You are on page 1of 4

A Question of Identity | Issue 62 | Philosophy Now 4/1/17, 9:19 PM

Philosophy Now Issue 62


https://philosophynow.org/issues/62/A_Question_of_Identity

A Question of Identity
Bob Harrison questions his identity.
Hello, you, this is me and thats him. But what are you? And what am I? And what is he? Three questions,
and in each case the answer is philosophically interesting. The interest turns on the further question: What is
a person?

John Locke offers a suggestion:

what person stands for... a thinking, intelligent being that has reason and reflection and can
consider itself as itself, the same thinking thing in different times and places. An Essay
Concerning Human Understanding

This is Lockes famous theory that psychological continuity is the key to personal identity: the idea that if you
can remember doing something, it was you who did it, and if you cant remember doing it, it wasnt you, but
a different person. It wouldnt be difficult to find a fair number of philosophers who would take Lockes
sixteenth century definition of person either as the right answer, or at least a very useful starting point on a
journey to such an answer. But what is the point of asking the question in the first place? What is the use of
making, as Locke does, a distinction between a man the living, thinking body and a person the
living, but purely mental being?

Locke would answer this question by explaining that he was concerned with two questions. Firstly, just what
would stand before God at the Great Judgment, and be recognised by the Almighty as me (or you, or
anyone)? Would it be our bodies, our souls, or both? Secondly, on a more down-to-earth level, Locke wanted
to answer an intriguing question about criminal responsibility. Suppose a man has committed a crime whilst
drunk or undergoing temporary amnesia. Suppose also, that because of his mental state at the time of the
offence, he genuinely cannot remotely remember a thing about it. Clearly on the evidence of witnesses and
perhaps he was caught in the act it was his own body, the same man who now stands in the dock, who did
it. But was it the same person? Should the present person be found guilty of the crime if the drunkenness or
amnesia had so changed his psyche that, at the time, he wasnt his true self? Can he rightly claim that at the
time of the incident the occupant of his body was a different person altogether; or perhaps some fractured
component of his own psyche that couldnt rightly be described as himself?

Psychological continuity was, Locke claimed, the answer to the question. The accused, considered as a man,
the physical being, is certainly guilty. His own hand struck the blow, his own voice had risen in anger. But if
the person, the psychological being, cannot remember one atom of it, then he is not guilty.

https://philosophynow.org/issues/62/A_Question_of_Identity Page 1 of 4
A Question of Identity | Issue 62 | Philosophy Now 4/1/17, 9:19 PM

But though Lockes theory answered the question, its not certain that it solved the problem; for it raises a
paradox that will try the wits of the jurists: the man in the dock may be guilty, but not the person in the man!
And if the man is punished, he will experience the pain, but the wrong person will suffer it.

Interestingly though, although Locke claims that the drunk/amnesiac is not the guilty person, he agrees with
the court in finding the accused guilty, but only because in the absence of any power to read the mans mind
they have no proof that he was as drunk, or is as forgetful, as he claims. He could, after all, be conning them.

But there is a further problem for this psychological continuity theory of personal identity. What are we to
make of things we cant remember, but, at least indirectly, we can be assured of them that we could in
principle remember them (because we did them)? Thomas Reid, taking issue with Locke a generation after
him, insisted on making a distinction between the remembering of something and being the person who did
it:

It is not my remembering any action of mine that makes me to be the man who did it. This
remembrance makes me to know assuredly that I did it; but I might have done it, though I did not
remember it.
Essays Concerning the Intellectual Powers

So Reid thinks that you can be the same person who did such-and-such twenty years ago, even though it has
slipped your mind entirely. In fact he claims that Locke has involved himself in a contradiction. He gives an
example which has become something of a classic in which he tries to point out the alleged contradiction
in Lockes theory (some think he succeeds, some dont!).

Suppose a brave officer, flogged when a boy at school for robbing an orchard, to have taken a standard from
the enemy in his first campaign, and to have been made a general in advanced life. Suppose also which
must be admitted to be possible that when he took the standard he was conscious of his having been flogged
at school; and that when he was made a general he was conscious of his taking the standard, but had
absolutely lost the consciousness of his flogging.

Reid points out that if there be any truth in logic the general and the boy who was flogged are the same
person. He expects Locke should see this as simple common sense. But, he points out, on Lockes theory, the
general is not the same person, because there is not the necessary psychological continuity. This, Reid claims,
means that Locke must believe that the general both is and is not the same person as the boy.

Apart from this, Reid claims there is a manifest absurdity in the psychological account of personhood, for it
claims that the person reduces to simply a succession of thoughts. For this reductionism Reid has no time at
all: I am not thought, I am not action, I am not feeling: I am something that thinks, acts and [feels]. Fair
enough. So My thoughts, and actions and feelings, change every moment they have no continued, but a
successive existence; but that self or I, to which they belong, is permanent.

Not that the story ends there, for if Reid has trounced Locke, David Hume too has dismissed Locke, together
with Bishop George Berkeley. Hume said that if he looked into his own consciousness, he found not a soul
nor a psychologically defined person, but only a bundle of sentiments, impressions, ideas what we would
today call mental states and events.

Reid, by the way, was no more awed by Hume than by Locke, and dismissed them both, along with Berkeley,
because one thing Locke, Berkeley and Hume shared was what Reid called the ideal system. This was not

https://philosophynow.org/issues/62/A_Question_of_Identity Page 2 of 4
A Question of Identity | Issue 62 | Philosophy Now 4/1/17, 9:19 PM

to say that their system was ideal in the sense of being perfect; but that it claimed our knowledge reached us
through the intermediary of ideas, a sort of mental go-between, giving us information about the world
outside ourselves. Reid thought that idea was an entirely superfluous concept which only complicated things,
and claimed that they all needed a more common sense approach.

Nor is this the end of the story, for a new development occurs in the twentieth century (new, that is to Western
thought: it had been current for centuries in Eastern philosophy). In a clever book entitled Reasons and
Persons, the Oxford philosopher Derek Parfit takes a radically different view from Locke, Hume or Reid.
Parfits ultimate concern is neither analytic nor metaphysical, but if I understand him aright, spiritual.
Although his view follows Locke in defining the self in psychological terms, it diverges from Locke on the
question of whether there is such a thing as a determinate self: a self which has something analogous to a
beginning and an end in space, or whatever is equivalent to space in the mental world. A determinate self, A,
is different from an adjacent (so to speak) determinate self B. That is to say, in some sense there is a point at
which A ends and B begins, and vice versa. But for Parfit, (to a backing track of Buddhist temple bells) the
idea of millions of wholly distinct psychologically-well-defined beings walking through life as if they are
aware of, yet never touch each other, if true, is an admission of some kind of fallen state, although with no
Adam or Eve, (but perhaps with some hope of an eventual Heaven/Nirvana).

Parfits vision of the present state of mankind is of beings walking in separate glass tunnels, ie seeing
themselves as atomistic individuals. But they are not separate: they are part of a great continuous stream of
consciousness, living in an illusion of distinctness. The meaning of Parfits glass tunnels is each mans
preoccupation with himself and his own interests as distinct from his part in the whole stream of
consciousness and not necessarily only human consciousness, but perhaps that of all sentient things (or
even of all living things?). His solution to the metaphysical lone-ness and spiritual loneliness of this situation
(what theologians sometimes call alienation) is to repudiate the glass tunnel by developing empathy with
ones fellows to such effect that the glass disappears and we perceive ourselves together as some kind of a
continuous self, ie recognising ourselves, though formerly functioning as if we were atomistic individuals, to
be in fact indeterminate: continuous with each other in a shared identity and interests. It seems Parfit has
himself tried this, and finds it deeply satisfying.

All of this (Locke, Parfit, et al I mean) makes good reading, but are they, and we their readers, barking up the
wrong tree? Is there after all any such thing as a person, a true self?

Suppose that there is no such thing as a self that what we call me or you is just a label for a number of
micro-electrical events in our brains. It just might be that by imagining there is such a thing as a self we are
multiplying entities without necessity; encumbering philosophy with excess baggage. What if the whole idea
of a self were only as meaningful as the notion of a right speed limit? I was stopped one day in Cheshire
for driving at thirty five miles an hour on a stretch of road where there was a thirty miles per hour speed limit.
I got away with a lecturing, but the lecture was very thought-provoking. Do you realise, asked the
policeman, that if a child ran out of one of those garden gates into your path, theyd have no chance? Youd
have their life on your hands. I admitted that he was right (hypocritically, for I didnt find his argument
convincing). But when a week later I found that the council had since changed the limit to forty miles an
hour, I was tempted to write jubilantly to the police and ask them what had happened to the vulnerability of
children such that they were now able to run out safely in front of a thirty-five-miles-an-hour car, which I
could now drive with impunity. One week the right maximum speed was one thing; the next week another.

What is the right closing hour for licensed premises; the right minimum age for consensual sex? In each
case, we have not discovered it. Instead we have adopted a convention. These conventions are agreed upon

https://philosophynow.org/issues/62/A_Question_of_Identity Page 3 of 4
A Question of Identity | Issue 62 | Philosophy Now 4/1/17, 9:19 PM

for good and useful reasons. But do they really identify some entity; some free-standing thing that would be
there whether we recognised it or not? No.

Similarly, is Locke chasing after moonbeams? Parfit might think so: he himself is not chasing the moonbeam
(if such it be) of a determinate individual self, but offering instead a quasi-Buddhist pointer toward a super-
self, or Self. Lockes reply could be that, if nothing else, the concept of self is useful to us in framing and
administering legislation (the drunken offender), while Parfit could justify his concept the indeterminate
Self by appealing to the realm of spirituality (and breaking down the glass tunnel).

Just to finally complicate the problem, let me remind you of Katherine Powers article about Professors Andy
Clark and David Chalmers in Philosophy Now Issue 55, May/June, 2006. She tells us their story of Otto, a
(fictional) man with a mild version of Alzheimers disease. Because he knows he is forgetful, Otto keeps a
thick notebook, and in it he notes down things he thinks it important to remember. When he faces a particular
situation in which his mind draws a blank he consults the notebook to make the right connections. Arguing
for the concept of an extended mind, Clark suggests that the notebook is actually part of the mans cognitive
process, and thus part of the man. Terry Dartnall counters that if he digs his garden with a spade, that doesnt
mean that the spade is part of him, although it played an essential role in the digging. Clark, undeterred,
mentions experiments in which it seems clear that Macaques (a genus of monkeys) use sticks as an extension
of their arms, and do so in a way that seems to point to the sticks being part of the cognitive process.

This topic looks as though it will generate much lively discussion over the coming years, but dont ask me
wholl win the debate. The question that interests me is: If it proves to be the case that we can use objects as
extensions of our mind, where does that leave us with regard to the question of personal identity?

Answers on a postcard please.

Bob Harrison 2007

Bob Harrison is a former minister, and is currently working on a book concerning the nature of God. He
(Bob, not God) holds an M.A. and an M.Litt. from Edinburgh University, where he has taught for the past ten
years.

https://philosophynow.org/issues/62/A_Question_of_Identity Page 4 of 4

You might also like