You are on page 1of 36

Pyrrhonian Skepticism

in Diogenes Laertius

Introduction, Text, Translation, Commentary


and Interpretative Essays by

Katj a Maria Vogt, Richard Bett,


Lorenzo Corti, Tiziano Dorandi,
Christiana M. M. Olfert,
Elisabeth Scharffenberger, David Sedley,
and James Warren

edited by

Katj a Maria Vogt

Molu Siebeck
SAP ERE
Greek and Latin texts of Later Antiquity (lst-4th centuries AD) have for
a long time been overshadowed by those dating back to so-called 'classi
cal' times. The first four centuries of our era have, however, produced a
cornucopia of works in Greek and Latin dealing with questions of philoso
phy, ethics, and religion that continue to be relevant even today. The series
SAPERE (cripta Antiquitatis Eosterioris ad thicam REligionemque per
tinentia, 'Writings of Later Antiquity with Ethical and Religious Themes'),
now funded by the German Union of Academies, undertakes the task of
making these texts accessible through an innovative combination of edi
tion, translation, and commentary in the form of interpretative essays.
The acronym 'SAPERE' deliberately evokes the various connotations of
sapere, the Latin verb. In addition to the intellectual dimension - which
Kant made the motto of the Enlightenment by translating 'sapere aude'
with 'dare to use thy reason' - the notion of 'tasting' should come into
play as well. On the one hand, SAPERE makes important source texts
available for discussion within various disciplines such as theology and
religious studies, philology, philosophy, history, archaeology, and so on;
on the other, it also seeks to whet the readers' appetite to 'taste' these texts.
Consequently, a thorough scholarly analysis of the texts, which are inves
SAPERE is a Project of the Gottingen Academy of Sciences and Humanities within
tigated from the vantage points of different disciplines, complements the
the programme of the Union of the German Academies funded by the Federal
presentation of the sources both in the original and in translation. In this
Republic of Germany and the State of Lower Saxony.
way, the importance of these ancient authors for the history of ideas and
their relevance to modern debates come clearly into focus, thereby foster
ISBN 978-3-16-153336-5
ing an active engagement with the classical past.
The Deutsche Nationalbibliothek lists this publication in the Deutsche National
bibliographie; detailed bibliographic data are available in the Internet at littp://
d11b.d11b.dc.

2015 by Mohr Siebeck, Tiibingen, Germany. www.mohr.de

This book may not be reproduced, in whole or in part, in any form (beyond that
permitted by copyright law) without the publisher's written permission. This ap
plies particularly to reproductions, translations, microfilms and storage and pro
cessing in electronic systems.

This book was supervised by Heinz-Gunther Nesselrath (representing the SAPERE


Editors) and typeset by Magdalena Albrecht, Janjenka Szillat and Andrea Villani
at the SAPERE Research Institute, Gottingen. Printed by Gulde Druck in Tiibin
gen on non-aging paper and bound by Buchbinderei Spinner in Ottersweier.

Printed in Germany.
104 Richard Betf

of the sceptic's choices as being dictated not by philosophical reasoning,


but by "non-philosophical observance" (acptMmo<pov TtlQfJCTLV, !vl 1 1.165);
Diogenes speaks of the sceptic suspending judgement when it comes to
philosophical investigations, but not about "matters that pertain to ordi
nary life and its observances" (Twv f3t(uTL1cwv tcai Tf]Qf]TUCWV, 9.108). Precursors of Pyrrhonism: Diog. Laert. 9.67-73

James Warren

The section of Diogenes Laertius' Life of Pyrr/10 from chapter 67 to chapter


73 begins with the tail end of a sequence of anecdotes illustrating Pyrrho's
life and outlook and ends when Diogenes embarks on a list of various scep
tical formulae which then paves the way for the exposition of the modes
that fills most of the remainder of the book. This section includes a brief
account of various precursors of Pyrrho's outlook. Diogenes' grand struc
ture of philosophical history places Pyrrho in book nine as part of the Ital
ian tradition inaugurated by Pherecydes and Pythagoras which includes
the Eleatic philosophers and Democritus, and culminates with Epicurus.
Pyrrho's connection with this tradition is evidently somewhat problem
atic, however, since he does not appear in the list at 1.15. He finds a way
into book nine in part through a cmmection with various followers of Dem
ocritus (Anaxarchus, Nausiphanes) and in part through a perceived simi
larity between Pyrrhonian scepticism and some concerns about knowledge
offered by Xenophanes, Democritus, and others. We can therefore dis
entangle two distinct ways of thinking about Pyrrho's place in Diogenes'
narrative. The first takes its cue from Pyrrho's behaviour and outlook, in
particular his apparent indifference in the face of conventionally troubling
situations; this is thought to illustrate something like the notion of tran
quillity that some ancient writers attributed to Democritus and which cer
tainly found later expression-albeit in different forms-in both Epicure
anism and the Pyrrhonism of Sextus Empiricus. The second takes its cue
from Pyrrhonism's sceptical epistemological stance and finds antecedents
for this too in philosophical history. These two ways of finding Pyrrho's
place in the grand story of philosophy, however, are not easy to reconcile.
This passage (9.67-73) does not have a clearly announced structure and
it is hard to detect even an implicit organizational method at work through
out. The overall impression is that Diogenes is lurching from biographical
material to concerns about philosophical successions and the demarcation
of different philosophical traditions and then back to thoughts about the
antecedents of Pyrrhonist scepticism. The result is somewhat disconcert
ing. For example, Homer and Democritus appear twice as predecessors:
both before and after the taxonomic interlude. And Philo of Athens ap
pears first as a source for the claim that Pyrrho liked these two authors at
106 fames W11rrc11 Prewrsors ofPyrrl1011is111: Diog. Laerl. 9.67-73 107

9.67 and then again as the subject of some verses by Timon at 9.69. But pretations of Pyrrho's philosophy. This passage also exemplifies a more
we can distinguish three basic textual units. First,
9.67-9 ends the biog general difficulty that ancient philosophers and ancient historians of phi
raphy with a report about Pyrrho's approval of Democritus and Homer losophy faced in accommodating scepticism as a tradition or movement in
and includes a pair of quotations from Homer supposed to illustrate affini their stories of the development of Greek thought.3
ties between the epic poet and Pyrrho before relating the famous tale of
Pyrrho and the pig and other brief anecdotes. Diogenes breaks off i n a
taxonomic interlude to give the list of Pyrrho's pupils that looks ahead to 1. Diog. Laert. 9.67-9: Philo of Athens and Pyrrho's
the tenth book and its account of Epicureanism and then he worries about approval of Homer and Democritus
how to name the school (9.69-70). 1 The next sub-section, 71-3, begins and
ends with more quotations from Homer (9.71, 9.73) but also includes men Diogenes begins this section with a reference to a certain Philo of Athens,
tions of other precursors of what Diogenes is finally prepared to call 'this who is offered as evidence for Pyrrho's approval of Homer and of Democri
hniresis': the seven sages, Euripides, Archilochus, Xenophanes, Zeno, and tus.4 This Philo might be the same person as the one mentioned at 3.40 as
Democritus once more. The signs we have of Diogenes' sources for this having written a sk6111111n on Plato; if so, then perhaps he was also Timon's
section are the opening report that Philo of Athens mentioned Pyrrho's competitor in writing satirical works about other philosophers and may
love for Democritus and for Homer (9.67), references to Posidonius, Nu have been a rival pupil of Pyrrho. It is possible that the first generation of
menius and Timon at 9.68-9 and the vague reference to some 'people who followers of Pyrrho were involved in something of a tussle over Pyrrho's
say' (p/rnsi) that Homer was the founder of the school (9.71) who must also image and philosophical legacy, as also happened with the first generation
be those according to whom (knt' n11to11s: 9.72) Xenophanes, Zeno of Elea, of followers o f another philosopher who committed none o f his thoughts
and Democritus are sceptics. We cannot rule out the possibility that Dio to writing: Socrates. Certainly, Philo interested Timon enough for there to
genes is working from some un-named intermediate source or sources for be a poem about him in the Si//oi which Diogenes quotes at 9.69 (= Timon
some or all of this information and it is likely that he is using a variety o f fr. 50 Diels, SH 824) and which is itself, like much of Timon's work, a clever
sources for these few diapters.2 reworking of a Homeric original.5
I will consider two of these sub-sections in turn: first, and more briefly, The first quotation at 9.67 is Homer, llind 6.146: Diomedes asks to hear
67-9 and then 71-3. As a pair they illustrate rather well the combination Glaucus' ancestry. The line cited here is the beginning of Glaucus' reply
of the ethical and the epistemological aspects of Pyrrho's outlook at work in which he first asserts that such things are not, in the final reckoning,
throughout this part of book nine and neatly announced in 9.61: "And very important before offering his own family story. Glaucus compares
in general he denied that anything is 'in truth' but thought that all hu humans to the leaves on trees, presumably in the sense that just as leaves
man actions are 'by habit' or 'by convention', for each thing is no more grow and then are shed as the seasons change, so too do human genera
this than that." The question of the precise original emphasis in Pyrrho's tions come and go. Given this constant change, we are supposed to infer,
own thought between these ethical and the epistemological strands is, of there is nothing particularly important about a particular person's lineage.
course, rather difficult to settle. Modern interpreters differ, often quite A comment that follows adds that Pyrrho also admired Homer for his com
significantly, in their assessment of the extent to which later sceptics influ parison of humans with wasps, flies, and birds.6 Here too the idea might
enced the presentation of Pyrrho's original position. This brief section in
1 For an excellent and concise account of this difficulty sec 3nuNsc11w1c 1999a, 232-7.
Diogenes neatly encapsulates the difficulties in our sources that give rise to
4 111is section fonns T20 in DECl.F.VA CA1zz1 1981, with commentary al 171-5. Com
these on-going disputes and suggests that certainly already by Diogenes'
pare the story of Pyrrho reading Democritus presented by Aristocles ap. Eus. Prnep.
time it had become difficult to reconcile all the various accounts and inter- cua11g. 14.18.27 (= F4.27 C111ESA1tA, T'
...3 DECl.l!VA CA1zz1), which is often taken to derive
from Antigonus of Carystus' biography (=23 DollAN DI ) and therefore share a source with
1 For a discussion of the notion of the Pyrrhonists as :i!ti!likoi ('inquirers'), which Dio
Diogenes. DECLEVA C\lzz1 1981, 171-2, suggests that the citation from Philo at Diog. Laert.
genes introduces at 9.69-70, see the contribution by Olfert in this volume. 9.67 also derives from Antigonus.
2 H1cKs 1925 ad 9.67 suggests that 9.62-7, including Philo's report of Pyrrho's liking for 5 In particular, it reworks Homer, Od. 21.364. Sec D1 MAltCO 1989, 224-5.
Homer and Democritus, derives from Antigonus of Carystus. BA 1tN 1;s 1992, 4286-7, argues 6 I assume that it is Homer who thus compared humans with wasps and the like and
against Janacek's view that all of Diog. Lacrt. 9.70-1 1 6 derives from a single source, namely that Pyrrho approved of him for this. Homer compares the Achaian army to a flock of
the Theodosius mentioned in 9.70. l11is is part of BArtNES' long (1992, 4257-90) discussion birds and a swarm of flies (Iliad 2.459-73) and Patroclus' men to a swarm of wasps (Iliad
of possible sources for Diogenes' presentation of the various modes, a discussion lhal ends 1 6.257-65). Dr:c1.EVA CA1zz1 1981, 173, suggests that the subject of eiknzc is Pyrrho and that
without any positive conclusions. it is Pyrrho who made these comparisons.
108 fnmes Wnrre11 Prmtrsors of Pyrr/1011is111: Diog. Laerl. 9.67-73 109

be that human lives are fleeting and insignificant, perhaps noting the sheer and childishness (paidari6des). The vocabulary of 'empty' or 'groundless'
number of human lives that come and go over time. striving is certainly reminiscent of both the Epicurean diagnosis of 'empty
Alongside his interest in Homer, Pyrrho's admiration for Democritus opinion' (ke11odoxia ) as the foundation of much unnecessary human misery
was thought by Philo worthy of mention. Democritus will also appear and also, closer to home, ofTimon's approval of Pyrrho's freedom from the
later as one of those whose epistemological outlook might have anticipated 'empty thoughts' (ke11eoplirosy11e) of the sophists (Timon fr. 48 Diels, cited
some aspects of Pyrrhonism, but here it seems that the connection between at Diog. Laert. 9.65).9 But it is also part of a more general debunking of
him and Pyrrho is based more on a particular outlook on human affairs and the supposed values that determine what most people spend their lives
aspirations. There is no reason to think that there is any direct connection pursuing or avoiding.1 0
between Pyrrho's approval of the Homeric sentiment, Pyrrho's approval What these two citations share, of course, is that they reflect no episte
of Democritus, and Democritus' atomist physical theory nor, in turn, is mological outlook whatsoever.11 Rather, they continue the depiction and
there any reason to think that Pyrrho's approval of Democritus in this re explanation of Pyrrho's particular - and often peculiar - diathesis. In
gard is any endorsement of Democritus' atomist physical theory, even as fact, 67-9 contains a concise list of various reports about Pyrrho's outlook
some kind of metaphor.7 More likely, there is a general similarity between and behaviour drawn from a variety of later sources: Philo, Posidonius,
Democritus' approval of a certain kind of balanced and moderate life of Numenius, and Timon. The two sources closest to Pyrrho, Philo and Ti
equanimity and Pyrrho's own advocacy of a certain kind of tranquillity. If mon, bookend this section. Philo introduces the thought about Pyrrho's
we think that the appreciation of the fleeting and temporary nature of hu preferred authors and Timon's verses on Philo then prompt Diogenes to
man life might encourage an outlook that regards much of what humans say something about the first generation of Pyrrho's followers. This in turn
happen to strive for or quarrel over as, in fact, only valuable by convention leads Diogenes to tl1ink about Pyrrhonism's place in the broader scheme
and not 'by nature', then there are clear parallels between the sentiments of philosophical successions and therefore of his own work.
attributed to Pyrrho at 9.61 and a certain interpretation of Democritus' own
ethical and metaphysical outlook. It is hard to make very much more than
2. Diog. Laert. 9.71-3: the catalogue of predecessors
this rather general claim without delving more deeply into both the con
tested evidence on Pyrrho and the fragments and testimonia that concern After the discussion of the proper nomenclature for the movement inau
Democritus' ethical outlook. It will suffice here just to note this alternative gurated by Pyrrho, Diogenes takes a look back at the precursors of this
account of Pyrrho's predecessors that looks not so much to accounts of Jzairesis. This account is both like and unlike 9.67-9: it contains more refer
knowledge or the impossibility of knowledge but rather to concerns about ences to and quotations of Homer and Democritus but it makes no claim
value and human happiness.8 that the authors it mentions were praised or held as predecessors by Pyrrho
The second quotation is Iliad 21.106-7: Achilles is addressing Lycaon, himself. What is more, the emphasis on the similarities - such as they are
son of Priam and half-brother of Hector. Lycaon offers himself as a sup - between these earlier authors and Pyrrhonism is more obviously epis
pliant to Achilles; Achilles replies that this time he will not be prepared to temological and metaphysical than the apparently ethical perspective of
ransom Lycaon. Patroclus is dead, who was much better than Lycaon, and Philo's report at 9.67-9. The source of this list is unclear. Diogenes intro
Lycaon will die too. Again, the quotation is followed by a brief explanatory duces it with the observation that 'some say' that Homer began this liniresis
comment: Homer is praised here for drawing attention to the fact that lm and it is not revealed whether these people are the Pyrrhonists themselves,
man life is not only unstable (abebaio11) - perhaps also reinforcing the idea eager to find an august heritage for their view and to combat the opposing
of the fleeting nature of human lives - but also full of folly (ke11ospo11do11) philosophies' similar claims, or a reference to a less partisan account of the
7 for this last proposal sec F. DECLEVA CA1zz1, "Pirrone e Dcmocrito. Gli atomi: un 9 Cf. LONG 2006, 72-3. See also D1 MA1tco 1989, 220-1. Compare also Timon fr. 11 DK
'mito'?", Ele11chos 5 (1984) 5-23, with critical response in DEn 2000, 187-8. (c SI-I 785): iivOQ<vTIOL ICEVEf]c; ohimoc; irr,\rnL itmmi and Dcmocritus' laughlcr at hum<m
8 For more discussion of these aspects of the philosophies of Pyrrho and Dcmocritus affairs as portrayed in the Pseudo-Hippocratic letters: e.g. Episl. 17.142-3: Tic; KEviJ
and !he various followers of Democritus - especially Anaxarchus and Nausiphancs - cmoul>iJ Ka i c\A6y1oi:oc, 11btv Ltvi11.:: b1arp(Qouoa;
10
who appear lo connect him with both Pyrrho and, later, Epicurus, see DErr 2000, 152-65; llind 21.107 is used by Callisthenes at Plut. Alex. 541 lo remind Alexander that he is
WA!utEN 2002; S. H. SvAVAl!SSON, "Tranquillity: Pyrrho and Democritus" in: 5. MAltCl!AND I mortal. Callisthenes and Anaxarchus - someone else offered as a philosophical inspira
F. VERDE (eds.), Epic11ris111e el Scepticisme. Convegni 22 (Rome 2013) 3-23. Timon ;ilso offers tion to Pyrrho (9.63) - arc paired as rival philosophical ad visors lo Alexander at Plut. Alex.
a reasonably positive assessment of Democritus, so far as we can tell from fr. 46 DK = 51-1 52.3-7.
820, quoled by Diogenes at 9.40. 11 Cf. BnuNsc11w1G 1999, 236.
110 f11111cs V\rrm Prewrsors of Pyrr!101Jis111: Diog. Lnerl. 9.67-73 111

history of scepticism. If this is a list produced by Pyrrhonists themselves know were also used elsewhere to support a positive dogmatic view. All
then their approach differs markedly from that of Sextus who, in general, of these U1emes will be illustrated as we discuss each of U1e precursors and
is more interested in stressing how his philosophy differs from its rivals.12 each quotation. There is no sense in this section that the various episte
If there is any structure to Diogenes' catalogue at 9.71-3 then it is at mological caveats offered by the thinkers in this list are connected at all
best a very rough and ready one.13 It divides the precursors roughly with the U1ought that there is a comfort, indeed a kind of happiness, to be
into two groups. It begins with poets and purveyors of 'traditional' wis found in avoiding holding dogmatic beliefs.15 This is an important part
dom: Homer, the seven sages, Archilochus, and Euripides; then it turns of the Pyrrhonist enterprise, but there is no sign of any connection made
to philosophers: Xenophanes, Zeno, Democritus, Plato, Empedocles, and by these predecessors between the proposed epistemological stance and
Heraclitus. It then goes back to Euripides and Homer begins and ends the human flourishing. Pyrrho's behaviour and charismatic tranquillity have
list. There are some interesting features. Plato appears in 9.72 but not in been covered earlier in Diogenes' Life and Diogenes only briefly returns to
the initial list at the begirming of the chapter. Euripides appears in both the matter of the effect of the various sceptical strategies on the Pyrrhon
groups, perhaps because of his familiar associations with a more philo ist's behaviour and outlook only at the very end of his account (9.107--8).
sophical kind of tragedy, the sophists and the like. The members of these This section is in some ways similar to the mud1 more extensive ac
groups do not fit perfectly well with the overall organization of Diogenes' count in Sextus Empiricus of previous philosophers' views on the crite
Lives into two principal successions of thinkers (see 1 . 13--1 5): the 'Ionian' rion (M 7.46-260) whid1 also includes references to views found in Homer,
(books 2-7) and the 'Italian' (books 8-10). While most fall into the sec Arci1ilochus, and Euripides (7.128). However, it is not clear U1at we should
ond of these hvo lists, Plato is certainly an 'Ionian' in Diogenes' classifi simply conclude that Sextus and Diogenes share a common source. Al
cation and both Heraclitus and Xenophanes are categorized as 'sporadic' U1ough they share a similar cast of characters, they regularly differ in the
philosophers outside the main traditions (8 9 1 , 9.20). 1-1 Within each of the
. particular texts and passages they choose to cite from those authors.16
two groups in 9.71-3, moreover, there is little sign of a concern for relative What is more, Sextus includes some of the people who are on Diogenes' list
chronology. Nor is there a consistent treatment of all the members of the among those who place U1e criterion in logos and are therefore not particu
group. Some of the characters have their views illustrated with a quota larly close to Pyrrhonism in outlook.17 It is likely, therefore, that if U1ere is
tion, others with a simple report. Sometimes the evidence presented is left a connection between the two catalogues then i t is a reasonably loose one.
to speak for itself; at other times it is accompanied by a brief explanation We know that both the sceptical Academy and Aenesidemus were inter
why it suggests a sceptical outlook. ested in offering earlier philosophers as examples of precursors for their
The overall impression is that our passage in book nine is not a system own positions (indeed, it is possible that Aenesidemus was interested in
atic attempt to document a particular and determinate Pyrrhonist episte doing so in part to try to wrest from the Academy the title of true heir of
mological outlook in earlier thinkers. Rather, it is a collection of famil this sceptical tradition). We can probably go no further than U1e conclu
iar and impressive names gathered in order to point to a set of loosely sion that both Sexh1s and Diogenes - or Diogenes' source - reflect this
related concerns about human uncertainty and the impossibility of mov interest.18
ing beyond conjecture, the mismatch between appearance and reality, or
the equal plausibility of two or more mutually inconsistent claims. There 15 As SrnLEY 1983, 9-10, notes.
1<. See the table in the Appendix, below.
is also an interest in the distinction between mere mortals and the gods
i ; Xenophancs appears both among those who say there is no criterion and also in the
in terms of their respective chances of cognitive progress, an interest in second group: M 7.49-52, M 7.110; cf. 8.366; PH 2.18. He was clearly a difficult case for
the terminology of custom or opinion (110111os and 1to111izei11), and the use both Sextus and Diogenes: see S. Ton, "Sextus Empiricus on Xenophanes' Scepticism",
of quotations for the purpose of illustrating a sceptical outlook which we Jntcr11ntio11nl /01m111lfor thc Study of Skcplicism 3 (2013) 1-23 and also n. 19 below. We might
also notice that Diogenes himself notes that Parmenides said that logos is the critcrio11: Diog.
1 See, for example, the different treatments of Xenophanes and Plato: n.30 below. Laert. 9.22.
13 BnuNsrnw1G 1999a, 236, calls this passage "workmanlike, if somewhat muddled''. rn
For the New Academy's use of these earlier philosophers see Cicero, Acnd. 1.44-5 and
H 1 discuss some of these issues with reference to texts that construct a philosophical 2.13-15 with the discussion in C. B 1tffrAIN I ]. PALMER, "The New Academy's Appeals to
tradition from Democritus to Epicurus, via Pyrrho, in WARREN 2002, 10-28. For an account the Presocratics", Plzro11csis 46 (2001) 38-72. For the claim that Aenesidcmus is a source for
of the general structure of Diogenes' work sec WAnllEN 2007. On the structure of book nine at least some of Sextus' discussion (in particular M 7.49-88), see SEDl.EY 1992, 25-6. (Cf.
in particular see DECLEVA C\IZZI 1992. On Diogenes' use of sources see MEJHll 1978 and Galen, /11 Hipp. tfr mcd. off. 1.658.10-12 K: LIUTOi ouv oi 'WU nu{j(/tuVO<; Eic; rn:11\mouhouc;
F. AllONADID, "Due fonti laerziane: Sozione c Demetria di Magnesia", Elc11c!zos 11 (1990) LtVb(lllC Ll Vctyoum Ti)v EaUTWV 7i(l0LliQHHV.) SEDLEY 1992, 27-34, goes on to argue that the
203-55. source of Sextus' account of the plzysikoi (M 7.89-140) is Posidonius' 011 the criterion , and
1 12 fames Warreu Precursors of Pyrrl1011is111: Diog. Lnerl. 9.67-73 113

Certainly, there are signs of a dispute about the origins of certain forms rather more significant in the light of the preceding discussion of whether
of scepticism that dates back at least as far as the end of the third century Pyrrhonism is a hairesis, the variety of labels used for this philosophical
BC For example, Diogenes notes that according to Sotion of Alexandria movement, and Theodosius' doubts about whether 'Pyrrhonism' is an ap
(fl. c. 200 BC) it was Xenophanes who first declared that all things are propriate term at a!J.20 Nevertheless, Diogenes first introduces Homer
akatalepta (9.20). Diogenes then adds the brief remark that Sotion was mis who, "according to some, began the hairesis " (9.71). 21 Later, the sayings of
taken (plaw5111c11os) but does not explain what the correct view is. In short, the seven sages "are sceptical" (skcptika ei1wi), Archilochus and Euripides
the structure of book nine in general and this brief section of it in particu "are sceptical" (skcptikos ek/cei11), and Xenophanes, Zeno, and Democritus
lar show the signs of a combination of different traditions in ancient philo are, according to these same people, "in fact sceptics" (skeptikoi t11gkhm1011si:
sophical historiography, some of which were championed by Pyrrhonists 9.72).
from Aenesidemus onwards and some of which might be traced back to Homer begins and ends the list. At 9.71 his position is accounted for
earlier Hellenistic sources such as the sceptical Academy and successional not with any quotation but with a pair of observations. Even taken to
and biographical works such as Sotion's 011 the s11ccessio11s of the philoso gether, they suggest that the requirements for identification as a member,
phers. (The curious and contested position of Xenophanes and Heracli let alone the founder, of this movement are remarkably lax. First, he ap
tus is just one indication of these differences.) The Pyrrhonists themselves parently gives different answers to the same question at different places in
may well have had something of an ambivalent attitude to these putative his poems. Second, he never gives a definite or dogmatic answer. The rela
ancestors. On the one hand, they allow Pyrrhonism to stand as the nat tionship between these two statements is not clarified but we can speculate
ural development of an earlier tradition of sceptical thinking, something that the fact of giving different answers to the same question at different
that might have been particularly useful at a time when Pyrrhonism was times is best explained by assuming that, on each occasion, the answer
in direct competition with Academic scepticism. On the other hand, i t given is offered without 'dogmatizing' (011de11 /10rik6s dogmatizei). Presum
was nevertheless important for the Pyrrhonists t o stress the distinctive na ably, the sceptical Homer should be thought to suspend judgment on the
ture of their own outlook and note the differences between their stance matter. Otherwise, we would simply have to assume that the apparent din
and all these alternatives (see e.g. Sext. Emp. PH 1 .209-41). Diogenes' p/16nin marks a genuine contradiction in Homer's views. The lesson to be
work retains the imprints of these different and sometimes incompatible drawn is that i t is possible to offer a view without strong commitment to
approaches.19 its truth: something that Diogenes will go on to explain is in fact the usual
Before we turn to look in more detail at each case in turn, we should tactic of the Pyrrhonist when offering and expounding other philosophers'
notice that Diogenes uses a variety of expressions to describe the sense in views (Diog. Laert. 9.74: mctoi d' ace den npeplcai11011to dog111atik6s . . . 111ede11
which these poets and philosophers are to be thought of as predecessors /corizo11tes . . . ). Since everyone would be familiar with Homer and therefore
of Pyrrhonism. What might have been accounted for as mere variatio looks with the fact that there are apparent contradictions between various pas
sages, i t is not a bad idea to use Homer in this way to exemplify the sense
that the source of the third section (M 7.141-260) is Antiochus. (Cf. SHOt.EY 2012, 88-93.
in which a Pyrrhonist might offer a point of view undogmatically. What
for a critical reaction to this last suggestion, see: C. B1mTA1N, "Antioch us' epistemology",
in: SEoLEY 2012 [104-301 108-13.) Diogenes uses Posidonius as a source for some of the is more, since Homer was regarded as something of an authority, this pro
biographical material about Pyrrho (9.78 1'287 EK); it is hard to see how this could have
= posal suggests that even the most authoritative of ancient poets was in fact
come from the 011 tlte crilerion. rather undogmatic.
19 for example, at the beginning of the Life of Pyrr/10 Diogenes appears to endorse As
After Homer, Diogenes moves on to the seven sages. There is some
canius of Abdera's view that it was Pyrrho who introduced the notion of nkaln/i!psin (9.61)
and at 9.70 he notes the view of Theodosius that Pyrrho was not the founder of scepticism. thing to be gained, we might suppose, in being able to trace the seeds of
Presumably, Diogenes here reflects the same divergence of interpretations of Xcnophanes' a philosophical view all the way back to those who were genuinely wise
position in the succession that leads Scxtus to place Xcnophancs twice in his own classi and Diogenes chooses to begin his entire account of the plcilosopltoi with
fication of views on the criterion. Hcraclitus does not appear in the list at 1 .13-16 while those who were in fact soplwi (1.13). All the same, the supposed grounds
Xenophancs docs appear in the Italian succession at 1.15. Diogenes notes again Sotion's
vil!w that Heraclitus was a pupil of Xcnophanes at 9.5; Sotion's views may have been in
for including the seven sages here are rather flimsy, even in comparison
fluenced by the presentation of these various philosophers in Timon's Silloi, on which he with the other members of the list. For example, it is not at all clear how
wrote a commentary, since it is clear that Timon looked to Xenophanes as something of a
211
poetic and perhaps philosophical predecessor: Athenaeus 8.336D. See also DECI.EVA CA 1zz1 Diog. Laert. 9.69-70; Theodosius' concerns may well be what provoked the comments
1992, 4223-30. (For the view that, at a certain level of analysis, there is a clear structure to by Sextus at PH 1.7.
21
the whole of 9.61-108, see e.g. BARNES 1992, 4242.) On whether Pyrrhonism is a lwiresis sec also Diog. Lacrt. 1 .20 and Sext. PH 1.16-17.
114 fames Warrc11 Pnwrsors of Pyrrlro11ism: Diog. Laa/. 9.67-73 115

the famous maxim "Nothing too much" (111edeJ1 aga11) is supposed to be PJ-1 3.244. A closer look at the two citations reveals an interesting differ
related to a Pyrrhonist outlook. Perhaps it is a pointer to the Pyrrhonist ence between the two. In Sextus, M 7, the context of the quotation from
notion of isosthe11eia or it looks back once more to the theme in the bio Archilochus is an account of Heraclitus' criterion of truth and, more im
graphical anecdotes of a distaste for strong commitments to things as hav portantly, the positive claim that human intelligence is derived from -
ing positive or negative value. Pyrrhonism is characterized by a lack of or perhaps part of - divine intelligence.23 Here in Diogenes, however,
unqualified commitment to anything in particular, opinions and objects of the quotation seems to be offered to illustrate the more pessimistic idea
pursuit or avoidance included, and we are perhaps asked also to trace back that human intelligence is at the mercy of divine intelligence and is not
this attitude of relative indifference to the seven sages. The next piece of itself in control or able to determine its own contents. Again, therefore,
evidence - the advice against making pledges - also turns up at Plato, what Diogenes cites in favour of a pessimistic view of human life and hu
Chmwides 165a: "pledges lead to ruin". What was presumably originally man achievements is elsewhere cited by Stoic sources or perhaps Stoiciz
advice against making unbreakable promises which might generate un ing interpretations of Heraclitus in favour of a positive view of the guiding
fortunate obligations is here in Diogenes being taken as a general warning power of divine reason over human lives. It is possible that these are two
against commihnents of any sort: it can be disastrous to assert anything examples of attempts to object to Stoicizing interpretations of Homer by
with certainty and with conviction (bebai6s, pepcis111e116s). providing alternative Pyrrhonist readings. As we shall see, some of the
Euripides and Archilochus come next (Archilochus fr. 131 West; Eu other examples offered by Diogenes also seem to concern a comparison
ripides, S11pplia11ts 734-6). They both stress the fleeting nature of human between a mortal form of cognition and some alternative, divine, under
ity and the inferiority of human thought compared with the will of Zeus. standing. In all these cases it appears that mortals' grasp on reality is re
They share the idea that human thought, indeed human life in general, is vealed as being somehow deficient in comparison; the contrast between a
subject to the whim of the divine. If what we think and do is not entirely divine understanding and our own encourages us to be less confident in
self-directed then the recognition of this kind of divine influence might the truth of our views about the world.
well undermine confidence in the accuracy and truthfulness of what we These two quotations also illustrate neatly how liberal are the criteria for
do happen to want or believe. The first citation is Euripides, S11pplia11ts inclusion as an example of sceptical leanings. Diogenes - or his source -
734-6: Adrastus is explaining how human hopes are fragile and human has to interpret the references in these texts to various psychological ca
cities and accomplishments can easily be dashed because they all depend pacities, states, or activities (tl111111os in Archilochus, phro11ei11 in Euripides)
on the will and whim of Zeus. This is an interesting text, because although as plausibly anticipating the later more precise philosophical terminology.
it is here offered in favour of a pessimistic view of human cognitive possi Of course, Diogenes does not need to come up with any precise account
bilities, elsewhere it is used to make a positive claim. Plutarch cites these of the sense of tlwmos here, provided the lines can plausibly be offered as
line at Stoic. Repug. 10568, adding that they were quoted with approval saying something roughly like the desired epistemological stance.
by Chrysippus because they present the view that nothing stays the same The next few citations come from people more commonly regarded as
or changes without the will of Zeus. This was offered by the Stoic as a philosophers and who have figured previously in Diogenes' work. First,
good illustration of the all-pervasive causal reach of fate and the underly Diogenes cites the opening of Xenophanes 834 (Diog. Laert. 9.72). It
ing rational divine will that guides the world. Plutarch notes that, given is not hard to see why sceptical philosophers were interested in this as
the approval of these lines, the Stoics cannot claim that fate is merely a pect of Xenophanes' philosophy. All four lines of this fragment are cited
predisposing cause; it must instead be a necessitating cause. In any event, also by Sextus; they appear at both M 7.49 and 7.110 since there were ap
Chrysippus offered these lines in defence of a positive view about the di parently two competing interpretations of Xenophanes' epistemology and
vine causation that governs the world. In Diogenes, in contrast, they are he is therefore listed twice in Sextus' classification.24 Diogenes' version
offered as a sign of the mutability and instability of human affairs.
23 This is perhaps rather ironic given l-Ieraclitus' famous attack on Archilochus and
The end of the second line of the Archilochus fragment is also cited at Homer in B42. We might wonder if, by citing Homer and Archilochus as anticipating Her
Sextus Empiricus at M 7.128 along with Homer, Odyssey 18.136-7 and is aclitus, Sextus' source has this fragment of Heraclitus in mind.
followed by a citation from Euripides (Tro. 885).22 The Homeric passage 2 Sextus Empiricus, M 7.49: "According to some" (k11ta ti1111s) this shows that Xeno
seems to be something of a favourite of Sextus, since he also quotes it at phanes thought all things are nkntnli'ptn; 7.110: some think this means he denied the p/11111-
tasin kntnli'pliki' but allowed the pl1r111tnsia rloxasliki'. Note that at M 7.50, Sextus cites after
22 Xenophanes a line of Euripides (Plroe11. 469). Although the Euripidcan quotation is differ
I's. l'lut. Vil. Hom. (b) 155 states that in these lines Archilochus is deliberately echoing
the lines from Odyssey 18. ent from the one here in Diogenes, it is clear that Sextus and Diogenes are both following
116 /11111.:s \!\'rirrcn Prcrnrsors of l'yrrl1011is111: Diog. Lncrt. 9.67-73 117

is again truncated in comparison with the rid1 account of various pre Cronus rather than Zeno and there are therefore reasons to doubt that this
classical and classical accounts of the criterion in M 7 both in the sense that is indeed an argument that was offered by Zeno himself.27 In Diogenes'
he offers only part of what Sextus offers but also because there is no sense Life of Zeno, Zeno is said to hold that there is no void (9.29), which itself
here in Diogenes of the interesting debate about Xenophanes' views that is perhaps an extrapolation from one half of the dilemma concerning mo
Sextus mentions. In fact, Diogenes' very brief citation omits not only the tion presented here. It is not made explicit just why the denial of motion
specification in line 2 that the subjects about which no man has ever seen is related to some kind of sceptical epistemology, but presumably if the
what is true and clear (lo saplzes) are "the gods and what I say about all argument does indeed demonstrate that motion does not occur, then our
things". It also omits the intriguing idea that even were someone to hap senses must systematically be misrepresenting the reality of things to us.
pen upon the truth it would not be recognized as such and - perhaps more This is a view attributed by Diogenes to Melissus (9.24: "there is no mo
surprising - the final comment that opinion (dokos) covers all. Instead, it tion in reality, although it appears that things move") and it is also pos
stresses (as we might expect) the simplest negative part of Xenophanes' sible that it is the intended force of a claim attributed to Timon by Sextus
statement. Diogenes' Life of Xenoplzmzes, we might also note, contains no at M 10.197: "Nothing divisible (111eristo11) can come to be in indivisible
discussion of this fragment nor any particular interest in Xenophanes' epis time (a111erei klzrom5i)" (= Timon fr. 76 Diels, SH 834), where examples of
temology despite this evidently having been a matter of some debate and divisible things include: coming-to-be and perishing.28 It is possible that
interest. Diogenes does cite Timon's qualified approval of Xenophanes' something like the Zenonian concerns about reconciling the reality of pro
modesty (Diog. Laert. 9.18 = Timon fr. 60 Diets, SH 834), however, in a cesses that take time with the idea that 'now' is really a durationless instant
line that also refers to Xenophanes' well-known criticisms of Homer. Most were put to use by Timon in service of a sceptical conclusion about the re
likely, the criticisms Timon has in mind are those famous attacks on Home liability of our senses. Diodorus' puzzles about motion were also thought
ric tl1eology that are also mentioned by Diogenes (9.18).25 to conflict with the way we tend to perceive motion and change; the two
Next, and very briefly, Diogenes attributes to Zeno of Elea a denial that were conflated and this argument was then attributed to Zeno himself.
motion is possible since any supposed moving body must be moving either The contrast between how things appear to us and how things really
where it is (which is impossible since being where it is it would be station must be is raised again in the next few quotations from Democrih.ts. The
ary) or else where it is not (which is also impossible since the body is not details of Democritus' own metaphysical stance are of course subject to a
there). This is our fragment B4. We can compare this problem with Aris great deal of controversy, but Diogenes' preferred interpretation is very
totle's treatment of the 'arrow paradox' in Physics 6.9 (A27 DK). In Aristo clear. He cites Bl 17 and 125 which both seem to stress that how things
tle's presentation, at least, the paradox threatens because there is no way really are is somehow inaccessible to us and is certainly not accessible
in which an arrow can be in motion 'now' if 'now' is understood as a du through sense perception. On this occasion Diogenes also gives one of
rationless temporal point; furthermore, the arrow can never move if time his short explanatory glosses: Democritus "threw out qualities" (tas poiote
is composed of such 'nows'. Diogenes' presentation makes no reference at las ekba/1611). This gloss sounds like a good Greek equivalent for 'elimi
all to the constraints on motion placed by an unextended 'now'. Rather, nativism': although we perceive things having various qualities such as
it seems as if in the case of a body supposedly moving 'in the place it is being hot or cold and often from opinions that things are indeed as they
in' the difficulty is caused directly by the spatial constraints of body be thus appear, these opinions must be mistaken since there are in fact no
ing in a place exactly its size and therefore offering no space for motion such qualities in reality. This view of the sceptical consequences of Dem
to occur.26 Other sources attribute this form of the argument to Diodorus ocritean metaphysics seems to have been the preferred interpretation of
both the Pyrrhonist and the Epicurean traditions, in contrast to Aristotle's
sources with similar strategies of combining philosophical texts <md tragic poetry in their interest in making Democrih.1s rather more like his fellow Abderite Pro
catalogue of examples. tagoras. Diogenes did not, however, make any reference to this aspect of
25
for Timon's attitude to Xenophanes see both fr. 59 and fr. 60 DK (S/-1 833 and 834),
both cited at Sextus Empiricus PH 1 .223--4). Timon may well also have seen Xenophanes
27
as something like a poetic model. See LONG 2006, 77 and 85-8. Diogenes gives the same argument at 9.99. The argument attributed to Zeno by Dio
26
To be sure, this might figure in Aristotle's presentation in the claim that at any 'now' genes is attributed to Diodorus Cronus by Sextus at M 10.85-11 1 where it is clear that the
the arrow will always be stationary because it will be "opposite something equal to itself" argument provoked quite a debate. Cf. Sextus, PH 3.71-5.
(katn lo iso11) and everything that is kata to iscm must be stationary (Physics 6.9, 239b5-7) but !H Sec F. Di:c1.EVA CA1u.1, "Timone di Fliunte: i frammenti 74, 75, 76 Diels", in: N.

it remains the case that Aristotle's version has an explicit interest in the way in which time BADAi.ON i (ed.), La Storia dc/111 Filosofi11 come Sapere Critico. St11di OfferIi 11 Mario Dnl Pm (Milan
is conceived in the paradox that is absent from Diogenes' presentation. 1984) 92-105.
118 /nmcs Wnrrc11 Prernrsors of Pyrr/1011is111: Diog. Lnert. 9.67-73 1 19

Democritus' philosophy in his Life which gives only a very brief account Next, Diogenes turns to Empedocles, citing first B2.7-8 and then skip
of atomism and mentions only that Democritus held the view that we see ping back (epn110) a couple of lines to give B2.5. Here too we have the fa
by means of the impact of atoms from external objects on our eyes (9.44).29 miliar implied contrast between mortal (mzrlrnsin: B2.7; cf. broleii! melis at
Plato appears next, very briefly, with the simple report that he "leaves the end of the fragment 82.10) and divine access to the truth and, in 82.5,
truth to gods and the sons of gods and seeks after the 'likely account"' (/011 a gesture towards the fact that each person's beliefs will depend upon that
eikotn logo11 zelei11). This is surely a reference to the famous qualifications person's particular experiences. This is one case in which Sextus Empiri
Timaeus gives to his cosmological account and to the possibility of mortals cus cites the same material as Diogenes (M 7.122-5). In fact, Sextus gives a
acquiring knowledge about certain aspects of the universe, including the rather more extensive quotation of the original text at M 7.123-4 and the in
traditional gods (see e.g. 29b-d, 40d).30 Although Diogenes has a lot to say terpretation he offers stresses how Empedocles has a complex view. First,
on the difficulty of interpreting Plato's works and although there is a long there is both a divine and a human form of right reason (orllws logos). Sec
tradition by his date of interpreting Plato as a sceptic of some kind, there ond, while B2 shows that Empedocles agreed that the senses cannot func
is no mention in the account of Plato's views in the Life of Pinto (3.67-80) of tion as the criterion of truth, there is nevertheless at the end of the fragment
the particular piece of evidence offered in book nine for attributing to him the reassurance that there is an extent to which human reason might nev
a sceptical outlook. ertheless attain the truth. Sextus concludes by citing B3 as evidence that
After Plato, Diogenes returns briefly in 9.73 to Euripides, citing fr. 638 Empedocles elsewhere offered a rather more positive assessment of the re
Kannicht: "Who knows if being dead is really living and what mortals call liability of the senses. Whatever the interpretative merits or deficiencies of
living is really being dead?" This same fragment is cited by Plato at Gorgins Sextus' discussion, Diogenes' account - as we might by now expect - is
492e and appears also in Sextus, PH 3.229 as part of an argument against in contrast much less nuanced and much more truncated.
the claim that death is bad per se . The question obviously has an epistemo As at Sextus, M 7.126, so too in Diogenes 9.73, Empedocles is followed
logical emphasis, but we might note in passing a similar thought attributed by Heraclitus. Diogenes cites without further comment only one fragment
to Pyrrho at Stobaeus 4.53.28 (=T19 Decleva Caizzi): "living and dying do - 847 - where Heraclitus is interpreted as advising against mere conjec
not differ" (111erle11 dinplterein). When he was then asked why he did not tures (eike) about the 'greatest matters'. Presumably, this is intended as
simply end his life, Pyrrho replied: "Because it does not differ" (011rleir rli an anticipation of the recommendation to suspend judgment rather than
nplterez). Pyrrho's claims seem to me more ethical in nature and perhaps form insufficiently reliable beliefs about important matters.33 Then Dio
are based on the idea that there is no difference in value between being genes offers a rather cryptic comment about Hippocrates, who apparently
alive and being dead.3 1 On this occasion in 9.73, Diogenes' Euripidean offered his view 'in a doubtful' or 'uncertain fashion' (e11rloinslos) and 'in
quotation continues the theme of a contrast between mistaken or uncer a manner appropriate for a (mere) human' (n11tltropi11os).34 We have seen
tain human opinions and an alternative correct divine account.32 enough to imagine that the second of these continues one of the principal
tl1emes of the passage. Enrloinzo and its cognates do not appear elsewhere
29 There is also no mention of any sceptical consequences of atomism in the Life of Le11-
cip1'11s. in Diogenes or Sextus, although it is used commonly enough elsewhere
JO The famous qualifications in 29b-d may themselves reflect an engagement with Xeno to mean something like 'to be uncertain' or 'to waver between competing
phanes' epistemology and with B35 in particular: sec BRYAN 2012. for the Academic options or conclusions' and also occurs in Hippocratic texts, sometimes
Cicero's treatment of Ti111ne11s 29b-d see, most recently, D. N. ScoJ.EY, "Cicero and the with the sense of a patient being in a precarious state that could either im
Ti11111c11s", in: M. Sc11orrnto (ed.), Aristotle, P/11/0 n11rl Pyll111gorem1is111 i11 tile Firs/ Ce11l11ry BC.
New Dircclio11s for Plrilosoplry (Cambridge 2013) 1 1 87-2051 202-4. Scxtus attacks Academic prove or deteriorate (e.g. Epidemics 1 .2). But in fact, Diogenes or his source
interpretations of Plato as a sceptic at PH 1.221-35, a passage which includes a brief dis
cussion of how Timon shows only qualified approval of Xcnophanes. alongside it: "The gods did not from the outset reveal all things to mortals but, by inquir
31 This is probably to be related to the general sense in many of the anecdotes about ing, in time mortals improve in their discoveries." On gods and men in Xenophanes sec j.
Pyrrho's life that he was indifferent to various things that most other people would pursue WARllEN, "Gods and Men in Xenophancs", in: V. HARTE I M. LANE (eds.), Politcin i11 Greek
or avoid. And it may also relate to the notoriously controversial claim - whid1, depending n11rl Ro111n11 Pililosopily (Cambridge 2013) 294-312.
on a much-debated emendation of 1011/0 to lo, is either an opening premise or else a conclu 33 111e Pyrrhonists, particularly Aenesidemus, had a complicated relationship with Her
sion of an argument based on the unreliability of the senses - that 'things' (prngmntn) arc aclitus. See e.g. Sextus, PH 1 .210-12 and Sc110F1F.1.n 2007.
'indifferent' (nrlial'Jwm): see Aristocles "1' Eus. Prncl'. c'lln11g. 14.18.3, 14.1 8.5.2 and 1 4. 18.7.1 :i. The text here is disputed. DollANDJ 2013 retains the MSS: epciln; MAncov1c11 1999
( F4 CIJJP.SAllA).
= prefers R1c1 1A 1ms' csliu Jin. H 1cKs 1925 translates: " ... shows himself as two sided and
32 Perhaps Xenophanes too should be included as an example of this thought, particu merely human"; B11uNsc11w1c 1999 has " . . . se prononce de faon dubitative et qui convient
larly if we emphnsise the reference to /is 1111i!r at the beginning of B34 and remember B18 a un hommc."
120 fames W11rreu Precursors of l'yrrlw11is111: Diog. L11crt. 9.67-73 121

has a specific text in mind. At Prorrlzetiko11 2.3, the Hippocratic author is with Homer and the chosen quotations have various thematic interests in
discussing medical predictions, their claims of accuracy and the spirit in common. It is, of course, not a convincing portrait of a long-lasting tradi
which they ought to be interpreted. He argues that even if some medical tion of sophisticated sceptical thinking before Pyrrho. But it does outline
prognoses have turned out to be accurate, we should nevertheless bear in various ways in which Pyrrhonism relates to earlier concerns about the
mind that at the time they were made they were asserted "tentatively and possibility of acquiring knowledge and the difficult task of dealing with
in a manner appropriate to humans" (e11doinstos te kni m1tlzropi11os).35 This the often varied and conflicting appearances we receive about the world.
is clearly an attitude that would chime well with Pyrrhonist views.
Finally, Diogenes comes back to Homer, giving this section some kind
Appendix
of ring-composition. This time, Diogenes quotes Iliad 20.248-50: Aeneas is
speaking to Achilles. Aeneas says that the two of them can, i f Achilles likes, Citation in Diogenes 9.67-73 Citation in Sextus, M7
trade accounts of their respective noble lineages_. But this would serve no Homer II. 16.1'16 (9.67) Ori. 18.1 36-7 (7.128)'
purpose. First, no one can be sure that such boasts are true. Second, even i f II. 21.106 (9.67)
are true they count for nothing in battle. Poseidon steps i n to whisk Aeneas
II. 20.248-50 (9.73)
Archilochus 131 West (9.71) 131 West (part) (7.128)
away from danger. Diogenes comments that in these lines Homer is talk
Euripides S11pplim1ts 735-7 (9.72) Tro. 885 (7.128)
ing about 'equipollence' (isostlzenein) and 'opposed statements' (n11tithesis fr. 638 N2 (9.72) Pliom 469 (7.50)
logo11). Presumably, the idea is that Aeneas and Achilles will not resolve Xenophanes B34 (9.72) B34 (7.50 and 7.110)
their dispute by trading accounts of their ancestry since their speeches will Democritus B9 (9.72) B9 (7.135)
Bl 17 (9.72) [alluded to at Cic. BIO (7.136)
carry equal weight. This is then taken to be an example of a more general
Acnd. 1.44] B6 (7.136)
problem, perhaps a problem faced in particular when we are dealing with B7 (7.136)
conflicts between noble and skilled opposing philosophical views.36 In any B8 (7.136)
case, the mention of isosthe11ein provides something of a bridge into the next Bl 1 (7.138)
section of the text in which Diogenes turns to explain various sceptical for B3 (7.139)
Zeno of Elea B! (9.72)
mulae.
Plato Ti. 40d (9.72) Ti. 27d (7.142)
Our discussion has been somewhat piecemeal, perhaps inevitably so Empedocles B2.7-8 and 2.5 (9.73) 8109 (7.120)
given the brief and somewhat staccato nature of Diogenes' list. Neverthe B2 (7.123)
less, there are some themes and general observations that we can high B4 (7.125)
J-!eraclitus B47 (9.73) Al6 (7.126)
light. For the most part, in the cases of those members of the list who
B48 (9.73) Bl (7.12)
also have independent Lives in Diogenes' work, the interpretations of the B2 (7.133)
epistemological views outlined here in 9.67-73 are not emphasized in the
corresponding Life. This might suggest that the source Diogenes is using
here in book nine is not one he regularly checked when composing other
parts of his work. Furthermore, what might at first glance have seemed a
somewhat chaotic jumble with no chronological or obvious thematic struc
ture, in fact displays some signs of coherence despite the obvious effects of
concision. It aims at a kind of ring-composition by beginning and ending

35 Prorr/1et. 2.3: bo1Cic.J bE auTwv El 'tl c.\ATj8c; AryETm 'tWVbE TWV 7tQi rnuc; yuva
l;oivouc;, iKE ivwv Tcv 11QOTEQOV ycyQaivc.JV, 7tQCTOV iv 'tWV C1f]dc.iv wv ,\ iyc.i
TEK tiQlta8m rniho yvovTa, E11ffICX [vbrnaauc: 'tE Kai c:iv8QW1tLVw.; 1tQOEl7tELV, aa b{
1mi TOUC: c.irrayy(,\,\ovrnc: 'tEQCX'tCubW'tEQWC: btfj)'Eia8m we: i)ivTO.
36 Again, we should notice the reference to the tendency of mortals (/Jrotoi 20.248) to
concoct many varied tales. Also, it is possible that the reference to the 'wide pasture (po/us
110111os) of words' in 20.249 is chosen because it chimes with the interest in custom and
convention seen earlier in quotations from Democritus (1101116i: B9 at 9.72) and Euripides
2
(11omizefni: fr. 638 Nauck at 9.73).
Mind and Language of the Laertian Pyrrhonist:
Diog. Laert. 9.74-77
Lorenzo Corti

1 . Introduction

The Pyrrhonian sceptic1 makes no judgements and has no beliefs; if so,


how could he speak? Different versions of this question animated a lively
debate between the ancient non-sceptic philosophers (or Dogmatists) and
their sceptic adversaries. The debate is echoed in the account of the scepti
cal use of language provided by our extant sources for ancient Pyrrhonism:
Sextus Empiricus, the most important source, devotes several passages to
the sceptic's speech acts, in particular the section on the sceptical phrases
or cpwvai in PH 1.187-208; and his later contemporary Diogenes Laertius
dedicates several sections of his Life of Pyrrlw (in particular Diog. Laert.
9.74-7) to the same subject. But if the Sextan account of the sceptic's lin
guistic behaviour has provoked much scholarly attention,2 Diogenes' par
allel pages have elicited just some scattered remarks. Still, it has been em
phasised that at least some of them deserve more attention than scholars
have given them so far.3 The aim of this paper is to contribute towards fill-

1 Ancient scepticism had two main varieties: the Pyrrhonian, inaugurated by Pyrrho of
Elis, and the Academic, associated with a particular historical phase of Plato's Academy.
In this paper I will deal exclusively with Pyrrhonian scepticism and will use the words
'scepl'ic' and 'scepticism' to refer to this variety only.
2 Cf. BunNYEAT 1980, 23-7; I'. D Esno noEs, "Le langage sceptique. Notes sur le CoJJlre lcs
gr1111111111irie1Js de Sextus Empiricus", Lm1gnge 1 6 (1982) 47-74; Ch. SrnuG11, "Sextus Empir
icus on Non-Assertion", P/Jro11csis 29 (1984) 137-64; BAl!NES 1990, 2623-26; J. BRUNSCllWIG,
"La formule lwso11 cpi to logo chez Sextus Empiricus", in: A. J. VoELKE (ed.), Le Sccpticisme
n11tiq11c: perspectives /Jistoriq11cs et systc111ntiq11es. Cahiers de la Revue de Thcologie et de
Philosophie 15 (Geneve et al. 1990) 107-21 (English trnnsl. in: BnuNsc11w1G 1994, 244-58)
and J. BnuNsc11w1G, "L'aphasie pyrrhonienne", in: C. LEvY I L. PrnNoT (eds.), Dire l't!1ideuce
(p/Jilosop/Jic et rl11!toriq11c m1tiq1Jcs). Cahiers de philosophic de l'Universi!e de Paris XII - Val
de-Marne 2 (Paris I Montreal 1997) 297-320; E. SPINELLI, "Sceptics and Language: phonai
and 16goi in Sextus Empiricus", Hisloirc Epistt!mologie Lm1g11ge 13/11 (1991) 57-70; VOGT 1998;
Cmm 2009; S. MARCHAND, "Sextus Empiricus' Style of Writing", in: D. MACllUCA (ed.), New
Essm1s 011 A11cirnt Pyrr!m11is111 (Leiden 2011) l 13-41; J. Tunru, "Pyrrhonian Skepticism Meets
Speech-Act Theory", 111tcr11ntio11nl /01mrnl for t/Jc Study of Skcpticism 2,2 (2012) 83-98; on the
sceptical formula oubi'v C.A,\nv see the studies indicated i11fm at n. 31.
J See BARNES 1992, 4257, ii propos Diog. Laert. 9.1 02-5 - a passage of crucial importance
for the understanding of sections 74--7.
124 Lowz:o Corti Mind and Lm1g1wgc of tire Laerlinn Pyrrl1011ist: Diog. Lnert. 9.74-77 125

ing this gap by analysing and elucidating the Laertian account in the light (ngocpgw8m Kai bLTJYE'ia8m). He then stresses that the sceptic utters
of the closest Laertian and Sextan loci similes. his expressions to show (briAouv) some of his psychological states (rraGri):
Diog. Laert. 9.74-7 may be divided into four main parts. Diogenes absence of precipitation and inner balance.
starts by characterising the sceptics as being devoted to a certain philo I suggest that we should understand section 74 in the light of sections
sophical activity: they overturn all the tenets of the philosophical schools. 102-4. Having provided an account of the Pyrrhonian attack against some
In doing so, they speak - they utter some characteristic phrases. In the rest central concepts and tenets of the dogmatic schools - proofs (9.90-1), crite
of our passage, Diogenes reports some remarks indicating how we are sup ria of truth (9.94-5), sign-inferences (9.96-7), causes (9.97-9), motion (9.99),
posed to understand these phrases. In the first section (74) he points out learning and teaching (9.100), coming into being (9.100), ethics (9.101) -
that the sceptic does not affirm or determine what he says, but just utters Diogenes reports a dogmatic objection5 followed by a sceptic reply.6 I take
and reports; he then adds that the sceptic's <pwvai - of which he mentions the former to run as follows. The sceptic holds no scientific or philosophi
"In no way more", "We determine nothing" and "Opposed to every ac cal tenets (b6ypm:a) and devotes himself to refuting (bLEAEyxELv) those of
count there is an account" - express some affections of his. The second scientists and philosophers. But precisely the fact that he carries out this
part of the passage (section 75) discusses several uses of the expressions activity implies that he holds some theoretical views. In particular, the
"more/rather" and "in no way more", and indicates that the sceptics use fact that, in the course of his refutation, he says things like "I determine
"in no way more" negatively. The following part (76) discusses the self nothing" or "Opposed to every account there is an account" entails that
applying property of two sceptical expressions in particular: "In no way he determines and holds some views: namely that he determines nothing
more" and "Opposed to every account there is an account". Finally, in the and that opposed to every account there is an account.
last section of the passage (77), Diogenes hints at a dogmatic reaction to The sceptic's reply may in my interpretation be analysed in four dif
the description of the sceptic's linguistic behaviour just sketched and puts ferent steps and represented as follows. First, two kinds of items are dis
forward another one of its feah1 res, by indicating how the sceptic uses his tinguished: what the sceptic feels and how things appear to him on one
words and statements. hand, and the non-evident things the Dogmatists make affirmations about
In the following pages I will put forward an analysis of each of the four (btaEmoua8m) on the other. The sceptic knows what he feels and what
sections and of the major features they ascribe to the sceptical <pluvaL I appears to him (for example, that it is day, that he lives, that he sees, that he
will end by discussing an intriguing difference between the account of the knows something); by contrast, he suspends his judgement on non-evident
Pyrrhonist we find in Diogenes and the corresponding account we find in matters such as scientific claims purporting to explain how he sees or how
Sextus. he knows - and therefore believes and knows nothing on the subject. Now
when the sceptic utters phrases about the first kind of items - saying for
example "The flag looks white to me" - he does that in a purely descrip
2. The sceptic does not affirm, but reports his feelings: tive fashion (btT]Yllta-rucwc;) and does not affirm (btaEmoua8m) that
Diog. Laert. 9.74 and 102-4 the flag really is white. And even when he pronounces on dogmatic claims
about non-evident items, saying for example "I determine nothing", he is
So let us start with section 74:1 How are we supposed to understand the not thereby committed to holding what he says. For saying "I determine
typical phrases uttered by the sceptic during his activity of overturning the nothing" is not like saying "The cosmos is spherical": the latter is non
tenets of the philosophical schools - phrases like "I/We determine noth evident, the former a confession (Ei;o10Aoyrimc;).
ing", "In no way more" and "Opposed to every account there is an ac Let me emphasise the structural similarities between 9.74 and 9.102-4.
count"? Diogenes starts by pointing out that the sceptic does not affirm Both passages provide a characterization of the sceptic's phrases - in par
(cmo<pa[vw8m) or determine what he says, but just utters and reports it ticular, of formulae like "I/We determine nothing", "Opposed to every ac
count there is an account", which he utters in the course of his attack on
1 For the Greek text of Diog. Laert. I refer t o the edition b y Dorandi included i n this
volume, indicating when I follow an alternative reading. As far as section 74 is con
the dogmatic tenets. An element common to both characterizations is the
cerned, at lines 166-7 I follow B1tuNsc11w1c 1999 (1111, n. 2) and excise TCt n;iv lt1\1\cuv after claim that the sceptic does not affirm what he says. In 104 the claim that
TIQrnpiQrnOm. For the translation of the Lai!rtian passages see the translation by Scharf
fenberger and Vogt in the present volume, with a caveat: I understand some words and 5 See Diog. Laert. 9.102, lines 468-73.
" See Diog. Laert. 9.102{line 474)-1 04(line 488). At 103(1ine 477) I accept Marcovich's
sentences in the Lai!rtian text differently from the way they do: for each of them I offer my
own translation or paraphrase. conjecture and read ciAAa b TIQi wv after ytvc;imw v.
126 Lorenzo Corti Millrl mzrl Lrng1111gc of the Lni!rlim1 Pyrrlzonist: Diog. Laat. 9.74-77 127

they are confessions corresponds to the claim in 74 that the sceptic's cpwva[ n i:v i:'KCCO'TOV cpccivi:: raL n-;.,v unoKE Ldvwv), but cannot "assert what it is
show his affections. in its nahire" (-r[ bf. EO'Tl we; 11QOc; TV cpumv 0:11ocr11vaa8m). Let us focus
Diog. Laert. 9.102-4 suggests that the characterization of the sceptical on what the sceptic cannot do. In PH Sextus often observes that, as a con
phrases put forward in 74 is to be understood as the sceptic reaction to sequence of his use of the modes, the sceptic cannot affir111 that the object
a dogmatic objection. In order to get clearer on both, let us turn to Sex of his inquiry has the property that is under consideration in the inquiry.
tus' account of the sceptic's mental attitude and linguistic behaviour. The The verbs used by Sextus for 'affirming' are the same we found in Diog.
sceptic is an inquirer capable of suspending his judgement on any issue of Laert. 9.74 and 103, that is btal3El3moua8m (see for example PH 3.55; 128;
his inquiry. He asks: "Is it the case that p?" where p is a proposition con 140; 182; 249; cf. PH 1 .35; 226) and O:nocpaivw8m (PH 1.87). How can Sex
cerning one of the non-evident objects the Dogmatists hold tenets about tus infer, from the fact that the sceptic suspends judgment on the question
- things like Providence or the atoms ("Does Providence exist?", "Is the whether it is the case that p (that is, cannot judge that p nor that not-p), that
world made of atoms and void?").7 As a meticulous inquirer, he collects he cannot affir111 that p? The standard way of characterizing the linguistic
whatever can be taken to speak for each of the two possible answers to his act of affirming something is that of 'manifesting a judgment'; so if some
question and considers it in the light of the modes of suspension of judge one utters a phrase affirming it, he manifests having judged its content to
ment. And here bwxtj supervenes; i t appears8 to the sceptic that neither be true. Affirming implies judging; but a sceptic cannot judge; therefore
of the two claims is more persuasive than the other: he can judge neither he cannot affirm. 1 0
that p nor that not-p.9 We may get other crucial features of the Sextan characterization of the
The psychological state of suspension of judgement has consequences sceptic's linguistic behaviour by focusing on the remarks he makes about
on the sceptic's linguistic behaviour - consequences which Sextus indi the sceptical <pwval. The crucial passage is PH 1.15. Commenting on the
cates, in particular, in the sections where he presents the modes of sus sceptical phrases like "In no way more" and "I determine nothing" (which
pension of judgement (PH 1.36-186). A paradigmatic passage is PH 1.87: he addresses further in PH 1.187-208) Sextus indicates that
the Pyrrhonist, who suspends his judgement on the question whether it is "in uttering these phrases they [sc. the sceptics! say what appears lo them and report
the case that p, can say "how each of the existing things appears to him" (6 their own feelings without holding opinions, affirming nothing about the external ob
jecls."11
7 Sextus often refers, sometimes confusingly, lo a dogmatic distinction between evident
and non-evident items of knowledge, which he reports in P/-/ 2.97-8 and in M 8.145-7. The
The sceptic, after having examined incompatible dogmatic claims (call
distinction might be expressed as follows: (i) it is evident lox a l t that p iffx can know that them p and not-p), reaches E11ox11 and says: "In no way more p than not-p".
p directly al t, without using an inference, whether on the basis of perception or through He thereby says what appears to him: the phrase he utters describes his
some sort of intellectual intuition; (ii) it is by nature non-evident to x that p iffx can know feeling ("In no way does p appear to me more persuasive than not-p"), and
that JI only by means of an inference - on the basis of other pieces of knowledge of his. for
instance, it is evident lo me now that it is raining: I can come lo know that it is raining just
not the properties possessed by some objects external to his psychologi
by looking out of the window. 13y contrast, it is by nature non-evident to me that there cal states ("In no way is p more persuasive than not-p").12 Furthermore,
are invisible pores in my skin. I can come to know that only by making an inference from in uttering this phrase, the sceptic affirms nothing, but reports a feeling
another piece of knowledge I possess: for instance, my justified belief that I sweat. for of his. Sextus puts forward here a double characterization of the scepti-
discussion and references see L. CORTI, "Hidden Causes: Ancient Sceptics and Doctors
and Modern '!11inkers on the Pcrccivability of Causal Links", in: C. NATALI / C. V1ANO
(eds.), Ailia I/. Awe 011 s1111s Aristolc. L; rlJ/111/ s11r /cs cn1Jscs 1l /'age /1d/e11istiq11c et i11rpfria/ 1t1
For discussion and further references see Co1n1 2009, 1 1 2-16.
(Louvain-la-Neuve forthcoming). 1 1 Sextus,
PH 1.15: i:v Ttj Tt(lO<f'O(l< u:..v cp1.JV1:..v rnuTc..iv TO iaun;> cpmv6[vov Aiyn
8 The verb cpaivEnBm ('to appear I to seem') may be used lo express the fact that one 1mi TO mlEJo.; anllyy(,\J\n Tll EllUTOU ciboE.c1CTTfaJ<'.;, qbi:v Tt[(/i TC;>v rE.u>BEv UTCOKlfJ lVhl\I
is inclined lo believe something. But it may also be used differently, in a plzerwmenologicai b111f3cf3r.l1oucvo.;. For U1is and the other Sexlan passages quoted I offer the Greek text
way, lo denote the fact that things appear in a certain way - which does not imply being edited by MuTSCl lMANN I MAU 1958 and the translation by AN NAs / BAtt NES 2000 (sometimes
inclined lo believe something. ("I ran half an hour to reach the cinema and have the im slightly modified, as in the present case).
pression that it is really hot: I am not inclined to believe that it is hot - nor that it isn' t - but 12 In conformity with this indication, when commenting on the sceptical phrases which
that is how I feel now"; "That argument looks sound - but don't be taken in by it.") The display a universal quantifier (phrases like "Everything is undetermined"), Sextus will
impressions or appearances (cpavTaaim) at stake in the sceptic texts this article comments carefully indicate that its domain includes only the dogmatic claims actually examined
on are psychological events of the latter kind: sec J. 13AttNES, "Aristotle and the Methods by the sceptic, of which he had the impression that they arc no more persuasive than their
of Ethics", Revue hrtcrw1tiorurie de Plii/osoplii 34 (1980) [490-5 1 1 ] 491 n. 1; BunNYEAT 1980, opposites and on which he suspended his judgement: d. /'/-1 1 .193; 198-9; 200; 202; 208.
34--5; BARNES 1990, 2623; Co1n1 2009, 13-14; 58-64. Elsewhere, however, Scxtus takes the universal quantifier to include every dogmatic claim:
'' Sec P/-1 1 .ll, 8-1 I; cf. BARNES 1990, 2609-11 and Co1m 2009, 16-23, with references. see i11fra, section 4.
128 Loren=o Corti Mind 1111d La11g11age of tire Lni!rtia11 Pyrr/1011ist: Diog. Lnert. 9.7'1-77 129

cal phrases, grounded on a double distinction. The first is the se111a11tic We may now put forward t11e main features of the Sextan characterization
distinction between phrases describing the speaker's feelings and phrases of the sceptic speech acts. The sceptic's phrases have a certain meaning:
describing objects external to the speaker. The second distinction concerns they mean a proposition of t11e form "It appears to me now tl1at P". The
the illocutionary force with which the sceptic utters his phrases: whether sceptic utters these phrases with a certain illocutionary force: he does not
he affirms what he says or does something else.13 affirm them - manifesting a judgement he has made- but expresses or con
All throughout his characterization of the sceptical phrases, Sextus fesses his characteristic psychological state, that of having a certain appear
claims that the sceptical cpcuva( show or indicate the sceptic's feelings11 ance, when he has it. Why does Sextus put forward this characterization of
- and that is, what appears to him to be the case. This is particularly evi the sceptic's linguistic acts? We find an answer in Pl-1 1.200, where Sextus
dent in PH 1.187-208. When he introduces all the sceptical cpcuva(, Sextus deals with the phrase "Everything is inapprehensible". Sextus, having in
says that they show a condition (btC.:8wtc;) and a feeling (nC.:8oc;) of the dicated the meaning and the illocutionary force of the phrase in conformity
sceptic (PH 1.187); he then says of some of them that they show a feeling with the above mentioned distinctions, concludes that the anti-sceptical
of the sceptic, or that the sceptic uses them in order to show that he feels a charges of 'self-refutation' ('TTE Ql't{JOmi) misconstrue the sceptical expres
certain way (PH 1.193; 194-5; 197; 201); and, commenting on other phrases, sions.18
he says first that they show a feeling of the sceptic (or that the sceptic uses This passage clearly indicates that the Sextan characterization is to be
them to show that he feels a certain way, or in lieu of a phrase which means understood as the sceptic reaction to a dogmatic charge of pragmatic (il
that he feels a certain way), and then that he uses them to show that things locutionary) self-refutation, which we may reconstruct from Sextus' re
appear to him in a certain way (PH 1 .196; 198-9; 200; 202-3). By saying that ply. The sceptic says 'P'; so surely he affirms that P. But affirming that P
the phrase uttered by the sceptic shows a feeling (an impression) of his, amounts to manifesting to have judged and to believe that P. Now a sceptic
Sextus speaks both of the sense of the phrase (the sceptical phrase means by definition cannot judge and believe that P. So we have a contradiction:
a proposition of the form "It appears to me now that P"), and of the illocu a sceptic cannot say that P. We know Sextus' reply: the sceptic, saying 'P',
tionary force with which he utters his phrases (the sceptic does not affirm does 110/ affirm t11at P; he avows that he is having the impression that P.
something, but expresses a feeling he has).15 We are now able to provide an interpretation of the dogmatic linguis
So the sceptic does not affirm what he says, but just reports or an tic objection of incoherence expressed in Diog. Laert. 9.102 and of the
nounces (cmayyAAELv, btf]yEia8m) the impression he has, whe11 he has sceptic reaction witnessed in 102-4 and 74. The dogmatic objection refers
it.16 The non-affirmative illocutionary force with which the sceptic utters to the charge of pragmatic (illocutionary) self-refutation we have just men
his phrases has been greatly clarified by Barnes, who suggests understand tioned. And the sceptic's reply runs as follows. Let us distinguish between
ing the sceptic's speech acts in terms of Wittgenstein's ' AuBerung' or 'Aus two items: the feelings we have, and the non-evident objects the Dogma
druck' - mere expression of a feeling: tists theorize about. When we utter phrases containing terms tJ13t denote
"Children cry when they are in pain: they thereby express their pain, but they do not the first kind of items, phrases like "The flag looks white to me", we do
state that they arc in pain . . . Adults, when they are in pain, may utter the sentence ' I
a m in pain' or some vulgar equivalent: they thereby express their pain, but they d o not 16 PH 1.200: "Our attitude is similar when we say 'Everything is inapprehensible': we
. . . state that they are in pain (they state nothing at all). The Pyrrhonist of PH, when
explain 'everything' in the same way, and we supply 'to me'. Thus what is said is this: 'All
he is mentally affected, may utter the sentence 'The tower seems round': he thereby
of the non-evident matters investigated in dogmatic fashion which 1 have inspected appear
expresses his mi8oc, but he docs not state that he is experiencing a certain nc.l8oc (he
to me inapprehensible.' This is not to make an affirmation that the matters investigated by
docs not state anything at all)."17
the Dogmatists are of such a nature as to be inapprehensible; rather, it is to report our
feeling 'in virtue of which', we say, 'I suppose that up to now I have not apprehended any
of U1cse things because of the cquipollcncc of their opposites.' Hence everything brought
forward to turn us about seems to me to be at a variance with what we profess" (Oun.1
1
3 This semantic and illocutiooary characterization of the sceptic's speech acts also ap bE: tpt(.lr'>E8a 1mi ornv Aiyi..orv 'nitvrn fOTiV Llh:CTTiiA1prn.' 1mi yit(l TO 'ni\vn.t' ooiw.::
peilTS in PH 1 .200. Elliptical formulations of it arc to be found in PH 1.4; 191; 196; 197; 199; U.riyouc8a 1cai To 'ioi' auvrnliEx6c8a, ,;i.:: Elvm TO AEyr'>vov T01ournv 'm\vTa oaa
203; 208: see Cairn 2009, 1 1 6-19 for details and discussion. icpc.;JbEUrm Tc;1v lioyan1((;_,; l;:11rnuivi..1v 1tb1jAi.1v cpaivETai 01 ii1mTaA11nrn.' TOIJTO be
1
4 The verbs used by Scxtus arc liriAow and rivui..1; Diogcns makes the same claim using (nT1v ou b1apEpmouivou TCEQi wu n'l nu(.lcx rnic boyc.lTJKoic CrirnuEva cpucnc.>.:: Elvm
b11A6w and a cognate of rivui.>, 1ivumc: (d. Diog. Laert. 9.74). T01auT11c c:...c dvmitKaTiiA1prn, 1.\,\,\1x i:o fournu m't 8oc itnayyiA,\ovrnc, 1mfl' 6, 1p11aiv,
15 For further discussion and references see Co nn 2009, 119-25. unoAapkcvr.1 OTI CtX(.ll VLJV oulii:v Kc.n(Ac1pov EKdW.iV eye;> li11'i TllV Tt;1v 1.\vrncnivc,JV
16 Cf. PI-I 1 .4; 193; 196; 197; 201. inoa8(VE1CTV 68EV 1mi Tll de: 7TC(11T(l07TllV q>EQOEva 7lll\1Tll timliOVTCT dvm liOKEi m
17 BA1tN1's 1990, 2625; for a discussion of this interpretation see Co11T1 2009, 148-60. i:1;1v i!Cp' 1;11;1v cim.l)')'E,Ll.n[vi.JV).

I
I
130 Lore11zo Corti Mi11d n11d Lm1g11ngc of tile Lni!rtim1 Pyrrlw11isl: Diog. l..t1crt. 9.7'1-77 131

not affirm that the flag really is white - we just report or avow our feeling tions; and when oubi::v aAAov is used avmQE'ItKwc; the sentence where it
according to which the flag is white. And even when we say "We deter appears will express the conjunction of two negations.
mine nothing", we do not refer to a non-evident object: we talk about what If we read the first part of 75 in the light of these remarks, we may un
we feel (since 'nothing' here means 'none of the dogmatic claims we have derstand it as follows: oubi::v aAAov is said 8i::nKwc;, to show that two
examined'), and we just confess it - we do not affirm it. Both the dogmatic things are similar: in this case, the sentence where it appears amounts to a
objection and the sceptic reply are placed at the level of illocutionary force. conjunction of assertions ("The pirate is no worse than the liar" = "The pi
rate is bad and the liar is bad"). The sceptic however uses oubf:v a1\1\ov
avmQE'ILKwc;, as it is used by someone who rejects something and says:
3. The Pyrrhonist uses ovbev pa.N\ov negatively: "Scylla existed no more than the Chimera did". In this case, the sentence
Diog. Laert. 9.75 where ou(bi::v) C'ct\1\ov appears amounts to a conjunction of negations:
"Scylla did not exist and the Chimera did not exist".21 So surely this text
Section 75 is structured in two parts: indicates that the sceptic, when he applies this expression to incompatible
(a) the expression oubi::v 1a1\Aov ('in no way more') may be said affirma dogmatic claims and says, for example, "Providence exists no more than
tively (8E'IL1Cwc;); the sceptic does not use it that way, but negatively it does not", is saying "It is the case neither that Providence exists nor that
(CcVCtlQE'IllCWc;). it does not exist".
(b) The expression a1\Aov ('rather/more') is used sometimes in a com This is the way the passage has been understood in secondary literature
parative way (auyKQL'IlKwc;), and sometimes affirmatively and neg so far.22 However, this is odd. For Diogenes has just said that the scep
atively (8nucwc; Keti avmQE'ItKcc;). tical ou 1aAAov sentences express a m\8oc; of CtQQE\fiia or inner balance
(74), and will suggest that it means "to determine nothing and withhold
To get clearer on (a), Jet us start from (b). The text clearly states here that
assent" (76).23 And even if we think, as some do,24 that other parts of the
Laertian account of the Pyrrhonist characterize him as a negative dogma
- aAAov can be used auyKQtrnccc;, and in this case the sentence where it
tist (as someone who, having refuted the existence of place, accepts that
occurs expresses a relation of comparison: an object possesses a property to
place does not exist), this would clash with taking him to accept conjunc
a higher degree than another object: F > xy; for instance, "Honey is sweeter
tions of negations of the form pA ( p) In other words, the commonly
.., .., .., .

than a raisin";19
- a1\Aov can be used 8nucwc; Kni L'i VCtlQEHK<;H:;, and in this case the sen
21 Diogenes, here, illustrates the negative use of ot"1bi:v i ' v\,\ov ('In no way more') made
tence where it occurs does not express a relation of comparison. For it
by the sceptics by means of a phrase which does not contain this expression, but the expres
amounts to the conjunction of an affirmation and a negation: GxAFx; for sion ou a,\Aov ('No more'): ov paA1\ov 11 I:Kl>1\,\a yiyovrv fj fj Xim<.>a ("Scylla existed
example, "Virtue helps rather than harms", which means "Virtue helps no more than the Chimera did"). This might be explained by the fact that the Pyrrhonists
and does not harm".20 treat the two expressions as equivalent, as Sextus indicates at P/-1 1.188: "This phrase [sc.
'No more'], then, we utter sometimes in the form I have given and sometimes in the form 'Jn
no way more'. It is not the case, as some suppose, that we use 'No more' in specific inves
Now this section on at\t\ov also seems to give us a clue on how to un tigations and 'In no way more' in generic ones; rather, we utter 'No more' and 'In no way
derstand the qualifiers 8cnKwc; and aVCtlQcnKwc;. If, when aAAov is more' indifferently, and will here discuss them as a single phrase" (TauTJ]V i:oivuv [sc. 'ou
used 8nucwc; Keti avmQETUac;, the sentence where it appears expresses a,\,\ov'] 6T t tv c;ic; i<pTJV TI(lO<pE(lOpEBa, 6Tt bt oiiTwc: 'oubi;v a1\Aov' oti yaQ c;,c; nvrc:
no comparative relation but the conjunction of a 8imc; (an affirmation) v11ot\a pavova1, Tl'jv i'v 'ov itAAov' EV rnic: E ibLKaic: l;.TjTfjawL TIUQaAapav o Ev, Tl'jv
bf. 'oiJbEV (t,\,\ov' EV Tai<; ")'EVLJmic;, ltt\,\' ab1acpOQCLIC: Tfjv TE 'oU pi\,\;\ov' 1mi Tl'jV 'oubi:v
and an avettQEmc; (a negation), then, when oub(v aAAov is used Gnucc;x;,
L\1\,\ov' TI(lO<p((l01rBcc, 1mi vuv c:.ic; TIE(li 1ac: bia1\rEcir Oa). In this and in the next lines
the sentence where it appears will express the conjunction of two affirma- I will indicate the fact the sceptics used the two expressions interchangeably by using the
formula ol>(btv) aMov.
19 Propositions of this form arc examined in Aristotle's To 'ics; for an analysis of Aris 22
l Cf. for example DE LACY 1958, 69; Srn1Krn 1983, 99; Wooo1w1:F 1988, 150; BllUNSCIJWIG
totle's account, sec for example E. CASAlll, "Note sulla logica arislolelica dclla compara 1999, 1112 n. 5; BETr 2000, 31 n. 34.
zione", Silc110 X (1984) 131-46; cf. Sturnm 1988, 511. 1.l Diog. Laert. 9.74: b1a Tfjc ouv ' ovb tv OQil;.orv' rpcvvfji:; TO Tfjc UQQf1im; rraBo<;

:w Cf. S1.u1rn1t l988, 51-5. This latter use of i


\1\,\ov is taken by Sluiler to throw light on b11Aourn1 6poiwc bi: 1m i 1na n;c; 'ou/Jtv aAAov' Kai T1;c 'rraVTi A6yc!-11\6yo<; itvTiKnTm'
one of the Stoic complex propositions reported by Diog. Laert. in 7.72: the proposition 1mi Taic; 6o imc:; 76: UfJlt LVEL ol>v l] cpr.ivri, 1mea rpqcn 1mi Tic.1v i:v n!J nuewv1, 'TlJ
"showing that something is the case more than something else" (lltLtumpuliv -rci i \,\,\uv T]bEv O(lii:nv, i
t AN itn(loaOnEiv'.
2'1
tt.':ic11a), an example of which is "It is rather day than night". Sec eh. 4. of Belt's contribution to this volume, with references.
132 Lorc11:0 Corl i Mi11d n11d Language of Ille Lni!rlimr Pyrrlrouisl: Diog. Lacrl. 9.74-77 133

accepted interpretation of the sceptic negative use of ou cCt\1\ov is con saying ayvow that p and cryvow that q - that is, "I do not know that p and
tradictory both with the Laertian account of this expression in 74 and 76, "
I do 11ot know that q .27
and with the Laertian account of the Pyrrhonist in 90-101. (Not to mention
Sextus, who explicitly denies that the sceptic uses ou at\t\ov to express a
4. The self-applying property of the Pyrrhonian
double negation - as the Democriteans do.)25
In order to get clearer on the matter, let us go back to the first part of u niversal formulae: Diog. Laert. 9.76
9.75: the sceptic uses ou(bi:v) l'ct\t\ov as someone who rejects something and
The struch1re of the passage is reminiscent of a chiasm: Diogenes starts by
says: "Scylla existed no more than the Chimera did". How does the rejecter
alluding to the self-applying property of "In no way more", and explains
use ou(bi:v) at\t\ov - what does the sentence he utters amount to? Brun
its meaning by quoting from Timon ("to determine nothing and maintain
schwig suggests that the text alludes to the following refutation: "Scylla
no position"); he then deals with the meaning and the effect of "To every
existed no more than the Chimera did; the Chimera did not exist; there
account" (which alludes to the equipollence of opposed accounts and en
fore Scylla did not exist either". But i f this is so, then the sentence at stake
tails suspension of judgement), and ends by discussing the self-applying
cannot mean "Scylla did not exist and the Chimera did not exist" (other
property of this phrase.
wise the refutation would be absurd: "Scylla did not exist and the Chimera .
Let us focus on the ascription, on Diogenes' part, of the self-applymg
did not exist; but the Chimera did not exist; therefore Scylla did not exist
property to "In no way more" and "To every account". In order to p
either"). If the text alludes to the refutation mentioned by Brunschwig, the
preciate Diogenes' remarks, it is particularly useful to compare them with
ou(bf:v) at\1\ov sentence must mean something different, namely that the
Sextus' parallel observations. Sextus ascribes the self-applying property to
two claims are on the same level - something like "The claim that Scylla
the universal sceptical phrases in two loci. At PH 1.14-15 he considers "In
existed is as persuasive as, or as believable as, or true as, the claim that the
no way more" and "I determine nothing", then focuses on the former and
Chimera existed".
finally generalizes his remarks on all the universal sceptical cpwva[ he will
If this is so, then the use of ou(bi:v) at\t\ov made by the rejecter is not
discuss at PH 1.187-208 (including "To every account"); and at the end of
so far from the use of ou(bi:v) cu\t\ov made by the sceptic according to
this discussion (PH 1.206) he directly addresses his remarks to all the uni
Sextus (and Diogenes himself). For, given a couple of incompatible dog
versal sceptical phrases. Let us give a sketch of the Laertian and the Sextan
matic claims, say p and q, this use amounts to saying: "It appears to me
observations about "In no way more" set side by side:
now that p is no more persuasive than q nor q than p - so that I can judge
"
neither that p nor that q . But why would Diogenes call this use of ou(bi:v)
at'v\ov 'negative'? Precisely because the sceptic uses it to express the fact
that he is incapable of giving his assent to p and q - and this is a double
negation. Despite appearances, Diogenes does not ascribe to the Pyrrhon
ist conjunctions of denials of opposite claims. Instead he ascribes to him
the standard conjunction of negations which, as Sextus reminds us, sus
pension of judgment may be expressed by: "Suspension of judgment gets
its name from the fact that the intellect is suspended so as neither to posit nor
27 Sextus, PH 1.191: "Thus, although the phrase 'In no way more' exhibits the distinctive
to reject anything because of the equipollence of the matters being investi
character of assent or denial. we do not use it in this way: we use it indifferently and
gated" (PH 1.19626 ); cf. PH 1.191: to say ou(bi:v) 1a1\t\ov p q amounts to in a loose way, either for a question or for 'I do not know which of hese things I should
assent to and which not assent to'" (t'] ouv 'oubtv C!AAov' cpcuVf] KllV _ E<pmvi:i
_ XCC(lCCICTf](lct
_
l (1Vtjcru,1c;, i1Eic; oux oiii:c.ic; aui:tj X(lWtE8':1, itAA' L11ccrp6(lw ccui:ij
cruy1ca-mElfoE"1c; 1) t
25 Scxtus, PH 1.213-14: "The Sceptics and the Dcmocriteans use the phrase 'No more' in illl(lCIAaitVOlfV KllL KllTllX(lf]CTTlf((;Jc;, r,i:ot avi:i nuaai:oc; 1'] avn TOU AEynv ayvoc"
different senses. The latter assign it the sense that neither is the case, we the sense that we i:iv1 i:v wuuuv XQTJ uuy1mmi: iEJwEJa 1, Tiv1 bt ij auy1mrni:iEJwEJm'. Fllowing ANNAS I
do not know whether some apparent thing is both or neither" (b1arpogcuc; 1iv101 xgc;ivTm BAnN"s 2000, 47 nn. ah and ai, I retain ouv with the MSS and auyKai:an8wEJm after the
i:t 'ot) Ci1\1\ov' cpwvtj oi n uKrnnKo i Kai oi t\ no i:ou t.110K(li10u EKivo1 tv ya(l ini ij with the Greek manuscripts). Isn't Scxtus denying here that the sccptic uses oubtv
i:ou lf]binoov dvm TLlTWUat Tiiv 1pwvtjv, ijic; bi ini i:ou ityvo[iV nOTE(lOV itcp6UQa . .
ak\ov in the way Diogenes labels itva1QCTtK1;1.;:? I-le is not: he ts not talkm about the
ou8 in(l6v n fon TC;iv cpmvo ivcuv). syntax and the sense of the sceptic ou(btv) C!A1\ov sentcncc and denymg . that tt aounts
. . . whrch the
26 Sextus, PH 1.196: ti inoxiJ bt E iQt']Tm itno i:ou i:m ' xw8a 1 i:ijv b1itvo1av c:.x; tju to a conjunction of negations; he is talkmg about the 11locut10nary force with
TlElivm n tjn itvm(lEiv Ilia i:ijv iuoaEJ[vnccv TC;iv Cqi:ou iv<.iv. sceptic utters it and denying that the sceptic affirms or denies anything.
134 Lom1:0 Corti Mi11d n11d L111g11ngc of Ilic Lnertitm Pyrrllo11i>t: Diog. L11crl. 9.74-77 135

Diog. Laerl. 9.76 Sextus, PH 1.14-1528 posed to defend the sceptic from the dogmatic charge of dogmatizing in
uttering his cpwval.
- Just as Providence exists no more than it - "In no way more" says that it too, along
Now let us deal with "To every account" (navTi Ac'ryc). This expres
does no!, so "In no way more" is no more with everything else, is no more so than
so than it is not so; not so; sion is the elliptical version of "Opposed to every account there is an ac
count" (navTi Aoy Aoyoc;: av'ttKHTm) which Diogenes refers to in 74
- so the sceptics abolish (ava1Qfiv) the - because of this, "In no way more" can
phrase "In no way more". cels itself along with everything else; and 102: all the Laertian remarks about the former should be taken to re
- so the sceptics utter their phrases in such
fer to the latter. The meaning of this Pyrrhonian formula can be greatly
a way that they are implicitly cancelled clarified by the remarks devoted by Sextus to its complete version, "Op
by themselves; posed to every account there is an equal account" (navTi Aoyc Aoyoc;: iaoc;
- therefore they cannot be said to have CtV'tLICELTm). Although the word Aoyoc;: may mean 'argument' (something
Myarn in uttering them. purporting to establish a given claim "by way of assumptions and conse
quence", as the Stoics characterized it), Sextus indicates that he takes it in
Three main differences are worth mentioning. First, Diogenes' reference the more general sense of something purporting to establish a claim 'in
to the parallel case of Providence does not explain why "In no way more" any way'. The Pyrrhonian formula, then, should be understood as fol
is no more so than it is not so. By contrast, Sextus offers an explanation of lows: for any consideration or account in favour of a given dogmatic claim
such a phenomenon - and his remark clarifies Diogenes' case: "In no way you can find an equally convincing consideration or account in favour of
more" says of a11y claim29 (for example, "Providence exists") that it is no another dogmatic claim, incompatible with the first.30 Let us now com
more so than not so - and therefore of itself, too. Second, Diogenes says pare the Laertian remarks about the self-applying property of "Opposed
rather vaguely that the sceptics abolish "In no way more", while Sextus to every account there is an account" with the Sextan observations on the
refers more precisely to its semantic and logical properties of being self self-applying property of the sceptical universal <p(vvai:
applying and self-cancelling. Third, Diogenes does not say a word about
the role of these remarks, while Sextus makes it very clear: they are sup- Diog. Laert. 9 .76 Sextus, PH 1.20631

- Opposed to "Opposed to every account - The sceptical phrases are cancelled along
there is an account" there is an account; with what they arc applied to - just as
211 Scxtus, PH 1.14-15: "Not even in uttering the Sceptical phrases about non-evident
- because of this (c;i.:;), "Opposed to ev purgative drugs do not merely drain the
matters - for example, 'In no way more', or 'I determine nothing', or one of the other humours from the body, but drive them
ery account there is an account" is over
phrases which we shall later discuss - do they hold beliefs. For if you hold beliefs, then selves out too along with the humours;
turned (m(JIT(JC.mdc;) by itself and de
you posit as real the things you arc said to hold beliefs about; but Sceptics posit these
stroyed after abolishing the other ac - so the sceptical phrases can be destroyed
phrases not as necessarily being real. For they suppose that, just as the phrase 'Everything
counts, by themselves;
is folse' says that it too, along with everything else, is folsc (and similarly for 'Nothing is
true'), so also 'In no way more' says that it loo, along with everything else, is no more so - just as the purgatives which, once - so we do not affirm definitely that they
than not so, and hence it cancels itself along with everything else. And we say the same of they have cleared out toxins from the arc true.
the other sceptical phrases. nlUs, if people who hold beliefs posit as real the things they body, are themselves eliminated and
hold belief about, while Sceptics utter their own phrases in such a way that they are im destroyed.
plicitly cancelled by themselves, then they cannot be said to hold beliefs in uttering them"
(a,\,\' oubi: iv 'tcfl 71QOCpEQW8a t TIEQi TWV abriAc.iv Tlt<; CTKETITIKCt<; <pwvitc;, o[ov TI'jv 'oubi: v
itAAov' r'J Ti]v 'oubi:v 6QiCc.i' r'J nva Twv iiMwv m(_li wv uau(_lov Ail.o v boyaTi i;Et.
6 i:v yitQ boyaTil;c.iv c;.ic; umtQXOV Ti8nm TO TI(litya EKclVO 0 AiyrrnL boyaTii;EtV,
6 bi: OKETITIKO<;: Titc; <pwvitc; Ti8TJOL rnurnc; oux c;.ic; TIUVTWC UTIUQXOUOUC u110Aapitvn 30 Sec PI-I 1.202-3; cf. ANNAS I BARNES 2000, 51 n. 205.
yt
'l (l OTI, c;iom(_l 1i 'rritVTa EaTi wbi]' cpwvr'J nit TWV tiN\c.iv Kai i:auTr'Jv i\'wbi] dvm
11 PH 1.206: "In the case of all the sceptical phrnses, you should understand that
,\(yc1, Kai i 'oubiv ia-r1v iu\1'j8ic;' 6oicuc,
oiiTcu<; Kai r'] 'oubi:v it,\,\ov' cTc'I n;,v itAAc.iv we do not ilffirm definitely that they ilre true - after all, we say that they can be de
1mi fou'tr;v 'Pl'JOL i itAAov dvm Kll i b.a rnino TOlc iiAAoic EaUTr']v OUITIEQIYQcX<pEL TO stroyed by themselves, being cancelled along with what they are applied to, just as
1>' UUTO Kai cni TWV t'iAAc.iv OICE71TlKC;,V <pwvc;,v Aiyoev. nAr'Jv it,\,\' d 6 boy aT ii;wv purgative drugs do not merely drain the humours from the body but drive themselves
Ti6TJOLV c;,.:: unc!cQxov rnino o boyaTil;CI, 6 bi: arcrnnKoc; Tit.:: <pc.JVl t .:: aurnii 71Qo<piQrTCH out too along with the humors" (rrEQi rram;JV yc'l(l Tc;1v mcrnrncc;,v <pc.JV<;Jv ircEivo XQr'J
c;J.:; 1>uvitpo u<p' auTwv m(_ll)'QCc<pmOm, ourc itv iv T 71(.>0<poQl;t 'tOUTc.iv boyaTil;nv 7l(.lOCIJ\fJ<pivm, on 7lC(li TOiJ 1U110ric aun'tc; dvm mtVThK OU b1a icpmou prOa, 0710lJ ye
AqOdfJ). 1mi i1cp' fllU'tC;JV ltlJTcIC llVCll(lCiaOm 1\E)'OJ.IEV 1>uvc.l00cll, UUITICQl)'(latpoivac fKElVOIC
29 That is, of any dogmatic claim: Sexhrs is considering the hypothesis that "In no way ITE(.li ,;,v AiyovTm, KaOcincQ Tit 1mOC1QTll<c 't Ti;1v cpo(lpltrcc.1v ou p uvov Touc xooi1c
more" is used as a self-applying dogmatic claim: sec i11fra. imec".mQEi wu m;11tnoc, ctAM 1 Kell rcwTit wic xuoic auveEciyn).
136 Lore11zo Corti Mi11d mul Lm1g11age of the Lni!rtim1 Pyrr!to11isl: Diog. Laa!. 9.N-77 1 37

There again, Diogenes does not explain why to "Opposed to every account Thus, both Diogenes and Sextus witness two strategies of defending
there is an account" an account is opposed. By contrast, Sextus' text hints the sceptic from the dogmatic charge that he affirms the universal formu
at the property of the sceptical phrases (including "Opposed to every ac lae he utters - and therefore shows that he believes them to be true. The
count there is an equal account") of being self-applying, and offers a way first amounts to indicating that the sceptic's universal formulae express his
of interpreting Diogenes' claim: being an account, "To every account an feeling of being unable to assent to any member of the couples of opposed
account is opposed" is self-applying and says that an account is opposed dogmatic claims he has considered. The second, that of the aumEQLYQC<Cp
to itself. (PI-1 1.14-15; 206; Diog. Laert. 9.76), amounts to arguing that all of the scep
What exactly does the logical property of the sceptical cpwvc<l hinted at tical universal formulae are self-cancelling - that is, that they are such that
in Diogenes' text amount to? In order to answer the question let us analyse if someone believes them to be true, then he does not believe them to be
its Sextan, fuller account. In PH 1.14-15, Sextus faces the same dogmatic true - and therefore unbelievable.
objection that is under discussion in Diog. Laert. 9.102. The sceptic ut Are the two strategies compatible? In the first, the sceptical phrase (say
ters phrases like "In no way more" or "We determine nothing" about non "ln no way more") is taken 110/ to be self-applying: for it refers to a feeling
evident objects - the dogmatic claims; he thereby affirms these phrases, of the speaker (meaning) and is not affirmed (illocutionary force), while the
that is, he shows that he judges and believes their content to be true. domain of its universal quantifier includes only claims concerning external
In section 2 we examined a way to defend the Pyrrhonist that appears non-evident objects (and not the speaker's impressions) that are affirmed.
both in Diog. Laert. (74 and 102-4) and in Sextus. This amounts to arguing By contrast, the second strategy implies that the sceptic universal formula
that the sceptical universal cpwvcc[ talk about the dogmatic claims actunlly falls within the scope of its quantificational domain, which includes formu
exn111i11ed by the sceptic speaker - and are confessions of a na8oc; experi lae describing non-evident objects (and not feelings of the speaker) that are
enced by him (in this case, "In no way more" stands for the non-dogmatic affirmed. The two strategies are not compatible. Still, we can save the co
phrase [Sl] "It appears to me now that, for any couple of incompatible dog herence of the sceptic's advocate, if we understand the strategies as two
matic claims about non-evident objects p and q which I have examined, p parts of a disjunctive answer. Either the sceptical universal phrase is self
is no more persuasive than q nor q than p - so that I can judge neither that applying, or i t is not. If i t is, then from the fact that the sceptic utters this
p nor that q"). In the passage we are examining, however, the defending phrase we cannot ascribe to the sceptic the corresponding belief. If it is
strategy of the reply is completely different. For both the Dogmatists in not, then it expresses a feeling. In that case, the sceptic does not affirm it
their objection and Sextus in his reply take "In no way more" to stand for and once again we cannot, from the fact that the sceptic utters this phrase,
a dogmatic claim: (S2) "For any couple of incompatible dogmatic claims p ascribe to the sceptic the corresponding belief.
and q about non-evident objects, p is no more persuasive than q nor q than p
- so that I can judge neither that p nor that q". The reply can be analysed as
5. How the Pyrrhonist uses his i\oyoL: Diog. Laert. 9.77
follows: "In no way more", understood as (S2), is a dogmatic claim: there
fore it is included in the domain of its universal quantifier. So (S2) says
The passage is structured in three parts. The first indicates the dogmatic
of itself what it says of any other dogmatic claim - namely, that it is not
reaction to the sceptic's remarks about the phrases he utters: they do not
pa,V\ov than the opposite claim. What does this mean? As we have seen,
abolish the statements, but actually reinforce them. In the second part
when the sceptic says of a dogmatic claim that i t is not pat\1\ov than its
Diogenes indicates how the sceptics used their words and statements and
opposite, he means that he has the impression that the former is no more
illustrates the point with a couple of examples. The third part appears
persuasive than the latter nor vice versa, and therefore that he believes nei
ther. In brief: "In no way more", understood as (S2), is a statement such ophy 18 (2000) [263-328] 266-89; on this issue cf. M. f. BunNYEAT, "Protagoras and Self
that that someone believes it to be true entails that he does not believe in Refutation in Later Greek Philosophy", The P/1ilosop/1icnl Review 85 (1976) 44-69, M. L.
McP11E111<AN, "Skcptical Homeopathy and Self-Refutation", Plmmrsis 32 (1987) 290-328,
any dogmatic claim and in particular he does not believe that (S2). (S2)
and A. BAILEY, "Pyrrhonean Scepticism and the Self-Refutation Argument", The Pltilosoplt
has such a logical form that it cannot be believed: so from the fact that the icnl Quarterly 40 (1990) 2714. for an analysis of self-refutation see ). L. MACKIE, "Self
sceptic utters "In no way more" in the sense of (S2) it cannot follow that Refutation: A Formal Analysis", Tire Pl1ilosoplticnl Q1111rtcrly 14 (1964) 193-203. On the form
the sceptic believes that (S2).32 and the semantic properties of the l'yrrhonian formula ou(bi'v) i'v\Aov see also M. R. Srni'
l'En, "Schizzi Pirroniani", Plll'orwsis 28 (1983) [265-97[ 272-5 and WoonnuFF 1988; on the
32 This account of the self-cancelling property of the sceptical universal <P<>Wli is in history and on the dogmatic uses of the expression ou(biv) aAAov . . . . . . see DE LACY
debted to L. C\STAGNOLI, "Self-Bracketing Pyrrhonism", Oxford St11dfrs in Ancient Pllilos- 1958, S1.u1TE1t 1988 and S. MAKIN, /1Jdijfcre11ce Arg11111e11ls (Oxford 1993).
138 Lorc11zo Corti Mi11d aud Lm1gw1ge "ftire Lai!rtim1 Pyrr/1011ist: Di(lg. Lnert. 9.7'1-77 139

to ground the sceptical use of statements just mentioned on some claims third part of the passage. This, as the yag suggests, seems to introduce a
about the nature of appearances and the object of the sceptical inquiry. couple of remarks on which the sceptic's use of words just mentioned is
The text of the first part is not certain: the subject of a[guv and grounded. I take the first remark to run as follows: that x appears to be F
ngoai:maxugil;,Etv is not expressed, and a lacuna after boyparnco( has does not imply that x is F. We have here a distinction between two different
been conjectured by Cobet. If there is no lacuna, the dogmatic reply should facts: the first is the psychological state of being struck by the impression
be taken to be addressed to the sceptic remarks in 76. The sceptic takes his that something is F; the second is the fact, external to the person who has
universal phrases and statements (1mv-ri Aoycfl in particular) to be self this impression, that x is F. The second claim is about what is/is not the
applying. But if one assumes that nav-ri 1\oycfl applies to itself, not only to object of U1e sceptics' inquiry, and why this is so: the sceptics do not inquire
the other Aoym, then one takes it to be even more powerful.33 into the things they think (vooumv), since U1ey are evident to them; they
If there is a lacuna, then it should include the subject of aignv and inquire into the things to which U1ey have access by means of perception
ngoaEmaxugi(;nv and indicate the sceptic's move which, according to (things which presumably are not evident to them).
the Dogmatists, does not abolish their statements, but actually reinforces A similar double distinction plays a crucial role in an important Sextan
them. In both cases, the second part should be taken to illustrate the sceptic locus: PH 1.19-20.35 Here Sextus faces U1e Dogmatic objection according
reaction to the dogmatic objection. to which the sceptic destroys his own appearances. Sextus reacts by in
The question, however, has no importance for the understanding of the dicating that (a) there are two things to distinguish, namely the fact that
second and more important part of the passage, the characterization of x appears to be F to someone, and what is said about what appears - the
the sceptic's use of 1\oym. In this part of the passage Diogenes puts for fact that x is F; and U1at (b) U1e sceptic does not (and cannot36) inquire into
ward two main claims. First, he explains wily the sceptics used the Aoym: items of the first kind - into the question whether x appears to him to be F,
it is necessary to use Aoym in order to abolish Aoym: for example, it is but only into items of the second kind - into U1e question whether x is F.
necessary to use the word 'place' in order to say that place does not ex The sceptic inquires and suspends his judgement on the question whether
ist, or the word 'necessity' in order to say that nothing happens by ne x is F, not on the question whether x seems to him to be F; he rejects the
cessity. Second, the text explains how the sceptics used their Aoym: they former, not the latter.
use them 'only as servants' (btaJCovmc;); when they say that "place does Both in Diog. Laert. 9.77 and PH 1 .19-20 we have a distinction between
not exist", they say 'place' ou boypanKwc;, anobcuc-rucwc; bi. It seems facts and a distinction between the objects of U1e sceptical inquiry. The dis
clear that the sceptic is reacting against a dogmatic objection suggesting tinction between facts is the same in the two passages. Now in PH 1.19-20
U1at he cnmwt say things like "place does not exist"; and that he reacts in there is a connection between the two distinctions: the latter is grounded
dicating that, when he uses U1ese words, he does that in a peculiar way. in the former. It is natural to expect such a connection to be at issue in
But unfortunately, the adverbs which qualify the sceptical use of language Diog. Laert. 9.77 too. Furthermore, it seems possible to reduce the dis
in the passage have raised perplexities: btccJCovmc; has been judged "no tinction between the objects of U1e sceptical inquiry in Diog. Laert. 9.77 to
more than a stopgap" and bto:Kivcuc; or btCCJCEvc; have been suggested in
its place; anobE LJcTL1cwc; has been taken as 'shocking', and unobELJcrnc&:1c;, 15 PH 1.1 9-20: "When we investigate whether existing things are such as they appear,
clTIOQ'lTLICWc; and am.xyyEAnKwc; have been conjechired.34 we grant that they appear, and what \Ve investigate is not what is apparent but what is said
Given the controversy on U1ese issues, it would be unsafe to ground about what is apparen t - and this is different from investigating what is apparent itself. For
our understanding of the passage on them. Let us rather have a look at the example, it appears to us that honey sweetens (we concede this inasmuch we are sweet
ened in a perceptual way); but whether (as far as the argument goes) it is actually sweet is
something we investigate - and this is not what is apparent but something said about what
lJ Cf. B1LuNscmv1G 1999, 1114 n. 2. The reply is hopeless: the point of the sceptical
is apparent"; frrav bf. i;IFWv, d TOlOUTOV fon TO UTCOKflEvov orroiov 'flCClVETC<l, TO f.v
remarks was to show that the fact that the sceptic says rrccvi:i 1\6ycf1 does not imply that the cin cpccivTLtt biboEv, [.rp:ouEv b' ou TC EQi wu cpmvovou L'u\1\L \ TCEQi f.icdvou o Aye-rm
sceptic believes it, since the phrase is self-applying and therefore unbelievable. I cannot TCEQi TOU cpmvo ivou TOUTO bt btmpEQEl TOU i;11TEiV TCEQi C<UTOU TOU qimvoivou. oiov
sec how the fact that rravi:i A6yc,.i is self-applying could strengthen it - i.e. suggest that the cpa iv ETm 1iiv yAu1a:l[.E1v TO ,\1 (wuw auyx<vQouv yAu1mC618a yCiQ ccio8T)nKw<:;),
sceptic actually believes its content. d bi: 1mi yAulCU fonv 6oov f.rri T<fl Aoyr,.i, LTJTOUEv 0 OUIC EUTl TO cpmvoVOV aAAit <To>
3-1 Sec the revised version of BAllNES 1992, included in his Essays i11 A11cie11t Pliilosophy IV,
TC[QL mu cpmvo ivou AEy6Evov. With ANNAS I BAllNES 2000, 8 n. d, I retain the MSS text;
forthcoming from Oxford University Press. BnuNsc11w1G 1999, 1114 n. 5, suggests under MuTSCHMANN I MAu 1958, following HE1N1-L 1932, add <on 1f.v> after o[uv.
standing tinobrncTucc;,.:; in terms of "in the context and for the needs of the sceptic demon 3'' Cf. PI-/ 1.22: "[Appearances] depend on passive and unwilled feelings and are not ob
stration of the non-existence of place". But this remark has no weight on the claim which jects of investigation" ([<pccvrnuia) [v mion yCiQ Kai t'touA1iniJ rrLlBEt KEtivq LtLTTJTOC
it is supposed to justify, i.e. that the sceptic can say things like "place does not exist". ionv).
1 40 Lore11:0 Corti Mind nnd Lm1g1111geof //re Lni!rlim1 l'yrrlrm1ist: Diug. Lnal. 9.74-77 141

the one witnessed in Sextus: the thoughts at issue in Diogenes' text may 2. Now, as a matter of fact,
be understood as the psychological states of having impressions; and the [(b*) the thoughts that do not at all imply the reality of what is being
things the sceptic has access to through perception may be taken to be the thought actually exist:] for - as the Dogmatists recognize - we
property possessed by the external objects. can think not only of real things but also of unreal things; and
In light of these remarks, Diog. Laert. 9.77 may be read as follows: the [(a*) the sceptic possesses the psychological states from which these
question whether x is F is different from the question whether x appears thoughts arise:] for I have already made clear that the sceptic
F; and the sceptic inquires and suspends his judgement on the former, not assents to any impression given by way of passive appearance
on the latter. But what does this have to do with the claim that the sceptic insofar as it appears to him.
cn11 say things like "Place does not exist"? 3. Therefore, the sceptic can think about the non-evident objects and
The link may be provided by another Sextan passage, Pf-1 2.10.37 In consider the claims which the Dogmatists hold about them.
this passage Sextus faces a dogmatic objection. The sceptic, who suspends According to Sextus, the kind of voqau:; which is permitted to the sceptic is
judgement about the existence of the non-evident objects that the Dogma the thought which (a) derives from his impressions and (b) does not intro
tist holds tenets about, cannot think about and inquire into them. Sextus duce the existence of what is thought. Sextus wants to show then that (b*)
reacts denying the dogmatic d1arge - that is, claiming that someone who there actually is a thought which does not introduce the existence of what
suspends judgment on the existence of the non-evident objects cmz think is thought and that (a*) the sceptic has impressions at his disposal. This
and inquire about them, and then arguing for this claim.38 Sextus' rea enables Sextus to conclude that the sceptic can think about non-evident
soning, as I understand it, can be taken as a two-pronged argument and objects.
schematized as follows: In (b*), Sextus claims that, as the Dogmatists themselves recognize, we
1. The sceptic can have the thoughts whid1: think about things that do not exist.39 Take Scylla and the Chimera, for
(a) arise from things which give him a passive impression and ap instance: they do not exist, and no one believes them to exist; still, it is
pear evidently to him; and possible to entertain thoughts about them (to think that the Chimera is a
(b) do not at all imply the reality of what is being thought of. revolting monster, to think about Bellerophon fighting the Chimera, etc.).
So it is possible for the Dogmatist to think about a non-evident and not
existing object such as the Chimera without believing it to exist; so it is for
the sceptic too.
37 The interpretation which follows stems from the detailed interpretation of PI-I 2.1-10 In (a*), Sextus indicates that the sceptic has the u11011i11wvTa necessary
and loci similes l have provided in Co1m 2009, 185-206; cf. G. f1Nr:, "Sceptical Enquiry", to think about the non-evident objects, and hints at a passage where he
in: D. C11A1tLES (ed.), Defi11itio11 in Greek Plri/osoplry (Oxford 2010) 493-525 and Voc;r 2012, has already said something that implies that. He surely refers to Pf-/ 1.1340
140-57.
JI! PH 2.10: "If they lsc. the Dogmatists) say they mean that it is not apprehension of this
(and 19), where he has said that the sceptic assents to his impressions in the
sort but rather mere thinking which ought lo precede investigation, U1en investigation is
not impossible for those who suspend judgment about U1e reality of what is non-evident. JY Sextus may have in mind Gorgias' 7tQi rpuarcuc, which he quotes in M 7.65-87; cf.
for a Sceptic is not. I think, barred from having thoughts, if they arise from U1ings which especially 80: "Scylla and Chimera and many non-existing things arc thought" (:!:KUAAa
give him a passive impression and appear evidently to him and do not at all imply Ule 1cai Xia1QC1 tcai 110,\,\a Twv ii ov;wv <pQovEim1).
reality of what is being thought of - for we can think, as they say, not only of real U1ings 40 PI-/ 1.13: "When we say U1at the Sceptics do not hold beliefs, we do not take 'belief'
but also of unreal things. Hence someone who suspends judgement maintains his scepti in the sense in whid1 some say, quite generally, that belief is acquiescing in something;
cal condition while investigating and thinking; for it has been made clear that he assents for Sceptics assent to the feelings forced upon Ulem by appearances - for example, Uley
to any impression given by way of a passive appcarnncc insofar as it appears to him"; ci would not say, when heated or chilled, 'I think l am not heated (or: chilled)'. RaU1er,
bi; roovo1 f] 1'.0lllU1'.fJV Mynv Kmci,\fJllV yEioBm (fJ1'.0EWo; 7TQOK1V, vorimv bi: we say that they do not hold beliefs in the sense in which some say that belief is assent
ltm\c. OUK fo-r1v l
t bUVCl1'.0V li:v] wic; i:m'.xova1 7TEQi c; U7TllQE.cwc; 1'.WV abtiAwv CriTEiv. to some non-evident object of investigation in the sciences; for Pyrrhonists do not assent
voorwc; yt'IQ ou1c anciQytTm 6 mccnn1e6c;, o !a1, c.
i n6 TC 1'.c;,v na0rin1ec;ic u11om11;6vTc..iv to any non-evident thing"; Aiyon bi: f] boyaTil.Elv 1'.0V mcrnrnc6v ou KaT' i:tccivo
<1eai> Kll1'.' EVllQYElllV rmvoivc.uv aun;1 yivotvric Kai f] navTc..Jc; Eioayoumic 1'.fJV 1'.0 CJT] mvocvov 1'.0U boyawc; 1CaEJ' 0 boya dvai <paoi ''ClVEC KOlVOHQOV 1'.0 rubOKEl\I
l UTtll(lXOV1'.ll voouEv, ,;,c; <pamv, a,\A' t)bri Kai
urra1.1E1v 1'.WV voovtvc..1v OU yilQ 6vov 1'.l TlVl TtQt l Q lCCl1'.ll rav rnaiav KL11'.fJVC.lYICClOivou; rraBrnt OVYKCl1'.ll1'.ief1'.lll
i yc.ln (wic; Yl
Tll llVU7Tll(ll(1'.ll. uerv 1m i LTJTWV 1cai vowv i:v 1'.t'.J mCC7T1'.IKIJ bm0tan i:vn 6 i:rpEK1'.UCOc; 6 oKrnrnc6c, olov ouK O.v drrm El cQmvocvoc ivxotvoc; 6t1 boicw 11 ElcQaivrnBa1
on yilQ wic; 1Cll1'.ll ravmoiav rraElf}TlKfJV U7TOTtl7T1'.0VCTIV lluu;1, 1me6 <paivC1'.Cll auu;i, 11 1j1uxcaBm), tiAAc.'l f] boymil.nv ,\tyoi:v 1mEJ' o Mya dvai paai nvrc; Tv nv1
ovy1ca1'.cnienm, bcbtjAu.11'.m. With ANNAS / l3AltNES 2000, 69 n. c, l omit ,\6yc after the 7tQ1.lyaT1 1'.c;1v KaTil Tile; moTtjac; Criwvcvc.iv 1.lbAwv ovy1mTaElrn1v (oubrvi yc.1Q
first auu;i. Tl;,v abAc.iv ovy1mrnTiElrn1 6 nuQQWV10c;).
142 Lorc11zo Corti Mi11d a11d Lm1g11agc of Ilic Lai!rtim1 Pyrrlt011ist: Diog. Lacrt. 9.7'1-77 143

sense that he acquiesces to them, he does not resist them.41 For to claim that the word 'place' entails that place exists: your understanding of this word
the sceptic assents to his impressions implies that the sceptic has impres presupposes the existence of its reference". And the sceptic replies: "Un
sions, that he finds himself in the psychological state denoted by the term derstanding a word designating a non-evident object does not presuppose
cpccvTC<atcc So Sextus is putting forward an a fortiori argument: the sceptic its existence: for it is an ordinary experience to understand words denot
can have the thoughts of the kind mentioned above: for we have already ing non-evident objects which do not exist, such as the Chimera.'14 So we
said that the sceptic assents to his impressions, and we have thereby pre are not forced by your argument to accept that place exists on the ground
supposed that he has those impressions which enable him to think about that we understand the word 'place'. In order for us to entertain thoughts
the non-evident objects denoted in the dogmatic claims. about place, to understand 'place' and to possess the concept of place45 it
In PH 2.10 the expression voi:iv is used to denote the act of thinking is not necessary to have beliefs on the matter: it is sufficient to have psy
about something: the question at issue in the dogmatic objection and in chological states of another kind - the impressions. And our suspension of
the sceptic reply is whether the sceptic can entertain thoughts about a non judgement does not prevent us from having these psychological resources.
evident object - consider and inquire into the dogmatic claims.42 But the For what we inquire into, suspend our judgement about and get rid of are
Sextan text seems to contain the traces of a li11g11istic parallel argument too. not our impressions (the fact that x appears to us to be F), but claims about
For the main dogmatic charge earlier in the Sextan passage (PH 2.1-10) how things actually are."46
is formulated in linguistic terms: "if the sceptics do not apprehend [what
the Dogmatists talk about], they do not even know how to talk abo11/ what
6. Conclusion: Laertian vs Sex tan Pyrrhonisrn
they have not apprehended" (PH 2.2).43 Now given that the object of 'ap
prehending', here, is "what the Dogmatists talk about", it is tempting to By way of conclusion, I would like to devote a few words to an interest
think that the apprehension at stake is a specific psychological state: that ing difference between the Sextan and Laertian account of the Pyrrhonist.
of understanding the 111ea11i11g of the terms occurring in the sentences af The crucial passage is Diog. Laert. 9.102-5. Here Diogenes reports two
firmed by the Dogmatists. In other words, Sextus' text suggests that the dogmatic objections, each followed by the pertinent sceptic reply: that of
Dogmatists attacked the sceptics with a semantic version of the argument incoherence (102-4), which we have examined in section 2; and that of un
we have considered so far, in which the crucial claim is that understanding livability (104-5).47
the meaning of the word 'y', which denotes a non-evident object, implies According to the first objection, the fact that the sceptic, in his refutation
knowing and believing something about y. That is: if y is a non-evident of the dogmatic claims, utters phrases like "I determine nothing", entails
object (say Providence), then to understand the meaning of 'y' implies to that he believes their content to be true (boypaTinv).
know and believe something about y. According to the second objection, if someone is a sceptic, then he re
Now in Diog. Laert. 9.77 the sceptic appears to react against a dog jects his perceptions (for example, vision), and therefore he destroys life -
matic objection according to which he cmmot say things like "place does he cannot live. I take this objection to run as follows: "Suppose that you
not exist". It seems to me that a linguistic argument analogous to the one are a sceptic. It appears to you that the fire in front of you burns. But
we have detected in PH 2.1-10 underlies Diogenes' text too, and that we you reject/mistrust your impressions. So nothing can prevent you from
can provide an interpretation of the Laertian passage in the light of the
44 So I take the philosophically exciting issue at stake here to be the following: how are
Sextan locus. The sceptic says things like "place does not exist": he utters
we to analyse sentences like "The Chimera is a revolting monster" and (shifting from sin
phrases that contain terms referring to non-evident objects. The Dogma gular to general terms) "Unicorns cannot fly" in order to account for the facts that (a) we
tist then raises an objection: "You say that place does not exist. But if place understand these sentences and (b) the Chimera and the unicorns do not exist?
does not exist, ho"."' can you talk about it? The fact that you understand 45 Cf. M 8.337-336a.
Jn the light of this interpretation, I find Barnes' 1'naKEvwc; (in lieu of the transmitted

b 1aKovo1c;) quite tempting. We may take it to be a sceptic allusion to one peculiar feature
41 For this interpretation see BARNES 1990, 2626--34 ;md CORTI 2009, 65-74, with references. of the Stoics' vacuous impressions (blllK ivo 1 cpavnwicu: cf. Sextus, M 8.67), that of not
42 The capacity of thinking about something (in our case, a non-evident object) implies implying the existence of what is U10ught: just as Orestes' impression of being assaulted
or amounts to U1at of possessing the corresponding concepts. So it is not surprising that in by the furies does not imply their existence, so the sceptic's understanding of "Place does
a locus similis to PH 2.1-10, M 8.337-336a, U1e question at stake is whether the sceptic can not exist" does not imply the existence of place.
have the concept (iixuv i:vv0tav) of a non-evident object such as demonstration. 4; For the objection of unlivability and the sceptic reply see Diog. Laert. 9.104(1ine 489)-5;
43 PH 2.2: "[Ql KaTa1\af3civn 6 cTKET[TlKO<; Til urro rc;,v boyawcc;,v AryoEva OU the text reporting the objection of incoherence and the sceptic reply is indicated at nn. 5
KltTm\af3civEl . .. d b'ov KarnArcf3tiVEL iiQCC, mQi W\I OU 1canu\r]1pv ovbi: olbE Mynv. and 6.
144 Lorenzo Corti Mi111l 1111d L111rg1111ge of the Lni'rtimr l'yrr/1011ist: Diog. L11at. 9.7,i-77 145

walking into the fire and getting burned. So you die." "But," the sceptic's And this is remarkable. Scholars have found two kinds of Pyrrhonist in
advocate replies, "the Pyrrhonist objects and rejects only claims about the Sextus' pages. The radical sceptic suspends his judgement over every issue
non-evident objects which lie beyond the things that appear. He suspends and has no beliefs whatsoever: still, he has impressions or appearances
his judgement on the question whether fire has a burning nature or on how and manages to live being guided by these psychological states of his. The
things change and perish: but he does perceive that fire burns and things urbane sceptic suspends his judgement on non-evident matters only: he
change and perish." has ordinary beliefs and can act by means of them.49
The sceptical replies to the two objections witnessed by Diogenes share I suggest that in Diog. Laert. 9.102-5 we may read another character
a common ground: they both (a) distinguish between two kinds of items, ization of the sceptic and of the defence of the possibility for him to act,
namely, what the sceptic feels/what appears to him to be the case on the different from the two we find in Sextus. The Laertian sceptic has no be
one hand, and the non-evident objects that lie beyond the things which ap liefs; he has impressions or appearances - for example, honey appears to
pear and that the Dogmatists make affirmations about on the other; and (b) him to be sweet; he knows that he has an appearance, when he has it; and
indicate that the sceptic has impressions and k11ows what he feels and what sometimes, when it appears to him that x is F (say, that honey is sweet),
appears to him, while he suspends his judgement about the non-evident he also k11ows that x is f. For in some cases in order for someone to know
objects. that x is F, it is sufficient for him to have the impression that x is F (it is not
What does the sceptic know, exactly? The expressions used by Dio necessary to judge and believe that x is f). And these pieces of knowledge
genes to denote them are "the things about which, insofar as he is a are sufficient for the sceptic to act successfully and to live.
man, the sceptic has feelings about" (mQL WV w avOQWTIOl m:mxoi:v); Is this Jromo snpiens 11011 i11dicm1s/crede11s a piece of ancient eccentricity?
"the things which appear to him in daily life" (noAJ\it 'IWV tv 'IcfJ icp It is not: although a tenacious philosophical orthodoxy from the Tltenetc
cpmvo ivwv) and "only his feelings" (ova 'ICt miOq); examples include t11s onwards wants knowledge to be characterized in terms of belief (and
that it is day (on IEQa tm:i), that he lives (on C:wi:v), that he sees, that takes knowing that p to imply believing that p), some heterodox philoso
he thinks something. Most of these locutions and examples indicate that phers resist. Among them, the one who has the more refined and inter
the sceptic knows that he has an appearance or a feeling, when he has that esting position for our inquiry is Zeno Vendler. According to his account,
appearance or feeling - for example, that when honey strikes the sceptic while believing that p is a psychological state determined by a previous
as being sweet, he knows that honey strikes him as being sweet. But the act of judging that p, for which we may and should have reasons, knowing
first two locutions and the first two examples suggest that the sceptic also that p is a mental state in which one falls and on which the act of judg
knows something else: namely, that when it seems to him that honey is ing has no influence. I do not want to defend this position here; but I do
sweet he also knows, at least sometimes, that honey is sweet.48 want to suggest that an analogous distinction between the mental state of
So Jet me stress two points. First, the replies do not concede that the having Mnta'Ia or beliefs, determined by a previous act of judgment or
sceptic 'believes' (boyta'IiC:u) something. Second, they represent the scep auy1ca'Ia8i:m, and the mental state of knowing or yLvwaKELV, triggered
tic as k11owi11g not only that he has an appearance, when he has this appear by a previous impression or cpavTaaia with the intervention of no judg
ance (say, knowing that honey appears to him to be sweet, when honey ment, may underlie the variant of ancient Pyrrhonism accounted by Dio
appears to him to be sweet), but also - at least sometimes - as knowing the genes in 9.102-5.50
object of his appearance, when he has it (say, knowing that honey is sweet,
when it appears to him to be sweet).
49 The Sextan sceptic also knows something: when he h<1s an appearance or feeling (when
honey strikes him <JS being sweet), he knows that he has that appearance or feeling (that
48 BARNES 1990, 2634 n. 105, understands the passage (in particular, 102-4) differently. honey tastes sweet to him/that it looks as though honey is sweet): cf. BA1tNES 1990, 2621 n.
He takes Diogenes' account to suggest that the Pyrrhonist both believes and knows th<1t 46.
he feels in a certain way or has a certain impression, when he h<1s it. The reply mentioned 51' See z. VENDLEII, Rt:s Cogit1111s. A11 Essay i11 Rational Psyclwlogy (Ithaca, NY I London
by Diogenes, though, does not concede that the sceptic believes anything, but only that he 1972) eh. V; for an analysis of Vendler's argument and ancient Pyrrhonism, cf. Cmm 2009,
kriows something. (In this respect, the difference between Diog. Laert. 9.102-4 <1nd the 238-48. In my book, I rnme to the conclusion that Vendler's /romo snpieirs 11011 crede11s is
locus similis PH 1.13 is striking: for Sextus, replying to an an<1logous dogmatic objection, not the Pyrrhonian sceptic: th<1t is, the Pyrrhonist <JS depicted by Sextus, whom the book
does distinguish between two alleged senses of boya and concedes that the sceptic has is devoted to. I did not focus on the Lai!rtimr account of Pyrrhonism and its peculiarities:
boya-ra, if we t<1ke this word in the first of its senses: see n . 40). And the examples of what I am very grateful to Katja Vogt and the co-authors of the present volume to have given
the sceptic knows include not just U1e fact that he is having a certain feeling or impression, me the opportunity to do so in an ideal working environment. I also would like lo thank
but also their objects. Jonathan B<1rnes and Myrto Hatzimichali for their precious comments.
Skeptical Investigation and Its Perks:
Diog. Laert. 9 .69-70 and 79-89

Christiana M. M. Olfert

1. Introduction

When we say we are 'investigating' or 'searching' for something, we might


mean one of several different things. For instance, on my way out of the
house in the morning, I might investigate the urgent question: "Where are
my keys?" Or, in a different context and for different purposes, I might
investigate whether there really is change and motion in the world, or
whether our perceptions of change and motion are mere illusions. Both of
these types of investigations or searches are arguably covered by the Greek
terms md\j)l(:; ('investigation') and TlT1latc; ('search'), and yet we can agree
that they are significantly different activities.1 The second kind of investi
gation is what we might call 'epistemic investigation': it aims to discover
the trnth about the existence of motion and change, and it will count as suc
cessful or unsuccessful depending on whether or not it advances our un
derstanding of this topic. In contrast, the first kind of investigation aims at
a practical result- geHi11g my hands 011 my keys and need not be concerned
-

with the truth in any special way at all, so long it achieves this important
result.
According to Diogenes Laertius, the Pyrrhonian Skeptic's philosophical
program is defined in terms of investigation and searching. But given the
broad range of things that might count as an 'investigation' or a 'search,' it
is not entirely clear what this means. Moreover, Diogenes' s descriptions of
the Skeptics' investigations only seem to add to the puzzle. One thing we
are told is that the Skeptics search for the truth (70). But we are also told
that the Skeptics "were always investigating but never discovered any
thing" (70); that by their own admission, they "determine nothing" (74);
that when they undertake their investigations, "ignorance of the truth fol
lows suit" (76); and that the purpose of their investigation is not to arrive
at some settled view or knowledge about the truth of things, but rather
"suspension of judgment" and "peace of mind" (107).

1
For a discussion and classification of the breadth of possible meanings of these terms,
see PALMER 2000, 366-7.
148 Christimrn M. M. Olfcrt Sk.:plicnl /1w.:stig11tio11 1111d /Is P.:rks: Diog. l..ircrJ. 9.69-7() mu/ 79-89 149

To anyone who is not already a practicing Skeptic, this combination of and searching are of central importance to the Pyrrhonians' philosophical
claims about the defining activity of Skepticism is puzzling. What kind of program - as we will see, both to its content and to its method.
investigation, if any, systematically and predictably results in ignorance, In order to understand what it means for Pyrrhonians to be 'Skeptics'
and discovers nothing? What does it mean to search for the truth if the and 'Zetetics', it will be helpful to start with a brief discussion of some
aim of this searching is not discovery of the truth, but a kind of mental Platonic antecedents of the notion of inquiry or investigation. In the Me110,
tranquility? And what sort of genuine investigation, which is not a mere the title character, Meno, begins to worry that he and Socrates will not
intellectual exercise but a sincere attempt to figure something out, proceeds be able to discover an answer to the question "What is virtue?" because
by pre-established formulas (called 'Modes' or 'Tropes') to a predictable both of them seem to have been reduced to a state of intellectual numbness
conclusion, namely, suspension of judgment and no determination? or perplexity about the question. Meno expresses this worry with three
These are some of the questions about the nature of Skeptical inves questions:
tigation that arise from Diogenes's description of Pyrrhonism in Book 9 "I-low will you search for (LT)Tlian<;} lvirtuej, Socrates, when you do not know at all
of Lives of E111i11e11/ Philosophers. In what follows, I will argue that despite what it is? I-low will you aim to search for something you do not know at all? If you
some appearances to the contrary, Skeptical investigation has all the fea should meet with it, how will you know that this is the thing that you did not know?"
(80d)
tures we usually think belong to the epistemic type of investigation de
scribed above. The epistemic credentials of Skeptical investigation have Socrates then reformulates these questions into a dilemma:
often been discussed by other interpreters, but I hope to add to this discus "Do you know what a debater's argument you have introduced, that a man cannot
sion by focusing on epistemic improvement or advancement, and the sense search either for what he knows or for what he does not know at all? For he cannot
in which Skeptical investigation aims to improve or advance the epistemic search for what he knows, because he knows it, and in that case is in no need of search
state of the investigator. In particular, I hope to show that the Skeptic - or ing; nor again can he search for what he docs not know, since he does not know for
what he is to search." (SOe)
anyone engaged in a Skeptical investigation - arguably achieves a number
of epistemic advancements or benefits when she achieves suspension of These passages are famous for their discussion of the so-called "Meno's
judgment. These, we might say, are the perks of Skeptical investigation. Paradox" about the possibility of investigation. But within their discussion
of the paradox, these passages also express some general and plausible
ideas about what constitutes a particular kind of investigation.
2. Investigation and Epistemic Improvement To start with, every genuine investigation has an o/Jjcc/, something that
the investigation is about. However, as Socrates points out, there are some
Investigation and searching feature prominently in Diogenes's description
restrictions on what can count as an object of investigation: we do not in
of who and what a Pyrrhonian Skeptic is:2
vestigate what we already know, but only matters that 'need' investiga
"All of these men were called 'Pyrrhonians', the appellation being derived from the tion (bi:i nfi yi: wtounf) <:1rrr1ano.J, Me110 80e). So in addition to an inves
name of their teacher, and they are also called 'Aporetics', 'Skeptics', 'Ephetics', ;md
tigative object, we may add that a genuine investigation must also have
'Zetetics', these labels being derived from their 'doctrine', if we may call it that." (Diog.
Laert. 9.69) a sli11111/11s, some feature of the object that provokes or calls for investiga
tion, which may be connected to our lack of full knowledge about it. Then,
As Diogenes suggests, these descriptors of Pyrrhonians as 'Skeptics' (lit as Meno and Socrates suggest, every genuine investigation must also be
erally, 'investigators') and 'Zetetics' (literally, 'searchers') are not merely gin with some co11tc11t. An investigation that starts with no information
hostile labels given to Pyrrhonians by outsiders and by their philosophical at all - a complete mental blank - about the matter under investigation
opponents. They are also self-descriptions, which arise from what Pyrrho has nowhere to go. Further, there also seems to be a question for Meno
nians themselves say and do.3 As such, it is safe to say that investigation about IIow investigation takes place, the steps by which it proceeds. This
suggests that, at least for Meno, a genuine investigation is not a (merely)
2 For the purposes of this paper, I will not enter into the debate about the differences
and similarities between Pyrrhonian and Academic Skepticism. I will frame my discussion random intellectual activity, but it has some sort of method, pla11, or other
in terms of Pyrrhonian Skepticism here simply because Diogenes does so: this book is structure by which it proceeds. Finally, Socrates and Meno also assume
specifically about Pyrrho and Pyrrhonists. In what follows, I will simply use 'Skcptics' to that investigation has an aim or e11d. In their case, this aim or end is to gain
refer to Pyrrhonians.
3 For these descriptions as self-descriptions, see e.g. 76, 78-9, 107. Fur a report by a 1 Tr;insl;itions of the Meno are adapted from G. M. A. GnunE, Plato. Meno, in: J. M.
Skeptic that he happily adopts these monikers, sec e.g. Scxtus Empiricus, PH 1.3. Cool'En, Pinto. Co111plete Works (lndi;inapolis 1997) 870-97.
150 Cll1'istin1111 M. M. Olfcrt Sk.:pticnl llm.'stigntio11 nml lts Perks: Diog. Lt1crt. 9.69-70 111ul 79-89 151

knowledge, and more specifically, to make a discovery about something of the so-called 'dogmatists':7 a group of philosophers engaged in epis
one did not have full knowledge of before the investigation. As such, we temic activities and projects, who claim not only to have engaged in epis
might say that Socrates' and Meno's central concern here is the possibility temic investigation, but also to have thereby discovered deep and impor
of a specifically epistemic form of investigation, which aims at gaining new tant truths about the world.8 But in order for Skepticism to count as a
knowledge. genuine alternative to dogmatism, so that we would be forced to choose
This last point deserves some more elaboration. ln fact, it incorporates between the two, the Skeptics need to be engaged in broadly the same kind
two distinct points about the aims of a specifically epistemic form of inves of epistemic project as those they claim to be competing with. Moreover,
tigation. The first is that an epistemic investigation aims, roughly, at get although Diogenes sometimes struggles to find the right generic term for
ting at the truth, avoiding false beliefs, and perhaps even achieving knowl practitioners in the Pyrrhonian tradition, and for their arguments and prac
edge, as opposed to simply getting practical results of a certain kind ("I tices, he does end up frequently describing them as 'philosophers' and as
don't need to know the precise truth about where my keys are; I just 11eerl doing 'philosophy' (61, 62, 70, 71, 74, 110, 1 12, 1 13).9 But we might won
111y keys!"). The second, importantly distinct point is that a genuinely epis der whether the Skeptics could really count as philosophers unless they
temic investigation does not aim at just any truths, but at 11ew truths which were engaged in truth-seeking activities that aim to improve our minds.10
constitute n real episle111ic i111prove111e11t or nrlvn11ce111e11t for the investigator. In For these reasons, it is important by the Skeptics' own lights U1at we try
contrast to other intellectual activities like contemplation or imagination, to understand them as engaging in epistemic investigation.11 Still, even
investigation as such aims to grasp or see or understand something signif
icant that one has not grasped, seen, or understood before.5 The prospect
truth. For more discussion of this debate, see PALMrn 2000, 366-73. Thank you to Richard
of making such a discovery gives our investigations a point or a purpose; it Belt and James Warren for emphasizing this point to me.
provides a standard of success for our investigations; and real discoveries 7 These arc typically thought to include Peripatetics, Epicureans, and Stoics, to name a

offer us genuine epistemic benefits. few.


A Sec Diog. Laert. 9.74, 77, 83, 103-8; for similar claims in Scxtus's text see e.g. PH 1.1,
These, then, are six important aspects of epistemic investigation that
2, 8, 10, 12, 14, and PH 2 in its entirety.
arise in the Me110: a ba11nfidc epistemic investigation has an object; a motive 9 For some of Diogenes' reservations about the correct title for the Pyrrhonians and what
or stimulus; some starting content; a method; and it aims both at knowl they do, sec e.g. 9.69, 70.
111
edge and truth, and at a discovery or epistemic advance that defines the For an alternative view of Skepticism as a philosophy or philosophical practice, com
parable to but distinct from dogmatism, see Srn11m1 2001, 117, 121-4.
success or failure of the investigation. So far, this seems to be a relatively 11
There is also another important piece of evidence that the Skeplics aimed at cognitive
standard and plausible conception of epistemic investigation. In what fol improvement. They famously compare their Skcptical arguments and sayings to medicine:
lows, r will ask whether the Pyrrhonian Skeptics engage in epistemic in "Whenever things arc at odds with each other and arguments have equal strength, igno
vestigation in this sense. rance of the truth follows suit. And also for this very argument a counter-argument lies
in opposition, which, after refuting the other arguments, is itself turned upside down by
itself and destroyed, just like medicines used for purgation, which, once they have cleared
out toxins from the body, arc themselves also eliminated and thoroughly destroyed" (Diog.
3. The Distinctive Feah1res of Skeptical Investigation
Lacrt. 9.76). The analogy between Skeptical investigation and purgative medicine is found
in P/-/ as well (sec Scxt. Emp. PH 1.28). At least one of the things this analogy seems to be
ft is important to the Skeptics' philosophical project that their type of in telling us is that Skeptical investigation, like medicine, can improve us or benefit us in some
vestigation qualifies as epistemic investigation in roughly the standard way. Now, it may be tempting to read this passage as claiming that Skeptical investiga
sense just described. For one thing, it is important to the Skeptics' self tion can have tl1empe11tic benefits that arc not specifically epistemic: perhaps it removes our
troublesome desire for knowledge (as Sedley argues), or more generally, perhaps it is "a
conception. As Diogenes tells it, the Skeptics are called 'investigators' and
therapeutic device to deter people from trying to be guided by reason" (as Striker argues)
'searchers' because they are "constantly seard1ed for the truth" (70).6 They (Stm1.f.Y 1983, 10; Srn1KER 2001, 124). However, it seems to me that the medical analogy need
also frequently present their Skeptical project as a direct competitor to that not be interpreted in only a narrow, non-epistemic sense. It could just as easily be read as
a comparison between bodily health and epistemic 'health': just as the health of the body
5 By this I mean simply that real intellectual improvement does not come from adding might be improved by the use of medical purgat"ives, so too might our epistemic 'health'
to one's list of tautological, trivial, or otherwise unimportant or uninteresting truths. be improved by the use of Skcptical arguments and investigative techniques (which, in
'' Some interpreters have also read the beginning of Sextus Empiricus's PH in this way, some importantly non-dogmatic fashion, self-destruct once they have done their beneficial
as claiming that "the Skeptics are still investigating" the /rulli. Other interpreters disagree, work). If this is right, then the medical analogy can be invoked as evidence in my argu
citing the fact that in a parallel passage to Diog. Lacrt. 9.70, namely PI-I 1 .3, Sextus does ment that Skeptical investigation aims at epistemic improvements, and consequently, that
11111 sny that the Skcptics' labels or names arc derived from the foct that they search for the it meets one of the requirements for a genuinely epistemic investigation.
152 Christiana lvl. lvl. Olfert Skeplicnl lnvestigatio11 11nd Its Perks: Diog. Lncrl. 9.69-70 1111d 79-89 153

regardless of how the Skeptics conceive of themselves, we might be in beliefs or views that would prevent ongoing inquiry into how things really
dependently interested in the questions of whether the Ancient Skeptics are.13
count as philosophers, and whether Skepticism really is a strong competi Next, we will want to know: What motivates the Skeptic to start an in
tor to dogmatism and to the cognitive practices we engage in everyday vestigation into the truth about some particular non-evident matter? As in
which are centrally concerned with uncovering the truth. In what follows, the Meno, not just any non-evident truth calls for Skeptical investigation.
then, I will describe the project of Skeptical investigation with a view to Rather, the Skeptical investigator is motivated to inquire when she notices
whether it counts as 'epistemic' in the sense described above, and if so, in 'discrepancies,' 'confusion,' and 'contradictions' in a set of appearances
which respects. and thoughts that she confronts (78).14 This class of intellectual puzzles
When we think about what it means for the Skeptics to be investigators, seems to be broad enough to include general discrepancies (e.g. "TI1e ap
we may start with what the Skeptics investigate - the object of Skeptical ple is sweet" [to our sense of taste] and "The apple is yellow" [to vision]) as
investigation.12 As we have seen, in the most general terms, Diogenes de well as outright contradictions of the form 'p and not-p' (e.g., "There is no
scribes the Skeptics as "searched for tl1e truth" (70). But which truths does change or motion" [say, according to Parmenides], and "There is change
the Skeptic search for? Diogenes tells us that "whether things appear a cer and motion" [say, according to Aristotle]). It is a feature of these discrepan
tain way is not the subject of investigation, accord ing to the skeptics, but cies and puzzles that, on the one hand, the Skeptic has several plausibly
rather whether in reality they are such" (91). After all, the way things seem true-seeming thoughts and impressions about some subject, and on the
to be is already manifest to the person to whom they seem that way. For other hand, it seems to her that t11ese thoughts and impressions cannot
example, the Skeptics simply acknowledge and do not investigate the fact all be true together witl1out significant qualifications.15 In such cases, the
that apples taste sweet or that snow looks white (103). Instead, in the most Skeptic can neither immediately determine what the truth is (because she
general terms, the object of Skeptical investigation is the trutl1 about what sees that not all of her thoughts and impressions about the subject can be
is 'really the case' in the sense of what is not obviously ('non-evidently')
the case. These non-evident things include facts about the way things in 1 3 There is also a famous and long-standing scholarly debate about whether and to what
the world really are, beyond how they 'merely' seem to be; facts about the extent the Skeptics can be said to have beliefs: for instance, whether we should say that
basic natures of things; and in general, any facts about things that would they believe l/Jat things appear to be n certain wny, or also t/1111, ill nil ordillmy sense, t/Ji11gs nrc
decisively resolve questions or puzzles we might have about what they re how they seem lo be, or again I/ml certain things seem to be trlle, or whether we should say that
the Skepl"ics have no beliefs whatsoever. for a range of positions adopted in this debate,
ally are (74, 77, 103). Like Meno in Plato's dialogue, then, the Skeptic is
sec e.g. BARNES 1997, 61-7; BuRNYEAT 1997, 30-1; Fmm1; 1997, 8-24; and Prn1 N 2006, 145-62.
investigating and searching specifically for truths that are not yet obvious However, the Greek terms for belief and believing -doxn and related verbs - appear only ;i
to her, the grasp of which would improve or advance her epistemic state. handful of times in Diogenes's text (see 92, 93, 101 ). (Th;inks lo Katja Vogt for emphasizing
But there is also supposed to be a distinctively Skeptical way of trying this point to me.) Moreover, the sense in which the Skeplic assents to or believes certain
to improve our understanding of non-evident truths, which distinguishes things is more thoroughly discussed by Sextus in PH, and his text is almost exclusively the
focus of the scholarly debate about Skeptical beliefs. For these reasons, I will not engage
the Skeptics from the so-called 'dogmatists.' These dogmatists are thinkers
with this particular scholarly debate here.
who hold beliefs and make declarations in a 'dogmatic fashion': they are J.1 TI1e 'appearances' and 'thoughts' (1patv6cva and vooucvil) among which the dis

in the business of forming settled views about the way things really are crepancies and contradictions arise are a very broad class of cognitive states, which in
in their fundamental, hidden, underlying natures, beyond the ways these cludes everything from sense-perceptions to quasi-perceptual appearances, to complex
thoughts and beliefs, lo abstract phi losophical doctrines, to what seems to be full knowl
things seem or appear to us (74, 77, 103). According to the Skeptics, the
edge of some subject. For some examples of the variety in the kinds of states that can
dogmatists take themselves to have already figured out the truth about give rise to the Skeptic's initial puzzle, sec especially the Third and Fifth Modes of the
how things are (about some particular subject), so they find nothing left Ten Modes of Aencsidemus. Note also that the relevant d iscrepancies can be achieved be
to investigate (about that very subject). But whereas the dogmatists have tween any combination of appearances and thoughts (between multiple appearances, be
hveen appearances and thoughts, and between multiple thoughts). For more on the broad,
ceased to investigate the hidden matters they think they have discovered,
non-technical notion of 'appearances' at issue in Skeptical investigation, see e.g. ANNAS I
the Skeptics are co11ti1111i11g to i11vestignle them. And they continue to inves 13AJINES 1985, 23-4; Srn1KER 1983.
tigate because, in contrast to other philosophers, they have no 'dogmatic' 15 Jn this respect, some Skcptical puzzles, and the investigations that follow, seem to

assume the truth of the Principle of Non-Contradiction (PNC) (sec e.g. HANKINSON 1995,
12
There may be some interesting differences between the process of investigation by 156-60; Srn1KER 1983, 100). Note, however, that the Skeptic need not be dogmatically com
which one becomes a Skeplic, and the investigations that practicing Skepl"ics undertake. I mitted to the truth of PNC or any similar principle. She may simply find it apparently
will not comment extensively on these differences here. plausible and a useful principle in helping her investigate the truth.
154 Christiana M. M. 01/ert Skcpticnl /nvcstigaliou and Its Perks: Diog. Li1cr/. 9.69-70 and 79--89 155

true together) nor can she simply forget the matter and avoid making a This account of how the Skeptic achieves suspension tells us a number
determination (because she finds several of her thoughts and impressions of things. First, as Diogenes says, suspension of judgment is a mi8oc;: it
about the subject compellingly true). So if, as we have seen, the Skeptic is is a way in which the Skeptic's mind is passively affected by the arguments
the sort of person to have a basic desire for or orientation toward the truth, she encounters, in combination with her concern for the truth and for epis
and in particular if she has a basic desire to search for truths that improve temic improvement. It is not something the Skeptic does. 19 But we also
her epistemic state, it is plausible that she will be dissatisfied and troubled know from how it is produced that suspension is not just any way of being
when confronted with such a puzzle.1 6 Here, she has an opportunity to passively affected. It is not the same thing as a feeling of doubt or uncer
improve her epistemic state, but cannot see precisely how to do so. So she tainty; nor is it merely a feeling of frustration or disappointment at not
will be prompted to investigate her seemingly plausible thoughts and im being able to resolve her puzzle; nor is it merely a state of ignorance of
pressions about the puzzle to see if she can discover which of them, if any, or a lack of interest in the puzzle, or a simple failure to make a judgment
is really true. about it. After all, these emotions and states can arise under a variety of
Now, what does the Skeptic hope to achieve in her investigation? This circumstances, but the Skeptic's suspension is a specific response to the
brings us to one of the most distinctive and puzzling features of Skeptical recognition that there are equally convincing arguments on different sides
investigation: "the skeptics say that their end is suspension of judgment, of her puzzle. As a result of this recognition, as long as the Skeptic con
which ... is accompanied by peace of mind as if by its own shadow" (107).17 tinues to be guided by her epistemic concerns, she simply cn1111ot settle on
To understand what exactly this state of suspension of judgment or non any solution to her puzzle.20 As Paul Woodruff nicely puts it, "the equal
determination is, we will need to examine how it is produced in the Skep power of opposed arguments . . . [is] supposed to leave one's mind poised
tic. As they tell it, when the Skeptics investigate their puzzle, they find in suspense between the force fields of the two arguments."21
several different, incompatible accounts of the truth equally convincing or However, Skeptical investigation does not merely happen to conclude
plausible (m8av6v) (79). Again, the effect that these equally convincing with suspension of judgment. The Skeptic deliberately aims at suspension
accounts have on the Skeptic is perhaps best understood in the context of and its attendant feeling of tranquility.22 To understand why, we can refer
her search for the truth. Precisely because the Skeptic cares about searching again to how the state of suspension is produced. Precisely because the
for the truth and for advancing her epistemic state, when she encounters Skeptic arrives at suspension by an exacting and thorough examination
equally convincing accounts of the truth about the puzzle under investi of all sides of the puzzle, it is likely that, once she achieves suspension,
gation, her mind is pulled equally in several different directions at once.18 she no longer sees any further avenues for epistemic improvement or ad
Her epistemic concerns prevent her from settling on any arbitrary, incon vancement. This is not to say that the Skeptic is no longer puzzled in any
sistent determination of where the truth lies. Instead, her judgment about sense: after all, the Skeptical philosophical project is called "'perplexing,'
the solution to her puzzle is suspended, and she makes no determination or aporetic, because they brought both those who put forward doctrines
about the truth of the matter. And since the equally plausible solutions and t1Ie111se/ves to a state of perplexity" (Diog. Laert. 9.70, my emphasis).
comprise everything she has been able to find during her investigation, But even if the Skeptic does not aim at suspension of judgment as an en
her investigation comes to an end. tirely unpuzzled state of mind, she may aim at it as an admittedly puzzled
1 6 Of course, one possible response to confronting such a discrepancy would be for the l'I For more about suspension of judgment as a rraOoc, see e.g. ANNAS I BARNES 1985,

Skeptic to assent to a claim such as: "The basic fact of the matter about this subject is ei 49-50; 5TltlKER 2001, lJ 6.
2
ther X or Y or neither." But this claim about the ba?ic natures of things, even if it is true, For the influence of the Stoic and Epicurean theories of cognition on the motive and
probably does not constitute an epistemic advance or improvement in the sense relevant the conclusion of Skeptical investigation, sec Vocr 2012a, 126-8.
to the Skeptics' aims. In other words, the fact that the Skeptic aims at genuine epistemic 21 WOOllllUFF 2010, 211.
22
improvement helps to explain why she is not satisfied to conclude with such a claim. Of course, there is a deep question here about the very sense in which Skeptical investi
17 More specifically, Diogenes reports that the Pyrrhonian Skcptics Timon and Acnesidc
gation 'aims' at anything at all. Jn order to be charitable to the Skeptic, we must understand
mus took suspension of judgment as their main investigative goal. the relevant notion of 'aiming' in a way that does not commit the Skeptics to a settled view
111 Again, if the Skeptic were concerned only with the truth and not with epistemic ad about the real existence or the fundamental nature or value of what she is aiming at. This
vancement, presumably all she would have to do in the face of equipollent arguments is would, after all, make her a dogmatist. For a discussion of some problems with a Skep
to judge that U1e answer to her puzzle is "Either X or Y or neither" (where X and Y are the tic's positive recommendation of an end or goal (1:ft\o;:), see SEDLEY 1983. It is also part of
incompatible solutions). But she docs not do this, precisely because the judgment "The Sedley's view in this paper that not all Pyrrhonists agree about the end or aim of Skcpti
truth is either X or Y" where X and Y arc recognized as the only viable alternatives does cism: whether it is suspension (Aenesidemus) or tranquility /1y 111en11s ofSllSf'C11Sio11 (Sextus)
not count as a significant improvement to her epistemic state. (SEDl.EY 1983, 21-2).
156 Clrristimrn M. M. Olfcrt Skepticnl lllvestigntio11 a11d Its Pc:rks: Diog. Lnert. 9.69-70 a11d 79-89 157

state in which she has tried everything in her power to solve her puzzle The first question has to do with the method of Skeptical investigation.
and improve her grasp of it.23 As we have seen in the Me110, some sort of meU1od is plausibly necessary
But this is only part of an answer to the question of why the Skeptic for us to be engaged in an epistemic investigation. In U1e Skeptics' case,
deliberately aims at suspension of judgment. Although Diogenes says re Diogenes suggests that their method makes use of the so-called Skeptical
markably little about the 0U1er part, he does note that U1e end of the Skep Modes or Tropes, which are patterns or formulas of argument which pur
tic's investigation is "suspension of judgment . .. nccompnnied by pence of port to lead the investigator toward suspension of judgment. But once we
111i11d (amQaia) ns if by its own shadow" (107). 21 Whatever it might mean look closely at the Modes themselves, we might wonder: Is U1e Skeptic's
for peace of mind to be U1e 'shadow' following suspension of judgment, aim of epistemic improvement consistent with the meU10d of using a small
this additional state of mind helps us to better understand the goal of U1e number of formulaic, predictable arguments in their investigations? After
Skeptic's investigation. The Skeptic acknowledges that, in response to the all, mere repetitions of logical patterns do not count as epistemic investiga
confusion and puzzlement wiU1 which she began to investigate, she is look tions. A child may repeat multiplication tables to herself without U1ereby
ing not only for a conclusion to her quest for epistemic improvement, but seeking to learn something new about the nature of multiplication. So in
also a removal of U1e troubled state of mind U1at prompted her to inves what follows, we will want to know: How does Skeptical investigation by
tigate in U1e first place. And the Skeptic has discovered that U1e state of way of these Modes constitute a genuine attempt to figure something out,
suspension itself brings on a further state of mental tranquility and peace, raU1er than a mere schoolbook exercise?
which is a response to a specific aspect of U1e investigation's starting-point: The second problem is one U1at we have already glossed over. On U1e
namely, her feeling of confusion and intellectual turmoil when she encoun one hand, we have seen the Skeptics say that their investigation aims at
ters a puzzle. So U1ere is also an important sense in which peace of mind suspension of judgment and peace of mind. On the other hand, I have sug
is also U1e end or goal of the Skeptic's investigation, and the distinctively gested that the major steps of Skeptical investigation are best understood
Skeptical way of achieving peace of mind is not by dogmatically determin in terms of the Skeptic's concern for U1e truth, and her aim of epistemic
ing the truth about her puzzle, but by arriving at suspension of judgment. advancement or improvement. But how do U1ese two sets of aims relate
So far, I have suggested that the main steps of Skeptical investigation to ead1 other? Given the Skeptics' consistent and explicit claims to aiming
are best understood in light of U1e Skeptic's deep concern with U1e truth at suspension of judgment, is it really plausible to also attribute to them a
and with epistemic advancement, which are also marks of U1e epistemic concern for the truU1 and a desire to better their minds for its own sake?
type of investigation that Meno and Socrates were after in the Me110. How What truths, and what sort of cognitive improvements, could they possi
ever, as we will see, some questions still remain about whether U1e Skep bly be after in the process of striving for the state of suspension - a state
tics' activities fully live up to the standards of epistemic investigation, and in whid1 they are no closer to solving their intellectual puzzles than they
consequently, whether the Skeptics live up to their own self-descriptions were when they began investigating?
and to our expectations of philosophical investigation.25 These problems need to be addressed if we are to make sense of the
Skeptics as engaging in bo11nfide epistemic investigation and as offering a
u This is also reporled in Sext. Emp. PH 1.3. real philosophical alternative to dogmatism. In what follows, I will ad
2' Sextus, by comparison, has more lo say about ntaraxia. See e.g. PH 1.12. !'or some dress each problem in turn.
conlemporary discussion see 5EDLEY 1983.
3 The Skeptics' critics, boU1 Ancient and contemporary, have raised a wide range of
objections againsl the Skeptics' devotion to ongoing invesligalion. There is the famous
4. The Ten Modes and Epistemic Investigation
apraxia challenge: roughly, if the Skeptics go on investigating rather than forming beliefs,
U1ey will be unable to act because acting requires that the agent has at least some beliefs.
There is also a closely relaled challenge that aims lo show that U1e Skeptics' position is In order to understand how the Skeptical Modes or Tropes (i:Q6nm) might
self-refuting in some way: roughly, U1e Skeptics cannot invcstigale, or even think, without contribute to the Skeptic's epistemic improvement, we must first review
holding some beliefs - for instance, about what counts as lhinking correctly and well, about what they are.26 The Skeptical Modes or Tropes are, broadly speaking,
what follows from what, and so on. Here, however, I will focus ins lead on a set of problems
argumentative formulas or schemas that are supposed to lead the Skeptic
and questions about the epistemic credentials of Skeplical investigation. for more on lhe
so-called 'apraxia challenge', see Diog. Laert. 9.104-8 and Sext. Emp. HP 1.23-4; sec
toward suspension of judgment. As such, they are centrally important to
also e.g. Bu1tNYl!AT 1997; l'1tEDE 1997; VoGT 2010. for the objection that the Skcptic cannot
26
investigate or think, sec e.g. Scxt. Emp. HP 2.1-12; Diog. Laert. 9.102-4; sec also e.g. for a condensed discussion of u,e historical origins of the Modes, see e.g. Srnnmt
Wooo1tul'I' 2010, 210-1 1 . 1983, 96-8.
158 Christiana M. M. Olfcrl Skc:ptical lrwstigatio11 arrrl Its Perks: Diog. Lncrt. 9.69-70 11111/ 79-89 159

the method of Skeptical investigation or inquiry. Diogenes introduces the uses them to be a 'converted' Skeptic. On the contrary, the Modes seem to
Ten Modes of Aenesidemus in the following passage: be designed to be accessible to a variety of investigators, including card
""n1e Pyrrhonian approach is a recording of appearances or of any kind of thought. In carrying dogmatists as well as those who have no particular philosophical
this recording, all things arc tossed together with all other things, and, when they are affiliation.28 The predictable outcome of using the Modes, however, is not
assessed in conjunction, they are found to have much discrepancy and confusion, as so ecumenical. According to Diogenes, the Modes serve (1) to identify
Aenesidemus says in his Outline of Pyrr/rmrism. Regarding the contradictions that arise
why we are convinced of the truth of contradictory or discrepant thoughts
in their investigations, the skcptics first pointed out the ways in which things persuade,
and then according to the very same ways they did away with confidence concerning and appearances; (2) to show that these sources of convincingness or per
these things. For what persuades us arc matters where sense-perceptions fit together, as suasiveness are eq11nlly 'convincing' or 'persuasive'; and (3) to show that
do things that never or rarely undergo change. And so, too, we are persuaded by mat these sources of convincingness or persuasiveness are opposi11g1 insofar as
ters where there is an accepted way of doing things and where things are established they convince or persuade us of opposing appearances or thoughts that
by laws, and by things that give pleasure and amaze us. 79. They showed, then, based
on oppositions in what persuades us, that both sides arc equally persuasive. 'The per cannot be true together.29 When we realize that all sides of the contradic
plexities they addressed' regarding presumed agreements between appearances and tion or puzzle are equally convincing, but cannot be true together, we are
thoughts were in Ten Modes (-rQOnm), according to which the matters under consider presumably led toward suspension of judgment and away from dogmatic
ation were made to be discrepant." (Diog. Laert. 9.78-9) beliefs.30
As we can see from this passage, the purpose of the Ten Modes of Ae However, from the brief outline of the Modes I have just given, it is not
nesidemus is to help 'us' - Skeptic, dogmatist, or lay person - move clear how exactly they are related to the Skeptics' project of epistemic im
from an initial puzzle (discrepancy, confusion) about our appearances provement. Part of the difficulty comes from the formulaic structure of
and thoughts, to the discovery that incompatible resolutions to the puzzle the Modes themselves. If we thought that the entirety of Skeptical inves
are equally convincing, from which suspension of judgment and peace of tigation consisted of repetitive, predictable patterns of argument like the
mind follow.27 Importantly, nothing in this introduction to the Modes,
nor in the descriptions of the Modes that follow, requires the person who text which might seem lo suggest a picture of Pyrrhonians as negative dogmatists, sec e.g.
Il1rrr 2010, Cha pier 1 .
27 My argument in what follows depends significantly on interpreting the Modes as 28 However, some scholars have worried about the extent to which use of the Modes,
schemas for producing equal persuasiveness on both sides of a puzzle, and hence suspen itself, presupposes that the investigator has a certain set of beliefs, dogmatic or otherwise.
sion of judgmcnt about the puzzle. I think this interpretation follows from the claim that See e.g. HANKINSON 1995, 156-60; WoomtUH 2010, 210-21. These concerns touch upon a
"They [the SkcpticsJ showed, then, based on oppositions to what persuades us, that both much broader worry about Skcptical investigation, which I have mentioned before: How
sides are equally persuasive" (tbd1cvuaccv ouv co<o "[(;JV (vccv-rii.iv Toi<; nfi0oumv icmc: can a Skcptic investigate, or even think, without beliefs? See n. 25 above.
t e mOccv<'nrimc:) (Diog. Lacrt. 9.79). This passage introduces all of the Modes, and I take
-ri 29 As I will explain in more detail below, contrary to some interpreters, I understand the
Diogcnes's presentation of the Ten Modes in Diog. Lacrt. 9.78-88 lo have the following Ten Modes - at least, as presented by Diogenes - to be arguments that presuppose that the
structure: first, he presents a general, schematic introduction to how the Modes arc sup Skeptic has already noticed a conflict or opposition between appearances and thoughts, not
posed to work; then he discusses each of the Ten Modes briefly, with the implication that arguments that generate or discover such a conflict or opposition. As we have seen above,
each of them should fall under the general schema presented in the introduction. This way Diogenes says that the Skeptics "first point out the ways in which things persuade and llrCIJ
of reading the text has a number of advantages. First, it clearly explains the purpose of the according lo the very same ways they did away with confidence concerning U1cse things"
introductory passage at Diog. Lacrt. 9.78; second, it provides a unitary description of all of (Diog. Laerl. 9.78, my emphasis). This suggests that the first step of the Modes is lo identify
the Modes and their conclusions, which is in line with their generally formulaic structure; what makes tire Skcptics' i11itial pu::lc corrninci11g, not lo present or generate the puzzle in
third, it gives us clear interpretative directions for how to expand and understand each the first place. If this is right, then according lo Diogenes, the Modes are not designed to
of Diogenes's highly compressed discussions of the particular Modes; and fourth, since artificially generate puzzles and inquiries, but they contribute lo the progress of an inquiry
the introduction describes the Modes as concluding with an cquipollenl opposition (from that has already naturally begun. For the other view of the Modes as gencrati11g puzzles,
which suspension of judgmcnt follows), this interpretation helps to tie all of the Modes or as beginning with the statement of a puzzle (including discussions of the Modes as
lo the general description of Skcptical philosophy given at Diog. Laert. 9.70 and 76 as presented by other sources), see e.g. ANNAS I IlAnNES 1985, 22-3; HANKINSON 1995, 156, 161;
'ephetic', after the suspension of judgmcnt that follows from their investigations. STRIKER 1983, 100. Other interpreters seem lo be more non-committal on the question of
Importantly, this interpretation entails that, despite how the Modes are sometimes pre whether the Modes themselves generate puzzles: sec e.g. PA1.1rn 2000, 364-6; WoOJJJtuH
sented in Oiog. Laerl. 9.79-88, they are not intended to be instruments for establishing 2010, 216-21.
final, definitive conclusions to the effect that we cannot knOIV the basic natures of things, 3" Although this is the usual outcome of Skeptical investigation, there is nothing to pre
or that the basic natures of things arc not really one way or another. Thal is, despite some vent the Skeptic (or a Skeptical investigator) from actually discovering the truth by using
appearances to the contrary, the Ten Modes are not methods of establishing what is some the Modes. In this case, the result of her investigation will not be suspension but assent
times called 'negative dogmatism' in epistemology and metaphysics. Rather, they arc all to some claim, and she will cease to be a Skcptic about that particular question. For more
ultimately tools for bringing the investigator to suspension. For other parts of Diogencs's about the possible dogmatic outcomes of Skeptical investigation, see e.g. PALMER 2000.
160 Clirislimw M. M. Olferl Skeptic11/ /11vestig11tio11 1111d Its Perks: Diog. L11erl. 9.69-70 mul 79-89 161

one outlined above, how could we reasonably expect this investigation to temic goals and concerns of Skeptical investigator are not guided by, but
improve anyone's epistemic condition, or to lead to progress in our un actively guide and motivate, her use of the Modes.
derstanding? The other part of the difficulty comes from how Diogenes As a final point about whether the Modes are compatible with gen
describes the conclusions of the Modes. Some of tl1e Modes suggest that uinely epistemic investigation, we might consider the role of positive, non
suspension of judgment will immediately follow from the use of the Mode Skeptical arguments in Skeptical investigation.32 Recall Diogenes's claim
(Modes 1, 5); other Modes seem to conclude that one ought to suspend that "The skeptics, then, continually overturned all the doctrines of philo

' II
judgment (Mode 2); still others seem to conclude with claims that (as it ap sophical schools, and . . . they go so far as to cite the views of others and
pears to the Skeptic) things are not how they appear, or that they are not report them" (74). He also says, in the paragraph before his introduc
knowable (Modes 3, 6, 7, 10).31 Given these different conclusions, we might tion of the Modes, that "the skeptics use A6yot (statements, arguments,
wonder: Precisely what role do the Modes have in Skeptical investigation or accounts) only as tools. For one cannot refute a 1\6yoc; (a statement,
in general, if this investigation aims at suspension of judgment and peace argument, or account) except by means of a A6yoc;" (77). Together, these
of mind? Answers to these questions should tell us more about whether points suggest that Skeptical investigation addresses more than individual
Skeptical investigation is entirely dictated by the Modes, and whether, and appearances and thoughts. The views of the so-called dogmatists often in
in what sense, the Modes may be used to contribute to the investigator's clude arguments or purported proofs which are supposed to convince us
aim of epistemic improvement. of their conclusions. This in turn suggests that addressing, opposing, and
In fact, there are a number of reasons to think that the Modes are not explaining dogmatic views will often require an examination of dogmatic
nearly as formulaic, and not nearly as exhaustive of Skeptical investigation, A6yot in the sense of the accounts and arguments intended to convince
as they might have initially seemed. We might begin by recalling that ac or persuade us of particular dogmatic claims.33 And something similar
cording to Diogenes, the first step in the use of the Modes is to identify the might also be said of our ordinary, everyday views, outside of any par
source of our conviction in the puzzle that is troubling us. This suggests ticular dogmatic context: we often can, and sometimes do, come up with
that the Modes are intended to be used only after we have already become plausible-seeming justifications for what we think to be true. If all of this
puzzled by something; they do not have the dubious role of both artifi is right, then it seems plausible that in order to achieve a thorough suspen
cially generating problems for us to investigate, and then resolving them. sion of judgment about her puzzles, the Skeptical investigator will want to
But if the Modes only work on puzzles we are antecedently troubled by, somehow address and examine the positive arguments, dogmatic or not,
then the Skeptical investigator is free to set her own epistemic priorities in favour of the pieces of her puzzle.
and projects, and her own goals for cognitive advancement. This might But when we consider how an examination of these arguments fits into
help to relieve some concerns about the role of the Modes in a genuinely Skeptical investigation, we see again that the Modes are neitl1er as formu
epistemic investigation: the use of the Modes does not interfere with or laic nor as exhaustive of Skeptical investigation as we might have thought.
dictate our initial hopes and intentions of improving our epistemic state. First of all, if the positive arguments in favour of various parts of a puz
In addition, common sense dictates that whatever the Skeptics have in zle are important to Skeptical investigation, these will have to be uncov
mind with their use of the Modes, it does not involve treating the Modes as ered and understood by the investigator independently of her use of the
mere intellectual exercises. In order to achieve suspension of judgment, we Modes. Again, this means that the Modes, as Diogenes records them, do
must engage with the Modes in a particular way. We must apply them to not exhaust the content of Skeptical investigation. Second, if it is true that
puzzles that are actually puzzling to us, in which we have a stake in settling
our convictions. We must approach them in a way that stimulates our in J! One scholar who emphasizes the importance of examining arguments in Skcptical
terest and our commitments. But these additional features of Skeptical in investigation is VoGT 2012a, 128-32.
vestigation are actively brought to the investigation by the Skeptical inves 33 In Diogenes' text, he seems to go on to cite an example of the kind of dogmatic logos he

has in mind: namely, the claim that '"place is not" (77). Of course, the particular thought or
tigator herself, and they do not automatically follow from thinking about
claim "Place is not'" or '"Place does not exist" is itself a Aoyoc:, which the Skeptical investi
or using the Modes. This, then, is another respect in which the Modes are gator might address and oppose with various claims to the effect that place exists. But we
limited in their contribution to Skeptical investigation, and again, the epis- should also keep in mind that Skeptical investigation, by way of the Modes, attempts to un
cover the source of plausibility or conviction we might assign to such claims. Since a claim
31 For more on the variety of ways in which the Skeptics say that suspension of judgment like "Place does not exist" is likely to be supported by some set of reasons or arguments
follows from the Modes, see e.g. ANNAS I BARNES 1985, 49-50; BARNES 1997, 58-9; Srn1KE11 (it is unlikely to be plausible to us otherwise), it follows that Skcptical investigation must
1983, 96, 98; Wooo1tuH 2010, 210-14. investigate these reasons or arguments (,\6yo1) as sources of plausibility for this claim.
162 C/1ristim1n M. M. Olfcrt Skc11tirnl illvcslignfio11 1111d Its Perks: Di11g. Lncrt. 9.69-70 mid 79-89 163

positive and dogmatic arguments must be incorporated into Skeptical in gation in epistemic terms, as a "search for the truth" and a philosophical
vestigation in some way, tl1en it might be that our use of the Modes is not competitor to so-called 'dogmatic' theories.36
quite so mechanical and unimaginative as one might have thought. For In response to this concern, some interpreters have pointed out that
instance, if tl1e Modes must respond to and explain the persuasiveness of there are a variety of ways in which Skeptical investigation might be
entire arguments, not only of individual appearances and thoughts; if they guided by considerations of truth and responsive to the norms of truth
must explain tl1e plausibility of premises and inferences in a positive ar without requiring that their concern for the truth is merely instrumental
gument; if they must sometimes serve as an equipollent argument to some or incidental to their aim of suspension of judgment. For instance, perhaps
specific positive argument; then in order to use the Modes effectively, the when we reflect on the important steps in Skeptical investigation, as I have
Skeptical investigator must choose them and tailor tl1em with care accord described them above, we see that they can reflect a concern for the truth,
ing to her particular puzzle and her particular investigation. When we and can indicate that the Skeptic vn/11es, ft11ds i111portn1 1 f, and cnres nbo11t the
combine tl1ese points with the ones above, we can begin to see how it might truth, without ni111i11g to discover the truth, precisely because discovery of
be possible for the Skeptical investigator to use the Modes in a way that is the truth may not be possible. Also, as Katja Vogt has rightly pointed out,
compatible witl1 a genuine attempt to figure something out and to advance when we say that an intellectual activity "aims at the truth", we might
her epistemic state through investigation. mean a number of different things: we might mean that it "aims to acquire
as many , tl1oughts, or views as possible", or that it "aims to acquire more
true beliefs than false ones", or that it "aims to acquire beliefs that are not

5. But Do The Skeptics Really Investigate? false", or simply that it "aims to avoid false beliefs."37 If, then, what it
means to aim at the truth can have a number of different interpretations,

Let us now turn to the second problem we discussed above. Given the perhaps we can understand the Skeptic's search for the truth not only in

Skeptics' prominent concern with suspension of judgment and peace of terms of a quest for the truth as such, but primarily as a quest to avoid

mind, it might seem that Skeptical investigation "aims not at getting things falsehood.38 This interpretation fits nicely with the Skeptics' description

right, but at leaving us in a state of suspension."34 But if this is true, then of their project as avoiding dogmatic beliefs and mistaken commitments

we will want to know: In what sense does Skeptical investigation count as that might arise from being persuaded by something false, and also reveals

a bo1infide epistemic investigation? And if the Skeptics are not epistemic in an important sense in which Skeptical investigators have a deep respect

vestigators, do they live up to their own descriptions of their philosophical for the truth.

program, and does Skepticism really count as a philosophical alternative From arguments like these, we might be convinced that the Skeptic

to dogmatism? deeply values the truth and that this is reflected in her investigation in a

In fact, there are two related problems in the vicinity here. First, inter variety of ways. But there is also a second, rather different problem that

preters have sometimes worried about the fact that Skeptical investigation we might have with the epistemic features of Skeptical investigation, one

ultimately aims at suspension of judgment and peace of mind ratl1er than which has received less attention in the literature. Recall that, according

the truth.35 As we have seen, epistemic investigation in the standard and to tl1e Meno, epistemic investigation does not aim at the truth or value the

plausible sense that we find in the Me110 aims at the truth (and possibly also truth in some way. As a form of i11vestigntio11, it also aims at making intellec

full knowledge). In light of this standard view of epistemic investigation, tu al gains or improvements of some sort. In Meno's terms, we want to use
investigation to come to know (in some sense) something we didn't know
we might worry that if Skeptical investigation does not aim at the truth
as its ultimate end, then it is not a genuinely epistemic activity. And this, before (in some sense), In order to be engaged in epistemici11vestigntio11,

in tu rn, is a problem for the Skeptics insofar as they describe their investi-
31' These worries might become even more pressing when we think about the role of the

Modes in Skcptical investigation. If we think of Skeptical investigation as proceeding by


J.I WooonuFI' 2010, 210. Also, sec Sm1i.:rn 2001, 117: "What leads the Sceptic into philo repetitive and predictable formubs - which is how I have argued we should 1101 think of
sophical investigations is disturbance and confusion; but he engages in the search for the i t - then it starts to look even less like our ordinary, epistemic notion of investigation, and
truth not just in order to find answers to puzzling questions, but in order to attain peace of more like a routine schoolbook exercise that is not particularly interested in the truth. for
mind. Contrast this picture with Plato's and Aristotle's description of the philosopher as contemporary discussion of further worry about the Skeptics' use of the Modes, sec e.g.
someone who ... desires to find the truth for its own sake." PAL!Elt 2000, 355-60; PE!llN 2006, 338.
35 for contemporary articulations of this challenge, see e.g. PA1.Mrn 2000; PEn1:-1 2006; 37 Sec VoGT 2012a, 133-7.

Srn11rnn 200I; Vocr 2012a. 38 See VoGT 2012a, 133-9.


164 C/1risti111111 M. 1\!I. Olfcrl Skcptical l11vcstig11ticm 1111d Its Paks: Diog. Lturt. 9.69-70 mul 79-89 165

then, it is not enough for the investigator to demonstrate a concern for the features of the Skeptics' philosophical project. For one thing, it would help
truth. In addition, as an investigator, she must be sincerely trying to figure to explain why the intermediate steps of Skeptical investigation seemed to
somethjng out, to improve her intellectual standing with respect to some us earlier to be so naturally and easily explicable in terms of aiming at epis
question or problem. So the end at whid1 investigation aims is not just any temic advancements or benefits. For another, it would help us to recognize
truth, but some kind of cognitive advancement over one's prior cognitive Skeptical investigation as a p/Jilosop/Jical project at all. So even though these
state. epistemic improvements are not explicitly identified or described as such
But this raises the question: Is it plausible, in the end, to attribute this by Diogenes, identifying them interpretively is nonetheless necessary to
aim to the Skeptics and to Skeptical investigation? There are some reasons our understanding of Skeptical investigation as epistemic investigation, to
to think not. Consider, for instance, that Skeptical investigation begins our charitable interpretation of the Skeptics as real philosophical oppo
with an unresolved puzzle, and ends with suspension of judgment, which nents to the dogmatists, and to our own appreciation of Skeptical investi
as we have seen, is itself described as a 'puzzle' or an unresolved state of gation as a live option in the philosophical landscape.
mind. The Skeptics even describe suspension of judgment as "ignorance The first epistemic benefit I have in mind derives fairly directly from
of the truth" (76). Moreover, it seems to the Skeptics (based on their past tl1e Skeptics' search for tl1e truth: if we interpret this search for the trutl1
experience) that all future investigations are likely to result in puzzlement in terms of a project of avoiding forming or finding oneself wit11 false be
and ignorance, and they actually aim at this kind of ignorance about their liefs, we see that Skeptical investigation benefits us by preventing the kind
unresolved puzzles and problems, precisely because it seems to them that a of cognitive failure that happens when we take false things to be true (or
better understanding of the nature of things cannot be achieved. Of course, true things to be false). And it could be argued that tl1is beneficial effect of
the puzzlement and ignorance that results from the investigation - namely, Skeptical investigation is best achieved by deliberately aiming to not set
suspension of judgment - comes along with peace of mind, which makes tle one's judgment on any particular view or thesis about tl1e way tJ1jngs
it importantly different from the puzzled and ignorant state of mind that really are. In this way, by aiming at suspension of judgment, Skeptical
motivates investigation in the first place. But it is not clear that this psycho investigation can be a form of preventative cognitive care.39
logical and phenomenological improvement in the Skeptic's mental life is A second cognitive improvement provided by suspension of judgment
really an epistemic improvement in the relevant sense. So, given that the comes from the way in which suspension is produced. Recall tl1at the Skep
Skeptics positively aim at a kind of ignorance and a lack of resolution to tic arrives at suspension by examining a wide range of reasons and sources
their puzzles, this type of investigation might seem to be epistemically self of conviction for different views about the puzzle that troubles her. As
defeating, or at least an epistemic wash, rather than an intellectual activity such, even if the state of suspension provides no resolution to the Skeptic's
genuinely aimed at cognitive improvement. And if this is right, then it puzzle, it does involve a grasp of the persuasive and unpersuasive reasons
seems that despite its respect for the value of truth, Skeptical investigation for various claims and an understanding of why they are persuasive or
might not count as epistemic investigation after all. unpersuasive; of what kinds of pitfalls and strengths these reasons and ar
However, despite these worries, I will argue that there are at least four guments have; and because of this, probably also what kinds of further
epistemic improvements or advancements that may result from Skepti proposals or reasons, and from what sources, would be needed in order to
cal investigation, all of which are connected with the Skeptics' stated aim push the Skeptic toward a particular resolution to her puzzle. Arguably,
of suspension of judgment. These may not be merely epistemic advance then, the Skeptic is in a much more sophisticated and informed epistemic
ments; as we will see, they may improve the investigator's life in more position with respect to her puzzle after investigation than she was at the
ways than one. But if I am right, then when the Skeptics aim at suspension beginning, insofar as she now has a clear grasp of the reasons and argu
of judgment, they are in fact aiming at a number of improvements to their ments that are, and might be, given for and against various parts of the
epistemic state, whether or not they make precisely these improvements puzzle. And she puts herself in this more sophisticated, better informed
explicit to themselves. I do not mean to say the Skeptics, themselves, were position by aiming at suspension of judgment, and specifically, by aiming
dogmatically committed to the claim that these improvements will really
follow from their investigations, and that they "really are" improvements 3 Importantly, l do not mean to suggest that U1is cognitive benefit is 1111iq11e to Skeptical
(in their natures, so to speak). However, if we could understand Skeptical investigation, and that it cannot be achieved by any other means. Rather, l mean to say that
investigation as aiming at epistemic improvements by aiming at suspen aiming at suspension of judgment plausibly docs achieve this benefit, and that it plausibly
does so at least as effectively as various forms of dogmatic investigation. The same holds
sion of judgment, this would allow us to explain and unify a great many for the other benefits I discuss below.
r
166 C/1ristim111 M. M. Olfert Skptical illv.!:;ligntio11 11111i lts Pak:;: Ding. Lncrt. 9.69-7() n11d 79--89 167

at it via examining a range of reasons, arguments, and views in careful connected to a similar notion in Epicurean thought.41 According to the
detail. Epicureans, peace of mind or tranquility is our highest good and greatest
A third epistemic benefit arises from the sensitivity and the precarious pleasure.'12 So if the Skeptics could plausibly claim to achieve this peace
ness of the state of suspension. Because this state is not a dogmatic set of mind through their investigations, then they could claim to be able to
tling of opinion but a state of cognitive tension among equally convincing achieve the dogmatists' version of our greatest, best good with their own
alternatives, remaining in suspension depends entirely on the continued Skeplical methods, and this, in combination with some of their other ar
equipollence of all the considerations for and against various solutions to guments, could potentially give the dogmatists convincing reasons to be
the puzzle. Any new, plausible consideration or argument that occurs to come Skeptics themselves. Along similar lines, I would like to discuss a
the Skeptic, or is presented to her by a proponent of one view or another, less frequently acknowledged connection between Skeptical investigation
could easily begin to tip her judgment in one direction or another and and dogmatic views about the benefits of rational activity. I have in mind
thereby unsettle her suspension of judgment.40 This new information or the Platonic and Aristotelian idea that we are greatly benefitted as specif
argument might re-open her puzzle by being opposed to arguments she ically rntional beings by Jiving a life devoted to ongoing rational activity.
has already considered, and perhaps also by being opposed to her state My final point is that we might find yet another epistemic benefit of Skep
of suspension itself, in which it seemed to her that the views about her tical investigation in that it promotes a life devoted to more, ongoing epis
puzzle were all equally convincing. And once the Skeptic's puzzle is re temic activity, which arguably has many of the same benefits as Plato's and
invigorated, then, being a good Skeptic, she will re-open her investigation Aristotle's notions of contemplation.43
into it. To see how, consider again the sensitivity of the Skeptic's suspension
One major advantage of this sensitivity of the state of suspension lies of judgment. As we have seen, by aiming at suspension of judgment, the
in the fact that the Skeptic can easily be prompted to perform yet another Skeptic aims to enter a state from which it is particularly easy to engage
round of investigation about the same puzzle. But as we have just seen, in in further, active investigations, as soon as she has acquired new informa
this new round of investigation, the Skeptic's understanding of the puzzle tion. So it seems to follow that investigation aimed at s11spe11si011 ofj11dgme11t
and what makes its various aspects puzzling is much more refined than promotes n life of engaged n11d sincere inlellect11nl activi01:14 My proposal now
it was before. Her previous state of suspension has framed the puzzle in is that this new investigation counts as an epistemic advance for the Skep
greater detail, so that her new investigation will be more focused, more di tic, not only by being a better investigation than the one before it, but also
rected, more refined, and more genuinely responsive to live concerns. So, simply because it is more ongoing, infornred n11d i11formative rntional activity.
rather than being a merely repetitive exercise, each new round of Skepti This ongoing, informed rational activity is an epistemic advance for the
cal investigation about the same puzzle is likely to be a beHer investigation Skeptic by being an increase in careful, thoughtful epistemic activity, by
than the previous one in many ways. This improvement in the quality of promoting a life devoted to such activity, and ultimately by promoting a
her ongoing inquiry is yet another benefit that the Skeptic acquires from
aiming at suspension of judgment.
The final epistemic improvement I would like to discuss is somewhat 41 See e.g. HANKINSON 1995, 155 n. 2; Srmr.EY 1983, 15, 24 n. 22.
more speculative, and of a slightly different nature. As we have already 42 Sec e.g. Epicurus, Letter lo Me11oece11s: A. A. LONG I D. N. SrmtEY (eds.), '17w He/le11iMic
noted, there are a number of important philosophical and dogmatic an l'l1i/osoplwrs, vol. 1 (Cambridge 1999) 127-32.
43 In fact, one of the reasons it is important to d is tingu ish truth and epistemic improve
tecedents of the Skeptics' ideas about investigation and what it can achieve.
ment as goals of intellectual activity is so thilt we preserve an important distinction between
For instance, it is no secret that the notion of peace of mind or tranquility, investigation on the one hand, and contemplation on the other. Roughly, we might think
which the Skeptics claim is a consequence of suspension of judgment, is Lhat both contemplation and investig11tion aim at and are concerned with the truth, but
only investigation, and not contempl11tion, also aims at improving the thinker's epistemic
state with respect to some question.
44 TI1is is contra Srn1KE1t 2001, 1 1 7-18: "When he finds himself unublc to discover the
40 As PE1t1N 2006, 349-50, puts it: "the Pyrrhonist's suspension of judgment is, and is truth, but nevertheless relieved of his worries once he has given up the project, the Scep
understood by her to be, provisional. . . . [it] can be disturbed or unsettled by Lhe intro tic also loses interest in the investigation of philosophicill problems." Of course, Striker's
duction of 11 new considcr11tion which bears on the matter 11bout which she has suspended claims here are specifically about the version of Pyrrhonism described by Sextus; she goes
judgmcnt. If this occurs, the Pyrrhonist once again finds herself distressed by a conflict on to argue Iha! 'Academic' Skepticism, as described by thinkers sud1 ilS Arcesi111us and
between candidates for belief. The distress, or rnther the desire to alleviate it, provides the Carneades, "cnu properly be described . . . as leaving all philosophical questions open and
Pyrrhonist with her reason to continue investigating the matter in question." continuing the seilrch for the truth" (SrnrKEI! 2001, 127, my emphasis).
168 Cltristin11n M. M. Olfcrt Skq1ticnl lrt11cstignti011 n11d Its Perks: Diog. Lacrt. 9.69-70 mul 79-89 169

life that is overall best - epistemically and otherwise - for rational beings it plausible that the best way to spend our life is to devote ourselves to
such as us. a highly complex form of rational activity, we may not find it nearly as
Of course, to claim definitively that the more epistemic nctivity (ofa certain plausible that the best way to spend our life is to repetitively, continually
ki11d), t/1e betterfor rntio11a/ bei11gs is to make a dogmatic claim, one that may think through things we already fully know. While Plato and Aristotle
be supported by dogmatic theories about the nature of rational beings, of praise the amazing epistemic achievement and the pleasantness of gazing
intellectual excellence, and of the value of an intellectually engaged and at such deep knowledge with our mind's eye, we might wonder: Is going
active life. For instance, we might think that both Plato and Aristotle ar over and over the same things in one's mind the very most attractive, most
gue for such a position. In the Rep11b/ic, Plato warmly describes the pro engaging, and most pleasant intellectual activity we can perform, even if
cess by which a true philosopher, after extensive education and training, it is about the most important topics? Is it more attractive, more engaging,
finally grasps the highest and most important realities: the Forms them and more pleasant than, say, the Skeptic's project of ongoing investigation
selves. Notably, however, Plato tells us that the philosopher's intellectual in response to stimulating puzzles, of continually revising and improving
activity does not stop once she has seen and known the Forms. Rather, the these puzzles and the strategies involved in investigating them, and of sin
philosopher's soul is "always pressing upwards, eager to spend time" with cerely striving to get at the truth about the fundamental reality of things
the Forms (Resp. 517c). As a philosopher, this person loves knowledge and from every possible angle? In considering these matters, we might also
truth, and she continues to think about the Forms because she continues to want to acknowledge that we are epistemically limited and fallible crea
love and to want to engage with them as sources of knowledge and truth tures, and that, as Aristotle admits, the best life for us needs to be sensitive
even once she knows them.45 And in fact, Plato tells us that for the best to facts about our specifically human epistemic capacities:19 With this in
kind of nature - a philosophical nature - the life devoted to such contin mind, we might also ask: Which conception of the good life for human be
ued, knowledgeable thinking about the Forms is the best and pleasantest ings best reflects our natural epistemic limitations - the one that demands
life one could lead.46 that we first come to know the most fundamental principles of the uni
A similar picture emerges from Aristotle's account of contemplation in verse, and then asks us to continue to think accurately and unflaggingly
the Nicomac/1em1 Etliics. There, he famously argues that the life devoted to about these very principles, or the one that asks us to continually improve
theoretical contemplation is the best and happiest life for human beings and refine our epistemic capacities without demanding that we unerringly
on the grounds that contemplation is the best rational activity of which come to k11ow anything? And finally, we might wonder which kind of epis
we, as rational beings, are capable.47 Again, however, the contemplative temic activity is the sort of thing we could devote our whole life to, as a
activity that Aristotle describes is not a process of learning, and has no continuous, ongoing project: reflective contemplation of things we have
natural stopping-point; it is the ongoing activity or activation of theoretical long since fully understood, or the project of trying to figure out a deeply
wisdom we have already acquired.48 On Aristotle's view, then, the best life motivating problem, one that requires us to be constantly responsive to
for human beings is a life devoted to the continuous activity of reflecting new information, new arguments, and new solutions?
on and re-appreciating what we already know about the most important If, like Plato and Aristotle, we find it plausible that the life devoted to
things in the universe. excellent rational activity is the best life for us - not only on epistemic
For our purposes, Plato's and Aristotle's views of contemplation share grounds, but overall - then depending on how we answer these questions,
two important, related features: first is the high value placed on contem we should take seriously the life of Skeptical investigation as a candidate
plative activity for rational beings like us, and second is the idea that this for the best life. At first, it might have seemed to us that Skeptical investi
highly valuable contemplative activity is a co11ti1111011s, 011goi11g epistemic gation, with its reliance on formulaic Modes and apparent lack of progress
activity that defines a whole life. However, for these thinkers, it is also on any questions of significance, was merely a stale exercise, more like a
the case that the best and most continuous rational activity must be one way of scratching an intellectual itch or a fruitless search for one's keys
of ret/1i11ki11g wliat we already k11ow because (in these texts at least) they as than a true epistemic inquiry. But now, when presented in a certain light,
sume that it is in fact possible to gain knowledge. Now, even if we find it may be the dogmatic picture of contemplative activity that looks like a
stale exercise rather than a genuinely engaging, deeply satisfying, and con-
45 See e.g. 581 b-c.
41' Sec e.g. 490a-b, 580d-586e.
17 See Nieomnc/1em1 Et/ties 1177a12-1178a8.
H Sec Nic11mncl1cn11 Et/ties 1177a20-23; 1 1 77a33-b3. ? Sec Nico11111chcn11 Et/1ics 1097b23-1098a21: the so-called 'Function Argument.'
170 Clrristia11a M. M. Olfcrl

tinuous life project.50 In fact, it may be that by the dogmatists' own lights,
Skeptical investigation, as a form of genuinely epistemic activity, meets
many of their own criteria for the best achievement of reason, and indeed,
for highest form of happiness for us as rational beings. If this is right, then
in a dialectical spirit, we might say that the fact that Skeptical investigation Diogenes Laertius on the Ten Pyrrhonist Modes
promotes a life devoted to ongoing intellectual activity is not merely one
among its many epistemic benefits. We might even be tempted to say that David Sedley
Skeptical investigation both aims at and actually achieves the best possi
ble benefit we could get as rational beings: the benefit of a rational life well
lived. 1. The Ten Modes

The most recognizable and recurrent manifestation of Pyrrhonist Scepti


cism, from the movement's revival by Aenesidemus in the first century BC
down to Diogenes Laertius' Life of Pyrr/10 in the third century AD, is its
trademark list of ten 'Modes' or 'Tropes'.1 These are, roughly speaking,
encyclopaedic catalogues of cases in whid1 appearances conflict, so pre
sented as to shut off any chance of finding a privileged perspective from
which such conflicts might be decisively arbitrated. Thus, in all surviving
versions, the first Mode compiles evidence that animal species differ as to
how they perceive the same things. If you think you can resolve such con
flicts by privileging the human viewpoint, the second Mode forestalls you
with an abundance of evidence that human perceivers similarly differ from
each other. If you respond to the latter difficulty by suggesting that one
particular kind of human perceiver (for example a sage) is the arbiter, the
third Mode awaits you, pointing out how even within a single human in
dividual the sense faculties disagree as to how they represent things. After
these first three Modes the order varies, but in Diogenes' version we get the
following sequence: Mode 4, based on the perceptual effects of observers'
differing bodily states; Mode 5 which surveys the cultural dependency of
innumerable beliefs and attitudes; Mode 6 which appeals to the probable
contamination of our sensory input; Mode 7, whid1 points out the differ
ences made by an observer's position; Mode 8, which collects a variety of
ways in whid1 differing quantitative proportions alter the way things affect
us; Mode 9, which points out that the same things impress us differently
depending on their familiarity or lack of it; and Mode 10, finally, which
seeks to show in some generalized way that all things are relative.
These 'Ten' Modes are to be distinguished in particular from a further
'Five' Modes, credited to the otherwise unknown Agrippa, which profess
1 111csc arc exhaustively presented and studied in the pioneering ANNAS I BARNES 1985.
The primary sources arc: Scxtus Empiricus PH 1.35-163; Philo, De ebrietnle 169-205; Aris
toclcs ap. Eusebius, Pmep. L'Vmrg. 14.18.11-12; Diogenes Lacrtius 9.78-88. Other apparent
references to the Ten Modes include: Favorinus as cited by Gcllius 11.5.4-5, and Plutarch's
50 PERIN 2006, 359, seems to agree, at least in spirit, with this suggestion: "The Pyrrhonist,
lost 011 Ilic Ten Modes ofPyrrlw (Lamprias catalogue 1 58, accepting the emendation ofi:onwv
more than her dogmatic counterpart, emerges as an advocate of reason." to 1:(lOi1lV). Sec further, ANNAS I BARNES 1985, chapter 3.

You might also like