You are on page 1of 21

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 103

Catalan Journal of Linguistics 9, 2010

103-123

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions


in Spanish?*
Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero
Universidad Carlos III.
Departamento de Humanidades: Filosofa, Lenguaje y Literatura
C/ Madrid, 126. 28903 Getafe (Madrid)
mvpavon@hum.uc3m.es
Received: April 8 2010
Accepted: September 25 2010
Abstract
The main purpose of this paper is to explore why there are no locative subordinating conjunctions in Spanish. As we will see, the absence of this type of conjunctions is due, on the one hand,
to its lexical-grammatical properties and, on the other hand, to the semantic structure of locative
expressions. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions share properties with both lexical and functional heads. They share with complementizers the requirement that they take an extended projection
of the verb as their complement. At the same time, just like lexical categories such as prepositions, they have lexical content and are associated with an argument structure. In this sense, adverbial subordinating conjunctions can be seen as semantic functions which can express several
types of relations and take events or states as their internal argument. However, the semantic
structure of spatial expressions must contain a place function that takes as argument a conceptual constituent corresponding to the semantic category Thing. The reason for the non-existence
of locative subordinating conjunctions is, then, the incompatibility between categorial and semantic requirements in their complement.
Key words: subordinating conjunctions, prepositions, complementizers, relative adverbs.

Table of Contents
1. Introduction
2. Adverbial subordination from
a semantic and syntactic point of view
3. Adverbial clauses headed
by conjunctions

4. Adverbial free relative clauses.


Differences with adverbial clauses
headed by conjunctions
5. The semantic of Place
6. Concluding remarks
References

This paper results from a wide revision of an early version presented to the IV Congreso de
Lingstica General (see Pavn Lucero, 2003a). I wish to thank Yuko Morimoto and Isabel Prez
Jimnez for helpful comments and suggestions. I thank also an anonymous reviewer for helping me
recognize, an respond to, many of the limitations of this work.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 104

104

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

1. Introduction
Adverbial subordinating conjunctions form a controversial class of words whose syntactic behaviour exhibits properties in common both with lexical and functional
categories. The limits of this class of words, along with their categorial status, is
still an unclear matter: they have been considered either a subclass of prepositions
or a subclass of complementizers. Subordinated sentences introduced by this type
of conjunctions may express a considerable number of semantic relations in Spanish,
from which spatial relations, among others, are excluded. However, there is another class of subordinated sentences, generally grouped together with adverbial subordinated sentences, which can express the meaning of location: adverbial free relative clauses.
The purpose of this paper is to explore why there are no locative subordinating conjunctions in Spanish. We will begin, in section 2, by offering a general outlook of adverbial subordination. In section 3, we will discuss the categorial status
of adverbial subordinating conjunctions and, consequently, the syntactic structure
of subordinated sentences headed by them. We will review the hypothesis that this
class of conjunctions is a subclass of prepositions, as well as the problems posed by
this hypothesis. We will also review their similitudes and differences with complementizers and, finally, we will assume the proposal, by Haumann (1997), that
adverbial subordinating conjunctions are a hybrid category, which share properties both with prepositions and complementizers.
In section 4, we will concentrate on the structure of adverbial free relative clauses and we will compare this structure with that of sentences headed by subordinating conjunctions. Finally, in section 5, we will account for the semantic structure of both types of constructions and we will see that the fact that there are no
locative subordinating conjunctions is due to the incompatibility between the semantic structure of locative expressions and the syntactic structure of sentences headed by adverbial subordinating conjunctions. The present study will focus on the
grammar of Spanish. However, if our proposal is correct, it would be predictable that
there are no locative subordinating conjunctions in any other language, and we will
outline some indications in some other European languages that this prediction is
in fact correct.
2. Adverbial subordination from a semantic and syntactic point of view
In many traditional and scholarly Spanish grammar books and references, the term
adverbial subordination covers several syntactic structures. All of the following
constructions have been treated as sentences that contain an adverbial subordinated clause (in italics in the examples):

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 105

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

105

(1) a. Mantena los ojos muy abiertos, para que supieran


que
He-kept the eyes wide open
so that they-would-know that
estaba vivo.
he-was alive.
He kept his eyes wide open so that they would know he was alive.
(Mario Vargas Llosa, La fiesta del chivo; example from CREA)
b. Pero fui algo
antes de nacer y ser
algo
But I-was something before of to-born and I-will-be something
despus de que mi cuerpo se disuelva.
after
of that my body - disintegrates
But I was something before I was born and I will be something after my
body disintegrates.
(Alejandro Jodorowsky, La danza de la realidad. Chamanismo y psicochamanismo; example from CREA)
c. La Rotunda trag
completa su racin de presos
y los
La Rotunda swallowed complete her portion of prisoners and the
cautivos se quedaron donde estaban.
captives - remained where they-were
La Rotunda completely swallowed her portion of prisoners and the captives remained where they were.
(Francisco Herrera Luque, En la casa del pez que escupe el agua; example
from CREA)
d. Si hubiramos
vivido con l, nunca se hubiera
puesto
If we-would-have lived with him, never - he-would-have become
enfermo.
sick
If we would have lived with him, he would never have become sick.
(Manuel Martnez Mediero, Las largas vacaciones de Oliveira Salazar;
example from CREA)
Despite the different semantic relations that each one of the highlighted clauses expresses with respect to the main clause (purpose in (1a), temporal location in
(1b), spatial location in (1c) and condition in (1d)), they correspond to very different syntactic structures. In (1a), there is a PP: the preposition para has a finite substantive subordinated clause as a complement. As we can see in (2), the complement
of para could be a non-finite (infinitive) clause or a neutral demonstrative pronoun,
without changing the purposeful meaning of the construction:
(2) a. Mantena los ojos muy abiertos, para
mostrar que estaba vivo.
He-kept the eyes wide open,
in-order to-show that he-was alive
b. Mantena los ojos muy abiertos, para eso.
He-kept the eyes wide open,
for that

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 106

106

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

The temporal clauses in (1b) are adverbial phrases headed by the adverbs antes
(before) and despus (after). These adverbs take a complement, introduced by
the preposition de (of), which may correspond to a finite or non-finite (infinitive) clause1, as is shown in (1b) (despus de que mi cuerpo se disuelva and antes
de nacer, respectively) or, as we can see in (3a) and (3b), to a pronoun or a DP:
(3) a. Fui algo
antes de eso.
I-was something before of that
I was something before that.
b. Ser
algo
despus de mi muerte.
I-will-be something after
of my death
I will be something after my death.
In (1c), the subordinated clause is a free relative introduced by the locative relative adverb donde; in (1d), finally, the conditional clause is introduced by the subordinating conjunction si. These are the two types of subordinated sentences we
are concerned with here, hence their structure will be discussed in the following
sections. It must be noted that, if the term adverbial subordination had to be restricted to a particular syntactic structure with distinctive features from any other class
of constituents, that would be (1d); that is, the construction headed by subordinating conjunctions. As we will see, the properties of this class of words, and its classification regarding other syntactic categories is a controversial matter in linguistic
theory. On the other hand, this structure excludes some of the semantic notions traditionally captured under adverbial subordination. Concretely, these structures
exclude spatial meaning, which can be expressed, however, by means of adverbial
relative clauses. As we have already stated, the main purpose of the following sections will be to explain the reasons for that fact.
3. Adverbial clauses headed by conjunctions
As has been previously noted, the categorial status of subordinating conjunctions
and, consequently, the structure of the clause they introduce, is a controversial matter. Different proposals have been made in order to classify this type of conjunctions.
Some of these proposals have in common their attempt to include subordinating
conjunctions in other types of syntactic categories: basically, complementizers and
prepositions. Nevertheless, we will assume a different perspective that considers
them an independent hybrid syntactic category, which combines properties of lexical and functional heads.
1.

When the complement is a finite clause, the preposition de is optional, so, in (1b), despus que mi
cuerpo se disuelva would be possible as well. This fact is related to the mixed nature of antes and
despus, as temporal adverbs and comparative words. For this reason, antes and despus can form
comparative constructions with a noun preceeded by que, and in this case the preposition would produce ungrammatical sentences: Marina termin el artculo antes (*de) que Alfredo (Marina finished the paper sooner than Alfredo). See, in this respect, Garca Fernndez (1999: 48.6) and Real
Academia Espaola (2009: 31.14d ff.).

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 107

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

107

3.1. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions as complementizers


Traditionally, conjunctions have been considered a part of speech made up of two
main classes: coordinating and subordinating conjunctions. The subclass of subordinating conjunctions is further subdivided into those that introduce substantive
subordinated sentences (in Spanish, que, that, and the conjunction si, if, that
introduces subordinated interrogative clauses2), as well as the conjunctions that head
adverbial subordinated sentences; that is, for the case of Spanish, simple units like
conditional si3 (if) or causal como (since), and a large number of complex units
such as causal porque or puesto que (because, since), temporal en tanto que
(while, insofar as), concessive aun cuando (even if), etc. An accurate description of this classification, as well as of the problems it poses, is available in Real
Academia Espaola (2009: 31.1).
According to this classification, adverbial subordinating conjunctions would
form part of the same syntactic class as complementizers. The hypothesis that
adverbial subordinating conjunctions are complementizers has been maintained as
well by authors such as Hendrick (1976) or Lasnik and Saito (1972). Obviously,
complementizers and adverbial subordinating conjunctions have in common the
fact that both take a sentential complement. Moreover, as the mentioned authors
point out, this hypothesis explains why sentences such as the ones in (4) and (5)
are ungrammatical in English and Spanish, respectively:
(4) a. *Unless that the strike has been called off, there will be no trains tomorrow.
b. *She watered the flowers because that they were dry.
c. *Since that the weather has improved, the game will be held as planned.
(Examples from Haumann (1997: 50))
2.

3.

Interrogative si has been traditionally considered a subordinating conjunction, but some authors
have included it in the same class as interrogative pronouns or adverbs. This proposal can be traced
back to some traditional Spanish grammarians such as Bello. This author (see Bello, 1847: 415)
considers si to be a relative adverb which he places in relation to conditional si (if) (relative
adverb for Bello) and affirmative s (yes) (which is categorised by Bello as a modal adverb).
More recently, Rigau (1984) argues that interrogative si in Catalan is an interrogative adverb, showing that it behaves like other interrogative words, like quan (when), que (what) or qui (who),
and differs from complementizer que (that). See also Real Academia Espaola (2009: 22.2p) for
some properties of interrogative si in Spanish that make it different from other interrogative words.
Some authors have proposed that (some) subordinating conjunctions are relative adverbs. As we have
just seen in the previous footnote, this is Bellos proposal. This author considers their ability to
link analogous constituents to be a defining property of conjuntions (see Bello 1847: 74); consequently, only coordinating conjunctions would properly be conjunctions, whereas subordinating conjunctions would form part of the same grammatical class as relative adverbs. Among other
recent proposals, Haegeman (2007) considers conditional subordinating conjunctions to be relative
adverbs, presenting arguments based on morphologic and ethimologic sources of some conditional
conjunctions in French and German. Nevertheless, in section 4 we will argue that adverbial subordinating conjunctions (such as conditional si) and the sentences they introduce show a syntactic
behaviour which is different, in many important respects, from that of sequences introduced by
relative adverbs.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 108

108

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

(5) a. *Volvera a viajar a Australia si que pudiera permitrmelo.


I-would-again travel to Australia if that I-could afford-it
I would travel to Australia again if I could afford it.
b. *Como que no contestaste
a mi carta, pens
que no estabas
Since that not you-answered - my letter, I-thought that not you-were
interesado en el trabajo.
interested in the job
Since you didnt answer my letter, I thought you were not interested in
the job.
c. *No pudimos evitar
que se saliera con la suya, aun cuando que
Not we-could keep-from that he-got-away-whit-it, even thought that
la mayora
no estbamos de acuerdo.
the majority (of us) not we-agreed
We couldnt keep from him getting away with it, even though most of us
didnt agree.
Taking into account the hypothesis presented, the reason for the ungrammaticality of these sentences would be the presence of two words of the same class
occupying the same syntactic position: the subordinating conjunction and the complementizer (that in English, que in Spanish). Nevertheless, we can show some
important differences in Spanish between both classes of words; differences which
have to do with the positions that the structures introduced by them may occupy
in the sentence.
Subordinated clauses introduced by the complementizer que in Spanish must
occupy argumental positions, as complements of lexical categories, such as P or
V, as well as the Subject position, as the examples in (6) show. On the contrary,
adverbial subordinated clauses like those in (7a, b) are adjuncts; that is, they occur
in non-argumental positions (they are not lexically selected by a lexical head):
(6) a. Su
decisin depende de que le
renueven los
{His/her} decision depends on that to-{him/her} they-renew the
papeles.
identification-papers
{His/her} decision depends on {his/her} identification papers being
renewed.
b. Creo que no podemos esperar ms.
I-think that not we-can to-wait more
I think we cant wait any longer.
c. Que ests aqu significa que no tienes que estudiar hoy.
That you-are here means that not you-have-to-study today
The fact that you are here means that you dont have to study today.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 109

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

109

(7) a. Mara no vendr


a la fiesta si no se
lo pides t.
Mara not will-come to the party if not to-her it ask you
Mara wont come to the party if you dont ask her.
b. Si todo
va bien,
llegaremos
sobre las ocho.
If everything goes all right, we-will-arrive by the eight
If everything goes all right, we will arrive by eight.
Adverbial subordinating conjunctions exhibit, in this way, contradictory behavior.
From the point of view of the internal structure of the constituent they head, this kind
of conjunctions is similar to complementizers. Nowadays, the subordinated sentences
headed by complementizers and those headed by adverbial subordinating conjunctions are completely different in terms of the position they may occupy with respect to
the main clause. For more arguments regarding the differences between complementizers and adverbial subordinating conjunctions, see Haumann (1997: 3.2).
3.2. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions as prepositions
As we have already mentioned, some authors, such as Jackendoff (1973, 1977),
Emonds (1985) and Larson (1990), have proposed that adverbial subordinating
conjunctions are prepositions. A similar hypothesis had been proposed previously
by authors such as Jespersen (1924), Hjemslev (1928) or Pottier (1962).
Basically, this hypothesis defends the position that prepositions, adverbial subordinating conjunctions and some adverbs are subclasses of prepositions which
differ in their subcategorization properties. For example, instead of considering,
as is traditionally maintained, that before and after are polycategorial words that,
depending on the context, can function as a preposition, (8a), an adverbial subordinating conjunction, (8b), or an adverb, (8c), it would be proposed that in each
case we have the same category. Before and after would be prepositions that can
take a DP as a complement, as in (8a), or a sentence, as in (8b); they can also be used
intransitively, that is to say, with no explicit complement, as in (8c):
(8) a. He did the washing-up {before/after} their arrival.
b. He did the washing-up {before/after} their parents arrived.
c. Their parents arrived at seven, and he did the washing-up {before/after}.
On the other hand, an adverb like, for example, always, could be considered
an intransitive temporal preposition, that is, a temporal preposition that takes no
complement. As to traditionally considered adverbial subordinating conjunctions,
such as unless or because in (9), they could be accounted for as prepositions that
invariably subcategorize a sentential complement:
(9) a. The planets future is questionable unless developed countries improve
global strategic collaboration.
b. I cannot check my messages because the computer is out of order.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 110

110

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

This is, however, a problematic hypothesis in many respects. In the following,


we will see some problems for its application to Spanish (see Haumann, 1997: 3.3
for discussion based on data from English). These problems have to do, basically,
with the syntactic (sentential) category that prepositions, on the one hand, and
adverbial subordinating conjunctions, on the other, take as a complement.
In Spanish, if a preposition takes a sentential complement headed by a finite
verb, the sentence must be introduced by the complementizer que (that), as is
shown in (10a, b). Nevertheless, as we have seen in (5a), que cannot introduce the
sentential complement of an adverbial subordinating conjunction, as the conditional si (if), (10c):
(10) a. No contaba
con que la perversidad de los
Not {he/she}-took into account - that the perversity of the
hombres degrada hasta la inocencia de un idioma.
men
degrades even the innocence of a language
{He/she} didnt take into account that the perversity of men degrades even
the innocence of a language.
(Maruja Torres, Hombres de lluvia; example from CREA)
b. Entrar
sin
que nadie
se percate que soy yo.
I-will-come-in without that anybody - notices that is me
I will come in without anyone noticing that its me.
(Volodia Teitelboim, En el pas prohibido. Sin el permiso de Pinochet;
example from CREA)
c. Est bien, lo har
si me
pagas en metlico.
It-is ok, it I-will-do if to-me you-pay cash
Ok, I will do it if you pay me cash.
(Juan Jos Mills, Dos mujeres en Praga; example from CREA)
Furthermore, in Spanish, the sentence in the complement of a preposition can
be a finite sentence headed by the explicit complementizer que or a non-finite sentence without an explicit complementizer: an infinitival sentence. The alternation
between both classes of sentences has to do, among other factors, with the relation between the main subject and the subject of the embedded clause4. When they
are not coreferential, the subordinated sentence is a finite one, as in (10a, b); subordinated infinitival sentences usually occur when both subjects are coreferential,
as in (11a, b). However, in clear contrast to prepositions, (11c) shows that subordinated sentences headed by conjunctions exclude a non-finite verb:

4.

The referential relation between both subjects is an important factor in the alternation between
finite and non-finite subordinated sentences in Spanish, but it is not the only one. As we will see
next, in sequences such as (12a) and (12b), a finite sentence with a coreferential subject is possible in some cases. See more about this topic in Hernanz (1999: 36.3.2.5) and Real Academia
Espaola (2009: 26.4, 26.11).

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 111

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

111

(11) a. Luis contaba con tener dos semanas ms para terminar


Luis expected - to-have two weeks more for to-finish
el artculo.
the paper
Luis expected to have two more weeks to finish the paper.
b. Entr
sin
percatarme de que estabas all.
I-came-in without to-realize of that you-were there
I came in without realizing that you were there.
c. *Solo lo har
si estar segura de que me
pagars
Only it I-will-do if to-be sure of that to-me you-will-pay
en metlico.
cash
I will do it only if I am sure that you will pay me cash.
As has been previously noted, most of the Spanish adverbial subordinating
conjunctions are complex units, a good number of which contain the complementizer que. The possibility of substituting the constituent introduced by que is precisely one of the main tests used for determining if the complex unit is grammaticalized as a subordinating conjunction or, on the contrary, if it maintains the
structure of a preposition (or another lexical item) followed by the complementizer that heads its sentential complement. Compare, for example, causal porque and
puesto que (because, since). Despite the fact that the first of these units is written
as a sole written word, the possibility of substituting the constituent introduced
by que by an infinitival sentence, or even a pronoun or a DP, evidenced in (12a-d),
shows that porque is not the result of a process of grammaticalizacion, but the
graphic union of the preposition por (because of) and the complementizer que:
(12) a. Le
castigaron
porque se haba portado mal.
To-him they-punished because - he-had behaved bad
He was punished because he had misbehaved.
b. Le
castigaron
por
haberse portado mal.
To-him they-punished because-of to-have behaved bad
He was punished because of his misbehaving.
c. Le
castigaron
por
su mal comportamiento.
To-him they-punished because-of his bad behaviour
He was punished because of his misbehaviour.
d. Le
castigaron
por
eso.
To-him they-punished because-of that
He was punished because of that.
By contrast, puesto que, formed with the past participle of poner (put) and
the complementizer, behaves like a compact grammaticalized unit. In this case,

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 112

112

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

que does not introduce an independent constituent that could be substituted by


another constituent, like a non-finite sentence, a pronoun or a DP:
(13) a. Avanzabas
con mucha cautela, puesto que la penumbra
You-moved-ahead with much caution, put
that the half-darkness
te
impeda caminar con seguridad.
to-you kept
to-walk with confidence
You moved ahead very cautiously, because the half-darkness kept you from
walking with confidence.
(Jaime Martnez Salguero, El combate mstico; example from CREA)
b. *Avanzabas
con mucha cautela, puesto no poder caminar
You-moved-ahead with much caution, put
not to-can to-walk
con seguridad.
with confidence
c. *Avanzabas
con mucha cautela, puesta5 la dificultad de
You-moved-ahead with much caution, put
the difficulty of
caminar con seguridad.
to-walk with safety
d. *Avanzabas
con mucha cautela, puesto eso.
You-moved-ahead with much caution, put
that
3.3. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions as a hybrid category
Seeing the problems posed by both the hypotheses reviewed in the previous paragraphs, we will assume the proposal by Haumann (1997: ch. 8), who argues that
adverbial subordinating conjunctions are a conflating category, unifying properties
of lexical and functional heads (Haumann, 1997: 262). This category has in common
with prepositions the fact that it has lexical content and it is associated with an argument structure. On the other hand, like complementizers, adverbial subordinating
conjunctions take an extended projection of the verb as their complement. Assuming
this proposal, the syntactic structure of an adverbial subordinated clause headed by
an adverbial subordinanting conjunction (Subcon) would be as follows:
(14) [SubconP Subcon [TP ...T... [VP ...V...]]]
In this structure, the adverbial subordinating conjunction takes as its complement
the same sentential projection as complementizers, which we assume to be TP6.
5.
6.

The past participle in the feminine form is due to the fact that, in cases like this, it should agree
with the DP.
In (14) we assume a standard analysis in which the sentential complement of C or Subcon is a projection of T(ime). For an argumentation in favour of this analysis (related to complementizer), see,
among others, Adger (2003: 155-203). Fernndez-Salgueiro (2008) also argues that the complement
of adverbial subordinating conjunctions is TP. This author assumes that this class of conjunctions

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 113

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

113

Nevertheless, in contrast to complementizers, adverbial subordinating conjunctions have lexical content. They express lexically the relation between the subordinated sentence and the main sentence, as is well known and has been previously referred to several times. Consequently, there must be a semantic relation between
the adverbial subordinating conjunction and its sentential complement. As we will
see in 5, it is this semantic relation that, ultimately, will explain why there are no
locative subordinating conjunctions. But, first, we will review the structure of adverbial free relative clauses.
4. Adverbial free relative clauses. Differences with adverbial clauses headed
by conjunctions
Relative clauses headed by relative adverbs may express three types of semantic
relations: manner, time and place. This kind of subordinated sentences can occupy
different positions with respect to the main sentence, but, basically, like any other
relative clause, they can modify an antecedent, that is, they can appear as the complement of a substantive or an adverb, as in (15), or they may not have any overt
antecedent, as in (16):
(15) a. [...] quizs llegue la hora cuando yo acabe suspirando por
perhaps comes the hour when I end-up pining
by
los buenos tiempos de la aviacin.
the good times of the aviation
Perhaps the time would come that I end up pining for the good times of
aviation.
(Gilberto Chvez Jr., El batallador; example from CREA)
b. Ayer
fui
caminando a travs de la jungla, all donde
Yesterday I-went walking
through - the jungle, there where
clarea la espesura.
thins-out the thicket
Yesterday, I went walking through the jungle, where the thicket thins
out.
(Ral Hernndez, Los malditos; example from CREA)
c. Turbaba
contemplar la manera como l la
seduca.
It-embarrassed to-see
the way
how he to-her seduced
It was embarrassing to see the way he seduced her.
(Germn Snchez Espeso, En las alas de las mariposas; example from
CREA)
and complementizers form part of the same class of words (along with coordinating conjunctions) and
maintains that differences between them are due to individual lexical properties. We wont dwell on
the discussion about the type and number of extended projections of the verb since this question does
not necessarily affect the main conclusions of our work. See also, among others, Cinque (1999) and
some of the contributions collected in Rizzi (ed.) (2004) or Guron and Lecarme (eds.) (2004).

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 114

114

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

(16) a. Eso es lo que sucedi cuando aqu me


trajeron,
comandante.
That is what happened when here to-me they-brought, commander
That is what happened when I was brought here, commander.
(Antonio Gala, Los invitados al jardn; example from CREA)
b. [...] la mquina no estaba donde haba estado siempre.
the machine not was where it-had been always
The machine wasnt where it had been always.
(Gabriel Garca Mrquez, Vivir para contarla; example from CREA)
c. Pensbamos las mismas cosas y queramos que el mundo fuera
We-thought the same things and we-wanted that the world was
como nosotras sobamos.
how we
dreamt
We thought the same things and we wanted the world to be as we dreamt
it was.
(Chavela Vargas, Y si quieres saber de mi pasado; example from CREA)
Relative clauses like those in (16) have usually been grouped, in many Spanish
grammar books and references, with adverbial subordinated sentences like those
analysed in the previous section7. However, there are basic differences between
them regarding the fact that relative adverbs, in contrast with subordinating conjunctions, play a syntactic function in the subordinated sentence (locative complement or adjunct) and appear in the initial position of the construction by means
of movement.
Adverbial relatives clauses in (16) are free relatives, that is, relative sentences
that lack an explicit antecedent. There have been several types of proposals to
account for the syntactic structure of free relatives, which could be grouped into
basically two types of analyses. In the first of these analyses, there is a covert
antecedent represented by an empty category. This proposal has been defended,
among others, by Groos and Van Riemsdijk (1981) (see also Van Riemsdijk, 2000)
and, for the Spanish language, Brucart (1999: 7.2.4.3). In the second analysis,
defended by Bresnan and Grimshaw (1978), de Vries (2002) and Donati (2006),
among others, the relative word would occupy the antecedent position. Adapting

7.

A case in point of the confusion regarding the distinction between both classes of subordinated
sentences is Real Academia Espaola (1928: 401) where it can be read (referring to locative
subordinated sentences): [...] Son un caso particular de las oraciones adjetivas, con las cuales se
confunden cuanto el antecedente es un sustantivo o un pronombre. Si digo: Esta es la casa en que
nac, expreso mi pensamiento con una oracin de relativo; y si sustituyo en ella el complemento en
que por el adverbio donde, y digo: Esta es la casa donde nac, enuncio una subordinada circumstancial [...] (They are a particular case of adjective sentences, in which they are confused when
the antecedent is a substantive or a pronoun. If I say: This is the house in which I was born, I
express my thought by means of a relative sentence; and If I substitute in this sentence the complement in which for the adverb where, and I say: This is the house where I was born, I enunciate
a circumstantial (adverbial) subordinated sentence). These words are reproduced in Real Academia
Espaola (1973: 537).

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 115

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

115

these two analyses to the adverbial free relatives we are dealing with, we could
schematically represent them as in (17a, b):
(17) a. [AdvP e [CP AdvReli [TP ...ti...]]]
b. [AdvP AdvReli [CP ...ti...]]
In both analyses, the syntactic category of the highest constituent is AdvP8. In
(17a), which corresponds to the first of the analyses previously referred to and fits
the standard analysis of headed relative clauses, the relative adverb has moved to
the specifier position of the relative clause that modifies a covert antecedent.
In (17b), the adverbial relative has moved out of the CP to occupy the position of
the antecedent9. Let us assume the more standard analysis, (17a), although the
choice of one or another is not relevant for the purposes of our work. What we
would like to emphasize is that, if we compare any of the structures in (17) with
(14), we can notice the following differences between adverbial relative sentences
and adverbial subordinated sentences headed by conjunctions:
1. The adverbial subordinating conjunction is generated in the initial position of
the constituent it heads; in contrast, the relative adverb occupies the initial position via wh-movement.
2. The sentential projection CP in (17) is not selected by the head of the AdvP,
in contrast with the TP complement in (14), which is lexically and categorially selected by the adverbial subordinating conjunction.
Moreover, there is evidence, in many other senses, that subordinating conjunctions and relative adverbs, and, consequently the constructions they introduce,
are syntactic elements with dissimilar properties. Some of them are herewith
exposed10:
1. All relative words, and, particularly, all relative adverbs, can appear in constructions with an explicit antecedent, like those mentioned above in (15). In contrast,
adverbial sentences headed by conjunctions cannot modify an alleged antecedent,
as the examples in (18) show:

8. A competing analysis would hold that the whole constituent is a CP. However, this analysis is usually rejected by arguing that the distribution of free relatives is similar to that of the constituents headed by the antecedent of full relatives, and not that of other CP constituents, such as declarative or
interrogative subordinated sentences (see Donati, 2006: 5).
9. In a conservative version of this analysis, the AdvRel would occupy the specifier position of the
AdvP, after moving from the specifier position of the CP. Nevertheless, de Vries (2002) considers
it to move to the head position. Donati (2006), who argues in favour of the possibility that
wh-movement operates with heads, holds that, in free relatives, the moved constituent is a head, and
not a phrase.
10. See Pavn Lucero (2003b: chapters 6 and 7) for a comparison, using similar arguments as those
exposed here, between temporal constructions headed by prepositions and subordinating conjunctions, on the one hand, and temporal constructions headed by relative adverbs, on the other hand.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 116

116

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

(18) a. *La nueva escuela funcionar en el supuesto si se terminan las


The new school will-work on the assumption if - finish
the
obras a tiempo.
works on time
b. *La nueva escuela funcionar pese al inconveniente aunque no
The new scholl will-work despite the inconvenience although not
se hayan terminado las obras.
- have finished the works
2. The relative adverb can be moved to its initial sentence position from different
levels in subordinated sentence. If this one contains another subordinated sentence
as a complement of the verb, the resulting construction may be ambiguous. For
example, in (19a) we could obtain two interpretations corresponding to the structures in (19b) and (19c). In (19b), in which the relative adverb has been moved
from the highest subordinated sentence, we would understand that Julias arrival
happened during the time while Marta was saying something; in (19c), in which
the relative adverb has been moved from the lowest subordinated sentence, we
obtain the meaning that Julias arrival happened at the time Juan was supposed to
arrive:
(19) a. Julia lleg cuando Marta deca que llegara
Juan.
Julia arrived when Marta said that would-arrive Juan
b. [AdvP e [CP cuandoi [C C [TP1 Marta deca ti [CP2 que [TP2 llegara Juan]]]]]]
c. [AdvP e [CP cuandoi [C C [TP1 Marta deca [CP2 que [TP2 llegara Juan ti]]]]]]
In clear contrast to sentences like (19a), conditional and concessive sentences
like those in (20a) and (20b) lack the possibility of an ambiguous interpretation.
In the only plausible interpretation for these sentences, the condition or the impediment for calling is the fact of saying something, and not what is said:
(20) a. Llmame si dices que hablas con ella.
Call-me if you-say that you-talk to her
b. Llmame aunque digas que no hablars
con ella.
Call-me even-if you-say that not you-will-talk to her
3. Our last argument to show the contrast between relative adverbs and subordinating conjunctions has to do with the fact that the former, but not the latter,
have the capacity of referring anaphorically to another constituent. Sentences
headed by relative adverbs may form pseudo-cleft-sentences like those in (21);
this construction is excluded in the case of subordinating conjunctions, as (22)
shows:

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 117

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

117

(21) a. A las ocho fue cuando llegaron.


At the eight it-was when they-arrived
It was eight when they arrived.
b. En tu casa ser
donde nos
veremos.
In your home it-will-be where to-ourselves we-will-see
It will be in your home where we will see each other
c. As
es como lo pintaron.
This-way is how to-it they-painted
This is the way they painted it.
(22) a. *(En) ese supuesto es si se terminan las obras a tiempo. (Cf. La nueva escuela funcionar si se terminan las obras a tiempo.)
Lit. It is (in) that case if the works finish on time. (Cf. The new school
will be operative if the works finish on time.)
b. *(Pese a) ese impedimento es aunque no se hayan terminado las obras. (Cf.
La nueva escuela funcionar aunque no se hayan terminado las obras.)
Lit. It is (in spite of) that impediment even thougt the works havent finished on time. (Cf. The new school will be operative even though the works
havent finished on time.)
In conclusion, we have reviewed two types of so-called adverbial subordinated sentences: those introduced by subordinating conjunctions and those introduced
by relative adverbs. The former type of adverbial subordinated sentences may
express several kinds of semantic relations with respect to the main clause: condition, concession, cause, purpose, time and so on. Adverbial relative sentences can
express time, place and manner11. Given that dissimilarity, there would be several
questions we could formulate regarding why, apparently, some semantic relations
are restricted to one type of construction and excluded from the other. In the following, we will try to answer only one of these possible questions: why are there
no locative conjunctions in Spanish? As we will see, the answer has to do with the
relation between the semantic and syntactic structure of the constituents headed
by adverbial subordinating conjunctions.

11. Apparently, the only semantic relations that can be expressed both by means of a free relative
clause and by a clause headed by an adverbial subordinated sentence are temporal relations. In
Spanish, there are a considerable number of temporal subordinators traditionally classified as conjunctions: apenas (hardly), mientras (while), en tanto que (insofar as), al tiempo que (while),
etc. In Pavn Lucero (2003b: VII.5), we presented some arguments putting in evidence that mientras is an adverbial subordinating conjunction, by comparing this lexical unit to the relative adverb
cuando (when). Probably similar arguments could be made with regard to other temporal subordinators. At any rate, there are likewise important similarities between them and relative adverbs,
as Real Academia Espaola (2009: 31.13e-h) points out.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 118

118

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

5. The semantics of Place


As we have previously put forward, the non-existence of locative subordinating
conjunctions in Spanish is due to the incompatibility between the semantic structure of locative constituents and the semantic and syntactic properties of subordinating conjunctions and, accordingly, the semantic and syntactic properties of the
constituents they introduce.
Let us first consider the semantic structure of locative constructions. In order to
account for it, we will assume the proposals by Jackendoff (1983, 1990, 2002), in
the theoretical framework of Conceptual Semantics. Based on these theoretical
assumptions, we will take (23a) as the basic conceptual structure for the semantic
category Place12 (Jackendoff, 1983: 162). According to this structure, Place could
be accounted for as a Place function which takes, as its internal argument, the
semantic category Thing. This would be the conceptual structure that would correspond to a PP like (23b): the preposition en (on) would correspond to the Place
function, and the DP la mesa (the table), would correspond to the internal argument13:
(23) a. [Place

PLACE-FUNCTION

[Thing X]]

b. [PP En [DP la mesa]]


Let us now return to the lexical-syntactic properties of subordinating conjunctions. In 3.3, we have assumed, following Haumann (1997), that adverbial subordinating conjunctions constitute a hybrid category which exhibits properties of
both the lexical and functional categories. As with lexical categories, like prepositions, adverbial subordinating conjunctions have lexical content and are associated with an argument structure; as with functional categories like complementizers, adverbial subordinating conjunctions take an extended projection of the verb
(TP) as its complement. The structure of the sentential constituent headed by a
subordinating conjunction is (14), repeated here:

12. We will use initial capital letters for conceptual-semantic categories.


13. In (23a), we try to illustrate a simple Place-function, which is sufficient for our purposes.
Nevertheless, as Jackendoff (1983) points out, there are more complex spatial concepts, such as
those based on the conceptual category Path, that can be expressed in prepositional phrases like
two miles from here. In any case, the conceptual category corresponding to the internal argument
is, ultimately, Thing. On the other hand, the conceptual structure corresponding to a PP like (23b)
would also contain an external argument, which would correspond to the object located in the
place expressed by the PP or the event/state occurring in that place. In the mapping from this conceptual structure to the syntax, this external argument would correspond, for example, to the subject of a sentence like (ia), el libro (the book), or to the whole sentence in (ib):
(i) a. El libro est
The book is
b. Dos hormigas
Two ants

en la mesa.
on the table
correteaban en la mesa.
scampered on the table

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 119

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

119

(14) [SubconP Subcon [TP ...T... [VP ...V...]]]


A structure like this one matches a subjacent semantic structure consisting of
a semantic function and an internal argument. The semantic category of the latter,
which invariably has to correspond to the syntactic category TP, must be Situation
(Event or State). The semantic category corresponding to the subordinating conjunction would vary depending on the concrete lexical item; for instance: si matches Condition and puesto que matches Cause. The lexical conceptual structure corresponding to (14) would be, temptatively, (24)14:
(24) a. [{Cause/Condition/ ...} {CAUSE/ CONDITION/...}-FUNCTION [Event/State X]]
If we confront now (14) and (24), we can easily see the reason why there are no
subordinating locative conjunctions: because the constituent TP complement of a
subordinating conjunction would not be able to correspond to the semantic category Thing; an extended projection of the verb could only correspond to semantic categories like State or Event. As a matter of fact, we could not find a syntactic
structure that would correspond to a conceptual structure in which a Place function would take an Event or a State as its internal argument. Prepositional or
Adverbial Phrases corresponding to the ontological category Place, like those in
(25a-b), have a DP as complement of the preposition. There are, on the other hand,
lexical items which lexicalize the place function and the internal argument in only
one word, such as the deictic locative adverbs in (25c):
(25) a. Sobre el tejado.
On the roof
b. Debajo de la cama.
Under of the bed
c. Aqu, ah.
Here, there
As we have seen in 4, a free relative clause can denote a Place. In that case,
the meaning of the construction could not be decomposed as a Place-function that
takes a Thing as an internal argument. As Jackendoff (2002: 384) points out: [...]
a relative clause identifies an individual by virtue of his/her participation in the
Situation (State or Event) denoted by the clause. In sentences like (16b) above,

14. As in (23a) above, the external argument, which in these cases would be matched by the main sentence, is not represented here for simplicity, seeing that we are concentrating on the internal structure of the adverbial subordinated clause. Furthermore, we express semantic categories like Cause
or Condition as if they were simple categories, despite the fact that they probably are complex categories that could be decomposed in other simpler categories. At any rate, the most relevant fact for
our purposes is that the internal argument would correspond to the ontological categories Event
or State in any case.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 120

120

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

repeated here as (26a), the Place denoted by the adverb phrase headed by donde
is determined by virtue of the fact that the State described in the relative sentence
is necessarily related to a Place. Following Jackendoff (2002: 384-386), we can
account for the semantics of a sentence like (26a) by recourse to the formal logic
notation for lambda-extraction. Temptatively, we propose a conceptual structure
like (26b) for the free relative clause donde haba estado siempre (where it had
been always):
(26) a. La mquina no estaba donde haba estado siempre.
[PLACE X]

b.

[STATE BE-ALWAYS-THE-MACHINE [PLACE X]]


PLACE

In this conceptual representation, the locative meaning of the sentence is represented in the first line as a Place that is determined by means of its participation
in a more complex semantic representation. The second line shows this representation; that is, it describes how the Place denotation is obtained by means of a State
which occurs in that Place.
If the answer proposed here to the question which opens this paper is correct,
it would be the case that there are no locative adverbial subordinating conjunctions
not only in Spanish, but in any other language. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions have two properties that characterise them as a particular class of words: on
the one hand, they take an extended projection of the verb as a complement: TP; on
the other hand, they have lexical content and are associated with an argument structure. From a conceptual semantic point of view, adverbial subordinating conjunctions would correspond, like prepositions, to a semantic function that takes a semantic category as an argument.
We have seen as well that the semantic category Place can be decomposed in a
function of Place that takes a Thing as internal argument. Locative prepositions,
as well as some locative adverbs, would correspond, from this point of view, to
Place-functions that take Things as arguments. Adverbial subordinating conjunctions could likewise be considered the lexicalization of functions of different types
of semantic categories. In any case, these functions must take Situations (Events
or States) as internal arguments, since adverbial subordinating conjunctions, as
well as complementizers, invariably take a TP as a complement. Seeing that a
Place-function must take a Thing as an internal argument, the impossibility of having locative subordinating conjunctions is naturally explained.
This is, obviously, a theoretical consequence of the semantic and syntactic characterization of adverbial subordinating conjunctions proposed here, and it would be
necessary to carry out significant research in order to check if this conclusion is
empirically supported. However, there are some indications in European languages
that point in the same direction. In most European languages, locative subordina-

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 121

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

121

tors predominantly consist of one monomorphemic word (see Kortmann 1997,


especially chapter 7), in contrast with other adverbial subordinators. On the other
hand, locative subordinators in most European languages are formally identical to
locative interrogative words. Here we have some examples:
(27) a. Locative relative adverbs: donde (Spanish); on (Catalan); dove (Italian); o
(French); where (English); wo (German); waar (Dutch); gdzie (Polish).
b. Locative interrogative adverbs: dnde (Spanish); on (Catalan); dove (Italian);
o (French); where (English); wo (German); waar (Dutch); gdzie (Polish).
The fact that locative subordinators are predominantly simple words could be
closely related to the basic semantic structure of spatial expressions, which takes a
Thing as internal argument. Many adverbial subordinators are originated in several types of constructions that contain a clausal complement (mostly phrases headed by simple or complex prepositions and adverbs; that is the origin of Spanish a
condicin de que, porque, siempre que, etc.). But, as we have previously seen, a
clausal structure cannot correspond to the semantic category Thing15. As to the
formal similarity between locative subordinators and interrogative words, it is a
consequence that relative and interrogative adverbs are basically the same class of
words that are characterized by being moved in the sentence, whether in the syntax or in the logical form.
6. Concluding remarks
In this paper, we have reviewed the syntactic categorial properties of adverbial subordinating conjunctions and assumed the proposal, by Haumann (1997), that they
unify properties of lexical and functional heads: specifically, properties of prepositions and complementizers. We have also compared the properties of sentences
introduced by adverbial subordinating conjunctions with the properties of adverbial
free relative sentences, which, in contrast to the former, can express spatial relations. After that, we have outlined the semantic structure of spatial expressions and
offered an answer to the question which opens this paper. The non-existence of
locative adverbial subordinating conjunctions is due to the incompatibility between
the semantic structure of spatial expressions and the syntactic structure of sentences introduced by this type of conjunctions.

15. In some languages, there is more than one locative relative-interrogative adverbs, like English
whence. Furthermore, there are also complex units based on a relative-interrogative adverb modified by a preposition, like German wohin (lit. where-to), woher (lit. where-from).

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 122

122

CatJL 9, 2010

Mara Victoria Pavn Lucero

References
Adger, David (2003). Core Syntax. A Minimalist Approach. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Bello, Andrs (1847). Gramtica de la lengua castellana destinada al uso de los americanos. Edited by Ramn Trujillo, Cabildo Insular de Tenerife, 1981.
Bresnan, Joan; Grimshaw, Jane (1978). The syntax of free relatives in English.
Linguistic Inquiry 9/3: 331-391.
Brucart, Jos Mara (1999). La estructura del sintagma nominal: las oraciones de relativo. In: Bosque, Ignacio; Demonte, Violeta (dirs.). Gramtica descriptiva de la lengua espaola. Madrid: Espasa-Calpe, pp. 395-522.
Cinque, Giuglielmo (1999). Adverbs and Functional Heads. A Cross-Linguistic
Perspective. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press.
CREA: Real Academia Espaola. Banco de datos (CREA) [en lnea]. Corpus de referencia del espaol actual. <http://www.rae.es>
Emonds, Joseph E. (1985). A Unified Theory of Syntactic Categories. Dordrecht: Foris.
Fernndez-Salgueiro, Gerardo (2008). Aspects of the syntax of (TP-) coordination,
across-the-board extraction, and parasitic gaps. Doctoral dissertation. University
of Michigan.
Garca Fernndez, Luis (1999). Los complementos adverbiales temporales. La subordinacin temporal. In: Bosque, Ignacio; Demonte, Violeta (dirs.). Gramtica descriptiva de la lengua espaola. Madrid: Espasa-Calpe, pp. 3129-3208.
Groos, Anneke; van Riemsdijk, Henk (1981). Matching effects in free relatives: a
parameter of core grammar. In: Belletti, Adriana et al. (eds.). Theory of Markedness
in Generative Grammar. Pisa: Scuola Normale Superiore, pp. 171-216.
Guron, Jacqueline; Lecarme, Jacqueline (eds.) (2004). The Syntax of Time. Cambridge,
MA: MIT Press.
Haegeman, Liliane (2007). Operator movement and topicalisation in adverbial clauses.
Folia Linguistica 41/3-4: 279-325
Haumann, Dagmar (1997). The Syntax of Subordination. Tbingen: Max Niemeyer
Verlag.
Hendrick, Randall (1976). Prepositions and the X-bar Theory. In: Emonds, Joseph
(ed.). Proposals for Semantic and Syntactic Theory. Los Angeles: UCLA Papers
in Syntax, pp. 95-122.
Hernanz, M Llusa (1999). El infinitivo. In: Bosque, Ignacio; Demonte, Violeta
(dirs.). Gramtica descriptiva de la lengua espaola. Madrid: Espasa-Calpe,
pp. 2196-2356.
Hjemslev, Louis (1928). Principes de grammaire gnrale. Kbenhavn: Munksgaard.
Jackendoff, Ray (1973). The Base Rules for Prepositional Phrases. In: Anderson,
Stephen R.; Kiparsky, Paul (eds.). A Festschrift for Morris Halle. New York: Holt,
Rinehart & Winston, pp. 345-356.
Jackendoff, Ray (1977). X-Bar Syntax: A Study of Phrase Structure. Cambridge, MA:
MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (1983). Semantics and Cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (1990). Semantic Structures. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Jackendoff, Ray (2002). Foundations of Language. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Jespersen, Otto (1924). The Philosophy of Grammar. London: Allen and Unwin.

CatJourLing 9 001-192_CatJL 13/02/11 19:30 Pgina 123

Why Are There No Locative Conjunctions in Spanish?

CatJL 9, 2010

123

Kortmann, Bernd (1997). Adverbial Subordination. A Typology and History of Adverbial


Subordinators Based on European Languages. Berlin-New York: Mouton de Gruyter.
Larson, Richard K. (1990). Extraction and Multiple Selection in PP. The Linguistic
Review 7: 169-182.
Lasnik, Howard; Saito, Mamuro (1992). Move . Cambridge, MA: The MIT Press.
Pavn Lucero, M Victoria (2003a). Relaciones entre sintaxis y semntica: de por qu
no existen conjunciones subordinantes locativas en espaol. In: Muoz Nez,
M. D.; Rodrguez-Piero Alcal, A. I.; Fernndez Smith, G.; Bentez Soto, V. (eds.).
IV Congreso de Lingstica General. Cdiz, del 3 al 6 de abril de 2000. Cdiz:
Universidad de Cdiz-Universidad de Alcal, pp. 2053-2062.
Pavn Lucero, M Victoria (2003b). Sintaxis de las partculas. Madrid: Visor.
Pottier, Bernard (1962). Systematique des lments de relation. Paris: Klinksieck.
Real Academia Espaola (1928). Gramtica de la lengua espaola. Madrid: Hernando.
Real Academia Espaola (1973). Esbozo de una nueva gramtica de la lengua espaola.
Madrid: Espasa Calpe.
Real Academia Espaola (2009). Nueva gramtica de la lengua espaola. Madrid:
Espasa Calpe.
Riemsdijk, Henk van (1981). Free relatives. In: Everaert, Martin; Riemsdijk, Henk
van (eds.). The Blackwell Companion to Syntax II. Oxford: Blackwell, pp. 338-382.
Rigau, Gemma (1984). De com si no s conjunci i daltres elements interrogatius.
Estudis gramaticals I: 249-278.
Rizzi, Luigi (ed.) (2004). The Structure of CP and IP. The Cartography of Syntactic
Structures, volume 2. Oxford-New York: Oxford University Press.
Vries, Mark de (2002). The Syntax of Relativization. Utrecht: LOT.

You might also like