You are on page 1of 35

What Was Primitive Accumulation?

Reconstructing the Origin of a Critical Concept

It has been said that we are living in an era of primitive accumulation (Federici, 2012,

p. 138). Whether or not processes of primitive accumulation especially mark the present,

invocations of the term certainly do. When Taiaiake Alfred credits Glen Coulthard with having

rescued Karl Marx from his nineteenth-century hostage chamber (2014, p. xi), he has in mind

Coulthards mobilization and reconstruction of Marxs concept of primitive accumulation. When

David Harvey claims that the hallmark of [] the new imperialism of the twenty-first

century is accumulation by dispossession (2004, p. 64), he is rechristening and reformulating

Marxs notion. When James Tully is pressed to identify how he would address the legacies of

imperialism, he refers to the recent history of dispossession, primitive accumulation, centralised

state building, militarization, economic exploitation, and ecological destruction in order to

refuse any appeal to strong states or economic development, advocating instead a turn to

cooperative, community-based, ecological and non-violent traditions of self-reliance (2011, p.

154).

All of these users of Marxs concept,1 however, want to sever the notion of primitive

accumulation from connections and connotations that burden it in Marxs text. They agree that,

in order to be redeployed in the present, Marxs concept must be reformulated. And there is

widespread agreement about the changes that must be made. First, Marx mistakenly portrays

primitive accumulation as a bloody moment in the past, since replaced by the relatively bloodless

workings of the mature capitalist system. Second, as much as Marx condemns the violent

expropriation of the peasantry, he also justifies it as a necessary step on the way to the

communist future.

1
I would like to take issue with the current rehabilitation of primitive accumulation.

Rather than sever the concept from the context of its emergence, I propose to examine it in that

context. Doing so reveals the stakes of Marxs discussion: a proper disaggregation of the

agencies responsible for capitalism. In the first instance, Marx is concerned to specify the agency

of capital. Marx identifies primitive accumulation as the prehistory of capital (1976, pp. 875,

928), not in order to consign it to the past, but in order to underscore the distinction between

hording up wealth money, land, products, whatever and using it as capital. The violence of

primitive accumulation can amass the former, but cannot make the accumulated wealth function

as capital. This distinction and the consequent distinction between capital and capitalism is,

Marx thinks, essential for understanding how capitalism operates, and what makes it different

from other forms of society. Within capitalism, capital is the agent of accumulation by

exploitation, not the agent of primitive accumulation.

This brings us to the second issue, for Marx, that of revolutionary strategy. As most

commentators note, the state is the overwhelming agent of primitive accumulation. What goes

unnoted is why. According to Marx, the state pursues policies of primitive accumulation because

it has become dependent upon capital accumulation economic growth for its own existence

and functioning. Policies of primitive accumulation are attempts by the state to secure the

conditions of economic growth. This dependency of the state upon capital makes the state into an

enemy of all attempts to refuse, evade, or escape capitalism. All such attempts will, just to the

extent that they are or promise to be successful, encounter the armed agents of the state. This is

where the state fits into capitalism. This epochal change in the role of the state explains Marxs

insistence upon the historical inevitability of conquest and expropriation. He does not justify

primitive accumulation as a necessary step on the historical path to socialism. He argues, rather,

2
that existing forms of petty production, and the forms of social solidarity they foster, are too

vulnerable to the violent encroachments of capitals mighty servant, the state. Liberation requires

a strategy of conquering the conqueror and expropriating the expropriators.

Returning primitive accumulation to the context of its origination, therefore, actually

brings Marxs argument up to date. The recent reformulations of Marxs notion are provoked by

very real and ongoing processes of coercive and violent expropriation, the forceful separation of

people from independent access to the means of living. But these processes underscore both the

complementarity of state action and capitalist production and the irreducible difference between

them. The continuing salience of capitalist accumulation to state action, and vice versa, indicates

the contemporaneity of Marxs analysis, not its obsolescence. Only by clarifying what primitive

accumulation was in Marxs text can we determine what it is and will be in the present and

future.

1. The renovation of primitive accumulation

During the twentieth century, Marxist debate over primitive accumulation was defined by

the contest between those who thought of it as an event in the past, and those who conceived it as

a continuous and ongoing process. For those who took primitive accumulation to be

accumulation in an historical sense (Dobb, 1963, p. 178), the adjective primitive

correspond[ed] to a clear-cut temporal dimension (the past) (De Angelis, 1999, sec. 1).2 They

focused, therefore, on pinpointing the historical origin of capitalism in Western Europe, and

especially in Britain. Opposed to them were those who argued that the mechanisms of primitive

accumulation [] do not belong only to the prehistory of capitalism; they are contemporary as

3
well (Amin, 1974, p. 3).3 Those who forwarded this argument focused on the ongoing

relationship between a capitalist interior or core and a non-capitalist frontier or periphery.

Despite their opposition to one another on political and historiographic grounds, the

parties to these debates shared the presupposition that primitive accumulation marked the point

of contact between capitalism and the non-capitalist world. After all, there is no contradiction

between calling primitive accumulation the pre-history of capitalism and agreeing that it is

ongoing. Rosa Luxemburg, the acknowledged fount of the thesis of continuous primitive

accumulation, understood capitalism to be ever-expanding into non-capitalist zones. This is why

she thought primitive accumulation to be ongoing; it marks the process of capitalism ingesting

non-capitalism (2003, chap. 2632). The prehistory of capitalism is being continuously re-

enacted at the point of ingestion.

The new reading of primitive accumulation with which this essay is concerned departs in

a crucial way from this common presupposition of the older debates. Rather than allowing that

processes of primitive accumulation mark the frontiers temporal and/or spatial between

capitalism and non-capitalism, the new accounts claim to locate primitive accumulation within

capitalism itself. David Harveys formulation is representative:

Marxs general theory of capital accumulation is constructed under certain crucial initial

assumptions which broadly match those of classical political economy and which exclude

primitive accumulation processes. [] The disadvantage of these assumptions is that

they relegate accumulation based upon predation, fraud, and violence to an original

stage that is considered no longer relevant or, as with Luxemburg, as being somehow

outside of the capitalist system. (2004, pp. 734)

4
According to Harvey, however, accumulation based upon predation, fraud, and violence is

immanent in the operations of capitalism as such.

The same conclusion is reached by Silvia Federici. She claims that Marx was deeply

mistaken when he assumed that the violence that had presided over the earliest phases of

capitalist expansion would recede with the maturing of capitalist relations, when the exploitation

and disciplining of labor would be accomplished mostly through the workings of economic

laws (2004, p. 12). Glen Coulthard concurs. Seconding Kropotkins objection to Marxs

erroneous division between the primary accumulation of capital and its present-day formation

(1995, p. 221), Coulthard argues that, in order to be relevant, the notion of primitive

accumulation must be transformed so as to include the persistent role that unconcealed,

violent dispossession continues to play in the reproduction of colonial and capitalist social

relations (2014, p. 9).4 Eschewing the terminology of primitive accumulation altogether in

favor of his own coinage, war capitalism Sven Beckert likewise argues that historians and

theorists should emphasize that slavery, colonialism, and forced labor, among other forms of

violence, were not aberrations in the history of capitalism, but were at its very core (2015, p.

441).

All of these scholars agree, then, that Marx erred insofar as he conceived primitive

accumulation as a violent process that obliterates all non-capitalist social forms and institutes in

their place relations of wage labor characteristic of nineteenth-century British industrial

capitalism (Ince, 2013, p. 8). They all seek to reformulate the concept so as to name the

political violence operative in the capitalization of social reproduction (Ince, 2014, p. 106). As

Massimo De Angelis put it in his influential early articulation of the new position, the

continuous element of Marx's primitive accumulation could be identified in those social

5
processes or sets of strategies aimed at dismantling those institutions that protect society from the

market (1999, sec. 5.2). Since non-capitalist or non-market social relations are always

reconstituting themselves,5 primitive accumulation must be conceived as the ever-renewed work

of dismantling these non-capitalist relations.

This critical intervention dovetails with a second. Marxs conception of primitive

accumulation is supposed to have been integral to a normative developmentalism that casts the

violent expropriation of the peasantry and other practitioners of natural economy as a painful

but necessary stage through which humanity must pass on the way to socialism.6 Thus, while

Marx was acutely aware of the murderous character of capitalist development, Federici

declares that there can be no doubt that he viewed it as a necessary step in the process of human

liberation (2004, p. 12). Likewise, Jim Glassman claims that for Marx, primitive accumulation,

however loathsome in its violence and hypocrisy, is a necessary step in the direction of fuller

human development (2006, p. 611). Tully insists, as well, that Marxs specific explication of

primitive accumulation enshrines several processes as unjust yet necessary and universal

preconditions of the development of capitalism to communism, including the dispossession of

Indigenous peoples; the destruction of non-capitalist modes of production; the individuation and

commodification of human productive powers []; and the commodification of the earth

(2014, pp. 2389).

This criticism of Marx buttresses the first; both take him to task for the teleological

Eurocentrism built into his conception of primitive accumulation. If capitalism looks like the

Carolina slave plantation as much as the Manchester garment factory, then the sense that the

slave plantation gives way to the garment factory disappears. If proletarian power is to be found

in a Quiche indian village in the Guatemalan hills as much as in the strike organizations of

6
Londons East End, then Marxs righteous horror of petty producers is just a vestige of

providential historicism, impatient for the rest of the world to catch up to Europe (Midnight

Notes Collective, 1990, p. 6). The colonial frontier is internal to capitalisms most intimate

workings, and so cannot be set off against a more developed metropolitan core, the operations

of which foretell the future of the periphery. Any attempt to renovate Marxs concept, therefore,

must grapple with the historicist bias that Marxism shares with mainstream developmentalism

and globalization narratives, a bias that judges the extent of capitalist maturation by the degree

to which wage labor regulated by free markets becomes the predominant form of organizing

production (Ince, 2014, p. 116).

These are powerful criticisms. It is easy to appreciate why they have won the day. I will

argue, however, that they miss the point of Marxs argument in Part Eight of Capital. Marx can

and does affirm that processes of primitive accumulation are internal to capitalism. He insists

nonetheless that they constitute the prehistory of capital because, while plunder, fraud, and theft

can stock up wealth that can be used as capital, they cannot actually make that wealth function as

capital. Capital works as capital by other means. The new reading of primitive accumulation

obscures the necessity of this displacement of wealth into capital, and, with it, the distinction

between capital and capitalism. Capital requires primitive accumulation, but cannot accomplish

this accumulation for itself. It needs other agencies to act to its benefit. In this light, I argue, the

historical trajectory Marx sketches in Part Eight loses the aspect of universal history and reveals

itself to be, instead, an account of capitals capture of the state, which undertakes capitals dirty

work because it has become dependent upon capital accumulation for its own existence. This is a

strategic reality that Marx urges his contemporary anti-capitalists to confront, not a theoretical

construction of historical development he foists upon them.

7
2. The context of Marxs concept of primitive accumulation

Primitive accumulation is set off by Marx against the accumulation of capital, or

accumulation by exploitation. In order to understand his conception of the former, we have to

understand his conception of the latter. And in order to do this, we have to appreciate that Marx

was an outlier among nineteenth-century socialists.7 Most socialists echoed the theory of the

Saint-Simonians, according to which the accumulation of capital, and the attendant exploitation

of the workers, are the direct consequence of the conquest of the land and the extortion this

allowed the landed to exact from the poor producer. In the words of The Doctrine of Saint-

Simon, Physical force and the exploitation of man by man are two coexisting, corresponding

facts. The latter is the consequence of the former (Bazard et al., 1972, p. 63).

In England, this theory was promulgated by the influential Owenite, William Thompson,

who declared that the present system of commerce was an empire of force and fraud (1850, p.

255), and by the Chartist agitator Bronterre O-Brien, who claimed that profitmongers and

landlords exercised an unlimited and irresponsible power of murder and robbery over the mass

of mankind (1885, p. 142). In Germany, Karl Heinzen argued that the rule of force dominates

capitalistic property relations (Bessner and Stauch, 2010, p. 151). Later, Eugen Dhrings

thesis, that all economic relations are founded in the violent exclusion of some from the use of

natural resources, was the subject of three chapters of Engelss Anti-Dhring (Engels and Marx,

1987, chap. II.24). In France, the greatest proponent of this view, after the Saint-Simonians

themselves, was Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. Proudhon argued that the regime of exploitation is

synonymous with the feudal regime, governmental regime, [or] military regime, and that,

whatever phraseology is used, doing away with farm-rent and lending at interest would

8
eliminate the last vestiges of the ancient slavery, and, with them, the sword of the

executioner, the hand of justice, the club of the policeman, [and] the gauge of the customs

officer (1923a, p. 287, 1923b, p. 337).

Marx disagreed vehemently, and, during the time he was working on volume one of

Capital, was especially concerned to combat the influence of Proudhons ideas within the

International Workingmens Association.8 He thought this way of thinking, by figuring capitalist

exploitation as just another form of rent-seeking or extortion, misled the labouring classes in

their struggle for self-emancipation. The Saint-Simonian theory made accumulation by

exploitation into a moral problem of rentiers accruing and abusing their power over the

propertyless. It took no account of the novel dynamism of capitalist exploitation, as opposed to

the conservatism of pre-capitalist labour relations. Neither could it account for the novelty of

struggles over the length and intensity of work.

Rather than being an index of the persistence of the pre-capitalist world, Marx argued

that exploitation takes a novel form under capitalism. As Marx puts it, as a producer of alien

industriousness, as a surplus-labour-pump and an exploiter of labour-power, [capital] surpasses

in its energy, measurelessness, and effectiveness all earlier systems of production based on

direct forced labour (1976, p. 425). This is what Marx wants to elucidate: modern workers

freely and more effectively and energetically do what ancient peoples had to enslave others

to get done. In the French edition, he calls this the great secret of modern society (1989, p.

143).

This secret lies in the market for labour-power, and in capitals exploitation of labour-

power via the wage contract. Labour-power is, Marx claims, a very special commodity. It is a

source not only of value, but of more value than it itself has (Marx, 1976, p. 301). This claim is

9
now generally dismissed, even by many Marxists. It has fallen before the criticism that, in a

growing economy, any basic commodity adds more value than is required to reproduce that

commodity; corn, therefore, is exploited at the same rate as labour-power (Roemer, 1982, chap.

6, appendix). This criticism is too clever by half, however (Schweikart, 1989). If we take the

method of production as given, the quantity of any non-labour material of production will

determine the quantities of all other non-labour inputs. For example, if we know how shoes are

manufactured, a given quantity of rubber for the soles, or of leather for the uppers, will

determine exactly how many shoes can be made, and how much of each of the other material

inputs will be required. The quantity of labour-power purchased, however for example, one

days labour will determine nothing, since how much actual labour one can wring from the

purchased labour-power is a matter of work discipline, skill, and other factors.

Therefore, Marx argues, the institution of the labour market motivates a dynamic and

expansive mode of production. Having purchased labour-power on the market and for a fixed

period, the capitalist wants to extract the maximum possible advantage from this purchase

while he or she can dispose of it (Marx, 1976, p. 342). Because the length and intensity of the

working day are indeterminate, and because the capitalist can only realize a profit by selling the

produce of labour, and because the surplus realized by the capitalist takes the form of money, of

which one can always have more, capitalist production gives rise to a boundless need for

surplus labour. Cases of frightful overwork were abnormal and exceptional in the pre-modern

world, but overwork is normal, proper, and essential for the capitalist world (Marx, 1976, p.

345). This conclusion is confirmed, Marx argues, by the existence of laws limiting labour-time.

Even though it is in the general interest of capital to keep the exploitation of labour-power within

sustainable limits, the collective action problem inherent in production for the competitive

10
market makes it impossible for capitalists to limit overwork voluntarily. Workers are equally

powerless to independently establish a limit to the workday. Only a law of the state, an

overpowering social deterrent, can control overwork under capitalism (Marx, 1976, pp. 4156).

Marx thinks this is a complete historical novelty.

Setting limits to the working day is not the end of the story. The expenditure of labour-

power can be intensified, and the labour process can be transformed by dividing and

mechanizing the labour. This ongoing revolution in the mode of production obliterates the

traditional forms and cyclical time of labour (Booth, 1991; Postone, 1993, chap. 5; Sohn-Rethel,

1978, pt. III). Hence, according to Marx, the capitalist use of labour-saving machinery, instead of

reducing labour-time, sweeps away all customary and natural limits to the length of the working

day (1976, p. 532). The fight to impose limits on work does not end with the passage of eight-

or ten-hours laws, but is endemic to capitalism because it stems directly from capitals use of

labour-power (Philip, 2001).

Contrary to what other socialists argued, therefore, the capitalists exploitation of labour

is not of a piece with feudal extortion. The accumulation of capital by the exploitation of labour-

power roots capitalism in the labour market, not in the soil. The mechanisms and dynamics of

capitalist exploitation derive from the impersonal domination of the labour market, not the

personal domination of the local monopolist.9 Hence, capitalist exploitation is open-ended and

flexible, rather than conservative and tradition-bound, and it contains a built-in drive towards

overwork that did not characterize previous forms of exploitation. Capitalist accumulation by

exploitation is a historical novelty.

11
3. The prehistory of capital

With this understanding of accumulation by exploitation in mind, it is easy to see why

primitive accumulation would pose a special problem for Marx.10 By tracing the primitive

accumulation of capital back to acts of forceful and fraudulent expropriation, Marx seems to be

erasing his divergence from previously-existing socialist theory. Indeed, many readers of Part

Eight have noticed exactly this problem. Michael Perelman claims, for example, that, Marxs

depiction of primitive accumulation as unfair and brutal stood in contradiction to the main

thrust of Capital, according to which the seemingly fair and objective rule of capital

necessarily leads to exploitation (2000, pp. 2930).11 Jason Read is less categorical, but is

clearly exercised by the same concerns. At times, he claims, Marx appears to argue that

primitive accumulation and the overt violence it involves disappear in the day-to-day relations of

exploitation; while at other times it appears that the violent lawmaking power of primitive

accumulation is merely privatized and brought indoors in the factory (2003, pp. 2829). Saint-

Simonianism, which Marx threw out the front door, seems to have snuck back in the window.

Given this concern, it is arresting that Saint-Simonian language crops up precisely in

Marxs summary statement of the history of primitive accumulation. Marx says that the rise of

the industrial capitalists, these new potentates,

presents itself as the result of a victorious struggle both against seigniorial power, with its

revolting prerogatives, and against the regime of the guilds, with the fetters it placed on

the free development of production and the free exploitation of man by man. But the

knights of industry only supplanted the knights of the sword by exploiting events not of

their own making. They have succeeded by means as vile as those that served the Roman

freedman to become the master of his patronus (1976, p. 875).

12
Alongside the contrast between the new industrials and the old knights of the sword, a staple

of Saint-Simonian writing, this is the only place in Capital where Marx uses the Saint-Simonian

phrase, the exploitation of man by man. That he makes these borrowings at just the point

where he begins to discuss the origins of modern private property in the forcible seizure of

common lands and the violent expropriation of both the small proprietors of Britain and the

native peoples of Africa and the Americas calls for closer attention. What close attention reveals,

however, is that, while Marxs language echoes Saint-Simonianism, his claims contradict the

Saint-Simonian theory, in two ways.

First, Marx reverses the historical tendency, for he denies the Saint-Simonian thesis that

feudalism was more exploitative than capitalism: the rules of the guilds, on the contrary, placed

fetters on the free exploitation of man by man. The Saint-Simonians thought of feudalism as

the rule of military force, a rule that was gradually dismantled by the peaceful rise of the

industrials, which left intact only the feudal remnants of the state and landed property. This is the

narrative taken over and exaggerated by Proudhon. On Marxs telling, however, the old order of

things involved both an industrial hierarchy and guarantees of existence. While the direct

producers were bound to the soil, or [] vassals to another person, they also had immediate

possession of their own means of production, and this gave them a measure of protection. This

older economic order collapsed into the constitutive elements of the capitalist economic

order only because it was undermined by its prime beneficiaries, the lords of the land (Marx,

1976, p. 875). The feudal order gave rise in England, during and after the Wars of the Roses, to

the military means and the pecuniary motives by which the lords would abolish feudal land

tenures and dispossess the peasantry. They thereby also abolished their own personal, feudal

power. In its place, they obtained monetary wealth and private property, and the new forms of

13
impersonal, social power that came with these. The knights of industry did not supplant the

knights of the sword, as the Saint-Simonians thought. Rather, the knights of the sword turned

themselves into modern landlords.

Marxs second intervention is more decisive, and is contained in the cryptic finale of his

prcis. He says there that the industrial capitalists have succeeded by means as vile as those that

served the Roman freedman to become the master of his patronus. This analogy is obscure but

precise. When Roman slaves were manumitted, their relationship to their master was not broken,

but was transformed into one of a client to a patron. For a freedman to become the master of their

patronus their former master would be a rank betrayal of the client-patron bond, a betrayal

that can only be compared, in Roman law, to a child murdering their own parent. By the act of

manumission, the patron gave to the freedman civil and social life. For the freedman to then

enslave their patron, to take away their civil and social life, is inconceivable.12

Marx, with this striking analogy, claims that the capitalists were the prime beneficiaries

of the lords dispossession of the peasantry, that they owe their status and powers to the lords

abolition of feudalism, but that the capitalists, instead of becoming the lords clientele, usurped

the lords place. The lords may have destroyed feudalism in their pursuit of money and private

property, but the rise of capitalism, in turn, subjected the lords of the land to the rule of the

emancipated capitalists, on whom they are now dependent. This dependency arises from the fact

that, whatever the proportion of surplus-value which the capitalist entrepreneur retains for

himself, or transmits to others [e.g., landlords], he is the one who in the first place appropriates it

in its entirety and he alone converts it into capital (Marx, 1976, p. 710).13 In short, Marxs story

insists that, after the lords betrayed their vassals, abolished feudal power, amassed landed estates,

14
and created the modern proletariat, the rising capitalists, emancipated by the abolition of

feudalism, seized dominion over the landlords who had freed them.

Therefore, contrary to both the Saint-Simonian story and the usual reading of Part Eight,

Marx does not argue that capitalists originally amassed capital via primitive accumulation, and

then, having monopolized the means of production, switched over to accumulation by

exploitation. Instead, Marx argues that landlords amassed land through enclosure and

expropriation, thereby creating also the modern class of wage labourers; the capitalists then rose

up between these two classes, coming to dominate both by exploiting the newly available

resource of unattached labour-power. The process of primitive accumulation incorporated the

soil into capital (Marx, 1976, p. 895), but not by making the capitalists the owners of the soil.

Instead, the owners of the soil, the landlords, became dependent, for the cultivation of their land,

upon the capitalists mediation. The producer no longer had possession of the soil, and the

possessor of the soil no longer had access to labour. What had been torn asunder must be

reunited. This is what the capitalist accomplishes by stepping between the landlord and the

workers. The capitalists power does not grow from conquest and plunder. The capitalists power

comes from being neither the conquerors nor the plundered.

Marx confirms this reading at the beginning of Chapter 29, when he claims that the story

of expropriation so far told has left unanswered the question, where did the capitalists originally

spring from? Marx answers by claiming that they arose from bailiffs, share-croppers, and free

peasants who were lucky enough to not be expropriated by the land-grabbers, and who were able

to capitalize on the enclosures of common lands and the expropriation of their neighbours by

expanding their field of production, utilizing the commons for pasturage, manuring larger plots,

and employing larger gangs of farm-hands in cooperative labour. Their produce went to market,

15
where it met the demand created by the annihilation of the domestic industry of the

countryside (Marx, 1976, pp. 9056, 908, 911).

This interpretation is further supported by what Marx wrote elsewhere. Already in 1845,

Marx and Engels had criticized the True Socialists for seeing the extremes of our society in

the opposition of rentiers and proletarians, an opposition belaboured by all moralists since time

immemorial, and resurrected by writers like Saint-Simon (1975, p. 464). Thirty years later,

Marx would insist that the landowners and the capitalists are distinct classes, noting that, in

England, the capitalist is mostly not even the owner of the land on which his factory stands

(2010, p. 343).14 In this relationship between capitalist and landlord, capital dominates. Thus,

Marx criticized Malthus and Ricardo for failing to recognize that industrialization and

cooperative labour the capitalist mode of production made rent differentials dependent upon

differential employments of the land, and on the development and distribution of the forces of

production. Landlords do not dictate terms to capitalists; on the contrary, the rent they can charge

depends upon the capitalists development of industry (Ramirez, 2009). Ricardo famously

argued that corn is not high because a rent is paid, but rent is paid because corn is high (1973,

p. 38). Marx rejoins that exploitation is not high because rent is paid, but rent is paid because

exploitation is high. Landlords can skim off the top only because the capitalist exploitation of

labour-power accumulates a mass of surplus-value sufficient to feed even a class of idle rentiers.

In Marxs own words, Even though landed property can drive the price of agricultural products

above their price of production, it does not depend on this, but rather on the general state of the

market, how far market price rises above the price of production (1981, p. 898). As he put it in

The Civil War in France: the landlord is now but the sleeping partner of the capitalist (Marx,

2010, p. 212).

16
Therefore, Marxs account of primitive accumulation does not undermine his account of

accumulation by exploitation, since capitalists neither carried out the original expropriation of

the producers nor inherited the monopoly power of the landed proprietors who did carry it out.

Capitalists are able to exploit labour-power because they are situated between the expropriated

masses and the few landed proprietors. It is from their position of relative freedom, vis--vis

feudal constraints, that they were able to subjugate not only the poor labourers but also their old

lords, who had delivered capital from its bondage only to become its clients.

Marx calls primitive accumulation the prehistory of capital, in short, not because

capital (or capitalism) has its historical origin in acts of violence and theft, but because modern

industrial capital originates in the opportunistic exploitation of new forms of freedom created by

acts of violence and theft. Violence and theft are prehistoric because they cannot create capital,

but only capitals preconditions.15 Acts of violence and theft are not yet the process of

capitalizing upon the conditions created by violence and theft. Capital requires others to do the

dirty work of creating its preconditions. As we will now see, this is crucial for Marxs

understanding of capitalisms colonial and imperial reach, and for the practical lesson of Part

Eight, how the labouring classes might overcome capital and establish a new mode of

production.

4. The dependency of the state

The element of Marxs argument in Capital that looks like normative

developmentalism is his claim, in Chapter 32, that to continue the old system of small domestic

industry and petty agriculture would be, as Pequeur says judiciously, to decree mediocrity for

all (1976, p. 928). This leads into his infamous claim that capital is the negation of private

17
property grounded in labour, and that the proletarian revolution will be the negation of the

negation (1976, p. 929). Hence, Marx seems to inscribe capitalism in a Hegelian progressive

history, within which primitive accumulation plays the role of the so-called bad side by which

reason works itself out. Elsewhere in Part Eight, however, Marx attacks the stoical peace of

mind of those defenders of the enclosures who argued that they were necessary in order to

produce more labour, or else to establish the due proportion between arable land and pasture

(1976, pp. 8889). These arguments excuse the atrocities of primitive accumulation by reference

to the economic progress they made possible, precisely what Marx is accused of doing. Since it

seems churlish to accuse Marx of such blatant self-contradiction and in the span of a mere

thirty pages it is only fair to see if Chapter 32 might be better interpreted in a different light.

If one leaves aside all preconceptions everything one knows about Marxs Hegelian

historicism Marxs point in Chapter 32 is simply that there is no going back. The workers

movement has to accept socialized production and organize to expropriate the capitalist class, not

attempt to retrieve the modes of production capital has displaced. The question is: what, if not

normative developmentalism, provides the directionality here? What has happened that

imposes a backward and a forward on history?

Here it is crucial to note that Chapter 32 is sandwiched between two chapters in which

Marx outlines the role of the modern state in primitive accumulation. There is a massive

literature devoted to Marxs understanding of the state. The better representatives of this

literature distinguish between two models of the state in Marx (Hunt, 1984, chap. 23;

Sanderson, 1963). The first, most commonly associated with the Marxist theory of the state,

figures the state as an instrument of class domination. The second figures the state as a parasite,

striving for or achieving a sort of independence vis--vis the bourgeoisie (Hunt, 1984, p. 4). I

18
argue that Part Eight of Capital contains a third model of the state, one that integrates elements

of the instrumental and parasitic models: the state as dependent agent of capital. The state is

parasitic in that it depends upon the accumulation of capital (as I will discuss below), and this

dependency accounts for both the states relative autonomy from the actually existing class of

capitalists, and for its very imperfect instrumental relation to capital as such. The state under

capital is self-activating but subservient, a servile and corrupt henchman rather than a free agent.

This relationship between the state and capital is crucial for understanding what Marx calls

systematic primitive accumulation (Marx, 1976, p. 915), one manifestation of which is E.G

Wakefields proposal for systematic colonization.

Marx claims that the state has been the agent of all the methods of systematic primitive

accumulation, without exception (1976, p. 915). Under the colonial regimes, the states of

Europe plundered the rest of the world, stealing means of production and labour-power on a

massive scale. They thereby gave a great boost to navigation and commerce. Also, the

treasures directly extorted outside Europe by the forced labour of indigenous peoples reduced to

slavery, by embezzlement, pillage, and murder flowed back to the mother-country in order to

function as capital there. Colonial expeditions and commercial wars were financed by the

selling of public bonds. This system of state finance gave rise to a market for speculators, to

national banks, and to a system of taxation that contains within itself the germ of automatic

progression. Taxes, in turn, together with protective tariffs, ruined the remnants of the petty

producers (Marx, 1976, pp. 91622).

Artisans, peasants, and indigenous peoples were simply overwhelmed by these state-led

initiatives, in the mother country and in the colonies. As even so committed a partisan of the

petty producers as Craig Calhoun has admitted, radical mobilizations of traditional communities

19
fell apart whenever they extended much beyond the range of direct, person-to-person communal

ties (2012, p. 98). Local resistances were not in the same league as the powers they sought to

resist, which were organized at the national and international level, and were capable of

employing to great effect the impersonal bond of monetary payments.

Marx does not try to explain how the state came to have an interest in the accumulation

of capital. He does, however, indicate mechanisms by which this interest is preserved and

recreated. The relationship between tax revenues and public indebtedness is one such

mechanism. Once the feudal ties have been severed, the central state can only act insofar as it

can pay its agents, and buy the weapons and other implements with which those agents enact the

states sovereign will.16 The modern state acts with money. It can acquire the money with which

it acts only if capital continues to accumulate within the territory it controls. This dependency of

the state upon capital accumulation holds whether one looks to tax revenues or to public

borrowing, and whether the government is despotic, constitutional, or republican (Marx, 1976,

p. 919). In Michael Heinrichs formulation, the material foundation of the state is thus directly

connected to the accumulation of capital; no government can get past this dependency (2012, p.

212).

Dependency is not passivity; the state is not a passive instrument of the bourgeois class,

but a servant of capital. Servants might anticipate their masters desire, or try to stay on the

masters good side while doing as little as possible, or try to play one master off against another.

Servitude demands strategic and opportunistic action, not passivity (Scott, 1990). Hence,

whenever the conditions of capital accumulation are threatened, we should expect the modern

state to act for the sake of securing those conditions, however irrational or superstitious its

strategy may be.

20
Marx argues, against the doux commerce thesis, that colonial and imperial conquest are

the predictable outcome of this dependence of the state upon capital. Capital can only pursue

accumulation by exploitation where the conditions created by primitive accumulation exist. As

capitals dependent agent, the state executes and enforces the expropriations that capital needs

but cannot itself carry out. Hence, Marxs sarcastic invocation of doux commerce to

characterize the treachery, bribery, massacre, and meanness of Dutch colonial administration

in Celebes, Java, and Malacca (1976, p. 916). The methods of systematic primitive accumulation

colonialism, protectionism, confiscatory taxation, and so forth are not crude anachronisms in

an era of peaceful commerce. They are predictable consequences of the states having entered

into the service of the makers of surplus-value (Marx, 1976, p. 922).17

This account of the states role in primitive accumulation is the crucial context for Marxs

Chapter 32. The negation of the producers possession of the means of production is also the

creation of agencies with both the power and the interest to destroy petty production. On the one

hand, the development of capitalist large industry erodes the skill base of petty production and

decimates demand for its products. On the other hand, the modern state, bound to the fortunes of

capital, pursues tax, tariff, and colonial policies that abridge the transitional phases to the

capitalist economic order by means of a pitiless vandalism, spurred on by the most infamous

motives, the passions most sordid and most hateful in their pettiness (Marx, 1976, p. 928).

The negation of the negation, the destruction of these agencies of industrial capital and

the modern state, cannot, argues Marx, be achieved by petty producers, traditional communities,

or experiments in communitarian cooperation. Rather, it can only result from the creation of a

new agency, with the power and the interest to destroy capitalist industry and the modern state.

Marx thinks that the increasing concentration of capitalist wealth, the progressive deskilling and

21
collectivization of labour, and the relative immiseration of the class of labourers dependent upon

wages all conspire to make that class of labourers, and only that class, capable of overthrowing

capitalism. The masses, unable to satisfy their needs except through cooperative, industrialized

labour, have the means, via their revolutionary combination, to expropriate a few usurpers

(Marx, 1976, pp. 92930). This coincidence of motive and means is the material condition for

overcoming capitalism.

For Marx, this conclusion is underscored by the situation in the British settler colonies, to

which he turns in the final chapter of Capital. As E. G. Wakefield discovered in Australia,

machinery and money cannot command labour that is, to act as capital where the bulk of the

soil is still public property, and every settler on it can therefore turn part of it into his private

property and his individual means of production (Marx, 1976, p. 934). Capital, to be capital,

needs primitive accumulation to occur. The cure for the anti-capitalist cancer of the colonies

(Marx, 1976, p. 938), according to Wakefield, is for the government of the mother country to set

an artificially high price on the land at the frontier, and use the money generated from the sale of

this land to import new labouring settlers. Thereby, the government can establish the conditions

of capital accumulation. This is systematic colonization, a policy taken up for a time by the

British government (Ince, 2013).

Wakefields plan carries a political lesson for Marx. The states interest in capital

accumulation implies that, wherever worker colonies or other efforts to escape from wage-labour

might actually endanger capital, worker separatists will confront not only the difficulties inherent

in the organization of a new moral world, but also governmental policies backed by force of

arms. Hence, the story of Wakefields discovery is an allegory about the necessity of large-scale

political action to overcome capitalism. From the founding of the International Workingmens

22
Association, Marxs hope was that the organization might succeed in re-electrifying the

political movement of the English working class (Marx to Engels, 1 May 1865; 1987, p. 150).

Marx incessantly promoted within the IWMA the view that labourers should organize

themselves by and for the sake of intervening in politics at the level of the state for the sake of

dismantling the state. The end of Capital is one more piece of this advocacy. Without openly

calling for a revolutionary movement to seize and overthrow the state, Marx nonetheless builds a

case for the necessity of such a confrontation.18

5. Conclusion

To sum up: the criticism directed at Marxs conception of primitive accumulation miss

the mark. Marx does not confine primitive accumulation to the past, or to the frontiers of

capitalism. He argues, rather, that primitive accumulation is an ongoing necessity internal to

capitalism, but always anterior to the specific operations of capital. Capital cannot carry out

primitive accumulation, even though it needs primitive accumulation in order to create the

conditions in which alone it can operate. Hence, capital cannot be the only agent of capitalism;

some other agency or agencies has to do the dirty work. In the case of England, the original

agents of primitive accumulation were the lords of the land. In general, however, the primary

agent of primitive accumulation has been and continues to be the state. Hence, also, Marx does

not inscribe primitive accumulation in a normatively developmentalist history. Rather, he urges

his fellow socialists to adopt a realist conception of the modern state. Dependent upon capital

accumulation for its operations, the state can be expected to outflank and destroy efforts to

escape from or stave off the capitalist mode of production. The magnitude of the states power,

and the reliability with which that power is utilized to foster the conditions of capital

23
accumulation, indicate to Marx that the workers must unite in large numbers and carry out a

political struggle to dismantle the state and expropriate the capitalist class.

If the stakes here were only the interpretation of Marxs chapters on primitive

accumulation, this defense of Marx would be of limited import. But if Part Eight of Capital is

not as Eurocentric and developmentalist as the new standard reading claims, then the conclusions

of Marxs argument cannot be dismissed. Perhaps Marx did not produce, in primitive

accumulation, a useful conceptual tool, which can be taken out of its context, sharpened and

cleaned up, and then put to our own uses. Perhaps his argument regarding primitive

accumulation ought instead to challenge us to reformulate our theoretical understanding of and

practical attitude toward both capital and the state.

Indeed, Marxs argument directly challenges the theoretical and political tendencies of

the contemporary critics of primitive accumulation. To be clear, these critics hold diverse not

to say contradictory views. They do not form a single theoretical school or political party.

Nonetheless, the framework of their critique of primitive accumulation indicates certain broadly-

shared assumptions. They assume that capitalism is inherently and violently expansive, or

imperialistic, and that anti-capitalist politics is, on the contrary, essentially a matter of securing

zones of independence from the violent processes by which capitalism develops. Anti-capitalism

is thereby figured as independence, sovereignty, autonomy, or secession from capitalism. This

suggests a strategy of exit, or an emphasis upon changing the world without taking power.

Hence, also, capitalism appears to be a moral problem, in the sense that a morally-problematic

recourse to violence is its linchpin. It can be overcome only by converting violent others to the

view that non-violent commoning is both morally superior and practically sustainable. The

ligaments of a non-capitalist world are present, therefore, in existing practices of resistance and

24
common-living. The task at hand is to scale up these local practices, and to knit them together in

networks of solidarity and mutual aid. In short, only "the diabolical global complex of war and

militarization" prevents the structural causes of poverty, exploitation, environmental

destruction and climate change from being subjugated to the democratic authority of the

billions who suffer and die from them (Tully, 2014, p. 244).19

Marxs analysis of primitive accumulation casts grave doubts on this set of assumptions.

If, as per Marx, primitive accumulation is not carried out by capital, then condemning the former

need not touch on the latter. If primitive accumulation is the prehistory of capital, then the

disavowal of violence is just as essential to capitalism as the continuation of plunder is its

predictable consequence (Ince, 2013, chap. 1). If the state is dependent upon capital

accumulation, then we should expect both that the more sovereignty communities enjoy, the

more pressure these communities will face to open up their settlement lands to exploitation as

an economic solution (Coulthard, 2014, p. 77), and that the prevalence of democratic authority

will not make a whit of difference in this dynamic. If the state is the servile agent of capital, then

we can expect that alternative ways of life will be easily tolerated so long as they pose no threat

to the accumulation of capital, and will face the full repressive power of the state if they do seem

to threaten that accumulation. If this is a credible hypothesis about state action, then it is not a

meta-narrative of historical development but a counsel of prudence that anti-capitalists organize

and plan with the likelihood of this eventual confrontation in mind.

Finally, if Marx was right about primitive accumulation, it is not the desire to secure a

form of life outside of capitalism that contains the germ of a post-capitalist world, but the need

for large-scale, even global, cooperation. Making this world requires not a refusal of the

technologically- and institutionally-mediated interdependency capitalism has foisted upon us, but

25
an acceptance of it as our fate. Pre-capitalist modes of life and cooperation may well inform and

inspire both anti-capitalist struggle and post-capitalist society, but since they grew up in response

to conditions that were, by definition, untouched by capitalist accumulation, it would be

extremely surprising if they were, as such, up to the task of governing a post-capitalist world. In

short, there is no reason to think that any of us know how to live in a post-capitalist and post-

imperialist way. Hence, there is no reason to think that converting others is the political task at

hand. To what would we convert them? Capitalism poses not a moral or ethical problem, but a

practical and political one. Surmounting this problem does not require a new or common ethical

sensibility, or a change of heart, but a novel set of institutions.

It should not surprise us that Marxs argument runs so directly against current concerns

with primitive accumulation. The contemporary critique is, after all, a reiteration of the socialism

and mutualism against which Marx constructed his own critical theory of capital, the Saint-

Simonian theory of exploitation cast in new language. This is the evergreen anti-capitalism of

reactionary radicalism (Calhoun, 2012). As Tully points out, it is the anti-capitalism of

William Thompson, William Morris, and Peter Kropotkin (2014, pp. 235, 239). He does not

mention that it is also the anti-capitalism of Pierre-Joseph Proudhon. This anti-capitalism

declaims against all predation, fraud, and violence, and imagines that it thereby rejects capital.

Marxs argument, however, is that capital, too, condemns all predation, fraud, and violence.

Unlike reactionary radicalism, however, capital knows how to benefit from that which it

condemns, and the states dependency upon economic growth guarantees that predation, fraud,

and violence will continue to be regularly visited upon those without the institutional resources

to prevent it.

26
1
Robert Nichols has recently argued that an irony of the debates over primitive accumulation is

that, while this is supposed to be a Marxist concept, it actually derives from Adam Smith. As

Nichols writes: In The Wealth of Nations, Smith spoke of an accumulation of stock that must

be previous to the division of labour. When Marx translated this into German, he rendered it as

die sogenannte ursprngliche Akkumulation, and then, when Das Kapital was translated into

English, it became primitive accumulation. Not only are the main terms (previous,

ursprnglich and primitive) not direct equivalents, but Marx distances himself from association

with the idea through his use of the qualifier so-called (2015, p. 27, n. 1).

I think a close look at the textual history indicates, on the contrary, that primitive

accumulation as opposed to previous, original, or sogennante unrsprngliche

accumulation is a Marxist concept through-and-through, deriving none of its sense from Smith.

While Nichols may well be right that ursprngliche Accumulation originated as Marxs

translation of Smith into German, this did not become primitive accumulation when Das

Kapital became Capital, but when it became Le Capital. This matters because the French

translation of 1872-5 was entirement revise par lautour (Marx and Engels, 1989, p. 3).

Marx himself, then, bears responsibility for the transformation of what had been the second

section of chapter six, Die s.g. Ursprngliche Accumulation, and then chapter twenty-four,

Die sogen. ursprngliche Akkumulation, into a full-fledged Part Eight, Laccumulation

primitive.
2
In this camp, De Angelis includes Lenin, Dobb, Sweezy, and Brenner, among others.
3
In addition to Amin, the Subaltern Studies Group, Luxemburg and Wallerstein are important

theorists of the continuous character of primitive accumulation.


4
These debates are ably reconstructed by Nichols (2015, pp. 1820).

27
5
The influence of Karl Polanyi is patent in this formulation of the issue.
6
Normative developmentalism is Coulthards phrase (2014, p. 9); natural economy is

Luxemburgs (2003, chap. 26).


7
A fuller version of the argument of this section can be found in my book, Marxs Inferno

(Roberts, 2017, chap. 4).


8
Marxs antipathy to Proudhons system has been surveyed by McNally (1993). The influence

of Proudhons ideas within the IWMA is the subject of Puech (1907).


9
Marx does not dismiss concerns about accumulated economic power and exploitation by

extortion. He denies only that these capture the capitalist exploitation of labour-power in its

specificity. This is not the place to enter into a full reconstruction of Marxs understanding of

capitalist exploitation and its relation to force and compulsion. This issue is a fraught one within

Marxological debates. One of the important current debates pits those who focus on the

specificity of capitalist property relations and the exploitation of wage labour (Robert Brenner,

Ellen Meiksins Wood, George Comninel, and others) against those who insist upon the

heterogeneity of forms of labour within capitalisms global ambit (Jairus Banaji, Neil Davidson,

Ashley Smith, and others). Without imagining that it gets to the bottom of the differences

dividing these scholars, drawing the distinction between capital and capitalism as this essay does

illuminates the debate, which can be more polemical than edifying. Those who follow Brenner

tend to reduce capitalism to the operations of capital, and thereby to cast anything involving

extra-economic coercion as non-capitalist or pre-capitalist. Their critics rejoin that capitalism

obviously encompasses all manner of slave labour, debt servitude, and colonial predation, and

then draw the inference that capital may just as well enslave labour as hire it. Both sides, in

short, collapse Marxs distinction between capital and capitalism. Clearly distinguishing between

28
the two may, therefore, allow for a more productive exchange. For a sense of the debate, see the

recent symposium on Banerjis work in Historical Materialism (Campling, 2013).


10
The argument of this and the following section draw upon arguments presented more fully in

Marxs Inferno (Roberts, 2017, chap. 6).


11
Perelmans account has been repeated by David Harvey, who claims that Part Eight goes

against the central presumption of the rest of Capital, the immanent criticism of political

economy (2010, p. 289; Perelman is cited on p. 293).


12
For details about Roman manumission and patronage, see Mouritsen (2011) and Patterson

(1982, chap. 9).


13
See also the citation of Thomas Hodgskin in Chapter 31: The capitalist may now be said to be

the first owner of all the wealth of the community (Hodgskin, 1973, p. 98; quoted by Marx,

1976, p. 914).
14
Marxs statement, in this context, that the monopoly of land ownership is the basis of the

monopoly of capital may appear to contradict my thesis, but does not. Only where the land has

been consolidated into private property in the hands of a few are the mass of people reduced to

propertylessness, and only then can the capitalist, owning the means of labour and renting the

land, arise. As a necessary concomitant of mass expropriation, and a necessary condition for

capitalist intermediation, the monopoly in landed property is a basis for capitalism without being

constitutive of capital.
15
Unlike Amin and Harvey, Marx never calls primitive accumulation the prehistory of

capitalism. Only this phrase, and not Marxs, would imply that primitive accumulation is

historically antecedent to capitalism.

29
16
The extent to which state agents will carry out their mandates simply because they are paid to

do so should not be underestimated. Legitimation and patriotic fervour are, often enough, simply

side-effects of sending the checks out on time.


17
Fowkes mistranslates Marxs Plusmacher as profit-mongers.
18
Maximillian Rubel was convinced that Marx had deliberately reversed the last two chapters

of Capital in order to disguise its revolutionary conclusion from German censors (Marx, 1968,

pp. 541, 17059). Despite the lack of any positive evidence for this thesis, Rubel could not

believe that Marxs final words would be a historical chapter that ended and concluded the

work with the defeat of the proletariat (Marx, 1968, p. 1706). It did not occur to him that defeat

also holds political lessons.


19
My characterization of these shared assumptions is obviously broad, but I have drawn the

language of this characterization from across the range of the authors discussed; (see, especially:

Coulthard, 2014, pp. 16579; Harvey, 2004, pp. 7583; Midnight Notes Collective, 1990, pp. 7

9; Tully, 2014, pp. 23844).

Bibliography:

Alfred T (2014) Foreword. In: Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of

Recognition. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, ixxi.

Amin S (1974) Accumulation on a World Scale: A Critique of the Theory of Underdevelopment.

New York: Monthly Review Press.

Bazard A, Enfantin BP and Barrault E (1972) The Doctrine of Saint-Simon: An Exposition; First

Year, 1828-1829. New York: Schocken Books.

Beckert S (2015) Empire of Cotton: A Global History. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

30
Bessner D and Stauch, M (2010) Karl Heinzen and the intellectual origins of modern terror.

Terrorism and Political Violence 22(2): 143176.

Booth WJ (1991) Economies of time: On the idea of time in Marxs political economy. Political

Theory 19(1): 727.

Calhoun CJ (2012) The Roots of Radicalism: Tradition, the Public Sphere, and Early

Nineteenth-Century Social Movements. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Campling L (Ed.) (2013) Debating Modes of Production and Forms of Exploitation: A

Symposium on Jairus Banerjis Theory as History. Historical Materialism. 21(4): 3143.

Coulthard GS (2014) Red Skin, White Masks: Rejecting the Colonial Politics of Recognition.

Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.

De Angelis M (1999) Marx on Primitive Accumulation: A Reinterpretation. Available at:

http://homepages.uel.ac.uk/M.DeAngelis/PRIMACCA.htm (accessed 2 February 2017).

Dobb M (1963) Studies in the Development of Capitalism. London: Routledge.

Engels F and Marx K (1987) Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works, vol. 25. New York:

International Publishers.

Federici S (2012) Revolution at Point Zero: Housework, Reproduction, and Feminist Struggle.

Oakland, CA: PM Press.

Federici S (2004) Caliban and the Witch: Women, the Body, and Primitive Accumulation.

Brooklyn, NY: Autonomedia.

Glassman J (2006) Primitive accumulation, accumulation by dispossession, accumulation by

extra-economic means. Progress in Human Geography 30(5): 608625.

Harvey D (2010) A Companion to Marxs Capital. London: Verso.

31
Harvey D (2004) The new imperialism: accumulation by dispossession. Socialist Register 40:

6487.

Heinrich M (2012) An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marxs Capital. New York:

Monthly Review Press.

Hodgskin T (1973). The natural and artificial right of property contrasted. Clifton, NJ: A.M.

Kelley.

Hunt RN (1984). The Political Ideas of Marx and Engels. Vol. 2. Pittsburgh: University of

Pittsburgh Press.

Ince OU (2014) Primitive accumulation, new enclosures, and global land grabs: a theoretical

intervention. Rural Sociology 79(1): 104131.

Ince OU (2013) Colonial capitalism and the dilemmas of liberalism: Locke, Burke, Wakefield,

and the British empire. PhD Thesis. Cornell University, Ithaca, NY.

Kropotkin PA (1995) The Conquest of Bread and Other Writings. Cambridge: Cambridge

University Press.

Luxemburg R (2003) The Accumulation of Capital. London: Routledge.

Marx K (2010) Political Writings: The First International and After. London: Verso.

Marx K (1981) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Vol. 3. New York: Vintage Books.

Marx K (1976) Capital: A Critique of Political Economy. Vol. 1. New York: Penguin.

Marx K (1968) uvres: conomie. Paris: Gallimard.

Marx K and Engels F (1975) Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works. Vol. 4. New York:

International Publishers.

Marx K and Engels F (1987) Karl Marx, Frederick Engels: Collected Works. Vol. 42. New

York: International Publishers.

32
Marx K and Engels F (1989). Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe. Vol. II.7. Berlin: Akademie Verlag.

McNally D (1993) Against the Market: Political Economy, Market Socialism and the Marxist

Critique. London: Verso.

Midnight Notes Collective (1990) Introduction to the new enclosures. Midnight Notes 10, 19.

Mouritsen H (2011) The Freedman in the Roman World. Cambridge: Cambridge University

Press.

Nichols R (2015) Disaggregating primitive accumulation. Radical Philosophy 194: 1828.

OBrien J (1885) The Rise, Progress and Phases of Human Slavery: How It Came into the World

and How It Shall Be Made to Go out. London: William Reeves and Martin James Boon.

Patterson O (1982) Slavery and Social Death: A Comparative Study. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Perelman M (2000) The Invention of Capitalism: Classical Political Economy and the Secret

History of Primitive Accumulation. Durham, NC: Duke University Press.

Philip B (2001) Marxism, neoclassical economics and the length of the working day. Review of

Political Economy 13(1): 2739.

Postone M (1993) Time, Labor, and Social Domination: A Reinterpretation of Marxs Critical

Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Proudhon P-J (1923a) General Idea of the Revolution in the Nineteenth Century. London:

Freedom Press.

Proudhon P-J (1923b) Ide gnrale de la rvolution au XIXe sicle, Ouvres compltes de P.-J.

Proudhon, nouvelle dition. Paris: Marcel Rivire.

Puech JL (1907) Le Proudhonisme dans lAssociation internationale des travailleurs. Paris: F

Alcan.

33
Ramirez MD (2009) Marxs theory of ground rent: a critical assessment. Contributions to

Political Economy. 28(1), 7191.

Read J (2003) The Micro-Politics of Capital: Marx and the Prehistory of the Present. Albany:

State University of New York Press.

Ricardo D (1973). The Principles of Political Economy and Taxation. London: Dent.

Roberts WC (2017) Marxs Inferno: The Political Theory of Capital. Princeton, NJ: Princeton

University Press.

Roemer JE (1982) A General Theory of Exploitation and Class. Cambridge, MA: Harvard

University Press.

Sanderson J (1963) Marx and Engels on the state. The Western Political Quarterly. 16(4): 946

955.

Schweikart D (1989) On the exploitation of cotton, corn, and labor. The Canadian Journal of

Philosophy. Supplementary volume 15: 28197.

Scott JC (1990) Domination and the Arts of Resistance: Hidden Transcripts. New Haven CT:

Yale University Press.

Sohn-Rethel A (1978). Intellectual and Manual Labour: A Critique of Epistemology. London:

Macmillan.

Thompson W (1850) An Inquiry into the Principles of the Distribution of Wealth Most

Conducive to Human Happiness Applied to the Newly Proposed System of Voluntary

Equality of Wealth. 2nd ed. London: Longman.

Tully J (2014) Responses. In: Freedom and Democracy in an Imperial Context. London:

Routledge, 223276.

Tully J (2011) Dialogue Political Theory 39(1): 145160.

34
35

You might also like