You are on page 1of 6

GENERAL, APPLIED AND THEORETICAL 861

least as often: culture. This new anthro- space-induced cuts in a book by anthropolo-
pology will still be true t o its heritage; gists!
anthropology will remain distinctive by the In summary, this reinvented anthro-
centrality of the study of culture in its pology looks to me very much like the same
endeavors. Whatever culture is (and these old anthropology at the same old stand.
essays do not address themselves to this There is one important difference. This new
anthropological perennial), it retains its anthropology will be candid about its
dominant place in the anthropological con- politics. This is a positive step, but I suspect
sciousness. that this reinvented anthropology will be
As remarked earlier, in many places the about as much use to serious revolutionaries
authors call for the introduction of new as the old anthropology was to reformers-
problems and the dropping of old. Almost as none.
often, attached t o the insistence that new
problems be tackled, is the remark that new Reference Cited
methods are not needed. Keep the old Frank, Andre Gunder
methods, use them on new problems. Only 1968 Comment on Social Responsi-
one essay (Naders) recognizes that new bilities Symposium. Current Anthro-
problems will probably require new methods pology 9:412-414.
to solve them. She shows, with good ex-
amples, that studying organizations with
power and responsibility in American
society (insurance companies, public Belief, Language, and Experience. RODNEY
agencies) requires something other than par- NEEDHAM. Chicago: University of Chicago
ticipant observation and other traditional Press (published in England by Basil Black-
ethnographic tools. Nader implicitly recog- well & Mott, Oxford), 1972 (publication
nizes that problem, method, and theory are date 1973). xvii + 269 pp., bibliography,
locked together in a dialectic where they index. $10.00 (cloth).
create each other. For this reason, Naders Reoiewed by BENSON SALER
essay will be of far greater use than any of Brandeis University
the others to an anthropologist wanting to
do some reinvented anthropology rather This book raises and explores some fun-
than merely talk about it. damental issues regarding the nature of
There are other continuities between the belief and relates them t o the problem of
old and the reinvented anthropology. As I specifying natural human capacities. Need-
see it, a common feature of the old anthro- ham offers his essay as a contribution to the
pology is the divorce between data and development of an empirical philosophy of
theory. Programmatic statements (which human nature. He writes (p. 188)that The
anthropologists often think of as theoretical) prime objective of the present mono-
are rarely accompanied by extensive bodies graph. . . has been to prove that [the] tacit
of data that support the program. At best, presumption [that people in all societies
casual snippets of data illustrate the points share certain posited, logical and psychic
of the theoretical anthropological essay. capacities] is not well founded, and that the
All of the essays in this book are, in one way essential capacities of man have yet to be
or another, programmatic, and none con- empirically determined by comparative re-
tains data, except in an illustrative way. For search .
example, many assertions are made about Needham was influenced in the crafting
the current state and character of anthro- of his essay by his understanding of the later
pology and academic anthropological organ- philosophy of Ludwig Wittgenstein. Need-
izations, but we are given no empirical hams intellectual debt to that philosopher
evidence about anthropology departments, seems evident in his attentions t o the uses of
what they are like, or what they do. In his words in the effort to illuminate their
introduction, Hymes regrets that limitations meanings, in his employment of the idea of
of space prevented inclusion of an essay on family resemblances (overlapping similar-
the structural types of anthropology depart- ities), and in the character of his skepticism
ments. A significant and typical choice for regarding the appropriateness of certain
862 AMERICAN ANTHROPOLOGIST [76,1974]

kinds of mentalistic formulations. But while defines beliefs as general propositions


it might prove to be an interesting exercise about the world (consciously) held t o be
to explore the convergence and divergence in true, and he states that Holding a belief is
views as between Wittgenstein and Needham, here explicated as exhibiting a disposition to
and though such a study might well aid in behavior symbolic of that belief
clarifying the positions of each, it is un- (1973:208).
necessary that I attempt to do so here. The In getting at what they commonly sup-
book under review, after all, was written by pose t o be inner mental acts or states of
Needham, not Wittgenstein. Our foremost diverse sorts, anthropologists perforce
concern must be with Needhams inquiry depend on selective observations of behavior
and argument as they are presented t o us. and their inferences about what they
Before actually proceeding to Needhams observe. In the case of beliefs, the major sort
essay, however, it will prove useful t o pause of evidence that is grist for observation and
and consider what many anthropologists inference is verbal behavior: public state-
seem to mean by beliefs. Goodenough ments that people make and seem to affirm
defines them as propositions that people as true. There are often vexing problems
accept as true (1963:155). By accept I relating to the translation of such state-
take him to mean a psychic act. He avers, ments, but I do not want to consider them
moreover, that people are likely to behave in at this moment. The point that I do want to
accordance with their beliefs, that beliefs are make is this: many anthropologists appear to
of significance in the organization of be- treat their informants utterances as good
havior. A number of anthropologists would (and perhaps sufficient) evidence for beliefs
seem to think of beliefs in a similar fashion. as inner mental conditions or acts, and they
In doing so, they approximate certain con- often seem willing to suppose that their
ceptualizations of belief offered by informants really believe what they seem
philosophers. to say. A few anthropologists, most notably
The philosopher Price (1969) dis- Leach (1967,1968), have warned against the
tinguishes two major approaches to belief facile description and ascription of inner
belief as occurrence and belief as disposi- mental states on the basis of such evidence.
tion. Occurrence analysts suppose beliefs t o But insofar as I am aware, those warnings
be kinds of mental acts: entertaining or have not gained much currency.
holding in mind propositions and deeming Needham is critical of the ways eth-
them to be true. Proponents of this view nographers use the term belief. If they
generally regard beliefs as inner experiences suggest that they are reporting the inner
that could be introspected by the believer if mental states of the peoples they study, they
he took the trouble to do so. Dispositional offer no real evidence t o support that
analysts regard beliefs as dispositions t o act assertion. If, on the other hand, eth-
or feel in certain ways. In this view beliefs nographic statements about beliefs refer
are likely t o be manifested in occurrences only to the collective representations that
but are not themselves occurrences. While prevail in particular cultures, then according
occurrence analysts are usually willing t o to the standard acceptation of belief as a
accept a dispositional sense of beliefs, psychic phenomenon the ethnographers
though treating it as secondary or derivative, reports are misleadingly phrased (p. 5).
dispositional analysts are disposed t o view Anthropologists seem to suppose that all
occurrent acts of believing as mythical. men everywhere have a distinct capacity to
While some anthropologists seem to have believe. But Needham questions that s u p
naively conflated or juxtaposed the occur- position. It is his contention, moreover, that
rence and dispositional views, on balance the supposed reality of a distinct, interior
most could probably be termed occurrentists state denominated belief requires examina-
who are attracted t o and often employ a tion. These issues are put in the form of two
dispositional viewpoint (as when, for ex- questions that dominate his essay. The first
ample, they assert that beliefs are manifested is the early Wittgensteins question, Is
in rituals). In a recent and sophisticated belief an experience? The second is, Does
essay, the anthropologist Hahn attempts to a capacity for belief constitute a natural
relate the two approaches explicitly. He resemblance among men? Needham
GENERAL, APPLIED AND THEORETICAL 863

answers no to both: him to suppose that LLWehave discovered


the notion of belief is not appropriate to grounds enough to conclude that the con-
an empirical philosophy of mind or to an cept of belief is not expressed in all lan-
exact account of human motives and guages, which provides occasion to doubt
conduct. Belief is not a discriminable that there is a universal capacity to be
experience, it does not constitute a natural recognized. . . (p. 175).
resemblance among men, and it does not In a crucial section of the essay (pp.
belong to the common behaviour of 64-108)Needham takes up various criteria
mankind [p. 1881. that others have offered for establishing the
Needham takes up his inquiry by ex- reality and nature of belief. He challenges
amining data on various languages in order each. Thus, for example, he considers
to discover if they have words that can be Humes criterion that belief is marked by a
cogently glossed by our word belief. He firmness and strength of conception. He
finds that the lexicons of several languages argues against this view, pointing out that in
possess terms some of whose meanings over- ordinary discourse belief statements often
lap various of the connotations of our belief connote uncertainty. Conviction is thus a
but whose other meanings do not. In other most uncertain feature to rely upon in any
languages meanings are so conjoined that it objective investigation of belief (p. 92). He
would be unjustified to abstract out one of concludes this section by avering that
them as definitive of belief. It is alleged that philosophers have been baffled by the
in Cuicatec and Tzeltal, for example, there is descriptive task of stating the criteria of
no way (according to Nida) of distinguishing belief, that when they try to describe
between Yo believe and to obey. And in belief it proves to be indeterminate and
still other languages, we are told, there is unanalysable, and that one can conclude
apparently no verbal concept at all which that there are no criteria of belief (p.
can convey exactly what may be understood 108). Where, then, does belief come from?
by the English word believe (p. 37). Most Needham answers:
immediately, this suggests the great dif-
ficulties of translating from one language to From the verb believe, and its inflected
another. But there are other conclusions to forms, in everyday English usage. State-
be drawn as well. ments of belief are the only evidence for
the phenomenon; but the phenomenon
The larger lesson to be gleaned from a itself appears to be no more than the
comparison of languages is not clearly stated custom of making such statements [p.
in the section on comparison. Rather, it is 1081.
gradually explicated throughout the essay in
consonance with other considerations. Need- There are, we are told, experiential
ham does not endorse the simple (-minded) discriminations.. . that are universally made
notion, no word, no concept. He writes by men among their states of mind (p.
that we cannot infer from the absence of a 136). Some have their locus, as it were, in
word that a certain thing does not exist (p. the human body, the one thing in nature
128). He seems to take seriously, moreover, that is internally experienced, the only
Whorfs idea of covert categories or crypto- object of which we have subjective knowl-
types, and he allows that belief might exist edge (p. 139), and these constitute natural
as a covert concept in the absence of a resemblances among men that all men recog-
clear verbal label. But he states that this nize. They permit direct inferences about
extreme hypothesis offers no more than a certain inner states of other people. Thus
formal possibility, and. . . I have been able neither familiarity with convention nor
to detect n o positive evidence whatever in power of analysis is required in order to
favour of it (p. 131). His comparative grasp something essential to the inner state
approach is predicated on the assumption of a man who is actually in pain (p. 140).
that we get at interior mental states, if at all, Further, to attempt, to want, to regret are
through language, and that psychological modes of consciousness that are fairly
vocabularies incline men to recognize readily identified and differentiated; there
psychological capacities and discriminable can be, it seems, no language which fails to
modes of consciousness. His inquiry leads provide for their conventional recognition,
864 AMERICAN ANTHROPOLOGIST [76,1974]

and they are kinds of natural resemblance analysis of collective representations (p.
among men (p. 144). So, too, are inten- 216). But because of the relativity intrinsic
ding and imagination (but see p. 235). to linguistic representation (p. 223), there
But belief is not. Imagination is real, belief will always be some uncertainty and
is not (p. 135). variability in the categories by which any
Our attention is also directed t o Livy- language organizes collective thoughts and
Bruhl who warned against a simplistic a p actions. We cannot ever achieve an objec-
plication of our concepts of belief and tive certainty in conceptual analysis (p.
experience to the thoughts of primitive men. 223). Language is an imperfect tool. We do
Primitives, the French theorist supposed, are not always mean what we say or say what
not indifferent to a distinction between we mean, and, in any event, we risk being
belief and experience, but they sometimes misunderstood. Yet we seek to understand
take for experience what we take for belief. man through language.
We must be careful, therefore, not to revert We want, says Needham, to discern a
imprudently to the postulate that there is constant order in the world, and We can
some definition of experience that is do so only through language, if at all. We
uniquely and universally valid. Needham can find distinct orders in different systems
makes of this a radical issue for his inquiry of collective representations, but the
and for any comparative interpretation of confused and contradictory testimonies of
forms of human understanding: the numerous cultural traditions argue only
The concept of experience, which is against any universal order underlying
commonly treated as though it denoted a human affairs and concerns (p. 244). I am
constant possibility of apprehension and not saying that human life is senseless, but
a permanent background to the varieties that we cannot make sense of it (p. 244).
of categorical thought, is itself an idio- Needham ends his book with this aphorism:
cratic and problematical construct [ pp. The solitary comprehensible fact about
171-1721. human experience is that it is incompre-
Indeed, Needham suggests that some lan- hensible.
guages may have no verbal concepts that In the Introduction to his book Needham
are at all equivalent to the acceptations of addresses a plea to dissentient colleagues in
experience upon which we have relied in social anthropology: that they should
assessing the status of belief (p. 172),and recognize a problem whether or not they
the outside observer cannot justifiably accept his conclusions. I think that most
presume a distinction between experience anthropologists who read this stimulating
and belief (p. 174). To the ext ent . . . that book will acknowledge that Needham has
the concept of beiief depends on that of made an impressive case for thinking serious-
experience, Lby-Bruhls invalidation of ex- ly about belief and not taking the term for
perience as a term of universal application, granted. We are in his debt for doing so. One
in the comparative analysis of alien con- may anticipate that many ethnographers will
cepts, is a further indication that belief henceforth show greater circumspection in
cannot be regarded as a natural resemblance talking about beliefs. Further, Needhams
among men and is not to be expected among inquiry is very likely to stimulate discussion
their collective representations (p. 175). about our understanding of human nature,
In the last chapter of the essay, Needham o u r epistemological assumptions, the
urges that the use of the word belief be significance of analytic philosophy for an-
abandoned in ethnographical reports, or in thropology, and a host of other matters.
comparative epistemology (p. 193). I suspect, moreover, that a number of
Needham once again asserts his opinion anthropologists will be impressed, and quite
that conceptions of human capacities are possibly persuaded, by Needhams argument
represented, with immense variation, in the regarding the unreality of belief as an experi-
categories of natural languages, and it is to ence. I think that many of us will agree that
language that we have t o look for the there is no distinct feeling or emotion that
formulation of problems and their resolu- distinguishes belief, and that Needham pre-
tion (p. 211). An empirical philosophy sents a telling case for concluding that belief
will be advanced by a universal comparative is not a distinct and discriminable experi-
GENERAL, APPLIED AND THEORETICAL 865

ence. But I suspect that many anthropol- number of twentieth century philosophers
ogists will be far less favorably disposed (Wittgenstein included) have opted for a
toward Needhams argument about the non- dispositional approach to belief, and they
existence of a universal human capacity for have made an interesting case for their point
belief and the radical skepticism and relativ- of view.
ism he espouses. Needham attempts to refute the dis-
Some anthropologists may call for a positional theory by attacking the idea that
common sense approach to the problem belief dispositions have duration:
of a capacity for belief. When we talk about If we inquire further into the mani-
a capacity for belief, they might ask, are festations of the belief disposition, we
we not talking about three capacities? A find that it has certain rather interesting
capacity to generate statements about the characteristics. It has duration, says Witt-
world, a capacity t o remember such state- genstein, and this independently of the
ments, and a capacity to deem them true. duration of its expression in a sentence,
Are we to doubt that all normal men for example. How do we know this? Well,
everywhere have those capacities? Do not there are recurrent acts and utterances
which we regularly designate as signs or
men regularly exercise those capacities? The expressions of belief. These are the
experiences of many anthropologists would evidences that we start from when we
lead them to conclude that men do have identify a persistent state of mind. But
such capacities and that the exercise of them what comes in between these recurrent
is important for culturally organized social signs? Nothing that we know of. And if
life. Whether or not all peoples have distinct we lack such evidence during the inter-
terms for the capacities that s u m to what we missions, in what consists the duration?
call belief is, in this view, immaterial and [p. 1041.
irrelevant. Elsewhere Needham writes: Does one ever
The view sketched above could be related at all say that one has believed something
to more sophisticated suppositions about uninterruptedly? Surely one does n o t . . .
symboling. Anthropologists maintain that all (p. 105). But this line of argument leaves me
normal men everywhere have highly evolved unconvinced.
capacities to create, manipulate, and store If man were burdened by the necessity of
symbols. These capacities and their realiza- having to keep all of his beliefs uninter-
tion are crucial for the possibility of a ruptedly in his conscious awareness, he
human form of existence. Through the would be rather limited BS to what he could
generation of symbols and their storage and retain. Fortunately, we have excellent
transmission in existential and normative storage facilities, and we can file things away
statements the experiences of past genera- in complex archives, retrieving them when
tions are utilized and built upon by succeed- we need them. I believe that studded snow
ing generations. Each generation is freed tires are useful on ice; but in August my tires
both from the burden of having to solve all and my belief are safely tucked away.
problems de nouo by trial and error and
from rigid dependence on in-born mechan-
isms. The capacity for belief is one aspect of References Cited
mans ability to symbol and, in this view, it Goodenough, Ward H.
clearly constitutes a natural resemblance 1963 Cooperation in Change. New
among men. York: Russell Sage Foundation.
Some anthropologists might link the Hahn, Robert A.
above considerations to the matter of dis- 1973 Understanding Beliefs: An h a y
position. In the section of his essay dealing on the Methodology of the Statement
with criteria for belief, Needham attempts to and Analysis of Belief Systems. Cur-
refute several posited criteria In my opinion rent Anthropology 14:207-229.
he does a skillful job in challenging most of Leach. Edmund R.
1967 Virgin Birth. Proceedings of the
them. But I do not think that he is con- Royal Anthropological Institute
vincing when it comes to dismissing dis- 1966:39-50.
position. Disposition, however, is a 1968 Correspondence: Virgin Birth.
criterion of considerable importance. A Man (new series) 3:655-656.
866 AMERICAN ANTHROPOLOGIST [76,1974]

Price, H. H. gists attention. Goddard gives a succinct if


1969 Belief. London: Allen & Unwin; predictable Structuralist critique of ortho-
New York: Humanities Press. dox British Structural-Functionalism, al-
though he weakens his point by unneces-
sarily simplifying the paradigm and by foot-
Ideology in Social Science: Readings in Criti- noting Ftadcliffe-Brown to the wrong book,
cal Social Theory. ROBIN BLACKBURN, e.g., notes 7, 8, and 9 on pages 66-68.But,
ed. New York: Random House (Pantheon), in 1974 is anyone surprised to be told that
1972 (publication date 1973). 382 pp., fig- normative facts may be shaped by facts
ures, further reading. $8.95 (cloth), $2.95 that are non-normative and which may be
(paper). [Originally published in England by hidden from view (p. 74)? Accepted or
Fontana/Collins, London.] denied, this formulation has been an object
of debate in anthropology for at least a
Reviewed by DAVID J. MCCREERY quarter century. Whether, on the other
University College, London hand, as he goes on to suggest, dialectical
materialism or the deep structures of
Although it seems likely that many Lkvi-Strauss do provide a more adequate per-
readers will wish to dispute specific theses or spective than traditional functionalism is
conclusions offered in this book, social another question. Godelier in his pioneer
anthropologists of whatever ideological 1966 essay reproduced here takes this up,
persuasion should find Ideology intriguing arguing for a rejection of both vulgar materi-
and stimulating. Often such collections fail alism and empiricism in favor of a synthesis
in the attempt to use the essays of several of purified Marxism-Marxism inaugu-
different writers, each of which was pro- rates the modern structuralist tradition (p.
duced in response t o a peculiar problem and 338)-with a modified Lbvi-Straussian
in the context of a peculiar problematic, to theory of structures. His analysis of the con-
support a broad central argument, but Robin tradictions within and between structures is
Blackburn overcomes this difficulty rather not easy to follow but worth attempting,
successfully by drawing his material from a particularly in conjunction with the fore-
limited theoretical perspective. Indeed, two- word t o the 1972 English language edition
thirds of the papers come from a single of Rationality and Irrationality in which he
source, the New Left Review, of which looks at some of the same ideas six years
Blackburn is an editor. At the same time, later.
however, such general theoretical consensus The position represented by Goddard and
does result in an occasional in-house debate Godelier is fairly well known in anthro-
which may mystify the non-initiate. pology, but it is interesting to see how
Together the sixteen papers argue that similar ideas are utilized by practitioners of
ideology is not solely the province of the other disciplines. To summarize here the
sectarian but pervades all social research, in- essays based in sociology, history, eco-
cluding that so often claimed to be value nomics, or political science would be impos-
free: The very notion that social science sible, but a brief indication of some of the
research can be conducted other than on the conclusions will suggest what is available.
basis of the prior development of concepts Martin Shaw applauds Alvin Gouldners dis-
and theories is held to be ideological (p. 9). section, in The Coming Crisis in Western
From the vantage points of various disci- Sociology, of empirical functionalism while
plines the essays explore the failings of in- faulting him for identifying Marxism with
ductive empiricism, examine certain key its disintegrating Stalinist shell (p. 44).
problems in social analysis, and, in a selec- Gareth Stedman Jones draws Marx, Lkvi-
tion of theoretical papers, suggest the Strauss, and Althusser into a consideration
holistic utility of a Marxist-Structuralist of alternatives to the weary process of fact
synthesis. accumulation (pp. 108-109)which, he says,
David Goddards Anthropology: the continues to characterize historical scholar-
Limits of Functionalism and M. Godeliers ship. The value of the concept of contradic-
Structure and Contradiction in Capital tion is studied by both E. J. Hobsbawm
most immediately draw the anthropolo- and Martin Nicolaus, and Norman G e m

You might also like