You are on page 1of 19

"As White as Anybody": Race and the Politics of Counting as Black

Author(s): Kenneth W. Warren


Source: New Literary History, Vol. 31, No. 4, Is There Life after Identity Politics?
(Autumn, 2000), pp. 709-726
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/20057632
Accessed: 05-12-2016 20:43 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted
digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about
JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

The Johns Hopkins University Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access
to New Literary History

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"As white as anybody":

Race and the Politics of Counting as Black


Kenneth W. Warren

I
With the Census 2000 questionnaires in the mail during March
of 2000, the word from black format radio to its listener base
was unequivocal: avoid the undercount. Fill out and return your
census forms.1 The Undercount, of course, is the term for the widely
known fact that the US census routinely misses some number of the
nation's citizenry in its attempt to count the nation's population. More to
the point, although the 1980 and 1990 censuses each missed less than two
percent of the population, those not counted tended to be poor, minority
urban dwellers. In 1980 "blacks made up 11.7 percent of the United States
population," but accounted for fifty-three percent of those missed by the
census.2 And despite concerted efforts to redress the problem, the US
Census monitoring board reported that "the 1990 undercount was larger

than the previous census." In 1980 1.2 percent of the population was
missed; in 1990 those missed accounted for 1.8 percent of the population,
or 4.7 million people in all. In addition, the 1990 "results also continued
an alarming trend: those left uncounted were disproportionately from
minority, low-income or urban communities."3 When coupled with esti

mates that as many as six million people, most of them white, were
counted twice, the official nation was presumably whiter and wealthier
than the "real" nation.4 Yet even as radio hosts urged black listeners to
make sure they were counted, they also professed only partial faith in the
efficacy of this strategy. Pointing to what they insisted were disparities
between the official and the actual crowd estimates for such events as the

Million Man March and a more recent rally in Tallahassee, Florida in


support of affirmative action, radio commentators complained that all
official counting of minority populations amounted to undercounting.5
The sense that it is becoming increasingly difficult to get individuals

and the nation as a whole to count as black is both a recent and

longstanding anxiety reflecting uncertainty about the ultimate point of


political representation at all levels. Should we be striving for a nation in
which people "like me"?in whatever way I define those attributes that
New Literary History, 2000, 31: 709-726

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

710

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

make someone "like me"?will always be present in assemblies that claim


to represent me?6 Or should we seek a nation in which even if there is no
one "like me" in an assembly representing me, I can nonetheless rest

assured that I will be represented responsibly and knowledgeably?


Historically, of course, the latter goal has been undermined by the fact
that for many people the production of assemblies that include no one
"like me" has been for the most part a result of deliberate policies of

exclusion. As Rogers Smith has demonstrated, US law has "long been


shot through with forms of second-class citizenship, denying personal
liberties and opportunities for political participation to most of the adult
population on the basis of race, ethnicity, gender, and even religion."7
Understandably, then, it has made sense to insist that people like me be
present in any body claiming to represent me.

Yet even in the wake of efforts to make the nation's politics more
inclusive, problems of representation persist. And for those who count
themselves among a numerical minority there is a high likelihood that no
one "like me" will be found in some representative body whose decisions
affect my well-being. And while there may be a number of possible ways to

approach this problem, this essay will take up one particularly vexed
response to the issue of nonrepresentation, namely, the attempt to
transform somebody who is apparently not like me into someone who
is?in other words, the attempt to make available to someone else those
feelings, beliefs, assumptions, behaviors, and so forth that presumably
would enable that person, if only for a time, to act for me, and perhaps
even, like me.8 Behind this attempt lies the idea that while true represen
tation necessarily rests on one's numbers in the general population it also
nonetheless demands more than a knowledge of those numbers.

This simultaneous reliance upon and distrust of official numbers

partially explains the continuing power of what has been called identity
politics in US public life. David Theo Goldberg has described the census
as "a technology that has racialized the social fabric and reflected the

distinctions alive in the general culture." For Goldberg, the census

authorizes "the prevailing language of imposed identity and identifica


tion."9 And in support of Goldberg's view, some of the official literature
of the US Census Bureau does seem to insist both that to know who we
are we must first know how many of us there are, and that consolidating
our identities is the first step in determining what we ought to do. The

census, then, is not simply presented as a tool for ensuring fair


distribution of resources and fair apportionment of representatives to
local, state, and national governments. Rather the Census 2000 website

declares the census to be a national self-portrait and prognosticator:


"The census serves as a vital statistical database that tells us who we are

and where we are going as a nation."10

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"AS WHITE AS ANYBODY"

It is far from clear, however, that a census enabling democratic


fairness is the same as a census telling "us who we are." The attributes
that help "the government decide how to distribute funds and assistance
to states and localities" are not necessarily those attributes that individu
als feel best express their identities. Recent decisions about the census
underscore this tension. After agreeing in October of 1999 that individu
als could for the first time in the history of the census check off more
than one race on census forms, the Office of Management and Budget
(OMB) announced in March of 2000 that those checking both "white"
and "minority" categories would nonetheless be counted as minorities.
The decision to allow individuals greater flexibility in designating racial
identity was made largely in response to pressure brought to bear by
individuals and groups describing themselves as multiracial. Although

"pure" racial groups have always been a social chimera, the growing
prominence of multiracial spokespersons pointed up graphically that
the older census forms could no longer tell us what we are, that is, a
nation that no longer fits into neat racial categories. However, the OMB

also argued that its subsequent decision to assign biracial Americans


traditional racial identities was necessary to enable the enforcement of
"anti-discrimination and voting rights laws."11 Taken together, the deci

sions arguably stand to create different official nations: one, to be


reported on the national census, reflecting sixty-three possible racial

classifications and another, emanating from local, state, and federal


agencies, reflecting only nine categories for civil rights enforcement.
Depending on how one wants to look at it, the nation, officially, will
either be more diverse than it seems or seem more diverse than it is.
That people identifying themselves as biracially white and black will

be made to "seem" merely black for enforcement purposes has the


apparent irony of making official the "one-drop" rule that has prevailed
for much of the nation's history. And not surprisingly, critics such as

Michael Lind and Orlando Patterson have censured the OMB on


precisely this implication: "We're back to the one drop rule," Lind

complained.12 And if he and Patterson are right, modern citizens are


being returned to the condition of Puddnhead Wilsons Roxy, who, as
Mark Twain's narrator tells us, "was as white as anybody, but the one
sixteenth of her which was black out-voted the other fifteen parts and
made her a negro."13 At one level of course, the return of today's
Americans to the condition of Roxy is only apparent. The labeling of
Roxy as black in the late nineteenth century differed in intent from the

OMB's year 2000 decision to describe multiracial people as black. Roxy


is made to count as black only as a result of a systemic process to deny
her freedom and equality, while her contemporary counterparts count
as black presumably to facilitate the removal of the vestiges of that

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

711

712

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

systemic bias. If being as white as anybody fails to count in both cases,


the reasons for this "failure" make all the difference.
And yet it is not entirely clear what it would mean to be "as white as
anybody." Given that race is a social construction, it might be just as
accurate to describe Roxy as being as black as anybody. But if everybody
is as black or as white as everyone else then maybe the problem is that
nobody is as white or black as she seems.
But as we've seen in light of the recent census debate, the problem of

figuring out how to describe someone like Roxy depends on the ends
one has in mind. For example, Goldberg, who otherwise supports the
practice of allowing people to designate their identities in any way they
please, nonetheless comes back to counting by race "only where it
signals class exploitation and exclusion?past, present, and predictably
future" (RS 58). On this view, what would matter for Roxy is not that she
is as white as anybody but rather that she is treated as if she were not?

which is of course Twain's point, or more accurately, only part of

Twain's point. The larger issue is whether or not justice would be served
if Roxy were indeed treated as if she were as white as anybody. Can it

ever be a good thing to treat everybody as if they were as white as


anybody?

This question is, in many ways, rhetorical. Most creditable voices on


whiteness agree that to treat somebody like Roxy as if she were as white

as anybody would entail treating somebody else as if he were not.


Whiteness is a category premised on inequality. As Charles Mills argues
in The Racial Contract, whiteness "is always the differential privileging of
the whites as a group with respect to the nonwhites as a group."14 Even
conservatives like Abigail Thernstrom and Stephen Thernstrom appear
to concur on this point, observing in America in Black and White that "the

concept 'white,' as we have seen, is not meaningful?including as it


does, such disparate groups as Cajuns, Armenians, French Canadians,
and Latvians. And thus, if today 'white' socioeconomic status is by many
measures higher than that of blacks, that is a picture that can and should
change."15 The way to redress the inequality inherent to whiteness would
be to create a world in which it would be impossible for a Roxy or for
anyone else to be as white as anybody.
Yet many of these critics also agree that it should nonetheless remain

possible to be at least as black as somebody. For example, when


Thernstrom and Thernstrom ask rhetorically whether their support of a

racially indivisible nation would require black Americans "to deny all
cultural differences associated with group membership," they answer
emphatically in the negative: "Of course not. Jews haven't; Armenians
haven't; Ukrainians haven't. Many Americans arrange their private lives
so as to spend much of their time with others of the same background.

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"AS WHITE AS ANYBODY"

713

Purging all racial distinctions from our law and our public life would
pose no threat to those who wish to live in a predominately black
neighborhood, attend an all-black church, and otherwise associate
primarily or even exclusively with their fellow African Americans" (540).

Thus, while one may no longer be black, Armenian, or Jewish in any


official sense, one may nonetheless go on being one of these identities
happily, if unofficially so. The heart of the argument of America in Black
and White is that the socioeconomic indicators and the discriminatory

practices that have distinguished white from black have diminished


significantly and will continue to do so if as a nation we do not insist on
government policies that highlight our presumed differences. A nation
no longer defined by white socioeconomic privilege, the United States
would also nonetheless be "a complex mosaic of groups with different
histories and different cultural traits that have led them to concentrate

in different social niches" (541).

Given the apparent consensus that black group identity will persist
even after the dissolution of whiteness, how can we account for the
suspicions mentioned at the beginning of this essay?the suspicions that
it is becoming increasingly difficult for blackness to count in the nation's
political life? There are perhaps many reasons. Most obvious have been
attempts during the 1980s and 1990s to dismantle affirmative action and

other race-sensitive policies. Abigail Thernstrom's opposition to the


racial districting measures employed to support the Voting Rights Act of

1965 would be among these. Thernstrom has specifically opposed the


creation of majority minority districts, and her arguments have contrib
uted substantively to the dismantling of such districts. Then, as men

tioned earlier, the rise of the mixed-race movement, along with the
possibility of selecting one's own race, has for many critics raised the
specter that a significant number of people might count themselves out
of blackness. And finally, the high level of police and gang violence and

the hyper-attentiveness to drug use involving black Americans has


engendered a fear that a policy of genocide has been directed towards
this portion of the population.
The possibility that these recent trends constitute a growing threat to
black numbers is responsible in part for the seemingly contradictory
logic sustained by Census 2000 in making people count as black even as
they are counted as other than black. And yet this contradiction is not
particularly new. In fact, what I intend to draw out for the balance of this

essay is the curious logic by which in order for it to be possible for


anybody to continue to count as black, it has to be possible to transform
somebody who does not count as black into someone who does. What I
have in mind might be phrased as follows: the only way to make "black"
those people whom we are already inclined to see as black would be first

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

714

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

to acknowledge the possibility of making black someone (or something)


whom we are not initially inclined to see this way.

II
To say that Ralph Ellison was a Negro (or if you will, black, or African

American) writer would appear to go without saying. To ask when


Ellison became a Negro writer might seem equally strange, although
Ellison, in refuting Irving Howe's contention that Richard Wright had
been Ellison's primary influence, did remark sarcastically, "I had been a

Negro for twenty-two or twenty-three years when I met [Richard]


Wright," as if it might have been possible that had he met Wright earlier

in his life, Ellison would have been a different kind of Negro. The
crucial question, then, might be to ask how Ellison became, and once
becoming, how he remained, a Negro writer? In the contemporary
environment one might add to this question the additional one of
whether or not we ought to continue to count Ellison as a Negro or
black writer.

Ellison is justly remembered for his insistence that intellectual lines of

affiliation do not necessarily follow social norms. His now-famous


response to Howe is worth quoting at some length:
But perhaps you will understand when I say [Richard Wright] did not influence
me if I point out that while one can do nothing about choosing one's relatives,
one can, as artist, choose one's "ancestors." Wright was, in this sense, a "relative,"
Hemingway an "ancestor." Langston Hughes, whose work I knew in grade school
and whom I knew before I knew Wright, was a "relative"; Eliot, whom I was to
meet only many years later, and Malraux and Dostoevsky and Faulkner, were
"ancestors"?if you please or don't please.16

Of course, claiming a "white" ancestor was not a strategy for making


Ellison himself white. Jerry Watts has observed that in "The World and
the Jug," Ellison "does not shy away from clothing himself in blackness,

a tactic that allows him to affect the air of the knowledgeable native
against the aggressive, ignorant interloper/colonizer."17 Watts is on
point in noting that throughout Ellison's various briefs for his own
individuality as a writer it nonetheless remained important for him to
continue to count as a Negro writer. But Ellison's maneuver here does
more than reiterate the central point of "The World and the Jug," that is,

that racial segregation is not an "opaque steel jug with the Negroes
inside waiting for some black messiah to come along and blow the cork"
but rather a "transparent, not opaque [jug], and one is allowed not only

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"AS WHITE AS ANYBODY"

to see outside but to read what is going on out there" (CE 163-64). In
addition, Ellison's insistence that he can choose his ancestors becomes a
way of making them, as well as himself, count for blackness: "I under
stand a bit more about myself as a Negro because literature has taught
me something of my identity as a Western man" (CE 164). This process
is most visible in Ellison's treatment of Ernest Hemingway. In an earlier
essay, "Twentieth-Century Fiction and the Mask of Humanity," Hemingway

had exemplified what Ellison describes as American literature's evasion

of blackness: "when I read the early Hemingway I seem to be in the


presence of a Huckleberry Finn who, instead of identifying himself with
humanity and attempting to steal Jim free, chose to write the letter
which sent him back into slavery."18 Yet for the purpose of rebuking

Howe, Hemingway's work had become in Ellison's eyes "imbued with a


spirit beyond the tragic with which I could feel at home, for it was very

close to the feeling of the blues, which are, perhaps, as close as


Americans can come to expressing the spirit of tragedy" (CE 186).19

I have remarked elsewhere on the supremely tactical aspects of

Ellison's essays,20 but what I want to stress here is that Ellison secures his
own identity as a Negro writer by making the previously white Hemingway

as close to a Negro as any American could be. The now-familiar claim,


associated with writers like Ellison, Albert Murray, and Stanley Crouch,
that America cannot help but be black, is of course part of what informs

Ellison's description of Hemingway in "The World and the Jug." This


argument against racial purity insists that everyone, black and white, is,
to quote Ellison, "'mammy-made' right here at home."21 The cultural
and political task facing the writer is to elicit recognition of that fact.
And yet in this discussion of Hemingway, exposing the unacknowledged
blackness of American culture is only part of the story.
Ellison's reading of Hemingway as being almost a blues artist?which

is to say, almost a Negro writer?is not the same as claiming that


anybody, or more precisely, any American writer, is almost a Negro
writer. Some are. Some are not. In fact, in "The World and the Jug,"
Wright becomes a sociological or a Marxist writer, which means he
comes perilously close to not being a Negro writer. It isn't that Ellison
doubts Wright's Negroness per se. Neither is he particularly interested
in drumming Wright out of the corps of Negro writers. Rather, in
lamenting "How awful that Wright found the facile answers of Marxism
before he learned to use literature as a means for discovering the forms
of American Negro humanity" (CE 167), Ellison faults Wright for lacking

the discernment he should have gained as a Negro and which, had he


gained it, would have enabled him to distinguish clearly between what
methods best lend themselves to revealing the humanity of the Negro.
Wright fails to tell us who the Negro really is.

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

715

716

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

A second instance when Ellison secures his identity as a Negro writer


occurs in the 1968 essay "The Myth of the Flawed White Southerner,"
where Ellison defends himself for choosing to attend the 1965 National

Festival for the Arts at the White House, sponsored by President


Johnson. Under normal circumstances Ellison's attendance at an event
like this would have occasioned no controversy. The Kennedy presi
dency had made it no longer an unusual event for a black American to
be invited to the White House. And the appropriateness of Ellison's
being invited to the National Festival was unquestionable. Besides being
the winner of a National Book Award for Invisible Man in 1952, Ellison
was also a charter member of the National Council on the Arts.
But the Johnson administration's prosecution of the war had begun to
galvanize the intellectual left, and the poet Robert Lowell, who had also

been invited to attend the National Festival, had called for the other
invitees to boycott the festival in protest. Ellison, however, chose to
attend?a decision which he justified in several ways. As he tells us in his
essay, the first factor in his decision (a factor incidental to our concerns
here) is that he felt that in the long run the government's decision to
support the arts was of more significance than its efforts to end the war
immediately. His exact words are, "I felt that governmental aid to the

American arts and artists was of a more abiding importance than my


hopes that the Vietnam war would be brought to a swift conclusion."22

Given the enormous human cost that the war occasioned, Ellison's

apparent preference for art over war protest seems at first glance callous

and morally reprehensible. On closer inspection, however, and on a


reading of the essay as whole, we can see that Ellison is not simply
expressing a preference for art over protest. Rather he is saying
something more like the following: "Sure, as much as anyone else I
wanted the war to end quickly. Given, however, the social division of
labor that defines a complex society and that my role as a novelist makes
me more immediately responsible for the condition of the arts in society

than it does for administering the war, it was my duty to be more

immediately concerned with securing for the arts a place in contempo


rary society than with anything else."

Ellison cannot, however, allow his response to rest here because he

still must explain why his view of the matter differs from that of other

artists or writers who were presumably as concerned as he about the


place of art in contemporary society but who did not see fit to attend the

White House Festival. Accordingly, Ellison offers another explanation


(and I should note here that I am not presenting these justifications in
the exact order in which they occur in the essay): he justifies his support
of Johnson in light of the President's role as the architect of the Great

Society programs of the 1960s. Regardless of the moral Tightness or

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"AS WHITE AS ANYBODY"

717

wrongness of the United States's involvement in Vietnam, Ellison gives


priority to "other costly wars of much longer duration right here at

home?the war against poverty and the war for racial equality?and
therefore I cannot so easily ignore the changes that the President has

made in the condition of my people and still consider myself a


responsible intellectual. My sense of priorities is of necessity different"
(CE557). Chiding his fellow liberal, white artists and intellectuals in the
North for what he calls "segregationist tendencies," Ellison insists that
Johnson, unlike these intellectuals, has made a difference in the lives of
black Americans, and that the Civil Rights struggle has as much a claim
on him as a black American as does the antiwar movement.

Having lauded the Johnson administration's Civil Rights record,


Ellison could simply have complained that his fellow intellectuals?if
they had been properly committed to the Civil Rights struggle?should
have joined him in rejecting Lowell's plea for a boycott. But as we see,
instead of arguing that his intellectual colleagues should adopt a course
of action similar to his, Ellison insists that his "sense of priorities is of
necessity different" from that of his fellow white intellectuals. He then
adduces race, region, and history to explain why he cannot see things
Lowell's way, calling our attention to a
personal and group history which had shaped my background and guided my

consciousness, a history and background that marked a basic divergence

between my own experience and that of the dissenting intellectuals. . . . [F]or

historical reasons none has ever been poor in the special ways that Negro

Americans are poor. Some began to write, as did I, during the 1930s, but here
again none came to writing careers from a background so barren of writers as
mine. To these racial and historical differences is added the fact that we spring
from different regions of the land. I had come from a different part of the
country and had been born of parents who were of this land for longer than

many of theirs had been, and I had grown up under conditions far more

explicitly difficult than they. Which outlines another important difference: I had
come from a region adjacent to that from which the President emerged, and
where the American language was spoken?by whites, at least?with an accent
much like that with which he speaks. (CE 554-56)

The strength of the contrast between Ellison and his fellow intellectuals

depends on his being the sole black intellectual on the horizon. If

historical, cultural, and regional factors are what make him different
from his critics, one has to presume that everyone sharing his background
would agree with him on this matter. He is not representing simply the
Ellisonian perspective, but the Negro Oklahoman perspective. It is from

this perspective that Ellison also claims a view of President Johnson


more discerning than the perspective available to a white, liberal New

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

718

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

Englander like Lowell. In Ellison's words, "growing up, a Negro Oklaho


man . . . one learned to listen to the individual intonation, to what was
said as well as to how it was said, to content and implication as well as to
style" (CE556). Johnson's accent and style, which Ellison believed to be
sources of difficulty for someone like Lowell, actually provide a point of

contact between the President and Ellison as well as between the

President and those whose point of view Ellison presumes to represent.


Ellison further immerses his individual perspective in that of the group
in his final justification of his support for Johnson by having recourse to

"the hopes, dreams and myths of my people," to which he must "be


true." He elaborates:
So perhaps I am motivated here by an old slave-born myth of Negroes?not the
myth of the "good white man," nor that of the "great white father," but the myth,

secret and questioning, of the flawed white Southerner who while true to his
Southern roots has confronted the injustices of the past and has been redeemed.
Such a man, the myth holds, will do the right thing however great the cost,
whether he likes Negroes or not, and will move with tragic vulnerability toward
the broader ideals of American democracy. (CE 561)

Ellison invokes the myth for two reasons. First, it helps secure his
difference, racially, from white intellectuals. Treating race solely as a
matter of history and experience and not biology, Ellison nonetheless
insists that this history and experience distinguish him from someone
like Lowell. The second operation performed by Ellison's myth is that it

creates two presidents. Ellison's president?the Negroes' president?is


different from Lowell's president. Although despised and distrusted by
Lowell, Lyndon Johnson, via Ellison, gets entrusted with the hopes of the
Negro. In much the same way that Hemingway becomes almost a Negro

writer, Johnson becomes almost a Negro president. Clearly not the


president of choice for leftist intellectuals and artists, Johnson just might

be "the greatest American President for the poor and for Negroes,"
which, according to Ellison is "a very great honor indeed" (CE562). One

does, however, have to be a Negro Oklahoman, or at least a Negro, in


order to see how President Johnson was almost a Negro president.

Yet as high as Ellison allowed his praise for Johnson to ascend, his
essay did maintain an insistence on racial distinction. Johnson may have
been in Ellison's eyes "the greatest American president for the poor and
for Negroes," but he remained a "flawed white Southerner."
We would have to wait until Bill Clinton came on the scene to see how

a "flawed white Southerner" could somehow become, according to


comedian Chris Rock, "the first black president" and moreover, could
do so while overseeing the final stages of the rollback of Johnson's Great

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"as white as anybody"

719

Society.23 By what alchemy had the honorific of blackness been bestowed

so cheaply?
By way of answer, one can turn to the events that led Chris Rock to

count a very flawed white Southerner as the first black president,


namely, the Monica Lewinsky affair. As the Kenneth Starr investigation
into the Lewinsky affair intensified during the summer of 1998, polling
data indicated that support for Clinton was higher among blacks than
among whites. A New York Times/CBS News poll published on September
19 of that year indicated differences of approximately thirty percentage

points between black and white respondents when asked, "Do you
approve of the way Bill Clinton is handling his job as President?" The
August results showed that a majority (sixty percent) of whites and an

overwhelming majority (ninety-four percent) of blacks approved of


Clinton's job performance.24
The larger story, however, was that most Americans who were polled
continued to support Clinton even as the details of his affair with
Lewinsky and lies he had told to cover it up became public knowledge.
Accordingly, in an article titled, "In a Typical Community, Typical Folks
Back Clinton," the Times reported that "It is the ordinary people of Stark
County [Ohio], not the political elite, who are behind the groundswell

for the President."25 Interviewing a group that appeared to consist


largely of white Republicans, the article's author, Michael Winerip,
discovered that a majority of the Americans did not believe that Clinton
deserved to be impeached for his offenses. Many labeled the President's
offense a "private" matter and cited the overall health of the economy as

reason to support Clinton (A 11).


Yet despite the across-the-board support for the President, the signifi

cantly higher level of support for Clinton among black Americans


seemed to demand an explanation, and the Times set out to find one.
Not surprisingly it did. So, roughly at the same time that the paper was
reporting that "typical folks" across the country supported Clinton, the
paper also began to report that black people supported Clinton but that

they did so atypically. The Times observed that black respondents


"admired" Clinton on pragmatic grounds and cited his stance on

affirmative action and his judicial and administrative appointments as


examples. But, the paper went on, "their support for him is not simply a
reflection of loyalty and political self interest. It is also the product of
distinct cultural traits born of the black experience in the United States,
including a broad distrust of prosecutors, an instinctive empathy for the

persecuted and spiritual emphasis on forgiveness and redemption."26


The idea that distrust of prosecutors is a "cultural trait" certainly raises
an eyebrow, but the Times can perhaps be forgiven for coming to such a
conclusion if only because, one after another, the black intellectuals and

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

720

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

officials who were asked to explain the reported statistical difference


cited reasons that were broadly "cultural." Gregory Jackson, a Detroit
businessman, opined that "African Americans are largely a very religious

people, and forgiveness is part of the culture. It has been a survival


technique. We couldn't survive with all that pent-up hatred, hostility and
fear, so we've had to forgive and move on." In the same vein, Harvard
law professor Christopher Edley observed that "When you have a whole

history of turning to the church for succor in the face of painful


circumstances, you have to believe that faith will not only heal your
wounds, but also reform the master," while the Reverend Joseph Lowery,

retired president of the Southern Christian Leadership Conference,


intoned, "We've drunk from the bitter cup of persecution and repres

sion, and if ever a president has been persecuted William Jefferson


Clinton has been persecuted" (A 10).
In his comments Lowery strikes the note of black identification with
the President that other respondents took up even when they didn't
turn to black religion as the explanation for the statistical difference.
George Wolfe, producer of the Joseph Papp Public Theatre, suggested
that Clinton had "been able to project, unlike any other President in
recent memory . . . that he is completely and totally comfortable with
black Americans." The President's reputed comfort with black Ameri
cans became almost complete identification when Harvard professor of
psychology Alvin F. Pouissant suggested that "some minorities were so
aware of Mr. Clinton's seeming affinity with black people that they
circulate rumors that he must have had black ancestry" (A 10).
The assumption that the difference in the polls must have a racial/
cultural explanation goes unchallenged throughout these remarks.
Large numbers of blacks and whites support Clinton, but these re
sponses presume that both groups necessarily support him differently.
To make a white President black is to make black Americans black,
which is to say, to make them different from whites even when they
appear to be doing the same things. For Clinton to be like "us," we have
to be more like ourselves, which is to say, like the image of ourselves as
differentiated by our experience. Even if, to the chagrin of conservative

pundits, many white Republican voters appeared willing to forgive


Clinton his sins, their forgiveness was not the same as black forgiveness,
which as we know was somehow distinctively black.

As the blackness of President Clinton began to be reiterated in the


nation's major media, novelist Toni Morrison weighed in to endorse
what she described as a rumor circulating among black men?the rumor
that "white skin notwithstanding, [Clinton] is our first black President."

Morrison continued:

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"AS WHITE AS ANYBODY"


Blacker than any actual black person who could ever be elected in our children's
lifetime. After all, Clinton displays almost every trope of blackness: single-parent
household, born poor, working class, saxophone playing, McDonald's-and-junk
food-loving boy from Arkansas. And when virtually all the African-American
Clinton appointees began, one by one, to disappear, when the President's body,
his unpoliced sexuality, became the focus of the prosecution, and when he was
metaphorically seized and body-searched, who could gainsay these black men
who knew whereof they spoke? The message was clear: "No matter how smart
you are, how hard you work, how much coin you earn for us, we will put you in

your place or put you out of the place you have somehow, albeit with our
permission, achieved. You will be fired from your job, sent away in disgrace

and?who knows??maybe sentenced and jailed to boot.27

In Morrison's estimation black men viewed the impeachment drama as


a reiteration of the fact that even if your accomplishments made you as
white as anybody, you could still be made out to be as black as everybody

else. Clinton's impeachment travail figured forth not the mean


spiritedness of US presidential politics but rather the collapsible dis
tance between the aspirations of upwardly mobile blacks and the
impoverished background they wanted and yet did not want to leave

behind.

That Clinton's difficulties confirmed certain "truths" about being


black in American society is further illustrated by Bebe Moore Campbell's
bestselling novel, Brothers and Sisters. Set during the wake of the Los

Angeles uprising, the novel opens with its MBA-degreed protagonist,


Esther Jackson, observing apprehensively as three white police officers
accost two young black boys on the street. From the bank window where

Esther watches the encounter the boys look "like gangbangers." None
theless Esther reacts to the scene instinctively and viscerally, saying to
herself, "Better not touch them.r The words are described as having
"roared through her body" so powerfully that she merges linguistically
with the young men: "The diction in her head was as slurred and
textured as the South Side Chicago neighborhood she'd grown up in."28
And as the plot of Brothers and Sisters unfolds, with Esther and another
black woman being falsely accused of stealing money from the bank,
Campbell drives home the point that vulnerability to public humiliation
is an unavoidable aspect of the black condition.

To find the material ground of Esther Jackson's reaction as well as


Toni Morrison's commentary on black male sensibilities one need look
no farther than the nation's aggressive law enforcement and incarcera
tion offensive of the 1980s and 1990s, which included among its tactics
mandatory sentencing, racial profiling, and a tendency of police,
prosecutors, and judges to regard the rights of the accused as inconve
niences to be circumvented whenever possible. While an impoverished

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

721

722

NEW LITERARY HISTORY

urban minority bore the brunt of this offensive, the ease with which
anybody black could be swept up in the policing dragnet brought home
how impossible it was for some people to be treated as if they were as
white as anybody. It was against this backdrop that one could imagine

that an answer had already been given to a question that had hardly
been formulated: did not the mere possibility that you were liable to be
treated as if you were as black as anybody somehow make you represen

tative of black people generally, even if you happened to be a white


President or a black MBA with dreams of getting into lending? On the
basis of that affinity, couldn't you be trusted to act on behalf of others

who were like you?


Of course, the idea that one is best represented by someone who
shares one's interests is central to politics. But the too-ready embrace of
the idea that one's interests derive from one's culture and one's tastes

may point up a weakness in the political order. The idea that a shared
culture operates in the manner of a prior restraint on the activities and
thoughts of political representatives seems particularly attractive when
one is, or feels oneself to be, unable to elect and hold accountable those
in power. If you have little or no capacity within the existing political
order and lack the social and political movements necessary to chal
lenge that order from outside, it is understandable to hope that there
will be someone in power who, though unlike you, will see themselves in
you and your fate as their own.
Turning back to Ellison we can find this logic clearly in evidence in his
posthumously published novel, Juneteenth. Late in that novel the Rever
end Hickman discovers the face of black America reflected in the visage

of Abraham Lincoln. Gazing at the face of Lincoln's statue at the


Lincoln Memorial, Hickman finds himself thinking, "That look, that's
us!" He continues: "Yes, that look and what put it there made him one of us. It
wasn't in the dirty dozens about his family and his skin-tone that they tried to ease

him into, but in that look in his eyes and in his struggle against the things which
put it there and saddened his features. It's in that, in being the kind of man he

made himself to be that he's one of us."29 Although Ellison, via Hickman,

alludes to rumors about Lincoln's having black ancestry (anticipating


the Clinton rumors), the identification of Lincoln with black Americans

is presented as primarily a matter of shared experience and condition?


"the peace and perception born of suffering" (282). These conditions,
despite Lincoln's shortcomings in regard to emancipation and racial
equality, count for Hickman as having made Lincoln more black than

white.

Yet even as Hickman venerates the kind of man who "joined us in what
we have been forced to learn about life," he also admits that the appearance

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

"as white as anybody"


of such a man is a rare occurrence: "It don't happen often, oh no" (281,

282). Indeed the plot of Ellison's unfinished novel turns on this

unlikelihood as Ellison centers his narrative on Hickman's apparently


failed attempt to mold a young man named Bliss, who is as white as
anybody, into an eloquent spokesmen for the plight of the downtrod
den. After apprenticing Bliss as a revivalist preacher, Hickman is cruelly
rewarded by the young man's having run away and grown up to become

a race-baiting US Senator. Reflecting on Bliss's career and Lincoln's


example, the Reverend Hickman remarks ruefully to himself, "And to
think, . . . we had hope to raise ourselves that kind of man" (283).

Because Ellison died before completing his novel, no one can know
exactly how he would have resolved Hickman's dilemma. But his belief

in the possibility of finding "that kind of man"?a belief already


anachronistic even as Ellison struggled to complete the novel?has
apparently lived out its career as tragedy only to have returned as farce

in the claim that the "saxophone playing, McDonald's-and^junk-food


loving boy from Arkansas" had somehow by the fall of 1998 become
"that kind of man."

Clinton had come to power by endorsing the New Liberal agenda


promulgated by the Democratic Leadership Council (DLC), which he
chaired on his way to the presidency in the 1980s. According to that

agenda, "the Democrats had become beholden to various 'special

interests,' usually perceived as blacks and other minorities, women, gays,


and lesbians." Consequently, for Democrats "the only way to win at the
presidential level and to govern effectively was to shed their traditional
support for and identification with the poor, the working class, and
minorities and to reach out to disaffected whites and economic elites by
moving to the right on issues such as crime, affirmative action, welfare,

and economic justice."30 In effect, according to the DLC, white male


democrats and the party they belonged to were the Roxy of the political

world?"as white as anybody," but unfortunately viewed as "negro"


because the party's dark and deviant minority had been successful in
out-voting its majority. Clinton had come on the scene to set the matter
right, and in a series of choreographed events that included returning to

Arkansas to oversee the execution of Rickey Ray Rector, a "mentally


incapacitated" black man,31 he succeeded in giving a Democratic candi
date a "white man's chance" of becoming President of the United States.

That Clinton's personal trials and d?class? tastes managed to secure


his blackness even as he pursued a policy agenda that undermined the
well-being of significant portions of the nation's minority population
underscores the troubling dynamics of the politics I've been describing:
Clinton became black only after having made other people black, that is,

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

723

724

new literary history

placing the needs and interests of certain portions of the popu

outside the day-to-day responsibilities of the nation's elected repr


tives. Yet even after having refused to represent the interests of

population in setting the Democratic party's agenda, Clinton

nonetheless "represent" the constituency he had spurned by becom

victim rather than a wielder of political power. In fact, the fo

situation might have contributed to the latter. What possibly embo

the House Republicans to pursue their strategy of impeachmen

their correct perception that Clinton's political well-being depende

the white and relatively conservative portion of his constituen


Clinton had made sure that the Democratic party would be se

representing the Reagan Democrats, the constituency that during


1980s had objected strenuously to the identification of the Democr
with blacks, gays, and the like. It was these so-called Reagan Democ
whom impeachment-minded Republicans thought they could mo
against the President.
As we all know, that story ended with the President apparently g
the last laugh. Yet, the fact that the Republicans overplayed their
and miscalculated the level of voter outrage over the Lewinsky aff
should not blind us to one crucial truth: Clinton suffered the slin

arrows of outrageous fortune not because he was our first bl

president, but rather because he so obviously wasn't.


This is not, however, to say that a politically progressive agenda s
be to elect a "real" black president. The specter of Clarence Thoma
a justice on the US Supreme Court reveals the insufficiency of
goal: making people count as black operates weakly and unpredi

in guiding political practice. Neither Thomas's impoverished


nings in Pinpoint, Georgia nor his capacity to express sympath

those "people who have seen their neighborhoods literally destroy

gangs and violence and drugs," as he did in writing his dissen

opinion in Chicago v Morales, has proved to be an obstacle to his ju


activism on behalf of a politically regressive agenda.33 In fact, wheth

are talking about Clinton?who, we might say, really isn't bla

Thomas, who we might say, really is?the political tactic of making


men count as black appears to have operated most forcefully when i

excused actions running counter to the interests of some the

people supposedly represented through the identification.


A politics that relies on getting a sufficient number of American
count as black begs several questions, only the least of which is de

what number would be sufficient. A more telling weakness o

politics?as revealed quite clearly by Ellison's non-exchange with Ro


Lowell over boycotting President Johnson's Festival of the Arts?is
such a politics is insufficiently discursive and argumentative. The u

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

725

"as white as anybody"


of Ellison's recourse to myth is that only someone sufficiently like Ellison
could understand Ellison; which, as it turns out, is simply another way of
expressing the politics of the census, that is, the more people there are
like me, the greater the likelihood that they already see things my way. If

such is the case, then, my goal should not be to win people over to a
politics but to adduce as many of them as I can as evidence that the
political opinions I am expressing are not merely my own. Politics
becomes little more than a show of numbers.

We need, however, to come back round to an idea of politics that


presumes the utility of discussion and consensus-building rather than
ascription and identity. Crafting a political left that does not merely
reflect existing racial divisions starts with the relatively mundane propo
sition that it is possible to make a persuasive appeal to the given interests

of working and unemployed women and men, regardless of race, in


support of a program for economic justice. This is not to suggest that we
ignore race. Rather, it is to recognize, as Anna Julia Cooper pointed out
in the final decade of the nineteenth century, that a standard justification

for the absence of blacks from certain assemblies was the claim that
blacks had already joined those assemblies "whither their racial proclivi
ties undeniably tend."34 Once this claim becomes an assumption, then

the response is to make no appeal at all?and the lack of any such


appeal is merely politics by the numbers.

The University of Chicago


NOTES
1 The comments attributed to black format radio were heard while listening to The Tom
Joyner Morning Show, WVON, Chicago, 28 February-3 March 2000.

2 House Subcommittee on Census and Population, Problem of Undercount in the 1990


Census: Hearing before the Subcommittee on Census and Population, 100th Congr., 1st sess.,
14 July 1987, p. 2.

3 US Census Monitoring Board, "Census 2000: A National Process Requires a Local


Focus," Report to Congress of the US Census Monitoring Board, Congressional Members,
106th Congr., 1st sess., 1 February 1999, p. 9.

4 Joe Torres, "Census Looks at Sampling vs. Head Count," Hispanic Magazine, 11.3
(March 1998), 12-14.

5 See note 1.

6 I am working here with the concept of "descriptive representation," as defined by


Hannah Pitkin in The Concept of Representation (Berkeley, 1967), pp. 60-91, and as applied
by Adolph Reed, Jr. to the "regime of race relations management" in the 1970s. See "The
Jug and Its Contents," in Stirrings in the Jug: Black Politics in the Post-Segregation Era

(Minneapolis, 1999), p. 4.
7 Rogers M. Smith, Civic Ideals: Conflicting Visions of Citizenship in U.S. History (New Haven,

1997), p. 8.
8 Among these attempts one can number Martha C. Nussbaum's argument in Poetic
Justice: The Literary Imagination and Public Life (Boston, 1995). In insisting on the

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

726 NEW LITERARY HISTORY


importance of novels to our political life, Nussbaum points out that novels demand "the
ability to imagine what it is like to live the life of another person who might, given changes

in circumstance, be oneself or one's loved ones" (p. 5).


9 David Theo Goldberg, Racial Subjects: Writing on Race in America (New York, 1997), pp.
52, 53; hereafter cited in text as AS.

10 Census 2000. 23 February 2000. <http://www.census.gov/prod/www/abs/decennial

.html>

11 Stephen A. Holmes, "New Policy on Census Says Those Listed as White and Minority
Will Be Counted as Minority," New York Times, 11 March 2000, final national ed., A7.
12 Stephen A. Holmes, "The Politics of Race and the Census," New York Times, 19 March
1998, final national ed., Week in Review, 3.

13 Samuel Langhorne Clemens, Puddnhead Wilson and Those Extraordinary Twins, ed.
Sidney E. Berger (New York, 1980), pp. 8-9.
14 Charles W. Mills, The Racial Contract (Ithaca, N.Y., 1997), p. 11.
15 Stephan Thernstrom and Abigail Thernstrom, America in Black and White: One Nation,
Indivisible (New York, 1997), p. 543; hereafter cited in text.
16 Ralph Ellison, "The World and the Jug (Part II)," in The Collected Essays of Ralph Ellison,
ed. John F. Callahan (New York, 1995), p. 185; individual essays will be identified in notes
and then cited in text as CE.

17 Jerry Gafio Watts, Heroism and the Black Intellectual: Ralph Ellison, Politics, and Afro
American Intellectual Life (Chapel Hill, 1994), p. 78; hereafter cited in text.
18 Ralph Ellison, "Twentieth-Century Fiction and the Mask of Humanity," in Collected

Essays, p. 95.
19 See also Ralph Ellison, "A Ver)' Stern Discipline," in Collected Essays, pp. 748-49.

20 Kenneth W. Warren, "Ralph Ellison and the Reconfiguration of African American


Studies," REAL: Yearbook of Research in English and American Literature, Vol. II, ed. Winfried

Fluck (Tubingen, 1995), p. 154.


21 Ralph Ellison, "Change the Joke and Slip the Yoke," in Collected Essays, p. 108.
22 Ralph Ellison, "The Myth of the Flawed W^hite Southerner," in Collected Essays, p. 554.
23 David Kamp, "The Color of Truth," Vanity Fair, 456 (August 1998), 127.
24 Kevin Sack, "Leaning on the Empathetic, Clinton Talks of Forgiving," New York Times,
29 August 1998, final national ed., A10.

25 Michael Winerip, "An American Place: Two Years Later; Bellwether's Rank and File
Strongly Support Clinton," New York Times, 30 September 1998, final national ed., Al;
hereafter cited in text.
26 Kevin Sack, "Blacks Stand By a President Who 'Has Been There for Us,'" New York
Times, 18 September 1998, final national ed., A10; hereafter cited in text.
27 Toni Morrison, "Talk of the Town," New Yorker, 5 October 1998, p. 32.
28 Bebe Moore Campbell, Brothers and Sisters (New York, 1994), p. 14.
29 Ralph Ellison, Juneteenth: A Novel, ed. John F. Callahan (New York, 1999), p. 280;
hereafter cited in text.
30 Philip A. Klinkner, "Bill Clinton and the New Liberalism," Without Justice for All: The
New Liberalism and Our Retreat from Racial Equality, ed. Adolph Reed, Jr. (New York, 1999),

pp. 12, 13.

31 See Klinkner, "Bill Clinton and the New Liberalism," p. 16.


32 Klinkner, too, suggests a causal link between Clinton's racial politics and his various
troubles. The illegal fund raising and the heightened political salience of "personal
responsibility," both of which gave Republicans ammunition for their attack, were caused
by Clinton's embrace of the New Liberalism.
33 Chicago v Morales, 177 IL 2d 440, 687 N.E. 2d 53 (1999). Affirmed. Thomas dissenting.
34 Anna Julia Cooper, A Voice from the South (New York, 1988), p. 36.

This content downloaded from 165.230.224.210 on Mon, 05 Dec 2016 20:43:29 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like