You are on page 1of 11

MURRAY SMITH

Film Art, Argument, and Ambiguity

The proposal that the medium of film, or indi- same territory. Indeed, Mulhall has gestured in
vidual films, might not only be the subject of just this direction in stating that he has a sense
philosophical study, but the vehicle of philoso- that theres some kind of open border between
phical activity, has recently come to the fore in, philosophy and literature.3
for example, several essays by Tom Wartenberg, But Mulhalls thesis in On Film is bolder
and in Stephen Mulhalls On Film.1 Mapping than this implies in two respects. First, if we are
out his position in the opening pages of that to take Mulhalls statement from the opening of
book, Mulhall writes: On Film at face value, it is not enough to say
that some filmmaking and philosophy inhabit
I do not look to these films [the Alien quartet] as the same territory, as one might imply in sug-
handy or popular illustrations of views and argu- gesting that a film has a philosophical theme or
ments properly developed by philosophers; I see tone. Rather, Mulhall wants to argue that films
them rather as themselves reflecting on and evaluat- can inhabit the territory of human self-reflection
ing such views and arguments, as thinking seriously in the same way as philosophythat films can
and systematically about them in just the ways that be philosophy in action. And what is that
philosophers do. Such films are not philosophys raw way or mode that a film, as much as a phi-
material, nor a source for its ornamentation; they are losophical text, can embody, on Mulhalls
philosophical exercises, philosophy in actionfilm account? This is the question that will pre-
as philosophizing.2 occupy me in this essay.
Second, it is important to note the type of
Mulhall is concerned here to stress the serious- film that Mulhall puts at the center of his dis-
ness with which he makes the claim that films cussion: the Hollywood narrative film, com-
can be philosophical. I take it to be relatively plete with all the usual trappingsstars,
uncontentious that, in some broad sense, a film spectacle, and, above all, stories. Mulhall is thus
can be philosophical. This is hardly surprising if not pursuing two other salient possibilities
we regard both film (as an art form) and philo- within the film as philosophy debate: the idea
sophy as extensions of the human capacity for that certain films might embody moral philoso-
self-consciousness, that is, of our capacity for phy in the way that Martha Nussbaum and
reflection on ourselves. Seen in this light, phi- others have argued that certain novels do (such
losophy arises from something about us that is, as, perhaps, Mike Leighs Vera Drake (2004));
if not exactly everyday, then is certainly cen- or the idea that there might be a film of ideas
tral to ourselves. If this is true, then philosophy genre, cousin to the novel of ideas, which
is not something merely abstract, a rarefied and explicitly strives for philosophical value (for
exotic practice set over against the meat and example, Chris Markers Sans soleil (1983)).
potatoes of life itself, but just a part of life itself. Mulhall takes on the most challenging possibi-
If we accept this view of the philosophical lity of all in proposing that some big-budget,
enterprise, then there is nothing controversial in popular entertainment filmsmoviesphilo-
the claim that philosophy and the arts in gen- sophize in just the same way as a traditional
eral, including film and literature, inhabit the philosophical text.
34 Thinking Through Cinema: Film as Philosophy

There are broadly two ways in which film- phers (in just the ways that philosophers do).
making can be aligned with philosophy in its It is hard to avoid the conclusion that Mulhall
more traditional formscall them the reductive believes that films, when acting as vehicles of
and the expansive strategies. The reductive philosophy, embody arguments (albeit, presu-
strategy involves showing how all the various mably, of an implicit and informal nature) in
things we might think a film to be doing (for support of theses (views).
example, engaging us through storytelling) can Is this a reasonable construal, given that
be shown to coalesce around a specific, narrow Mulhall speaks only of films thinking seriously
conception of philosophical activity. To be and systematically? Surely, it might be said,
really persuasive, this strategy needs to there are ways of thinking seriously and system-
reduce the key activities of a film to the philo- atically other than in the form of argument. Be
sophical without creating the sense that those that as it may, Mulhall himself brings the con-
activities are thereby travestied or mistakenly cept of argument into the equation by writing
described and, ideally, by showing that those of the arguments of philosophers and by then
activities are best illuminated by casting them in insisting on an identity between the activity of
terms of philosophical activity. The expansive some films and the activity of philosophers as
strategy takes the opposite tack. Rather than traditionally conceived. It is also notable that
showing how a films design might fit some Julian Baggini, in a sympathetic review of
very specific criteria of membership in the cate- Mulhalls book, strives to characterize philosophy
gory work of philosophy, the expansive stra- without recourse to the concept of argument,
tegy begins with a looser, more inclusive but finds the term irresistible (referring to it sev-
conception of philosophy. This creates a eral times in his attempts to capture the sense in
philosophical context in which many activities which we are to understand a narrative film as a
that, on the face of it, do not look very phil- potential form of philosophy).5
osophicallike filmmakingturn out to be The trouble isa narrative is not, literally
philosophical, or at least to have important phil- speaking, an argument.6 Of course, the idea that
osophical dimensions. One particular tactic a narrative might imply an argument, or in some
sometimes employed as a part of the expansive other way act to realize an argument, is an
strategy is to break down the work of philoso- ancient idea. It is implicit in the assumption that
phy into various constituents so that we see both certain narratives carry messages, morals,
the breadth and variety of activities that doing or lessons, in the sense that these morals
philosophy might entail, as well as seeing how are like the conclusion of an argument. Some
film might perform some of these activities very critics and theorists have spelled out this intui-
effectively some of the time.4 tion more explicitly: Andr Bazin, for example,
For the most part, Mulhall employs the wrote that the thesis implied by Ladri di bici-
expansive strategy; that is the import of his clette [Bicycle Thieves] (Vittorio de Sica, 1948)
open border metaphor. Traffic between the is wondrously and outrageously simple: in the
domain of real philosophy and any adjacent world where this workman lives, the poor must
realm of self-reflective activity does in fact steal from each other in order to survive. But
exist and should be embraced, so Mulhall this thesis is never stated as such, it is just that
implies. But the metaphor cuts both waysnote events are so linked together that they have the
that Mulhall does not claim that there is no bor- appearance of a formal truth while retaining an
der, and so maintains the idea that there is anecdotal quality.7 What distinguishes Mulhall
something distinctive about philosophy that is the strength of the claim he wishes to make
marks it off from other forms or products of with respect to the potential argumentative
self-reflection. And when it comes to character- force of narrative form. But the precise
izing philosophy in action, Mulhalls strategy relationship between narrative and argument
looks more reductive than expansive. In the remains impressionistic and undertheorized.
quotation with which I began, Mulhall states What is needed is an analysis of how a narrative
that films are capable of thinking seriously and can deliver the basic constituents of argument
systematically, and are able to reflect on and premises, a pattern of inference, and a
evaluate the views and arguments of philoso- conclusion.8
Smith Film Art, Argument, and Ambiguity 35

I. FICTION AS THOUGHT EXPERIMENT including fiction films, comic books, popular


and literary novels, and short storiesare,
If the analogy between narrative and argument relatively speaking, immensely detailed and
appears to be too strained or too vague, the elaborate.12 This difference raises the suspicion
expansive strategy opens up the possibility of that the thought experiment serves different
identifying alternative links between philoso- purposes in philosophy and artistic storytelling,
phy and narrative filmmaking. For example, in respectively. Just what is all that detail doing
an essay concerned with the extent to which and there?!
the ways in which fictional narratives can be Carrolls identification of the thought experi-
vehicles of knowledge, Nol Carroll argues that ment as something straddling the domains of
such narratives very often function as either philosophy and narrative art, then, allows us to
counterexamples to some philosophical argu- ask whether the role of the thought experiment
ment, or as thought experiments conveying a in each domain is the same. At this juncture, an
philosophical thesis or implication.9 A thought example will help us. In an essay on the nature
experiment, in the words of Tom Wartenberg, of personal identity and the role of the body in
asks a reader to consider a certain possibility relation to it, Bernard Williams concocts the
that she might not have considered before, a following thought experiment (with a nod to a
possibility that is often at odds with her estab- similar thought experiment proposed by Locke).
lished patterns of belief and action. Once this
possibility is entertained as a real possibility, Suppose a magician is hired to perform the old trick
then the reader is confronted with the question of making the emperor and the peasant become each
of what justifies her customary belief rather other. He gets the emperor and the peasant in one
than the possibility put forward in the thought room, with the emperor on his throne and the peasant
experiment. The thought experiment is, in in the corner, and then casts the spell. What will
Wartenbergs resonant phrase, a device for count as success? The requirement is presumably
challenging the tenacity of the habitual.10 that the emperors body, with the peasants personal-
Carroll goes on to note that since philosophy ity, should be on the throne, and the peasants body
has freely conjured up fictional counterexam- with the emperors personality in the corner. What
ples and thought experiments throughout its his- does this mean? In particular, what has happened to
toryRen Descartess evil demon, Hilary the voices? The voice ought to count as a bodily
Putnams brain in a vat, Robert Nozicks function; yet how would the peasants gruff blasphe-
experience machine, and so onit cannot with- mies be uttered in the emperors cultivated tones, or
out contradiction deny that fictional narratives the emperors witticisms in the peasants growl? A
may deliver knowledge: in the great and ongo- similar point holds for the [facial] features.13
ing quarrel between philosophy and poetry,
philosophy cannot win without undermining Williams is concerned here to take one view of
itself.11 Or, to put it in terms closer to Mulhalls, personal identity, in which the body plays no
philosophy cannot deny that fictional narratives essential role in the individuation of persons,
may be vehicles of philosophical insight, or and confront this view with an imagined sce-
philosophy in action. Putting Carrolls narioa thought experimentthat reveals, or
point in Mulhalls terms, however, involves at least suggests, deep flaws in that conception
closing a gapbetween knowledge in general of personal identity. Williams only needs to
and philosophical knowledge more speci- elaborate and extend the basic premise of the
ficallythat may turn out to be problematic. thought experiment over a few sentences in
But to tackle this question now would be to order to reveal the conceptual confusion on
jump the gun; we need to approach it more which (he argues) the dualistic conception of
circumspectly. personal identityof the self as a disembodied
One might go a step further than Carroll and soulrests. The thought experiment here plays
think of fictions in general just as thought a variety of roles, including a rhetorical role
experiments. But if we do so, we will realize by shifting mode briefly from more abstract
that unlike the fictions posed as thought argumentation, Williams engages the readers
experiments by philosophers, artistic fictions attention through variety and through the gently
36 Thinking Through Cinema: Film as Philosophy

absurd humor of the scene he asks us to imag-


ine. But the primary role of the thought experi-
ment is epistemic: Williams wants us to think
clearly and precisely about the nature of per-
sonal identity and the role of the body, and he
uses the story of the emperor and the peasant as
a way of exposing a confusion that needs to be
addressed if we are to arrive at a clear, if com-
plex, account of personal identity.
All of Me (1984), a romantic comedy directed
by Carl Reiner and starring Steve Martin, is
based on the same premise as Williamss
thought experiment. Martin plays a lawyer,
Roger Cobb, who is instructed by his boss to
deal with the legal affairs of a rich client, FIGURE 1. Bodily cohabitation.
Edwina Cutwater (played by Lili Tomlin).
Cutwater is dying and has engaged a guru to caricatured gesture. In other words, if we look
transport her mind into the body of a willing to the film for an implied answer to Williamss
transplantee, Terry Hoskins (Victoria Ten- question, concerning the prospects of a dis-
nant)whose own mind will in turn transmi- placed mind expressing itself in an alien body,
grate into the universe as a whole. Cobbs that answer is: crudely, and with difficulty.
main legal task is to revise Cutwaters will so The comedy of the scene is thus intimately
that Terry Hoskins becomes her sole inheritor related to the incongruity of Cutwaters mind in
the logic being that, once the mind switch has Cobbs body (indeed, there is even an echo of
occurred, Cutwater simply repossesses her own Williamss emperor/peasant contrastCutwater
estate, now housed in a new and healthy is an aristocrat, Cobb the son of a barber, and an
body. However, at the moment of mental trans- unaccomplished lawyer). This is compounded
plantation, a mishap results in Cutwaters mind by the situation into which Cobb-Cutwater is
entering Cobbs body, which is then cohab- thrustno sooner has this new entity mastered
ited by Cobb and CutwaterCobb retaining the art of walking than s/he has to negotiate a
control of the left side of his body, Cutwater visit to the mens room. In passing, we should
taking control of the right side of her body also note that this scene establishes a convention
(for the most part). whereby whenever Cobb looks in a mirror, he
Immediately following the transplantation, sees not his own body, but Cutwaters (that is,
Cobb struggles to comprehend what has hap- we see Lily Tomlin, playing Cutwater, in mirror
pened to him, while Cutwater stretches her new reflections of Cobb). This occurs first when
limbs. This is the scene in which the physical Cobb catches sight of Cutwater as he looks into
comedy implicit in the thought experiment the wing mirror of a car, and is then confirmed
takes hold. Cobbs body flails around as both in an extended exchange in the restroom between
Cobb and Cutwater attempt to assert control Cobb standing before a urinal and Cutwater
over it. Martin performs the idea of Cutwaters reflected in the mirror above it (Figure 2).
presence in Cobbs body through a parody of The film also develops a subplot concerning
prissy femininityfalsetto voice, swinging hips, Cobbs philandering boss, Burton Schuyler
angled hand on hip, and so forth (Figure 1). The (Dana Elgar), who is being sued for divorce.
humor here undoubtedly connects with the Under pressure within Schuylers practice and
philosophical issue raised by Williams, espe- seeking to become a partner, Cobb is compelled
cially when he asks: [H]ow would the peas- to take on the role of defense attorney represent-
ants gruff blasphemies be uttered in the ing Schuyler. In one scene, we see Cobb in
emperors cultivated tones, or the emperors court during proceedings. But there is a prob-
witticisms in the peasants growl? For the only lem. Distracted by the presence of an additional
way Cobbs body can give expression to mind within his body, Cobb has been up most
Cutwaters mind and character is through of the night preparing legal arguments. Now
Smith Film Art, Argument, and Ambiguity 37

languagenot least because, Cobb jests, Wattell


is white. We can see that Wattell is in fact
black, and the whole exchange is a playful one.
But it exposes a curious aspect of Wattells
experiencealthough he is black, he himself
has no access to, nor evidence of, that part of his
physical being from which the social notion of
blackness builds. It might as well be a fiction
as far as he is concerned. So here we see a kind
of disconnection between bodily identity and
interior identity.
Cutwater also speaks of a disjunction
between her inner self and her bodily identity.
In explaining the motivation behind the trans-
FIGURE 2. Body and soul. plantation scheme, she describes a childhood
and a lifetime of physical infirmity, and thus an
exhausted, he has fallen asleep. Or rather, inability to give expression to (what she feels to
Cobbs mind has fallen asleep, but Cutwaters be) her vivacious and life-affirming character.
mind is still awakein other words, Cobbs Her body simply will not live up to the desires
body is awake but is animated at this point only and values that, on her account at least, consti-
by Cutwaters mind. Called into the proceed- tute the core of her personality. So if, in the case
ings by the judge, Cutwater is compelled to per- of Wattell, the visible aspect of bodily identity
form Cobbs masculine gestures, using Cobbs is only experienced in a remote and abstract
body. Once again, this proceeds through carica- way, here the body is represented as an impedi-
ture. Where in the earlier scene Martin effected ment to the realization of the self, rather than
a parodic rendering of femininity in order to simply as a constitutive part of it. In both cases,
give expression to Cutwater, here he executes a there is discord, rather than integration, between
burlesque of masculinity in order to represent the inner self and the bodily self. Thus, different
Cutwaters imitation of Cobba performance facets of All of Me have contrasting implica-
incorporating a broad swaggering gait, tobacco tions with respect to the role of the body in per-
spitting, crotch scratching, and a boot stuck on sonal identity. While the central line of action
the prosecuting attorneys desk. Comic capital concerning mental relocation underlines the
is again extracted from the awkward fit of a positive significance of the body to personal
mind in an alien body. Across the two scenes, identitythe body as expressive vehicle of
then, we have considerable elaboration of the identityother strands of the plot play up the
basic thought experiment: instead of a simple way in which the body may block the expres-
switch of minds, we have two minds in one sion of or otherwise problematize certain
body; and in the courtroom scene, we see the aspects of identity.
displaced mind (Cutwaters) mimicking the After various twists and turns, including the
home mind while the latter is unconscious. accidental transplantation of Cutwaters mind
These are the scenes in which the parallel from Cobbs body into a bucket of stable water,
with Williamss thought experiment is most Cutwaters mind is eventually successfully relo-
salient. But other aspects of the film resonate cated in Terry Hoskinss body. This sets up a
with the problem of the bodily dimension of fitting conclusion for a romantic comedy. Cobb
personal identity, drawing out the social impli- has lusted after Hoskinss body throughout,
cations of that dimension of identity. Cobbs while growing unexpectedly fond of Cutwater
closest friend in the film is a blind, black sax during her stay in his body. The transplant-
player, Tyrone Wattell (Jason Bernard) (Cobb ation of Cutwaters mind into Tennants body
moonlights as a jazz guitarist, playing alongside thus apparently grants Cobb his ideal synthesis.
Wattell). In the course of some comic repartee, In the final scene, Cobb and Cutwater (now
Wattell calls Cobb a honky mook. Cobb embodied by Tennant) dance. But there is one
retorts that Wattell really should not use such more twist. With its final gesture, the film
38 Thinking Through Cinema: Film as Philosophy

reverts to the convention whereby Cutwaters its original form even as it inhabits another
mind becomes manifest through her original body, the original mind being manifest in the
body whenever the new host is seen in a mirror. mirror views. The paradox thus resides in the
Following Cobb and Cutwater/Tennant onto the fact that Cutwaters persisting soul can only be
dance floor, the camera pans away from them represented by her body! The film seems
after a few seconds in order to pick up their committed, then, to both dualism and monistic
reflections in a mirror. As the film ends, then, physicalism. You might even say that it rests on
instead of seeing Cobb dance with Cutwater/ the paradox of personal identity: personal iden-
Tennant, we see him dance with Cutwater/ tity both requires, and yet is independent of, the
Tomlin (Figure 3). body. Or at least, All of Me gives expression to
This is a paradoxical conclusion. On the one inconsistencies in our assumptions about per-
hand, the film seems to insist on the centrality sonal identity that this paradox, as I have stated
of a particular body (Tomlins) to Cutwaters it, summarizes and condenses.14
mind (it is hard to imagine Tennant dancing
with just the kind of free-form playfulness that
characterizes Tomlins movements). On the II. DRAMATIC IMAGINING, DRAMATIC PARADOX,
other hand, the film has established, via the AND AMBIGUITY
mirror convention, that Cutwaters mind (or
soul, we might very well say here) persists in It might seem that in discovering this paradox in
All of Me that I have acceded to the very conten-
tionthat mainstream films can philosophize
that I have been questioning. But this would be
to mistake what, precisely, is at stake in the
debate and in the account of All of Me that I have
advanced. What is at stake here is not whether
the film has a philosophical theme, or philosoph-
ical implications, or that the film can be used to
introduce just the kind of philosophical conun-
drums regarding personal identity that Williams
analyzes. I am not seeking to deny any of these
possibilities. Rather, the question I am asking
is: What is the film doing with the scenario
that it shares with the thought experiment in
Williamss essay? Is the films project in some
important sense a philosophical one?
Let me answer this question by comparing
my account of the film with both the commen-
tary on the film provided by Christopher Falzon
and with the sort of stance that we can imagine
Mulhall taking toward it. Falzons goal is to
introduce various philosophical concepts and
arguments via films. All of Me is one of the
films he draws on to introduce dualism; Falzon
interprets the film as straightforwardly assum-
ing a dualistic worldview.15 One can see why he
might think this, given the fact that it is fictional
in the film that minds can move from body to
body (via metal bowls and buckets of water, no
less). But the burden of my analysis of the film
has been to show that it is not straightforwardly
dualistic.16 The awkwardness of fit between a
FIGURE 3. The soul as body. mind and an alien body resonates with
Smith Film Art, Argument, and Ambiguity 39

Williamss thought experiment, designed to part of the artistic value of many genres; in
expose the problems with dualism, as does the some cases, like that of documentary film-
fact that Cutwaters continuous-but-displaced making, the epistemic value of a film may be
inner self is represented by her bodily being absolutely central to the artistic value of the
(her body, face, and voice). Making the film the film. There is more to be said on the way in
primary object of analysis, and capturing such which the epistemic dimension of a work of
nuances in the thinking of the film, aligns my narrative film art relates to its aesthetic dimen-
interpretation of All of Me more closely with sions: the way that it subsists as part of the over-
Mulhalls approach, as Mulhall is eager to go all fabric of the work. The preliminary point
beyond the use of films as handy illustrations here, however, is to highlight the relative
of philosophical concepts. But this returns us to importance of the epistemic and the artistic (the
the following question: Is the complexity of comic, in this case) in works of different sorts.
narrative filmmaking manifest in a film like All Thus a work of philosophy and a work of art
of Me best described and analyzed in terms of will, typically, rank these priorities differently;
philosophizing, or are there other more apt philosophical insight and the creation of com-
ways of capturing such complexity? edy are both facets of both Williams's essay and
Unlike Williamss essay, the film uses the All of Me, but they are weighted quite differ-
thought experiment primarily as a vehicle of ently, and thus function differently, in the two
comedy. The primary goal of the film is to elab- cases. But it is also true, as I have just sug-
orate the comic ramifications of its philosoph- gested, that the relative significance of the epis-
ical premise. If we were to judge the artistic temic and various artistic values will vary
value of the film, the most apt criteria would be among different kinds of artworks.
comic complexity and ingenuity. Put schemat- We can deepen our understanding of the dif-
ically, the priority of the epistemic and the artis- ferent role played by the thought experiment in
tic (in this case, comic complexity) are flipped, philosophical argument, and artistic narrative,
relative to their roles in Williamss essay. So respectively, through the contrast proposed
the film has an epistemic dimensionwe might by Richard Moran between hypothetical and
well be brought to reflect on personal identity dramatic imagining. To imagine something
by the film and learn something from itbut it hypothetically is to pose the possibility of some
is subsidiary to its comic imperative. This sub- counterfactual in a spare and abstract way.
ordination of the epistemic to the artistic is Dramatic imagining involves elaborating and
surely the main reason why narrative films ramifying the bare counterfactual in one or
based on philosophical themes, like All of Me, more ways. We might imagine experiencing the
will often compromise the logic of the philo- events from the inside, that is, as a witness or
sophical problem that they dramatize. A film- as a participant, rather than merely imagining
maker working with a comic priority will that the events occur; Moran writes that dra-
normally opt for those features (of plot and sty- matic imagining involves something like
listic design) that maximize the comic rather genuine rehearsal, trying on [a] point of view,
than the epistemic value of the film. Thus, All of trying to determine what it is like to inhabit
Me may not be conceptually watertight, but it is it.18 Or we might imagine the ever-widening
very funny. As that sage of Hollywood, Sam circle of possible consequences that follow
Goldwyn, might have put it: Pictures are for from the basic thought experiment, that is, the
entertainmentif I wanted to make a philo- initial set of explicitly stated counterfactuals. As
sophical point, Id publish an essay in Proceed- I have already implied, this second form of
ings of the Aristotelian Society.17 dramatic imagining is evidently important for a
In saying this, however, I do not want to be film like All of Me, but the first form may be
understood as suggesting that the relationship significant too, insofar as some of the comedy
between artistic value (and its various instantia- depends on, or will be most fully appreciated
tions in comedy, tragedy, horror, and so forth) through, our ability to imagine what it feels like
and epistemic value is a mutually exclusive one. to be in a certain sort of absurd or humiliating
The conveying of knowledge or prompting of situation. One consequence of such dramatic
conceptual thinking is certainly an important imagining is that we are much more likely to be
40 Thinking Through Cinema: Film as Philosophy

engaged emotionally than we would be if the but elusive contrast between philosophy and art.
same scenario were imagined in hypothetical In part, this arises from the concreteness and
fashion. particularity of art, as distinct from the abstract,
The nature and relevance of this contrast conceptual character of philosophy.22 The epi-
could easily be misunderstood. The point is not stemic content of a work of art does not enter
that philosophical thought experiments require into it, and is not conveyed to us, in such a phi-
no elaboration; rather, philosophical thought losophical manner. The meaning and experience
experiments seem to require relatively little that works of art typically create is one charac-
elaboration.19 This quantitative difference terized by sufficient complexity and indirection
points us toward a different kind of imagining at that it resists restatementor paraphrasein
stake in the two practices, and supports the clear and unequivocal terms. In other words, no
argument advanced here that the philosophical matter how philosophical the theme of a
thought experiment, on the one hand, and the narrative, to the extent that it is designed as an
artistic thought experiment, on the other, are artwork it is apt to put a spanner in the philo-
geared toward different tasks. Mulhalls rejoin- sophical works. As Cleanth Brooks, one of the
der might be that there is no reason why a film- architects of the New Criticism, put it: When
maker might not be both a comic and a we consider the statement immersed in the
philosopher, just as Einstein might be regarded poem, it presents itself to us, like the stick
as both a physicist and a philosopher.20 Some immersed in the pool of water, warped and bent.
philosophers are, after all, pretty funny, and All Indeed, whatever the statement, it will always
of Me is not unique in deriving comedy from show itself as deflected away from a positive,
philosophical ideas. Once again, though, the straightforward formulation.23 Few criticisms are
point is not to deny the evident possibility of more apt to strike terror into the heart of the philos-
overlap between a philosophical and an artistic opher than the assertion that such-and-such a prop-
(here, comic) project, but to ask whether there is osition is ambiguous, while in the world of art,
not some tension between the goals of philoso- that term is more apt to be used as a term of praise.
phy and the goals of art, and that for this reason Brooks often used the idea of paradox
we find that, typically, a film or a text will (along with ambiguity and irony) in order to
organize these goals hierarchically. Most works describe the form of poetry, and to distinguish
will manifest in their design an overriding, such form from rational statement.24 Paradox,
dominant goal even as they may instantiate sec- in this sense, comes to mean the unification or
ondary goals, or enlist the techniques and forms holding-in-balance, within the form of an art-
we associate with these secondary goals as work, of contrasting attitudes or meanings. The
means to securing the primary goal, as we have paradoxicality of All of Me, then, might be
seen in the case of Williamss use of humor as a seen in these terms, as a dramatic rather than
means of exposing the incoherence of dualism.21 strictly philosophical, conceptual phenomenon.
The particular artistic properties that charac- Instead of interpreting the films treatment of
terize All of Me will not, of course, be found in the bodily dimension of identity as a symptom
every work of art. We would not expect or want of its philosophical inconsistency, that paradox-
to find comedy in a tragedy or a horror fiction ical treatment might be seen (and valued) as a
(not, at least, as the defining emotion of such compact dramatization of our conflicting intui-
works). But if we move up one level of abstrac- tions about the place of the body in personal
tion, we begin to find properties with greater identity. The film provides us with a comic-
reach across the arts and across particular works dramatic image of our understanding of person-
of artproperties like complexity, ingenuity, hood and the body. That is something we are
inventiveness, density, ambiguity, and profund- likely to value in a work of art, but not value in
ity. And while we can imagine finding these a work of philosophy (or, at least, not in the
same properties in works of philosophy, it is not same way or to the same degree). To recall a
clear that we would value them in just the same criterion I proposed earlier, we might ask our-
way in a work of philosophy as in a work of art. selves whether a narrative film like All of Me is
Something like ambiguity, in the New Critical best illuminated on the basis of this artistic
sense of the term, lies at the heart of this vital conception of paradoxicality or on the basis
Smith Film Art, Argument, and Ambiguity 41

of more strictly philosophical models of argu- 6. See Jerry Fodor: The Ring isnt an enthymeme, a
ment, thought experiment and paradox? paradox or a dilemma. It isnt any kind of argument at all, in
What Wotan Wants, review of Finding an Ending, by Kitcher
In The Heresy of Paraphrase, Brooks and Schacht, London Review of Books, August 5, 2004, p. 8.
argued that the danger posed by the heresy is 7. Andr Bazin, What is Cinema? vol. II (University of
that we bring the statement [of a poem] into an California Press, 1971), p. 51.
unreal competition with science or philosophy 8. Nol Carroll offers an analysis of narrative in terms
of what he terms the narrative enthymeme, where the
or theology.25 This is precisely the danger of intelligibility of a narrative depends on an often implicit
Mulhalls argument. Mulhall is motivated to presupposition or premise that the narrative goes on to bear
defend popular film from the familiar charge out. However, the generalizations embodied in these pre-
that it necessarily lacks sophistication, and suppositions are commonplace, often serving ideological
especially conceptual sophistication, and so ends, and insofar as they are ideological, they will be
(among other things) epistemically defective. The model
Mulhall is driven to argue that at least some thus offers little direct assistance to those who hold that
popular films can be assimilated wholesale to popular narratives can forge philosophically groundbreaking
philosophy. But is not Mulhalls position thinking. See Carroll, Film, Rhetoric, and Ideology, in
colored by the ancient view that the worth of art Explanation and Value in the Arts, ed. Salim Kemal and
Ivan Gaskell (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
will always pale in comparison with the worth 1993), pp. 215237.
of philosophy? A different path is open to us if 9. Nol Carroll, The Wheel of Virtue: Art, Literature,
we recognize and challenge this assumption. and Moral Knowledge, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art
We can, and should, take popular films seri- Criticism 60 (2002): 326.
ouslybut as works of art, rather than as works 10. Wartenberg, Experiencing The Matrix, p. 145.
11. Carroll, The Wheel of Virtue, p. 19.
of philosophy. After all, in the larger scheme of 12. David Gooding describes thought experiments as
things, comic artistry is probably as important sparse, carefully-crafted narratives, likening them to
to human flourishing as philosophy. What it jokes, in Thought Experiments, in Routledge Encyclope-
means to take popular filmmaking as an art seri- dia of Philosophy, ed. E. Craig (London: Routledge, 1988).
Of course, the level of detail evident in an artistic fiction
ously, of course, is still another matter.26 will vary immensely according to genre and the style of par-
ticular authors. The fact of that variety, however, does not
MURRAY SMITH undermine the overarching contrast that I propose between
School of Drama, Film and Visual Arts the artistic fiction and the philosophical thought experiment.
University of Kent 13. Bernard Williams, Personal Identity and Individua-
tion, in Problems of the Self: Philosophical Papers
Canterbury 195672 (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1973),
Kent CT2 7NX pp. 1112. Lockes thought experiment concerned the trans-
UK fer of the soul of a prince into the body of a cobbler,
though Locke draws precisely the conclusion that Williams
disputes: that bodily identity is not a necessary condition of
INTERNET: mss@kent.ac.uk personal identity. Williamss thought experiment is thus a
counter-thought experiment. John Locke, An Essay Con-
cerning Human Understanding, ed. Peter H. Nidditch
1. Stephen Mulhall, On Film (London: Routledge, 2002); (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1975), II.xxvii.15.
Thomas E. Wartenberg, Experiencing The Matrix, Midwest 14. My interpretation here treats the conclusion of the
Studies in Philosophy 26 (2003): 139152. For a parallel narrative as a matter of the internal logic of the film,
treatment of opera as philosophy, see Philip Kitcher and whether conceived generically, thematically, or philosophi-
Richard Schacht, Finding an Ending: Reflections on Wag- cally. But it is likely that another, external factor was
ners Ring (New York: Oxford University Press, 2004). important in determining the form of the final scenestar
2. Mulhall, On Film, p. 2, emphasis added. power. Martin and Tomlin were undoubtedly the two major
3. Quoted by Julian Baggini, Alien Ways of Thinking: stars in the film, and so by convention the film needs to end
Mulhalls On Film, Film-Philosophy 7 (2003), available at with the depiction of their romantic union, rather than the
<http://www.film-philosophy.com/vol72003/n24baggini>. union of Martin and Tennant. (Or, more strictly, the film
Baggini quotes from Post-Analytic Philosophy: In Conver- needs to end with the romantic union of Cobb and Cutwater
sation with Stephen Mulhall, in New British Philosophy: represented by Martin and Tomlin rather than by Martin and
The Interviews, ed. Julian Baggini and Jeremy Stangroom Tennant.) I do not mean to suggest that such external con-
(London: Routledge, 2002), p. 241. siderations will necessarily undermine the artistic, including
4. See, for example, Thomas Wartenbergs treatment of epistemic and even philosophical, goals of Hollywood film-
illustration, in Beyond Mere Illustration: How Films Can makers. This ending has been prepared for by the mirror
Be Philosophy, The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criti- motif and, more broadly, by the very casting of Tomlin into
cism 64 (2006): 1932. the primary and authentic female romantic role in the film.
5. Baggini, Alien Ways of Thinking. Art and commerce need not be antithetical. But equally, it
42 Thinking Through Cinema: Film as Philosophy

will not do simply to ignore these external factors in the philosophizing that Mulhall has in mind, the film is a very
shaping of films. It is always a question as to how far the apt example. All of Me is precisely the sort of film that Mul-
filmmakers of a given film have managed to channel the hall focuses on: a studio picture designed within a clear
force of such external factors toward their own internal, generic framework (comedy in the case of All of Me, horror
artistic ends. in the case of the Alien films) that sustains its sophistication
15. Christopher Falzon, Philosophy Goes to the Movies: through the narrative values for which Hollywood is famed.
An Introduction to Philosophy (London: Routledge, 2002), And the film has a direct generic relationship with screwball
pp. 51, 6263. comedy, one of the favored genres of Mulhalls major influ-
16. Falzons commentary on the film Suture (David ence, Stanley Cavell.
Siegel, Scott McGehee, 1993) suggests that that film, 22. For a discussion of this contrast see the exchange
unusually and quite self-consciously, is premised on a between Ren Wellek, Literary Criticism and Philosophy,
more thorough-going dualism, as contrasted with the various, Scrutiny 5 (1937): 375383, and F. R. Leavis, Literary
complex, and sometimes conflicting intuitions that find Criticism and Philosophy: A Reply, Scrutiny 6 (1937): 59
expression in All of Me. Falzon, Philosophy Goes to the 70. Leavis argues staunchly for the importance of the con-
Movies, p. 64. creteness of artas exemplified by poetryand the signifi-
17. What Sam Goldwyn actually said was: Pictures are cance of its contrast with philosophy in this respect. Hegels
for entertainment, messages should be delivered by Western definition of art as the unveiling of truth in the form of
Union. Allegedly. sensuous artistic configuration, which he distinguishes
18. Richard Moran, The Expression of Feeling in Imag- from the purely conceptual form of truth as it is manifest
ination, The Philosophical Review 103 (1994): 105. See in philosophy, is a canonical example of the contrast.
also Tamar Szab Gendler, The Puzzle of Imaginative G. W. F. Hegel, Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art, Vol. 1
Resistance, Journal of Philosophy 97 (2000): 5581. (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1975), trans T. M. Knox, p. 55.
19. Immediately following the paragraph in which he 23. Cleanth Brooks, The Heresy of Paraphrase, in The
sets out the thought experiment concerning the emperor and Well Wrought Urn (London: Methuen, 1968), p. 172.
the peasant, Williams explicitly states: The point need not 24. Brooks, Heresy of Paraphrase, p. 172. Although
be elaborated... Williams, Personal Identity and Individ- Brooks was writing of poetry, his analysis freely draws
uation, p. 12 on analogies with the other arts, including painting,
20. Stephen Mulhall, Ways of Thinking: A Response to architecture, and drama; extending his analysis to narra-
Andersen and Baggini, Film-Philosophy 7 (2003), avail- tive filmmaking thus does not violate the spirit of the
able at <http://www.film-philosophy.com/vol7-2003/ argument.
n25mulhall>. 25. Brooks, Heresy of Paraphrase, p. 164.
21. Another objection might be that All of Me is not a 26. My thanks to audiences at the 2003 ASA confer-
good or fair example to test Mulhalls argument. Is a cute ence in San Francisco, and the Philosophy Work-in-
little Hollywood comedy really a robust enough example to Progress Seminar at the University of Kent, especially
raise questions about the philosophical potential of film- Tom Wartenberg, Alan Thomas, and Edward Harcourt,
making in general? In fact, in terms of the kind of filmic for comments on earlier versions of this essay.

You might also like