You are on page 1of 25

Foucault _ Chomsky FULL VERSION transcript

published by roarmag.org
FULL TRANSCRIPT OF THE DEBATE:
HOST:
In the 17th century, when Galilei discovered that the Earth turned around the Sun
instead of the other way around, many people were in a state of great shock. They had
thus far believed that humans were at the center of the cosmos and around this idea
they had built their whole belief system. Suddenly, this did not seem to be the case
anymore. Foucaults theory can be clarified by pointing out that he takes a Galilei-type
standpoint in relation to culture. Since the time of Galilei, people have thought that
when it came to culture and society, humans were at the center. After all, it is they
who created them. Foucault denies this. He argues that when it comes to culture, it is
not the subject that counts, but the structure, the universal. Something that is in itself
understandable if one realizes that the rules according to which mankind behaves
were already invented long before one was born, and the name of the inventor
remains completely unknown to us.
One can compare Foucault to Galilei, but from another perspective, one can also
compare Chomsky to Galilei because his work in the science of language, linguistics,
has had a great revolutionary influence all over the world. Chomsky has brought
about a major transformation in the field of linguistics. Interestingly, Chomskys
theories point in the exact opposite direction as those of Foucault. Chomsky gives
much more primacy to the subject. In the confrontation between these two completely
different thinkers, it is moreover good to remember that they work in very different
fields. Foucault is a cultural researcher; Chomsky is a language researcher. In other
words, Foucaults interest lies in the history of scientific language, while Chomskys
interest lies in the daily language we use.
It is interesting, and maybe also not coincidental, that the debate between these two
thinkers only really gets exciting in the second half when they start discussing politics.
Still I believe it is good that this is preceded by a theoretical part, because in any
discussion about philosophy and society, what matters are not the political

standpoints certain thinkers happen to take but rather the arguments on the basis of
which they do so.
It might also be nice to note that this discussion took place in the auditorium of the
technical college of Eindhoven (NL): a discussion between two philosophers, two
researchers, whose work is characterized by great precision, great detail and also
great clarity. Moreover I thought it was quite symbolic that the debate took place in a
space with a lot of glass: the inner- and outer-world blended together. During the
broadcast you could see the traffic outside passing by. Symbolic indeed, because the
relationship between inner- and outer-world is central to the first half of the fourth
philosophers debate about human nature and the ideal society.

ELDERS:
Ladies and gentlemen, welcome to the fourth debate of the International
Philosophers Project. Tonights debaters are Mr. Michel Foucault of the College de
France, and Mr. Noam Chomsky of the Massachusetts Institute of Technology. Both
philosophers have points in common and points of difference. Perhaps the best way to
compare both philosophers is to look at them as mountain-diggers working at
opposite sides of the same mountain with different tools, without even knowing if
they are working in each others direction.
All learning concerning man, ranging from history to linguistics and psychology, are
faced with the question of whether, in the last instance, we are the product of all kinds
of external factors, or if, in spite of our differences, we have something we could call a
common human nature, by which we can call each other human beings.
So my first question is to Mr. Chomsky, because you often employ the concept of
human nature, and in this connection you are using terms like innate ideas and
innate structures. Which arguments can you derive from linguistics in order to give
such a central position to this notion of human nature?
CHOMSKY:
Well, let me begin in a slightly technical way. A person who is interested in studying

languages is faced with a very definite empirical problem. Hes faced with an
organism, a mature, lets say adult speaker, who has somehow acquired an amazing
range of abilities, which enable him in particular to say what he means, to understand
what people say to him, to do this in a fashion that I think is proper to call highly
creative. Now, the person who has acquired this intricate and highly articulated and
organized collection of abilities the collection of abilities that we call knowing a
language that person has been exposed to a certain experience; he has been
presented in the course of his lifetime with a certain amount of data, of direct
experience with a language.
We can investigate the data thats available to this person; having done so, in
principle, were faced with a reasonably clear and well-delineated scientific problem,
namely that of accounting for the gap between the really quite small quantity of data,
small and rather degenerate quantity of data thats presented to the person, to the
child, and the very highly articulated, highly systematic, profoundly organized
resulting knowledge that he somehow derives from this data. Furthermore even
more remarkable we notice that in a wide range of languages, in fact all that have
been studied seriously, there are remarkable limitations on the kinds of systems that
emerge from the very different kinds of experience to which people are exposed.
There is only one possible explanation, which I have to give in a rather schematic
fashion, for this remarkable phenomenon, namely the assumption that the individual
himself contributes a good deal, an overwhelming part in fact, of the general
schematic structure and perhaps even of the specific content of the knowledge that he
ultimately derives from this very scattered and limited experience. That is, to put it
rather loosely: the child must begin with the knowledge, certainly not with the
knowledge that hes hearing English or Dutch or French or something else, but he
does start with the knowledge that hes hearing a human language of a very narrow
and explicit type, that permits a very small range of variation. And its because he
begins with that highly organized and very restrictive schematism, that he is able to
make the huge leap from scattered and degenerate data to highly organized
knowledge.
I would claim then that this instinctive knowledge, if you like, this schematism that
makes it possible to derive complex and intricate knowledge on the basis of very
partial data, is one fundamental constituent of human nature. But then I assume that

in other domains of human intelligence, in other domains of human cognition and


even behavior, something of the same sort must be true. The collection of this mass of
schematisms, innate organizing principles, which guides our social and intellectual
and individual behavior, thats what I mean to refer to by the concept of human
nature.
ELDERS:
Well, Mr. Foucault, when I think of your books like The History of Madness and
Words and Objects, I get the impression that you are working on a completely
different level and with an opposite aim and goal; when I think of the word
schematism in relation to human nature, then you are just trying to work out that
there are several periods, several schematisms. What do you think about this?
FOUCAULT:
Well if you permit, I will answer in French because my English is so bad that I would
be ashamed of answering in English. It is true that I mistrust the notion of human
nature a little, and for the following reason: I believe that of the concepts or notions
that a science can use, not all have the same degree of elaboration. Lets take the
example of biology. Within the field of biology, there are concepts that are more or
less well-established, like the concept of a reflex. But there also exist peripheral
notions, which do not play an organizing role within science, they are not
instruments of analysis and they are not descriptive either. These notions simply
serve to point out some problems, or rather to point out certain fields in need of
study.
For instance, there exists a very important concept in the field of biology: the concept
of life. In the 17th and 18th centuries, the notion of life was hardly used when studying
nature: one classified natural beings, whether living or non-living, in a vast
hierarchical tableau. Life was a concept they didnt use and didnt need. At the end of
the 18th century a number of problems arose, for instance in relation to the internal
organization of these natural beings. Moreover, thanks to the use of the microscope,
different sorts of phenomena suddenly came to light that could not have been
perceived until then and whose mechanisms and function had been unclear in the
past. The developments in chemistry have also highlighted certain problems in

relation to the connections between chemical reactions and the physiological


processes of organisms.
And thats how an entire field appeared, one that was completely new for biologists,
one that is nowadays known as life. Life was a concept that served to point out new
fields of study that science still had to discover. I would say, as a historian of science,
that the concept of life was an epistemological indicator; an index of the problems
that still had to be uncovered. And I wonder whether perhaps one could say the same
thing about human nature.
HOST:
Foucault is therefore comparing Chomskys concept of human nature with the
concept of life as it is used in biology and in its history. He does this because he sees
the concept of human nature more as an indication of a research program rather than
as an indication of humans potential for achievement. For him, human nature acts as
a scientific shopping list and nothing more. Chomsky is willing to accept this as long
as it is clear that the fields of biology, physiology and neurology still dont have the
means to adequately describe human nature and human capacity for language.
Quite early on in the debate, the moderator Mr. Elders finds it difficult to keep the
interaction flowing between the two speakers. This is partly due to the different
languages they speak, but most importantly due to the fact that Chomsky and
Foucault inhabit such different worlds of thought, to the point in which their ideas
easily slide past each other. We actually observe the curious phenomenon of two
brains thinking simultaneously, where one picks up the last claim of the other in
order to further elucidate it from his own system of thought.
For Chomsky the concept of creativity plays an important role, and the following part
of the debate will be largely dedicated to this issue. For him, creativity is actually a
characteristic of all human beings. Everybody uses it. People stuck in traffic who,
unexpectedly and on the spot, have to think about what to do next. A teacher who
doesnt want to fall into a pattern of authoritarian behavior but when confronted with
a difficult pupil, has to come up with an alternative type of behavior. But above all,
this creativity applies to the child who learns a language and who curiously learns to
produce new language.

Foucault is opposed to this idea. He constantly emphasizes the so-called


epistemological field within which human activity takes place. This epistemological
field or episteme is described as the totality of unconscious rules that manage the
totality of all separated fields of knowledge. Foucault also talks of tableau, which he
also calls system of elements. In the debate he also mentions the word grille: bar
or grid. Perhaps its best to understand it as a network that all people are part of
within a particular culture, whether they want it or not. It is a set of rules to which
people obey in their thoughts and derive their search for identity, coherence and so
forth. This system is not a creation of particular individuals: it decides the rules of the
think-and-do habits we call culture, which every individual is subjected to. Such a
system is not a thing or an idea: it lies precisely in between the two.
For Foucault, the history of thought should not be associated with the history of ideas
or with the development of the mind, but rather it should be understood as
discontinuous transformations transitioning from one network to another. Foucaults
approach highly differs from Chomskys, for whom creativity plays a central role. At
this point we clearly realize Foucaults tendency to dethrone the subject, as already
illustrated with the example of Galilei. The philosophy of Foucault is a philosophy in
which the philosopher constantly disappears from sight. One could say that,
paradoxically, it is a philosophy without philosophers: an idea that has to be
generalized because according to Foucault, humans are greatly absent within their
own culture. In this respect, we can understand Foucaults strong and negative
reaction towards the moderator who showed interest in his private matters. When
Foucault debates, it is about everything except Foucault himself.
This is an introduction to the following, quite detailed theoretical part of the debate,
which seems to mainly focus on one question: to what extent is the individual able to
discover something new, and if so, how should we make sense of this? This seems to
me to be a very relevant question, especially if we remind ourselves that new forms of
behavior, knowledge and science will need to be unveiled, as long as we want to
survive together in this world. We now resume the debate where Foucault explains
why he does not pay much attention to the creativity of the individual from a
historical perspective.
FOUCAULT:

Within the traditional history of science, the creativity of individuals has been
accorded maximum importance. The history of science, up until recently, essentially
consisted of showing how an individual, whether it was Newton or Mendel, had been
the creator, or rather the discoverer of a reality that was already existing in things and
in the world, a reality that no other person had previously discovered.
I believe the postulate that lies dormant within the traditional history of science is
that truth exists in order to be known; yet the human mind, due to the effect of a
number of inhibitions or obstacles, has not managed to see this truth. The mind is
made to see the truth and a contingent obstacle is impeding him to see it. According
to some historians, this obstacle could be linked to socio-economic conditions, or to
different forms of mentality, or to the belief and naivety in old religious myths and
moral themes. All of these could act as obstacles, as blinders to those who want to see
the truth. In reality, the mind is meant to see, it is made to have access to the truth. In
this traditional conception of the history of science, on the one hand there is an
emphasis on the creativity of the individual who has the right to possess the truth,
and yet a system of obstacles will prevent him from capturing, formulating and
constructing this truth to which he is essentially entitled to possess.
I believe the problem that is being posed is the exact opposite. What happens when
we witness a great scientific transformation? In a great scientific transformation for
instance the birth of biology in the mid 17th century, or the birth of philology at the
end of the 18th and the beginning of the 19th century it is true that a number of
obstacles, prejudices and preconceived ideas tumble and disappear. What strikes me,
is that at the moment of its birth, science not only gets rid of a certain number of
obstacles but also eliminates and masks a certain amount of existing knowledge and
wisdoms.
Its as if applying a new grid, which allows for the appearance of phenomena that had
been previously masked while at the same time masking already existing knowledge.
Therefore, a science, the advancement of science and the acquisition of science, is not
simply the oblivion of old prejudices, or the fall of certain obstacles. It is a new grid
that masks certain things while allowing for the appearance of new knowledge.
Therefore, when I criticize the notion of creativity, what I mean is that truth is not
acquired through a kind of continuous and cumulative creation, but rather through a
set of grids stacked on top of one another, which leak old and collect new knowledge.

CHOMSKY:
I think in part were slightly talking at cross-purposes, because of a different use of the
term creativity. In fact, I should say that my use of the term creativity is a little bit
idiosyncratic and therefore the onus falls on me in this case, not on you. But when I
speak of creativity, Im not attributing to the concept the notion of value that is
normal when we speak of creativity. That is, when you speak of scientific creativity,
youre speaking, properly, of the achievements of a Newton. But in the context in
which I have been speaking about creativity, its a normal human event. Im speaking
of the kind of creativity that any child demonstrates when hes able to come to grips
with a new situation: to describe it properly, react to it properly, tell one something
about it, think about it in a new fashion for him and so on. I think its appropriate to
call those creative acts, but of course without thinking of those acts as being the acts
of a Newton. Its the lower levels of creativity that Ive been speaking of.
Now, as far as what you say about the history of science is concerned, I think thats
correct and illuminating and particularly relevant in fact to the kinds of enterprise
that I see lying before us in psychology and linguistics and the philosophy of the
mind. That is, I think there are certain topics that have been, in your words, repressed
or put aside during the scientific advances of the past few centuries. But now, I think,
we can overcome, it is possible to put aside those limitations and forgettings, and to
bring into our consideration precisely the topics that animated a good deal of the
thinking and speculation of the 17th and 18th centuries, and to incorporate them
within a much broader and I think deeper science of man that will give a fuller role
though it is certainly not expected to give a complete understanding to such notions
as innovation and creativity and freedom and the production of new elements of
thought and behavior within some system of rule and schematism. Those are concepts
that I think we can come to grips with.
FOUCAULT:
I believe that what Mr. Chomsky said and what I tried to show is actually very similar.
Indeed, there exist in fact only possible creations, possible innovations. One can only,
in terms of language or of knowledge, produce something new by putting into play a
certain number of rules which will define the acceptability or the grammaticality of

these statements, or which will define, in the case of knowledge, the scientific
character of the statements.
Thus, we can roughly say that linguists before Mr. Chomsky mainly insisted on the
rules of construction of statements and less on the innovation represented by every
new statement, or the hearing of a new statement. In the history of science or in the
history of thought, we placed more emphasis on individual creation, we had kept
aside and left in the shadows these communal, general rules, which obscurely
manifest themselves through every scientific discovery, every scientific invention, and
even every philosophical innovation. These are not only linguistic rules but also
epistemological rules, which characterize contemporary knowledge.
CHOMSKY:
Well, perhaps I can try to react to those comments within my own framework in a way
which will maybe shed some light on this. How is it that we are able to construct any
kind of scientific theory at all? How is it that, given a small amount of data, its
possible for various scientists, for various geniuses even, over a long period of time, to
arrive at some kind of a theory, at least in some cases, that is more or less profound
and more or less empirically adequate? This is a remarkable fact. And, in fact, if it
were not the case that these scientists, including the geniuses, if they didnt have built
into their minds somehow an obviously unconscious specification of what is a
possible scientific theory, then this inductive leap would certainly be quite impossible:
just as if each child did not have built into his mind the concept of human language in
a very narrowing way, then the inductive leap from data to knowledge of a language
would be impossible.
So even though the process of, lets say, deriving knowledge of physics from data is far
more complex, far more difficult for an organism such as us, far more drawn out in
time, requiring intervention of genius and so on and so forth, nevertheless in a certain
sense the achievement of discovering physical science or biology or whatever you like,
is based on something rather similar to the achievement of the normal child in
discovering the structure of his language: that is, it must be achieved on the basis of
an initial limitation, an initial restriction on the class of possible theories. And the fact
that science converges and progresses shows us that such initial limitations and
structures exist. That is, I dont think that scientific progress is simply a matter of

accumulative addition of new knowledge and the absorption of new theories and so
on. Rather I think that it has this sort of jagged pattern that you describe, forgetting
certain problems and leaping to new theories.
FOUCAULT:
And transforming the same knowledge.
CHOMSKY:
Right. But I think that one can perhaps hazard an explanation for that fact.
Oversimplifying grossly, I really dont mean what Im going to say now literally, its as
if, as human beings of a particular biologically given organism, we have in our heads,
to start with, a certain set of possible intellectual structures, possible sciences. Okay?
Now, in the lucky event that some aspect of reality happens to have the character of
one of these structures in our mind, then we have a science. And it is because of this
initial limitation in our minds to a certain kind of possible science that provides the
tremendous richness and creativity of scientific knowledge.
It is important to stress, and this has to do with your point about limitation and
freedom, if it were not for these limitations, we would not have the creative act of
going from a little bit of knowledge, a little bit of experience, to a rich and highly
articulated and complicated array of knowledge. Its precisely because of this that the
progress of science has the erratic and jagged and transformational character that you
described. And that doesnt mean that everything is ultimately going to fall within the
domain of science. Quite the contrary. Personally I believe that many of the things we
would like to understand, and maybe the things we would most like to understand,
such as the nature of man, or the nature of a decent society, or lots of other things,
might really fall outside the scope of possible human science.
ELDERS:
Well I think we have now two questions out of this statement. One question is: Mr.
Foucault, do you agree with the statement about the combination of limitation,
fundamental limitation?
FOUCAULT:

It is not a matter of combination. Creativity only becomes possible thanks to a system


of rules: it is not a mixture of order and freedom. Freedom can only be truly exercised
thanks to a system of regularity. Where perhaps I dont completely agree with Mr.
Chomsky is when he places these regularities within the sphere of the human mind or
human nature. I would like to know whether one cannot discover this system of
regularity and of constraint, which makes science possible, somewhere else, even
outside the human mind: in social forms, in relations of production, in class struggles,
etc.
ELDERS:
But what does this theory of knowledge mean for your theme of the death of man or
the end of the period of the 19th and 20th centuries?
FOUCAULT:
But this is not related to what we are talking about.
ELDERS:
I dont know, because I was trying to apply what you have said in relation to your
anthropological concept. You have already refused to speak about your own creativity
and freedom, havent you? Well, Im wondering what are the psychological reasons
for this.
FOUCAULT:
You can wonder about it, but I cant help that.
ELDERS:
But what are the objective reasons, in relation to your perception of understanding, of
knowledge, of science, for refusing to answer these personal questions? Does it have
to do with your conception of society? When there is a problem for you to answer,
what are your reasons for making a problem out of a personal question?
FOUCAULT:
No, Im not making a problem out of a personal question; I make of a personal

question an absence of a problem. In the entire tradition of the history of thought,


ideas and sciences, one has always questioned the problem of knowing. At what age
was Newton weaned in order to conceive the law of universal gravitation? At which
period did Cuvier meet his first mistress in order to finally discover fossils and
comparative anatomy, etc.?
I believe these types of analyses, which I am now simplifying, are not very interesting.
It is much more interesting to understand the transformations of a certain knowledge
within the general field of science and within the so-called vertical field which consists
of a society, a culture, a civilization at a particular moment in time. Once we finally
grasp the totality of this transformation, we realize that the little individual moments
of a wise mans life are not important.
HOST:
Foucaults last comment suggests yet again how the individual life of the researcher
tends to disappear from sight. Then what about the relation between man and his
culture when it comes to politics, also when asking the question of how we can change
culture and society? After all, one can show that in the history of science and culture,
the input of the individual remains almost negligible, but the question how do I act?
the political question remains standing.
It may thus become clear by now that, from Foucaults perspective, this question
rapidly develops into how far can mankind escape from its own culture?. It is
important to note that Foucault doesnt want to distance himself from politics. In the
contrary, he says I would have to be ideologically blind to not interest myself for that
which is most substantial to human existence: economic relations, power relations,
you name it. Therefore, Chomsky and Foucault do agree on the importance of the
political question.
It may also be informative to explicitly mention that Chomsky defines anarchosyndicalism as his political standpoint. In his opinion, it is necessary to abolish the
different forms of capitalism in order to favor direct workers participation in workers
councils and so on. Decentralization, socialization and participation are keywords in
Chomskys political program. Chomsky might say he sees no obvious relationship
between his scientific and political views, but the following opening statement reveals

that he heads straight from his scientific conceptions to politics. His political and
scientific views may not flow logically from one another, but they certainly are
heading in the same direction.
CHOMSKY:
Let me begin by referring to something that we have already discussed, that is, if it is
correct, as I believe it is, that a fundamental element of human nature is the need for
creative work, for creative inquiry, for free creation without the arbitrary limiting
effect of coercive institutions, then, of course it will follow that a decent society should
maximize the possibilities for this fundamental human characteristic to be realized.
That means trying to overcome the elements of repression and oppression and
destruction and coercion that exist in any existing society, ours for example, as a
historical residue.
Now a federated, decentralized system of free associations, incorporating economic as
well as social institutions, would be what I refer to as anarcho-syndicalism; and it
seems to me that this is the appropriate form of social organization for an advanced
technological society, in which human beings do not have to be forced into the
position of tools, of cogs in the machine. In which the creative urge that I think is
intrinsic to human nature, will in fact be able to realize itself in whatever way it will, I
dont know all the ways in which it will.
FOUCAULT:
I would say that I am much less advanced than Mr. Chomsky in this respect. That is, I
admit not being able to define, not even to propose, an ideal social model for the
functioning of our scientific or technological society. On the other hand, one of the
tasks that seems immediate and urgent to me, over and above anything else, is this: it
is the custom, at least in our European society, to consider that power is localized in
the hands of the government and that it is exercised through a certain number of
particular institutions, such as the administration, the police or the army. One knows
that all these institutions are made to transmit and apply a certain number of orders
and to punish those who dont obey.
But I believe that political power also exercises itself through the mediation of a
certain number of institutions that look as if they have nothing in common with

political power and as if they are independent from it, but in fact they are not. One
knows that the university and more generally all teaching systems, which simply
appear to disseminate knowledge, are made to maintain a certain social class in power
and to exclude the instruments of power of another social class. Another example is
psychiatry, which in appearance is also intended for the good of humanity, is at the
knowledge of psychiatrists. Psychiatry is another way to bring to bear the political
power over a social class. Justice is yet again another example.
It seems to me that the real political task in our contemporary society is to criticize
the workings of institutions, particularly the ones that appear to be neutral and
independent, and to attack them in such a way that the political violence, which has
always exercised itself obscurely through them, will finally be unmasked so that one
can fight against them. If we seek to advance straight away a profile or a formula of
the future society without having thoroughly criticized all the relations between the
different forms of political violence that exercise their power within our society, we
run the risk of letting them reproduce even in the case of the noble and apparently
pure forms, such as anarcho-syndicalism.
CHOMSKY:
Yes, I would certainly agree with that, not only in theory but also in action. That is,
there are two intellectual tasks: one, and the one which I was discussing, is to try to
create the vision of a future just society. Another task is to understand very clearly the
nature of power and oppression and terror and destruction in our own society. And
that certainly includes the institutions you mentioned, as well as the central
institutions of any industrial society, namely the economic, commercial and financial
institutions and in particular, in the coming period, the great multinational
corporations, which are not very far from us physically tonight [i.e. Philips in
Eindhoven]. Those are the basic institutions of oppression and coercion and
autocratic rule that appear to be neutral. After all they say: Well, were subject to the
democracy of the market place.
Still, I think it would be a great shame to put aside entirely the somewhat more
abstract and philosophical task of trying to draw the connections between a concept of
human nature that gives full scope to freedom and dignity and creativity and other
fundamental human characteristics, and relate that to some notion of social structure

in which those properties could be realized and in which meaningful human life could
take place. And in fact, if we are thinking of social transformation or social revolution,
though it would be absurd of course to draw out in detail the point that we are hoping
to reach, still we should know something about where we think we are going, and such
a theory may tell it to us.
FOUCAULT:
Yes, but then isnt there a danger here? If you say that a certain human nature exists,
that this human nature has not been given the rights and possibilities that allow it to
realize itself in our contemporary society Thats really what you have said, I believe.
CHOMSKY:
Yes.
FOUCAULT:
And if one admits this, doesnt one risk defining this human nature which is at the
same time ideal and real, and has been hidden and repressed until now in terms
borrowed from our society, from our civilization, from our culture? I will give an
example by greatly simplifying it. Marxism, at the end of the 19th century and the
beginning of the 20th century admitted that in capitalist societies man hadnt reached
his full potential for development and self-actualization; that human nature was
effectively alienated in the capitalist system. And Marxism ultimately dreamed of a
liberated human nature. However, to conceive and dream of this human nature? It
was, in fact, the bourgeois model. Marxism considered that a happy society was a
society that gave room, for example, to a bourgeois type of sexuality, to a bourgeois
type of family, to a bourgeois type of aesthetic.
And it is moreover very true that this has happened in the Soviet Union: for humans
to finally be able to realize their true nature, a kind of society, simultaneously real and
utopic, had been reconstituted and transposed from the bourgeois society of the 19th
century. The result, that you also realized, I think, is that it is difficult to conceive of
what human nature precisely is. Isnt there a risk that we will be led into error? Mao
Zedong spoke of a bourgeois human nature and a proletarian human nature, and he
considers that they are not the same thing.

CHOMSKY:
Well, you see, I think that in the intellectual domain of political action, that is the
domain of trying to construct a vision of a just and free society on the basis of some
notion of human nature, we face the very same problem that we face in immediate
political action. For example, to be quite concrete, a lot of my own activity really has
to do with the Vietnam War, and a good deal of my own energy goes into civil
disobedience.
Well, civil disobedience in the U.S. is an action undertaken in the face of considerable
uncertainties about its effects. For example, it threatens the social order in ways
which might, one might argue, bring about fascism; and that would be a very bad
thing for America, for Vietnam, for Holland and for everyone else. So that is one
danger in undertaking this concrete act. On the other hand there is a great danger in
not undertaking it, namely, if you dont undertake it, the society of Indochina will be
torn to shreds by American power. And in the face of those uncertainties one has to
choose a course of action.
Similarly, in the intellectual domain, one is faced with the uncertainties that you
correctly pose. Our concept of human nature is certainly limited, partial, socially
conditioned, constrained by our own character defects and the limitations of the
intellectual culture in which we exist. Yet at the same time it is of critical importance
that we have some direction, that we know what impossible goals were trying to
achieve, if we hope to achieve some of the possible goals. And that means that we have
to be bold enough to speculate and create social theories on the basis of partial
knowledge, while remaining very open to the strong possibility, and in fact
overwhelming probability, that at least in some respects were very far off the mark.
ELDERS:
Well, perhaps it would be interesting to delve a little deeper into this problem of
strategy. So, for example, in the case of Holland, we had something like a population
census. One was obliged to answer questions on official forms. Would you call it civil
disobedience if one refused to fill in the forms?
CHOMSKY:

Right. I would be a little bit careful about that, because, going back to a very
important point that Mr. Foucault made, one does not necessarily allow the state to
define what is legal. Now the state has the power to enforce a certain concept of what
is legal, but power doesnt imply justice or even correctness, so that the state may
define something as civil disobedience and may be wrong in doing so. For example, in
the United States the state defines it as civil disobedience to, lets say, derail an
ammunition train thats going to Vietnam; and the state is wrong in defining that as
civil disobedience, because its legal and proper and should be done.
Its proper to carry out actions that will prevent the criminal acts of the state, just as it
is proper to violate a traffic ordinance in order to prevent a murder. If I was standing
at a street corner and the traffic light were red, I was standing in my car and then I
drove across the traffic light to prevent somebody from, lets say, machine-gunning a
group of people, of course thats not a violation of law, its an appropriate and proper
action; no sane judge would convict you for such an action. Similarly, a good deal of
what the state authorities define as civil disobedience is not really civil disobedience:
in fact, its legal, obligatory behavior in violation of the commands of the state, which
may or may not be legal commands. So one has to be rather careful about calling
things illegal, I think.
FOUCAULT:
Yes, but I would like to ask you a question. When, in the United States, you commit an
illegal act
CHOMSKY:
Which I regard as illegal, not just the state
FOUCAULT:
When the state considers it illegal. Do you make your action because you find it just,
by virtue of an ideal justice? Or do you make it because class struggle renders it useful
and necessary? Do you refer to an ideal justice?
CHOMSKY:
Again, very often when I do something which the state regards as illegal, I regard it as

legal: because I regard the state as criminal. But in some instances thats not true. Let
me be quite concrete about it and move from the area of class war to imperialist war,
where the situation is somewhat clearer and easier. Take international law, a very
weak instrument as we know, but nevertheless it incorporates some very interesting
principles. International law in many respects is the instrument of the powerful: that
is, international law permits much too wide a range of international forceful
intervention in support of existing power structures that define themselves as states
against the interests of masses of people who happen to be organized in opposition to
states.
But, in fact, international law is not solely of that kind. And in fact there are
interesting elements of international law, for example, embedded in the United
Nations Charter, which permit, in fact, I believe require the citizen to act against his
own state in ways that the state will falsely regard as criminal. Nevertheless, hes
acting legally, because international law also happens to prohibit the threat or use of
force in international affairs, except under some very narrow circumstances, of which,
for example, the war in Vietnam is not won. Which means that, in the particular case
of the Vietnam War, which interests me most, the American state is acting in a
criminal capacity. And the people have the right to stop criminals from murdering
people. Just because the criminal happens to call your action illegal when you try to
stop him, it doesnt mean it is illegal.
A perfectly clear case of that is the present case of the Pentagon Papers in the United
States, which, I suppose, you know about. Reduced to its essentials and forgetting
legalisms, what is happening is that the state is trying to prosecute people for
exposing its crimes. Thats what it amounts to.
FOUCAULT:
So it is in the name of a purer justice that you criticize the functioning of justice? It is
important for me to know about this, because in France there is currently a debate
about this problem of justice and of a popular judicial institution. A certain number of
people, including Sartre, believe that in order to make a critique of the current penal
system or of police practices, we have to create a kind of tribunal which, in the name
of a superior, ideal and human justice, will condemn the practices of the French
judges or policemen.

Moreover, there is another group of people, myself included, who say this shouldnt
be done because when they refer to an ideal justice, which the tribunal is supposed to
apply, they refer to a certain number of judicial ideas which were formed in our time
by a certain number of individuals who are themselves, directly or indirectly, a
product of their societies. We have to attack the practices of justice, we have to attack
the police and their practices: but in terms of war and not in terms of justice.
CHOMSKY:
Surely you believe that your role in the war is a just role; that you are fighting a just
war, to bring in a concept from another domain. And that, I think, is important. If you
thought that you were fighting an unjust war, you couldnt follow that line of
reasoning. I would like to slightly reformulate what you said. It doesnt seem to me
that the difference is between legality and ideal justice; its rather between legality and
better justice. Now this better system may have its defects, it certainly will. But
comparing the better system with the existing system, without being confused into
thinking that our better system is the ideal system, we can then argue, I think, as
follows: the concept of legality and the concept of justice are not identical; theyre not
entirely distinct either.
Insofar as legality incorporates justice in this sense of better justice, referring to a
better society, then we should follow and obey the law, and force the state to obey the
law and force the great corporations to obey the law, and force the police to obey the
law, if we have the power to do so. If in those areas where the legal system happens to
represent not better justice, but rather the techniques of oppression that have been
codified in a particular autocratic system, well, then a reasonable human being should
disregard and oppose them, at least in principle; he may not, for some reason, do it in
fact.
FOUCAULT:
I would simply like to reply to your first sentence, when you said that if you didnt
consider the war you wage against the police to be just, you wouldnt wage it. I would
like to reply to you in terms of Spinoza and tell you that the proletariat doesnt wage
war against the ruling class because it considers such a war to be just. The proletariat
wages war against the ruling class because it wants, for the first time in history, to

take power. And its because it wants to take power that it considers such a war to be
just.
CHOMSKY:
Yeah, I dont agree.
FOUCAULT:
One wages war to win, not because it is just.
CHOMSKY:
I personally dont agree with that. For example, if I could convince myself that
attainment of power by the proletariat would lead to a terroristic police state, in which
freedom and dignity and decent human relations would be destroyed, then I wouldnt
want the proletariat to take power. In fact the only reason for wanting any such thing,
I believe, is because one thinks, rightly or wrongly, that some fundamental human
values will be achieved by that transfer of power.
FOUCAULT:
I will answer you this: when the proletariat takes power, it may be quite possible that
the proletariat will exert a violent, dictatorial and even bloody power towards the
classes over which it has just triumphed. I cant see what claim anyone could make
against this. But if you ask me what would happen if the proletariat exerted bloody,
tyrannical and unjust power towards itself, then I would say that this could only occur
if the proletariat hadnt really taken power, but that a class outside the proletariat, or
a group of people inside the proletariat, or a bureaucracy or petit bourgeois elements,
had taken power.
CHOMSKY:
Well, Im not at all satisfied with that theory of revolution for a lot of reasons,
historical and others. But even if one were to accept it for the sake of argument, still
that theory is maintaining that it is proper for the proletariat to take power and
exercise it in a violent and bloody and unjust fashion, because it is claimed, in my
opinion falsely, that that will lead to a more just society, in which the state will wither

away, in which the proletariat will be a universal class and so on and so forth. If it
werent for that further justification, the concept of a violent and bloody dictatorship
of the proletariat would certainly be unjust.
For example, I am not a committed pacifist. I would not hold that it is under all
imaginable circumstances wrong to use violence, even though use of violence is in
some sense unjust. I believe that one has to estimate relative injustices. But the use of
violence and the creation of some degree of injustice can only itself be justified on the
basis of the claim and the assessment which always ought to be undertaken very,
very seriously and with a good deal of skepticism that this violence is being
exercised because a more just result is going to be achieved. If it does not have that
grounding, it is really totally immoral, in my opinion.
FOUCAULT:
As far as the aim of the proletariat in leading a class struggle is concerned, I dont
think it would be sufficient to say that it is in itself a greater justice. What the
proletariat will achieve by expelling the ruling class and by taking power is precisely
the suppression of class power in general.
CHOMSKY:
Okay, but thats the further justification.
FOUCAULT:
That is the justification, but not in terms of justice but in terms of power.
CHOMSKY:
But it is in terms of justice; its because the end that will be achieved is claimed as a
just end. No Leninist or whatever you like would dare to say We, the proletariat, have
the right to take power, and then throw everyone else into crematoria. If that were
the consequence of the proletariat taking power, of course it would not be
appropriate. The idea is and for the reasons I mentioned Im skeptical about it
that a period of violent dictatorship, or perhaps violent and bloody dictatorship, is
justified because it will mean the submergence and termination of class oppression, a
proper end to achieve in human life.

FOUCAULT:
But it seems to me that, in any case, the notion of justice itself functions within a
society of classes as a claim made by the oppressed class and as a justification by the
oppressive class.
CHOMSKY:
I dont agree with that.
FOUCAULT:
And in a classless society, I am not sure that we would still use this notion of justice.
CHOMSKY:
Well, here I really disagree. I think there is some sort of an absolute basis if you
press me too hard Ill be in trouble because I cant sketch it out ultimately residing
in fundamental human qualities, in terms of which a real notion of justice is
grounded. I think its too hasty to characterize our existing systems of justice as
merely systems of class oppression; I dont think that they are that. I think that they
embody systems of class oppression and elements of other kinds of oppression, but
they also embody a kind of a groping towards the true humanly, valuable concepts of
justice and decency and love and kindness and sympathy and so on, which I think are
real.
FOUCAULT:
Well, do I have time to answer?
ELDERS:
Yes.
FOUCAULT:
How much?
ELDERS:

Two minutes.
FOUCAULT:
Well I would say that is unjust!
CHOMSKY:
Absolutely, yes.
FOUCAULT:
No, but I dont want to answer in so little time. I will simply say that I cant help but to
think that the concepts of human nature, of kindness, of justice, of human essence
and its realization All of these are notions and concepts that have been created
within our civilization, our knowledge system and our form of philosophy, and that as
a result they form part of our class system; and one cant, however regrettable it may
be, put forward these concepts to describe or justify a fight which should, and shall in
principle, overthrow the very fundaments of our society. This is an extrapolation for
which I cant find the historical justification.
ELDERS:
Well, I think we can immediately start the discussion.
QUESTION:
Mr. Chomsky, I would like to ask you one question. In your discussion you used the
term proletariat, we as proletarians. Its the irony of history that the moment
young intellectuals coming from the middle class and upper class, call themselves
proletarians and say We must join the proletarians. But I dont see any classconscious proletarians. And thats a great dilemma.
CHOMSKY:
It is not true in our given society that all people are doing useful, productive work, or
self-satisfying work obviously thats very far from true. Lots of people are excluded
from the possibility of productive labor. And I think the revolution, if you want,
should be in the name of all human beings; but it will have to be conducted by certain

categories of human beings, and those will be, I think, the human beings who really
are involved in the productive work of society. Now what that is will differ, depending
upon the society. In our society it, I think includes intellectual workers.
So I think that the student revolutionaries, if you like, have a point, a partial point:
that is, its a very important thing in a modern advanced industrial society how the
trained intelligentsia identify themselves. If they are going to be technocrats, or
servants of either the state or private power. Or, alternatively, whether they are going
to identify themselves as part of the workforce, who happen to be doing intellectual
labor. If the latter, then they can and should play a decent role in a progressive social
revolution. If the former, then theyre part of the class of the oppressors.
QUESTION:
I have one small additional question, or rather a remark to make to you. That is: how
can you, with your very courageous attitude towards the war in Vietnam, survive in an
institution like MIT, which is known here as one of the Great War contractors and
intellectual makers of this war?
CHOMSKY:
There are two aspects to that: one is the question how MIT tolerates me, and the other
question is how I tolerate MIT. Well, as to how MIT tolerates me, here again, I think,
one shouldnt be overly schematic. Its true that MIT is a major institution of war
research. But its also true that it embodies very important libertarian values, which
are, I think, quite deeply embedded in American society, fortunately for the world.
Theyre not deeply embedded enough to save the Vietnamese, but they are deeply
enough embedded to prevent far worse disasters. And here, I think, one has to qualify
a bit. There is imperial terror and aggression, there is exploitation, there is racism,
lots of things like that.
But there is also a real concern, coexisting with it, for individual rights of a sort which,
for example, are embodied in the Bill of Rights, which is by no means simply an
expression of class oppression. It is also an expression of the necessity to defend the
individual against state power. Now these things coexist. Its not that simple, its not
just all bad or all good. And its the particular balance in which they coexist that
makes an institute that produces weapons of war be willing to tolerate, in fact, in

many ways even encourage to be quite honest, a person who is involved in civil
disobedience against the war.
Now as to how I tolerate MIT, that raises another question. There are people who
argue, and I have never understood the logic of this, that a radical ought to dissociate
himself from oppressive institutions. The logic of that argument is that Karl Marx
shouldnt have studied in the British Museum which, if anything, was the symbol of
the most vicious imperialism in the world, the place where all the treasures of Empire
were gathered, the rape of the colonies was all poured in there. But I think Karl Marx
was quite right in studying in the British Museum. He was right in using the resources
and in fact the liberal values of the civilization that he was trying to overcome, against
it. And I think the same applies in this case.
QUESTION:
But arent you afraid that your presence at MIT gives them a clean conscience?
CHOMSKY:
I dont see how, really. I mean, I think my presence at MIT serves marginally, I hope a
lot, I dont know how much, to increase student activism against a lot of the things
that MIT stands for, for example.
ELDERS:
Well, ladies and gentlemen, I think this has to be the end of the debate. Mr. Chomsky,
Mr. Foucault, I thank you very much for your far-going discussion on both the
technical and theoretical way, as the political way. I thank you very much both on
behalf of the audience, here and at home.

You might also like