibliography, 34(1): 5371.
Gracia, Jorge J. E., Eduardo Rabossi, Enrique Villanueva y Marcelo Dascal (eds.), 1984, Philosophical
Analysis in Latin America, Dordrecht, Boston, Lancaster: D. Reidel Publishing Co.
Hale, Charles A., 1986, Political and Social Ideas in Latin America, 18701930, in The Cambridge
History of Latin America, (Volume 4), Leslie Bethell (ed.), Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
pp. 367643.
Hanisch Espndola, Walter, S. J., 1963, En torno a la filosofa en Chile, 15941810, Santiago:
Universidad Catlica de Chile.
, 1968, Rousseau, la ideologa y la escuela escocesa en la filosofa chilena, 18281830, Santiago:
Instituto de Historia, Universidad Catlica de Chile.
Huneeus Gana, Jorge, 1910, Cuadro histrico de la produccin intelectual de Chile, Santiago: Biblioteca
de Escritores de Chile.
Jaksic, Ivn, 1984, Philosophy and University Reform at the University of Chile, 18421973, Latin
American Research Review, 19(1): 5786.
, 1989, Academic Rebels in Chile: The Role of Philosophy in Higher Education and Politics. Albany,
N.Y.: State University of New York Press.
Jobet, Julio Csar, 1970, Doctrina y praxis de los educadores representativos chilenos, Santiago:
Editorial Andrs Bello.
Jorrn, Miguel and John D. Martz, 1970, Latin American Political Thought and Ideology, Chapel Hill:
The University of North Carolina Press.
Kilgore, William J., 1969, The Development of Positivism in Latin America, Inter-American Review of
Bibliography, 19: 2342.
Krebs, Ricardo (ed.), 1981, Catolicismo y laicisimo: Las bases doctrinarias del conflicto entre la Iglesia
y el Estado en Chile, 18751885, Santiago: Ediciones Nueva Universidad, Pontificia Universidad
Catlica de Chile.
Lipp, Solomon, 1975, Three Chilean Thinkers, Waterloo, Ontario: Wilfrid Laurier University Press.
Milliani, Domingo, 1963, Utopian Socialism, Transitional Thread from Romanticism to Positivism in
Latin America, Journal of the History of Ideas, 24: 523538.
Molina, Enrique, 1953, La filosofa en Chile en la primera mitad del siglo XX, Santiago: Editorial
Nascimento.
Ortega y Gasset, Jos, 1965, Misin de la universidad y otros ensayos afines, Madrid: Editorial Revista
de Occidente, 4th edition.
, 1983, Recuerdo del paso por Chile del filsofo Jos Ortega y Gasset, Occidente, 301(MayJune
1983): 3238.
Oyarzn, Luis, 1953, El pensamiento de Lastarria, (Coleccin de Estudios Jurdicos y Sociales),
Santiago: Editorial Jurdica de Chile.
, 1949, Lastarria y los comienzos del pensamiento filosfico en Chile durante el siglo XIX, Revista
de Filosofa, 1(August): 2756.
Pontificia Universidad Catlica de Chile, 1982, La presencia de la filosofa en la Universidad Catlica
(18881973), Santiago: Pontificia Universidad Catlica de Chile.
Rodrguez, Rogelio, 1983, Un filsofo en el exilio, Pluma y Pincel, 10: 3236.
, 1985, Un filsofo que no calla, Pluma y Pincel, 16: 1214.
Sacks, Norman P., 1972, Jos Victorino Lastarria: Un intelectual comprometido en la Amrica Latina,
Revista Chilena de Historia y Geografa, 140: 153193.
Salazar Bondy, Augusto, 1968, Existe una filosofa en nuestra Amrica?, Mexico: Siglo XXI.
Sarti, Sergio, 1976, Panorama della filosofa Ispanoamericana contemporanea, Milan: Cisalpino-

Golliardica.
Schultz, Margarita and Jorge Estrella, 1978, La antropologa de Flix Schwartzmann, Santiago: Editorial
Universitaria.
Schutte, Ofelia, 1987, Toward an Understanding of Latin American Philosophy: Reflections on the
Formation of a Cultural Identity, Philosophy Today, 31(Spring): 2134.
Schwartzmann, Flix, 1971, La Philosophie au Chili, in La Philosophie Contemporaine, Raymond
Klibanski (ed.), Florence: La Nuova Editrice, pp. 635642.
Sehlinger, Peter Joseph, 1969, The Educational Thought and Influence of Valentn Letelier, Ph.D.
Dissertation, University of Kentucky.
Spindler, Frank M., 1980, Francisco Bilbao: Chilean Disciple of Lamennais, Journal of the History of
Ideas, 41(3): 487496.
Stabb, Martin S., 1967, In Quest of Identity: Patterns in the Spanish American Essay of Ideas, 1890
1960, Chapel Hill: The University of North Carolina Press.
Varona, Alberto, 1973, Francisco Bilbao: Revolucionario de Amrica. Buenos Aires: Ediciones
Excelsior.
Vial Larran, Juan de Dios, 1983, Situacin de la Filosofa en Chile, in Las ciencias sociales en Chile,
1983: Anlisis de siete disciplinas, Santiago: Corporacin de Promocin Universitaria, pp. 117125.
Vicua Subercaseaux, Benjamn, 1909, Memoria sobre la produccin intelectual en Chile, Santiago:
Sociedad Imprenta y Litografa Universo.
Vidal Muoz, Santiago, 1956, Apuntes sobre la filosofa en Chile, Cursos y Conferencias, 48(March):
3960.
, 1977, La filosofa en Chile, Cuadernos de Filosofa, 6: 1944.
Woll, Allen L., 1982, A Functional Past: The Uses of History in Nineteenth-Century Chile, Baton Rouge
and London: Louisiana State University Press.
Woodward, Ralph Lee (ed.), 1971, Positivism in Latin America, 18501900: Are Order and Progress
Reconcilable? Lexington, Mass.: D. D. Heath and Company.
Zea, Leopoldo, 1949, Dos etapas del pensamiento en Hispanoamrica: Del romanticismo al positivismo,
Mexico: El Colegio de Mxico.
(ed.), 1980, Pensamiento positivista latinoamericano, Caracas: Biblioteca Ayacucho.

Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources


Chilean Association of Philosophy (in Spanish).

Related Entries
Comte, Auguste | Latin American philosophy

Acknowledgments
Acknowledgments: The author wishes to thank Andrs Estefane, Francisco Gallegos, Susana Gazmuri,
Sergio Missana, Juan Luis Ossa for their helpful comments.
Copyright 2015 by
Ivan Jaksic <ijaksic@stanford.edu>
Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.
Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free
The SEP would like to congratulate the National Endowment for the Humanities on its 50th anniversary
and express our indebtedness for the five generous grants it awarded our project from 1997 to 2007.
Readers who have benefited from the SEP are encouraged to examine the NEHs anniversary page and, if
inspired to do so, send a testimonial to neh50@neh.gov.

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright 2015 by The Metaphysics Research Lab, Center
for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University
Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

You might also like