You are on page 1of 2

Nightingale

the ways in which the "literary"aspects of the Laws shape our response to its
"philosophical" proposals (Nightingale 1993: 279)

a "philosophical" readershipat which the theoretical argumentsthat occupy


the first third of the dialogue (624A-715E) are aimed; and, second, a young
and "unphilo- sophical" audience that is addressed by the "preludes" and
the laws proper Nightingale 280

nowhere does he suggest that this text (or the Republic) differs from the
other treatises by virtue of its form.15In treatingthe Laws as a treatise,
Aristotle initiates the interpretativeapproachthat is adopted by most of its
modern-day defend- ers. This approach,which proceeds by extracting a
political and/or ethical "system" from the rough surroundingsof the rest of
the text, all but ig- nores the fact that the Laws contains a good deal more
than argumentsand proposals 282
Cicero (Leg. 1.5.15) and the scholiast (in the Hypothesis) say that the Athenian is meant to repre- sent Plato
himself. The fact that Aristotle at Politics 1265al 1 refers to the dialogue as one of oi TOU YWKpd- TOU; k6yot has
led L. Strauss, TheArgumentand Action of Plato's "Laws" (Chicago, 1975), pp. 1-2 and Pangle, "Laws,"p. 51 1,
n. 2, to identify the Athenian with Socrates. But Aristotle was no doubt using this term to designate the genre of
the dialogue ratherthan to make a veiled identification between the Athenian and Socrates. I prefer not to ask
"who is the unnamed Athenian?"(an unanswerable question anyway), but rather"why is the Athenian left
unnamed?" 284

The argumentation in the Laws is, I believe, wholly unsocratic, but this is
because the Athenian is made to expound his own beliefs rather than to elicit
and examine those of his companions 295

Plato and his heirs saw themselves as close to political action Fossheim 89
!2

You might also like