You are on page 1of 32

Aristotle's Theory of Exchange: An Inquiry into the Origin of Economic Analysis

Josef Soudek

Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society, Vol. 96, No. 1. (Feb. 29, 1952), pp. 45-75.

Stable URL:
http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0003-049X%2819520229%2996%3A1%3C45%3AATOEAI%3E2.0.CO%3B2-S

Proceedings of the American Philosophical Society is currently published by American Philosophical Society.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained
prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in
the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/journals/amps.html.

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic
journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers,
and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take
advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

http://www.jstor.org
Mon Jul 30 01:29:37 2007
ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF EXCHANGE
AN INQUIRY INTO THE ORIGIN OF ECONOMIC ANALYSIS
JOSEF SOUDEK *
Queens College

ONE of Aristotle's most challenging contribu- equivalents," if the economic basis of society,
tions to the development of economic thought is division of labor and exchange of the products
his theory of exchange. If this essential part of of specialized labor, is to endure. Less trans-
the philosopher's teachings has been neglected parent than the purpose of his reasoning are his
in the recent literature on the historv of economic approach to the problem and what he must have
doctrines, the blame does not go wholly to the considered its solution.
economist. Aristotle's presentation of his views The methodological tool Aristotle has devised
on this matter, in the fifth book of the Nicom- for his investigation is a kind of "mathematical
achean Ethics (1129a-1133b), belongs to the model," thus setting a precedent to what has
obscurest parts of his writings. Repeated efforts become, among mathematically oriented econo-
a t illuminating and interpreting "this much tor- mists, a generally accepted practice. That this
tured passage," undertaken ever since a t least model or mathematical pattern to Aristotle had
the days of Albertus Magnus, have, in the opin- more than mere logical significance, can be safely
ion of James Bonar, yielded no satisfactory result neglected by the economist. However, it seems
since "except in regard to money there is no to be worth noting its ontological implication in
clear analysis of economic facts" supposed to Aristotle's philosophy in order to grasp how he
be found in Aristotle's work.' Accepting Bonar's has been moved to apply the theory of propor-
discouraging verdict as serious enough a warn- tion to his empirical inquiry. So uncommon and
ing, another attempt a t clarifying Aristotle's unexpected appears Aristotle's procedure to his
theory can be made only in the hope that our modern interpreters that they either minimize its
enriched knowledge of pre-Socratic philosophy, importance for the discussion of this empirical
primarily the Pythagorean tradition, accumu- topic or completely eliminate it from the presen-
lated since Bonar's influential book, may help tation of the master's thesis. True enough, the
shed some light on the master's c o n c e s s and explanation of the "model" itself meets with con-
methods. Such investigation seems doubly siderable difficulty but its position in the archi-
warranted in view of the fact that this dark tectural structure of his work can be securely
passage in the Ethics, exactly because of its established.
obscurity, through the ages has instigated pro- The essence of the resulting theorem should
vocative interpretations, and has kept alive be equally explicable. Exchange of goods in the
the interest in one of the fundamental issues of market is motivated by mutual need and regu-
economic theorizing. lated by the relative "value," the ability to
The objective of Aristotle's theory appears to satisfy want, of the skills applied to the produc-
be plain enough: it is the proof that every ex- tion of the goods to be exchanged. The fact
change of goods has to be an "exchange of that the theorem contains two perfectly con-
* T h e author expresses thanks t o the late Erich Frank sistent parts-one concerning the motive of ex-
who first discussed with him some basic ideas; t o Professor change and the other concerning the exchange
Kurt von Fritz of Columbia University for helpful criticism ratio of goods-has given rise to two t>*pesof
and corrections of the original draft of the manuscript misinterpretations. Either Aristotle is said to
and, most of all, to Professor Paul Oskar Kristeller of
Columbia University for many valuable suggestions and have developed two theories of exchange which
generous help in getting this paper published. Friends are inconsistent with and unrelated to each other,
and colleagues offered assistance in research and in the or he is supposed to have ventured into the field
preparation of the manuscript which was deeply appre- of the "labor theory of value." The latter mis-
ciated. Opinions expressed and errors made are, of course,
the sole responsibility of the author.
conception has been advanced, in mediaeval
Philosophy and political economy, 40, 2nd ed., London, times, bl- scholastic philosophers, and more
Sonnenschein, 1909. recently by classical philologists whose masters
JOSEF SOUDEK

were educated in the economic theory of Adam exegesis. However, we have tried to under-
Smith and John Stuart Mill. stand his thoughts within the social and intel-
As a matter of fact, Aristotle was not so much lectual framework of his own time as afforded
concerned with the value of goods as with the by most recent historical research. Reconstruc-
value of the human skills which have produced tion of procedure and purpose of Aristotle's theo-
them. The value of both, in Aristotle's view, is rizing was more of our concern than justifica-
determined by the degree of want satisfaction tion of his results. There can be but little doubt
they offer. This is for him the common denomi- that he has not given a satisfactory answer to the
nator of different goods and different skills re- fundamental question of every market economy,
quired for their production. The "equalization the rules of exchange, simply because he was
of skills," he spoke of, is to him identical with preoccupied with the isolated exchange between
an equal degree of utility yielded by propor- individuals and not with the exchange of goods
tionate amounts of goods produced by different by many sellers and buyers competing with each
skills. His is-to coin a phrase-a "theory of other. But it must be admitted that he has
the value of labor," diametrically opposed to the done spadework of high quality, and that the
"labor theory of value." Both theories try to inconsistencies of his endeavor are fewer than is
explain the rules governing the exchange of goods generally assumed.
in the market. But while one stipulates a meas- I
ure for the value of skilled labor and its produce,
the other proposes to give a measure for the - of economic -goods
T o Aristotle, the exchange
value of goods only. One expresses the value in the market was primarily an ethical problem:
of skilled labor in terms of the goods it "com- exchange of goods as the material content of
mands in the market"; the other determines the social relations can exist only as long as it repre-
value of goods to be exchanged in terms of the sents an exchange of equivalents. "For if this
labor they contain. be not so, there will be no exchange and no inter-
Aristotle realized, as every modern economist course" (Eth. Nic., V, 5, 1133a, 24).2 The "arts
does, that it is not easy to find an objective Passages of the Ethics are quoted from the translation
expression for this essentially subjective common of the Nicomchean Ethics by W . D. Ross, Ethica iVico-
machea, vol. 9 of The Works of Aristotle, Oxford, Clarendon
denominator. Money solves the problem in a Press, 1925; those of the Politics from the translation by
merely practical and superficial manner. T o B. Jowett, Politics, vol. 10 of the same edition, Oxford,
demonstrate that in exchange a real equality of 1921; the translation of the Metaphysics is that by W. D.
want satisfaction is accomplished, he employed Ross, hletuphysica, vol. 8 of the same edition, Oxford,
a rather difficult concept: the comparison by 1908; and the translation of the Rhetoric is by W. Rhys
Roberts, Rhetorica, vol. 11 of the same edition, Oxford,
each individual of the relative utilities of the 1924. The method of citation is the customary: the first
goods involved in exchange-the utility of what number (capital Roman numeral) refers to the book of the
one gives and what one receives. Equal ratios respective work; the second number (Arabic numeral) or
of both utilities to each party to the exchange capital letter refers t o the chapter of the book; the third
number t o the page in the Bekker-Berlin edition of the
means "exchange of equivalents." He thus Greek text of Aristotle's works (the small letter following
anticipated by more than two thousand years the page number indicates the column of the page) and
Jevons' theory of exchange. the fourth number (Arabic numeral) refers to the line on
This, we presume, is the essential content of the page of the Berlin edition. For example, Eth. lVic.,
Aristotle's theory. That its meaning stands out V, 4, 1132b, 12 means that the quoted sentence is from the
1Vicomachean Ethics, book V, chapter 4, in the English
less clearly than we have indicated goes partly translation; 1132b is the page and column where the Greek
to his account. 4 s will be shown in due course, text can be found in the Berlin edition and 12 is the line
Aristotle was not intent to engage in the forma- on the page of this edition. Reference to pagination of the
tion of anything resembling a systematic theory Greek original is necessary because the English translation
was compared with the original text.
of economics. He was, therefore, not aware of Parentheses in quotations are those of the translator
the place of his theorem in the context of a and signify that these sentences, in the opinion of the
science of economics. translator, are merely explanations of preceding statements
Our interpretation of Aristotle's approach to or references to earlier statements. In one instance (Eth.
the problem of exchange and his solution of it is, Nic., V, 5, 1133a, 14-16, in our quotation on page 61)
the translator put a sentence into parenthesis assuming
of course, not unconnected with the present that it was probably a n isolated note of Aristotle's inter-
status of economic thinking and thus probably polated by a n early editor. The author of this article does
as historically "determinated" as any previous not always concur with the translator's use of parentheses.
VOL. 96, NO. I, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 47

. . . would have been destroyed" (ibid., 14) if is inherent in the goods themselves; rather are
the partners to the exchange were not assured they assigned to them by man.
that what they give away and receive is of equal In the exchange of goods, each party to the
value. "Equality" of goods exchanged, some exchange is supposed to receive from the other
sort of "justice," is thus the premise and postu- party a quantity of goods in proportion to the
late of the exchange in the market. However, value of its respective skills. Goods as such,
exchange of goods takes place because what the apart from their relation to men, cannot be
parties desire is different from what they possess related to each other; it is the people who are
and offer; the goods offered are the product of a related to each other through the medium of
skill unlike the skill that has produced the desired goods. An exchange ratio of goods is neither a
goods. "For it is not two doctors that associate ratio of goods as such nor of people exchanging
for exchange, but a doctor and a farmer; or in these goods; it is a ratio simultaneously set be-
general people who are different and unequal; tween the people who "put to use in exchange"
but they must be equated" (ibid., 16). the goods and between the goods which "belong"
Plato has already exposed the division of labor, to them or are "due" to them.
the difference in skills, as the basis of exchange in The establishment of these ratios links ex-
the market (Republic, 369 B), but he has paid change to the principle of "justice" in general.
little attention to the way in which the products In order to understand the working of this prin-
of different skills "are equated." What he has ciple as it applies to exchange, we have to clarify
contributed to the solution of the problem will a whole set of concepts and also the methodo-
be discussed later; it must have appeared quite logical approach by which Aristotle has devel-
unsatisfactory to his disciple. '4ristotle1 there- oped his concepts and adapted them to concrete
fore, advanced the theory of exchange to the situations. The concepts relevant to our prob-
point where the paradox becomes apparent: lem are the idea of justice, the forms of the so-
goods are exchanged on account of their "in- called "particular" justice, and the distinction
equality" and yet on the basis of some sort of between nature and convention. As will be
"equality" that has to be established if exchange seen, these three concepts are interrelated with
is to be effected. The objective of Aristotle's each other. The idea of particular justice em-
theory is thus to find a principle that makes it braces its two forms--distributive and corrective
possible to "equate" what is apparently "un- justice-while the forms of justice correspond
equal." to the two opposites, "nature" and "conven-
If a modern thinker, a man of the industrial tion." Distributive justice is based on the
age, raises the question, according to what rule "natural" inequality of men, whereas corrective
are goods exchanged in the market, then he justice concerns itself with that equality of men
searches for something that these goods have in that is instituted by "convention." Further-
common. Modern economic theory is the theory more, the idea of justice and its two forms oper-
of goods and not of people using and producing ate on two different levels: they regulate the
goods. Not so with Aristotle. Distribution of relationships between men on the level of indi-
wealth and income, purchase and sale, lending vidual action (Ethics) as well as on the level of
and letting, or exchange in the market are social action (Politics). Finally, the idea of
human relations concerning money or economic justice and its two forms not only regulate
goods. Economic goods have no "value" as human action; they also reveal the ontological
such; they may become valuable to people if pattern of all things existent. I t is a pattern of
put to use in particular conditions. ,4ristotle1s abstract relationships expressible in terms of
famous distinction between the two "uses" of mathematical proportions.
goods, the use in consumption and the use in Since it does not matter a t what point we
exchange (Pol. I, 9, 1257a, 6 ff.) has little in begin to disentangle this complex of intercon-
common with the spirit of the "value in use" nected categories, we choose to start with the
and "value in exchange" of Adam Smith and the methodology. I t is the strangest and, to our
Classical Economists. Neither of the two uses thinking, the most difficult aspect of Aristotle's
reasoning. Aristotle was not striving to build up
Where he disagrees with the English translation of the
Greek original he gives his own translation in square a philosophical "system" as we know it from
brackets, sometimes inserting an explanatory remark to modern European philosophy. He did not
the translation into the quotation, also in square brackets. concern himself with constructing a self-suffi-
48 JOSEF SOUDEK soc
[PROC. AMER. P H ~ L .

cient and in itself consistent system of ethics has a relation to persons, and that equals ought to
or politics, "an edifice of dogma," revolving have equality. But there still remains a question:
around unalterable categories apart from histor- equality or inequality of what?
ical and empirical observations. Rather did he Since he deals in this context with the distribu-
form his categories "as an instrument of living tion of power in a state, he mentions four
research," as Werner Jaeger put it.3 distinctive elements in equality or inequality:
Aristotle analyzed the various forms of just virtue, wealth, birth, and power. Equality
behavior to discover the pattern of justice exists, therefore, only for those who are equal in
underlying human action in its individual and regard to one of these qualities. What of the
social aspects. His aim was not to categorize the others? They are to be treated "unequally"
realm of experience by applying one or a variety although not arbitrarily. Theirs is a claim to a
of abstract principles to his empirical data. treatment in proportion to their share in the
He construed "models" abstracted from empir- respective quality. In the state Aristotle thinks
ical observations to clarify and classify human to be the best, i.e., in aristocracy, in which the
behavior; yet he referred back to reality to most virtuous rule, equality would exist among
contest the validity of his models and to modify the most virtuous. The others would partic-
them in order to make them fit his ever changing ipate in the rule in accordance with the state of
experience. their virtue and they would be ruled in view of
Aristotle's "models," however, have not the state of their virtue. Because "that which
merely heuristic character. His procedure tran- is right in the sense of being equal is to be
scends the more obvious purpose of classifying considered with reference to the advantage of
and defining various types of human action; it the state, and the common good of the citizen.
lays bare the ontological nature of what is And a citizen is one who shares in governing
known from and observed in social practice. and being governed" (Pol., 111, 13, 128313, 40-
"The human world of state and society and 42). This is also true of states which, in
mind appears to him not caught in the incalcul- .Aristotle's opinion, are not the best ones, but
able mobility of irrecapturable historical destin?., still desirable ones such as the "constitutional"
. . . but as founded fast in the unalterable government as perceived in Solon's reform. In
permanence of forms that, while the>- change a "constitutional" government there exists a
within certain limits, remain identical in essence conflict between the rich and virtuous on the
and p ~ r p o s e . " ~The empirical behavior of man one hand and "the many" on the other. A
reveals a pattern that, a t the same time, is a compromise has to be effected; it will be reached
design and a nomothetic rule. People live and by assigning certain functions to the rich and
act "justly," whenever their actions are in virtuous and other functions to the many who
harmony with this pattern; whenever they are neither rich nor virtuous.
deviate from it, they destroy "justice," the
fundament of everj- societ>~. The realization of . . . What power should be assigned to the mass
of freemen and citizens, who are not rich and have
this correspondence between observable behavior
no personal merit? . . . There is a danger allowing
and its ontological pattern constitutes the pecu- them to share the great offices of state, for their
liarity of Aristotle's methodological approach. folly will lead them into error and their dishonesty
What is, then, "justice"? Essentiallj , it is a into crime. But there is a danger also in not letting
principle of distribution, be it of wealth, honor, them share, for a state in which many poor men are
or power. In a wa!-, it is equalitarian; in excluded from office will necessarily be full of ene-
another way it is not. It is "equalit) for equals, mies. The only way of escape is to assign to them
inequality for unequals.' ' Aristotle describes it some deliberative and judicial functions. For this
thus in the Politics (111, 12, 1282b, 16-22) : reason Solon and certain other legislators give them
the power of electing to offices, and of calling the
All men think justice to be a sort of equality; and magistrates to account, but they do not allow them
to a certain extent they agree in the philosophical to hold office singly . . . (Pol., 111, 11, 1281b, 23-
distinctions which have been laid down by us about 24).
Ethics. For the)- admit that justice is a thing and
Justice refers to "a relation between persons
Werner Jaeger, Aristotle. Fundamentals of the history concerning something" or a relation of persons
of his development, 374. Trans. by Richard Robinson,
Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1934. to something. But neither is it any relation
"bzd., 389. nor a general relation such as "inequality" or
VOL. 96, NO. 1, 19.521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE

"equality." This is -exactly the pitfall of the simply an act of wickedness, an "injustice"
oligarchs and the democrats, in Aristotle's eyes, of the kind Aristotle calls "universal." On the
that the ones identify justice with inequality in other hand, a case of "particular" injustice would
general and the democrats with equality in be adultery committed for the sake of gain. If
general (Pol. 111, 9, 1280a). T o say that justice a man commits adultery and pays for it, then
is anv relation a t all is to sav too little: and to he is simply self-indulgent and lacking in virtue.
maintain that justice is either equality or in- By paying for his weakness, he accepts the
equality is to say too much. Justice expresses a penalty for his injustice. However, if he gets
relation between persons in accordance with paid for adultery, then he is not self-indulgent
their specific relation to something. For ex- but "grasping." And every action motivated
ample, the social relation between persons of bl- the desire for gain falls under the type of
varying degree of virtue is just if their status in "particular" justice or injustice, as the case may
society corresponds to their degree of virtuous- be.
ness. The abstract principle of justice, therefore, "Economic" dealings, i.e., human relations
is "proportion." "This, then, is what the just concerning economic goods, ainong other deal-
is-the proportional; the unjust is what violates ings, are subject to the rule of "particular"
the proportion" (Eth. Nic., V, 3, 1131b, 16-17). justice since the)- are motivated by the pleasure
he principle of justice corresponds to a derived from gain. There are three forms of
mathematical Dattern that underlies all individ- "particular" justice: distributive, corrective, and
ual and social relationships which are "iust." "commutative" justice. Aristotle, in analyzing
I t is proportion. In arithmetic a proportion is particular justice in general, mentions only two
a rule by which, when three numbers are given, forms, the distributive and the corrective, the
a fourth is found having the same ratio to the first concerning the distribution of wealth and
third as the second to the first. Or, in general, the second relating to business transactions.
proportion is an equality or identity between Exchange of goods in the market presents a
ratios (Eth. Nic., V, 3, 1121a, 31). special case of economic dealings, somehow
related to both distribution and business trans-
T h e just, therefore, involves a t least four terms; for
the persons for whom i t is in fact just are two, and
actions, yet not identical with either of them
the things in which i t is manifested, the objects dis- and, therefore, requiring a different treatment as
tributed, are two. And the same equality \\.ill exist far as the principle of particular justice is
between the persons and between the things con- concerned. I t involves and presupposes both
cerned; for as the latter-the things concerned-are forms of justice though it belongs neither to the
related, so are the former; . . . (Eth. Nic., V, 3, one nor the other; it constitutes a third form
1131a, 18-22). and follows its own pattern, empirically and
mathematically. The failure to recognize the
nature of this pattern has been the source of all
Justice, not as an abstract idea but as a con- the misunderstandings and misinterpretations
cretely definable principle, governs man's conduct which have obscured the meaning of Aristot~e's
in his dealings with his fellow-men. Depending theory of exchange.
on the sort of dealings and the motivation of it, Distributive iustice deals with distribution in
there are two types of justice: the universal and the more narrow sense of the word. I t regulates,
the particular. While universal justice "is e.g., the distribution of returns on funds in a
concerned with all the objects with which the partnership. In this case "the distribution is
good man is concerned," particular justice made from the common funds according to the
relates to "honor or money or safety-or that same ratio which the funds put into the business
which includes all these, if we had a single name by the partners bear to one another" (Eth. Nic.,
for it-and its motive is the pleasure that arises V, 4 , 1131b, 29-31). Aristotle himself gives an
from gain . . ." (Eth. Nic., V , 2, 1130b, 1-5). example of such distribution in another context:
T o illustrate this dichotomy, '4ristotle gives, "It would not be just that he who paid one mina
among others, the following examples: A man should have the same share of a hundred minae,
fails to help a friend with money out of meanness. whether of the principal or of the profits, as he
Seither does he gain or loose by his behavior who paid the remaining ninety-nine" (Pol., 111,
nor does his friend. Since no gain was involved 9, 1280a128-31). The distribution of returns-
on either side, the failing friend committed 1 : 99-would correspond to the contributions to
50 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC. AMER. PHIL. SOC.

the common fund, namely, 1 : 99. If we express ematical proportion because A and B are no
this ratio in terms of abstract magnitudes, so magnitudes or quantities in the mathematical
that A and B represent returns, and C and D sense; they are logical symbols and as such they
the respective shares in the jointly raised cannot be fitted into a strictly mathematical
capital, then A would be to B as C is to D. proportion. Aristotle has had two, for him,
The mathematical pattern underlying distri- completely legitimate reasons to do so. The
butive justice is that of "geometric proportion" first one has been explained already: he was
-A : B : : C: D. Aristotle calls this a "discrete unable to conceive of goods outside their relation
proportion," because the middle terms-B and to people. A share in a partnership as such did
C-are different. In a geometric proportion the not deserve a return; rather was it the man who
first term and the third term and the second and had contributed a share of one mina who
the fourth term can be brought into conjunction deserved a return in proportion to his contribu-
(alternand0)-A : C: :B : D-or the first term can tion. A : C makes good sense if C represents the
be added to the third term and the second term amount of money which goes to A as his return
to the fourth term (componendo) and then the on his share of capital; but such ratio is no
ratio of the sum of the first and the third term mathematical relation. The other reason is less
to the sum of the second and the fourth term obvious and rather hypothetical. Aristotle, in
\\.ill be equal to the ratio of the first to the confounding or blending good mathematics with
second term-A + +
C :B D : :A :B . "The a sort of symbolic language, was following a
conjunction, then, of the term A with C and of tradition which he apparently accepted as
B with D is what is just in distribution; . . . for generally known and understood, namely the
the proportional is intermediate, and the just is Pythagorean social philosophy but which, con-
proportional" (Eth. Nit., V, 3, 1131b, 9-11). trar). to his assumption, was not fully compre-
I f we applj this formula to our above example, hended either by his own pupils or his contem-
then A would stand for the first man's contribu- poraries. The author of the ,%fagnu Moralia
and Speusippus, Plato's successor and ilristotle's
tion of one mina and B for the contribution of
rival, testify to our contention. -lristotle him-
the other man of 99 minae-A : B : : 1 : 99. If the self has censured Speusippus for his mistaken
return were 100 minae, then A would receive interpretation of Pythagorean use of mathemat-
1'100 and B 99 '100 in accordance with the ics, though mainly in the field of mataphysics
alternando form of the proportion-1 : 1,100 (see Met.. N. 3. 1090b-1091a). In c h a ~ t e r111
: : 99 : 99) 100. The intermediate, the criterion of this essay we shall submit evidence for our
of justice, Alristotleis looking for, is, therefore, h>-pothesis as to this aspect of ,Aristotlels
the proportion 1 : 99; the just is the proportional. thinking; a t this point, however, we like to
The simple form of proportion and the alter- leave it as a preliminary statement.
nando of it are mathematical proportions as nre The other form of particular justice, the
would use them, too. In determining geometric "corrective" justice, "plays a rectifying part in
proportion in distributive justice, however, transactions between man and man" and applies
Aristotle had another form in mind, viz. the to two kinds of "transactions," voluntary and
componendo. The four terms of the proportion involuntary ones. "Voluntary transactions . . .
constituting the pattern of particular justice [are] sale, purchase, loan for consumption,
consist of t\vo terms representing persons and pledging, loan for use, depositing, letting
two terms representing things (Eth. Nic., V, 3, . . .," while "involuntary transactions" include
1131a, 19), as explained above. A and B would theft and robbery with violence JEth. b-ic., V, 2,
stand for the two partners of the partnership 1131a, 2-1 1). That Aristotle summarizes actions
L ~ ~Ciand d D for either their shares in the common of so divergent a character within one category
fund or the returns on their shares. The propor- (uvvaXXaypa~a)will prove to be not without good
tion \vould then be A + +
C :B D : : C :D. Part- reason. Here we shall confine ourselves a t
ner A and his share of one mina are to partner B first to a discussion of the "voluntary trans-
and his share of 99 minae as 1 mina is to 99 actions" which occur in every day's business
rninae; correspondingly, partner A and partner practice and are partially related to the exchange
B and their respective returns on their contribu- of goods. The ~ r o b l e mas posed in "corrective"
tions would be as 1 100 mina to 99/100 mina. justice is that of a "loss" or "gain" or deviations
Now, this is to us not acceptable as a math- from the intermediate, the mean. He writes:
YOL. 96, so. I, 19521 ,-\RIS'TOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 51

These names, both loss and gain, have come from of athletes has to determine the right amount of
voluntary exchange; for to have more than one's own food for his trainees. Shall he give them 10
is called gaining, and to have less than one's original pounds of food for a meal or 2 pounds? Or shall
share is called losing, e.g., in buying and selling and he give them the "happy medium"? The trainer
in all other matters in which the law has left people will probably do none of the three things.
free to make their own terms; but when they get Ten pounds of food for a meal, the one extreme,
neither more nor less but just what belongs to them-
selves, they say that they have their own and that is too much for a beginner but not for an accom-
they neither lose nor gain. Therefore, the just is plished wrestler, while two pounds of food is too
the intermediate between a sort of gain and a sort little even for a beginner. Therefore, he will
of loss . . . ; it consists in having an equal amount determine the amount of food not in terms of
before and after the transaction (Eth. Nic., V, 4, general standards but in view of the weight
1132b, 11-20). -
and gvmnastic accom~lishmentof his trainees.
*

The "mean relatively to us" is thus a medium


Corrective justice follows the pattern of between two extremes both of which could be
"arithmetic proportion." Contrary to geometric considered as possible shares in distribution.
proportion which is "discrete," arithmetic pro- This kind of mean may be required in cases where
portion is "continuous." A proportion is con- the proper share cannot be determined in exact
tinuous if the middle terms are identical. In quantities but only in general ways and where
other words, a proportion is continuous if the the shares have to be corrected in view of
intermediate, the middle term, "is equidistant particular personal circumstances. The "mean
from each of the extremes . . . for it exceeds relatively to us" would represent a genuine
and is exceeded by an equal amount" (Eth. Nic., correction of distribution which otherwise has
11, 6, 1106a, 29-32). An arithmetic proportion followed the rule of geometric proportion.
would be, to quote one of his examples, the The mean applying to voluntary transactions
following equation: 10 - 6 = 6 - 2. This is is the one "which is one and the same for all
strictly speaking not a proportion but a series men." I t is a mean between things (pCaov TOG
of numbers in arithmetical progression. Yet in ~ ~ i r y ~ a r oregardless
s) of their relation to par-
Aristotle's time the term "proportion" (ivaXoyia), ticular persons though not to people generally.
originally reserved for a series of numbers in The four terms are now material objects ex-
geometrical progression-where the intermediate pressed or expressible in quantities, and the
terms exceed and are exceeded by the same middle terms are identical in nature and quantity
ratio-was already extended to all manners of (as explained by Aristotle in a more general and
numerical series5 The equality in such propor- principal manner in Physics, VIII, 8, 262a, and
tion arises from the fact that the sum of the Metaphysics, B, 4, 99913). The transactions to
middle terms, the "means," is equal to the sum which corrective justice applies are purchase,
of the "extremes." In the above example sale, loans, deposits, etc.-transactions, then,
10 + 2 =6 +
6. If the four terms of arith- in which one object only is involved and this
metic proportion are a,b,c,d, then a - b = c - d is defined in monetary terms or in specified
quantities such as the amount of bushels of wheat
Corrective justice concerns itself with estab- in a "loan for use" to a farmer. Aristotle has
lishing equality by finding the mean between the failed to give us an example of a transaction
extremes, the intermediate between excess and subject to corrective justice; we offer, therefore,
defect. The "mean," which is the "just," of one of our own-following Burnet in the inter-
what and for whom? I n reply t o this question, pretation of this by no means unequivocal
-
--\ristotle distinguishes between two kinds of concept-presuming that it represents Aristotle's
means in arithmetic proportion: the one "which intentions. A man has bought a house for 12
is one and the same for all men" and the other minae. After taking over, he discovers damages
which is a mean "relatively to us.'' T o illustrate which, in his opinion, lower the value of the
his distinction, Aristotle gives the following property to 8 minae. He goes to court and
example of a "mean relatively to us": A trainer sues for the restoration of the 4 minae by which,
he claims, he was overcharged. The seller of
J. Burnet, T h e ethics of Aristotle, 216-217, London, the house still claims that the house was worth
hlethuen, 1900. Burnet cites the three "proportions" of
Theon of Smyrna as a n example of this use of the term the 12 minae which he has received. Sow, the
"proportion." judge establishes a value of the house which will
52 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC.
AMER.
PHIL. SOC.

be the intermediate between the two claims, between the old landowning and the rising
i.e., 10 minae. Thus he acted according to the mercantile classes were accompanied, among
rule of arithmetic proportion: 12 - 10 = 10 other ideological antagonisms, by a fight over
- 8. According to the expression of Aristotle, the nature of justice. The adherents of the
in the original deal, the seller has "gained" 2 tribal organization, in which the political power
minae and the buyer has "lost" 2 minae; there- rested with the landowners and the oligarchic
fore, the seller has had a "double excess": his rulers, saw in justice a principle derived from the
own "gain" and the "loss" of the seller. "For natural inequality of men and protecting the
when something is subtracted from one of two social institutions built on it. The "natural
equals and added to the other, the other is in laws" were declared unchangeable. Their op-
excess by these two" (Eth. ,?iic., V, 4, 1132a, ponents, representing the merchants and manu-
32-35). The equals Aristotle is referring to facturers and striving for a democratic rule,
are the amount of money the seller should have considered justice a principle of equalization and
received and the amount of money the purchaser the laws based on this principle subject to
should have paid, as ruled by the judge. These change and modification as the conditions of
two amounts, the middle terms of the proportion, society required. Pericles' "equality before the
are the two sides of the same transaction, the law" served them as an illustration of what they
outlay of the purchaser and the receipt of the understood by justice.
seller, and are, of course, identical. They Though it is difficult to trace the origin of the
represent the "value" of the object as estab- concept of justice as "conventional" law, it is
lished by the judge, and express the "just price." reasonable to assume that it has sprung up in
The judge has acted as "a sort of personified the circle of the Sophists and that it has been
justice"; Xristotle calls him, by way of analogy, used by them as a philosophical argument.
the "intermediate" itself. In establishing the But we have evidence that it has been known
"just price," the judge has found an intermediate and discussed in other quarters of Greek society,
"which is one and the same for all men." "For too.6 T o say that laws are man-made does not
it makes no difference whether a good man has imply that they are arbitrary; though change-
defrauded a bad man or a bad man a good one able, they follow a set rule and as distinct a
. . .; the law looks only to the distinctive char- principle as "natural" laws. Protagoras seems
acter of the injury, and treats the parties as equal to have stated that clearly enough (Thaetetus,
. . ." (Eth. Nic., I-,4, 1132a, 2-5). Whereas 172B). Plato combined the new 'conventional-
distributive justice determines the proportion ism" with his own "naturalism" in the Republic
among natural unequals in accordance with (369 B,C) to explain the origin of the city;
their merits and capacities, corrective justice according to him, the city owed its existence to
treats the parties to a deal as equals b~ looking an "agreement" between citizens, yet on the
a t them exclusively as agents in a typical basis of a "naturalistic" ~rinciple, viz. the
transaction and abstracting from the natural division of labor.7 Xristotle followed his teacher
inequality of their individualities and circum- in this combination of naturalism and conven-
stances. Corrective justice is universal in
scope and abstract in character. e Ernest Barker, Greek political theory. Plato and his
The contrast between the two forms of partic- predecessors, 2nd ed., 64-85, London, Methuen, 1925, offers
ular justice thus implies more than a mere the best discussion of the antithesis of nature (physis)
and law (nomos) in Sophist philosophy. He illustrates the
difference between geometric and arithmetic antithesis by analyzing a fragment from the writings of
proportion; it involves also the antithesis the Sophist Antiphon. I n more recent literature on Greek
between "nature" and "law" or "nature" and political theory this antithesis was treated, among others.
"convention" as the two opposing principles of by K. R. Popper, T h e open society and its enemies, 1. The
spell of Plato, London, G. Routledge & Sons, 1945.
justice. Distributive justice is "natural justice," Popper maintains that, apart from Pindar and Herodotus,
corrective justice the justice as instituted by the Sophists Antiphon, Hippias and Protagoras were the
laws of society and conventional agreement pioneers in the field (p. 204). Cf. also A. D . Winspear,
between people. This is Xristotle's answer to T h e genesis of Pluto's thought, N . Y . , Dryden Press, 1940.
one of the great ideological conflicts in Greek and, \Tinspear cites the Pythagorean Philolaus as using the
phrase "by nature and not by custom," although not in
particularly, Athenian society in the fifth and connection with justice, and the materialist -4rchelaus as
fourth centuries. The breakdown of tribalism applying it to justice (p. 144).
in the sixth century and the subsequent warfare Popper, op. cit., 66.
VOL. 96, NO. 1, I ~ S Z ] ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 53

tionalism, and blended it with elements of warning against confusing distributive and
Pythagorean theory. I t is interesting to note corrective justice with the principle that regu-
in Aristotle's theory to what aspects of individual lates exchange of goods was given no attention.
and social life the two principles apply: "natural" Aristotle says: "Now, 'reciprocity' fits neither
justice rules, among other departments, that of distributive nor rectificatory justice. . . . But in
distribution of wealth and partly also the associations for exchange this sort of iustice
u

exchange of goods insofar as exchange of goods is -


does hold men together-reci~rocitv in accord-
based on the division of labor; "conventional" ante with a proportion and not on the basis of
justice regulates, again among other depart- precisely equal returns" (Eth. Nic., V, 5, 1132b,
.merits, that of business transactions and con- 23-25).
tracts and the exchange of goods insofar as
exchange is associated with money, the typical In order to understand why Aristotle has
creation of a mercantile societv. "Natural" introduced a third form of particular justice,
justice loses its absoluteness if not its primacy whv he has defined the forms of articular
and becomes confined to one realm of society; iustice in mathematical terms, and why he has
the other realm is handed over to L'conventional" assigned logical categories an ontological char-
justice. acter, we have to go briefly into Aristotle's
The twofold connection of distributive and relation to Pythagorean philosophy.
corrective justice with the exchange of goods
makes it evident why the commentators of in exchange was confused with corrective justice we quote
from the two widely used books on the history of Greek
Aristotle, from a t least Thomas Aquinas on, philosophy by Zeller and Ueberweg. Zeller in his authori-
until today, with few exceptions, have main- tative History of Greek Philosophy says Aristotle "dis-
tained that there are two principles of particular tinguishes justice in dividing from justice in correcting.
justice only and that exchange of goods belongs The first has t o apportion the honors and advantages
which accrue t o the individual from the community ac-
either to the one or the other. ~referablvthe cording t o the worth of the recipient, the second must
latter one. The single exception to this tradi- see that the balance of gain and loss is kept on either side
tion in recent times, of whom we know, is D. G. in voluntary contracts. . . . For the first, Aristotle per-
Ritchie, the English philosopher and historian versely maintains, the principle of geometrical proportion
of the philosophy of law. Ritchie asserted that holds good, for the second the principle of arithmetical
proportion" (italics are ours). Eduard Zeller, Outlines of
Aristotle distinguished three types of justice, the history of Greek philosophy, Trans. by Alleyne and
the third one being what he named "Catallactic" Abbot, 212, N. Y., H. Holt, 1890. Zeller has toned down
or "Commutative" J u s t i ~ e . ~He further pointed his disapproval of Aristotle's method in subsequent edi-
out that each of the three principles follows a tions of his work. In the 13th edition he writes: "For the
distinct mathematical formula; the formula of first-as Aristotle curiously observes-the principle of
geometrical proportion holds good" (italics are ours).
"Commutative Justice" is "Reciprocal Propor- Zeller, Outlines of the history of Greek philosophy, 13th ed.,
tion." Ritchie's hypothesis was rejected by as revised by W. Nestle and translated by L. R. Palmer, 191,
eminent an authority as Burnetg and apparently N. Y., Harcourt, 1931. In another work on Aristotle and
went unnoticed by other scholars. The more the earlier peripatetics, translated by Costello and Muir-
head, N. Y., Longmans, Green, 1897, Zeller deals more
recent editors and commentators of the Ethics closely with the concept of "proportionate reciprocity' '
continue to adhere to the traditional interpreta- but is unable t o see its relation to either distributive or
tion in face of Aristotle's own statement to the corrective justice (2: 172, n. 2). Friedrich Ueberweg, too,
contrary and in spite of the difficulty to fit distinguishes two types of "particular" justice and, prob-
exchange of goods into either of the two types of ably following Thomas Aquinas' practice, confounds cor-
rective and commutative justice. I n his popular History
particular justice. Aristotle's insistence that of philosophy (trans. from the 4th German ed. by G. S.
the three types of justice correspond to definite Morris, N. Y., C. Scribner's Sons, 1903), he writes:
mathematical patterns was easily dismissed as a "Justice . .. is further divisible into two species, of which
fancy if not as something worse.1 And his the one is applied in the distribution of honors and posses-
sions among the members of a society, while the other takes
Aristotle's subdivision of "Particular Justice," Classical the form of commutation in intercourse or trade. .. .
Review, 8 : 185-192, London, 1894. Ritchie found a lonely .
Distributive justice . . rests on geometrical proportion.
forerunner of his own hypothesis in Pufendorf who made . ..
. . Commutative justice . proceeds by arithmetical
the same distinction in his, De Jure Naturae et Gentium and not by geometrical proportion, since it regards not
(p. 191, n. 1).
the moral worth of the persons involved, but only the ad-
The Ethics of Aristotle, 217.
vantages gained or injury suffered by them. . .. I t is the
lo T o cite examples of how Aristotle's mathematical arithmetical equality whose place in the economy is justly
patterns of justice were regarded and how reciprocal justice vindicated by Aristotle" (1: 175).
54 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC.AMER.PHIL.SOC.

We are fully aware that the affinity of Aristotle's nature such as two amounts of money, the
reasoning with Pythagorean doctrines was not problem consists in finding the proper amount
solely based on his own acquaintance with and that is the "mean." But in exchange the
Pythagoreanism but was mediated also through two goods are not identical or, as he calls it,
the influence of Pythagorean concepts in Plato's not "equal" (iuov) ; they have to be "equalized"
work. How strongly Plato's own thought on before the proper price can be established.
such fundamental issues as the cosmology bears Reciprocity takes place "in accordance with a
the imprint of Pythagorean reflections ma), proportion and not on the basis of equality"
be seen in the Timaeus. Furthermore, the (K~T hvaXoyiav
' ~ a ~i i Kj ~ T
iu6rqra).
' T o identify
concept of eternal forms underlying the observ- "reciprocity" with corrective justice or justice
able facts of natural and social life may belong to in general, as the Pythagoreans have done, is,
a much older and more general tradition of therefore, incorrect. Modern commentators of
Greek intellectual life. But the Pythagoreans the Ethics have accused Aristotle of imputing
have given this old idea a new version and a into the theory of the Pythagoreans what they
more distinct form. And Aristotle, on his part, cannot have meant. They maintain that the
has put Pythagorean methods and concepts to Pythagoreans have used a numerical formula
a more specific use than Plato; he has employed without ethical implications to explain exchange
them in his analysis of concrete social phenom- or that the term "reciprocity" signified to them
ena. Pythagorean mathematical and symbolical the same as to Aristotle.12 We think that we
concepts served him both as ontological cat- can trust Aristotle's knowledge of Pythagorean
egories and heuristic principles. Werner Jaeger philosophy which was more complete than ours
pointed to this feature in Aristotle's writings: can possibly be. More important seems to us
T h e old geometrical cosmos of t h e G r e e k s w a s the fact that Aristotle in this context e x ~ r e s s l ~
differentiated b u t n o t broken b y Aristotle's p i c t u r e refers to the Pythagoreans when discussing
of t h e world. T h e new ideas of t h e f o u r t h c e n t u r y exchange, and that he states his deviation on
were introduced i n t o i t s typical outlines. R e a l i t y this point from their teachings which he appears
is now seen f r o m within; i t is n o longer solid, b u t t o to have faithfully accepted otherwise.
a certain e x t e n t t r a n s p a r e n t . Aristotle completes T o s ~ e a k of Aristotle's relation to the
t h e reception of P l a t o n i s m i n t o t h e o r d i n a r y Greek Pythagoreans is to put it too generally. Pythag-
picture of t h e \vorld.ll oreanism covers a broad range of ideas from
Yet Aristotle has not simply adopted Pytha- esoteric mysticism and political reformism to
gorean notions. He has, a t the same time, re- a rationalistic mathematical theory. Aristotle
fined them as tools of analvsis. This becomes was apparently most attracted to the rationalistic
quite apparent in the way in which he applied elements in Pythagoreanism but not disinclined
the Pythagorean concept of "reciprocity" to his to adapt discriminatingly some of their political
theory of exchange. In introducing the principle theorems and metaphysical speculations. The
of "reciprocity" as a third form of particular authority of his information on Pythagorean
justice he registers serious reservations toward philosophy and the source of some of his own
the manner in which the Pythagoreans used it reflections in the field of social theorj- were hereby
(Eth. Nic., IT, 5 , 1132b, 21ff.). His argument Archytas and his school, a particular group of
seems to run like this: The Pythagoreans have philosophers to whom he referred as the "so-
meant by "reciprocity" exchange of equal things called" Pythagoreans.
in the sense of the "lex talionis." the Biblical -1rchytas who lived in Tarentum in the second
"an eve for an eve." If this were so, "reci~roc- half of the fourth century was a splendid figure,
ity" would form the principle of corrective a man of great versatilit). and remarkable
justice. In dealing with things of identical accomplishments in many fields. He was a
l1 O p . cit., 389-390; cf. also Winspear, op. cit., 96. Win- l2 SO J . A. Stewart, Aiotes o n the Nicomachean Ethics of
spear says that the principle of "mathematics as a ground dristotle 1: 462, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1892. Harold
of explanation" for phenomena "seems to have been used Cherniss is inclined to follow Stewart's criticism of Aristotle
by the Pythagoreans, and was certainly used by their and to give even more credit to the Pythagoreans. He
disciple Plato . . . as a static and conceptual 'ground of writes: "It is not, however, certain that the Pythagoreans
explanation' underlying isolated and atomic appearances did not rather mean to express by the word [bv.r~xsrrovBb~]
. . ." in contrast to the materialist philosophers who reciprocal proportionality." Aristotle's criticism o f Preso-
used the same principle as a dynamic concept for the cratic Philosophy, 226, n. 39, Baltimore. Johns Hopkins
explanation of change. Press. 1935.
VOL. 96, KO. 1, 19521 XRISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE

professional soldier and was elected seven times Of Archytas' various achievements in rnath-
as commander-in-chief of his native city, an ematics and the sciences, only one is pertinent
honor never bestowed on any other commander to our study. I t is his theory of proportions.
in Tarentum. He won fame as a philosopher, In his book On Music, of which a fragment has
mathematician, musician, inventor, and author. come down to us, he defined the three proportions
He came to power pobably close to the time of which were supposedly developed by Pythagoras
Plato's journey to Sicily in 367 B.C. Plato himself: the arithmetic, the geometric, and the
made the acquaintance of -4rchytas in about 368 "subcontrary" which he renamed the "harmonic"
and a friendship ensued between the two men in proportion. He defined them thus:
the course of which Flato cemented relations \Ye h a v e t h e a r i t h m e t i c m e a n when, of t h r e e t e r m s ,
between Archytas and the tyrant of Syracuse, t h e first exceeds t h e second by t h e s a m e a m o u n t a s
Dionysius 11, the friend of Plato. Aristotle, t h e second exceeds t h e t h i r d ; t h e geometric m e a n
through his teacher, was therefore well acquainted when t h e first is t o t h e second a s t h e second is t o t h e
with the teachings of Archytas. He documented t h i r d ; t h e "subcontrary" ~ h i c hwe call t h e " h a r -
his interest in the great Pythagorean by writing monic" when t h e t h r e e t e r m s a r e such t h a t , by w h a t -
a work on the philosophy of Archytas and in e v e r p a r t of itself t h e first exceeds t h e second, t h e
giving extracts from Archytas' books in one second exceeds t h e third by t h e s a m e p a r t of t h e
of his essays.13 third.16
Archytas' connection with the philosophy and An example of the harmonic proportion given
political ambitions of the Pythagoreans is by no by the Pythagorean Philolaus is 1 2 - 8:s - 6
means clear. For good reasons, Aristotle refers = 12:6. In this proportion the first term, 12,
to him as a "so-called" Pythagorean as Plato
did, too. I t is true that Archytas liked to
exceeds the second term, 8, by of itself, viz., +
4, and the second term, 8, exceeds the third, 6,
create the impression that his innovations in
mathematics and the sciences-mechanics and
+
by of the third term, viz., 2. "That is, if b is
the harmonic mean between a and c , and if
astronomy, mainly-were merely a continuation a
of the Pythagorean tradition; Erich Frank a =b
n
+ c
n
+
-, then b = c - whence in fact
suggested that Archytas did that in order to
confer on his new theories the flair of tradition a- --b - a- or -1 - -1 = -1 - -."
1
and dignity and thus to make them more b - c c' c b b a
acceptable to his contemporaries. Actually, Heath has given the following explanation of the
Archvtas' serious endeavors in the exact sciences nature of the three proportions: "If a > b > c,
had little in common with the auasi-scientific the following formulae show the first three
and numerological doctrines of the older Pythag- means, the arithmetic, geometric, and harmonic.
oreans and their probably mythical founder.14
Formula Equivalent
The same is true of him as a statesman and
political reformer. Although his "political prin- a-b a b c
( 1 ) b - -c ; --6 ; - a+c = 2b (arithmetic).
ciples were strongly influenced by Pythagorean-
ism," he was not an exponent of the rule of the a-b a
Pythagorean club in Tarentum.15 - ;
(2) b-c - ac = b2 (geometric).
l3 Diogenes Laertius in his Lioes of eminent philosophers,
a-b a 1 1 2
- + - = -(harmonic).""
V , 25, mentions among the writings of Aristotle a work
"On the philosophy of ,L\rchptas," consisting of three (3) - - - -
b-c c a c b
books, and one book "Extracts from the Timaeus and
from the Works of Archytas." Both works of Aristotle The harmonic proportion, therefore, is the
are lost. Erich Frank infers from this and other evidence
that Archytas has been the main source of Xristotle's
reciprocal of the arithmetic proportion. In
information about Pythagoreanism. Erich Frank, Plato modern language, as pointed out earlier, we
und die sogenannten Pythagoreer, 361, n. 196, Halle, &lax have reserved the term "proportion" to the
Niemeyer, 1923. geometric proportion and consider the arithmetic
l 4 Erich Frank, ibid., 75-76.
15 Kurt Von Fritz, Pythagorean politics i n southern Italy. l6 Sir Thomas L. Heath, A manual o f Greek mathematics,
.4n analysis of the sources, 97, N. Y . , Columbia Univ. 51, Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1931. The above quoted
Press, 1940. Von Fritz notes that Archytas "was not passage is apparently Heath's translation of fragment 45B
strategos because he was a Pythagorean and because the in Hermann Diels, Die Fragmente der Vorsokratiker, 271-
Ppthagoreans ruled his city, but he was freely elected 272, Berlin, Weidmannsche Buchhandlung, 1903.
under constitutional procedure." l7 Heath, ibid., 52.
JOSEF SOUDEK

and harmonic proportions as series of numbers order in a society of unequals is therefore a rule
or terms. The arithmetic proportion is a which establishes relations between its members
series of numbers in arithmetic progression as according to their relative worth and puts
2,6,10, and the harmonic proportion is a series individuals in positions corresponding to their
of reciprocals in arithmetic progression as in abilities. The mathematical (symbolic) expres-
6, 4,h. sion of such rule is the "geometric proportion."
In Aristotle's time these were the three Archytas is quoted as having said that the law of
fundamental proportions. The Pythagoreans a state is in conformity with nature "when it
have added another seven to the original three imitates the justice of nature. This is propor-
but the first three proportions retained their tional justice, which comes to each man according
prominent place in the teaching of the Py- to each man's worth."lg The rule of proportion
thagorean~. The Plato-commentator Theon of seems to be an ideal justification of an aris-
Sml,rna (second century A.D.) wrote in a Seo- tocratic society and undoubtedly has been used
pythagorean spirit a manual on mathematical as an ideological weapon by those Pythag-
subjects "such as a student would require to oreans who defended the aristocratic order
enable him to read Plato" (Heath, ibid., fO), against rising democratic tendencies. However,
in which he treats these proportions much as this inference is not compelling. The symbolical
-4ristotle has done in his writings. Il'hether expression of Pythagorean political theory was
Aristotle, in using his "reciprocal proportion- general and fluid enough to allow various and
alitl,," meant to refer to the harmonic pro- differing applications of the principle, as long
portion is open to conjecture. -4s a matter as the central idea of proportionalitl- was
of fact, in the harmonic proportion there is retained. I t was a conservative, but not neces-
what Aristotle called a "cross-conjunction" be- sarily a politically reactionary, principle.20 This
tween the first and the third term as can be can be demonstrated in the case of Archytas'
seen in the above formulation of the harmonic own activities as a statesman. \Then Archytas
proportion by Heath. rose to power in Tarentum, the old conflict
I{-e have dealt more closely with Archytas' between the "commercial" classes of traders.
theory of proportions because in the political craftsmen, and fishermen, whose activities
theory of the Pythagoreans the geometric formed the main source of Tarentum's wealth
proportion, in a symbolic manner, has played a and who were strongly imbued with democratic
leading role. This holds good in Archytas' ideas, and the landed aristocracy whose wealth
derived from agriculture reached a new high.
political ideas, too, to judge from the little we
Archytas, inspired by Pythagorean ideas,
know about it. According to the Pythagoreans,
brought about a certain political balance and
"the eternal fact of inevitable inequality under- carried out agricultural reforms, such as granting
lies everything and is the basis for social institu- the use of land to the poor. He thus defended
tions. Society is made up of individuals differ- a democratic society against the claims of the
ing in virtue and other qualitie~."'~ A reasonable old aristocracy , b y demonstrating that in a

8' Edwin L. Minar, Jr., Early Pythugoraean politics in
democratic society offices would go to those who
practice and theory, 109, Connecticut College Monographs, deserve them on the strength of their services
No. 2, Baltimore, Waverly Press, 1942; cf. also Winspear, to the cornmunit)..
op. cit., 88-89. Winspear claims that the Pythagoreans Archytas or members of his school in Tarentum
have also known arithmetic proportion as a symbol for seem to have made the most liberal use of such
democratic equality. " . . . In the fifth century, probably,
this aversion t o equality took the form of a preference for analogies between proportions and political
geometric or harmonic proportion rather than arithmetic. rules, be it to explain the principles of certain
Later (in the fourth century) Pythagorean thinkers found types of government or to stipulate rules for
that they could d o lip-service to equality as they did to
democracy, and a t this stage arithmetic proportion as a who, being opposed to aristocratic rule, was genuinely
key to the nature of justice achieved some favor among in favor of "equality" as he understood it.
them" (ibid., 94-95). We are inclined to agree with I9 LIinar, ibid., 112. He quotes from fragments of
Winspear that in the fourth century Pythagoreans em- Archytas' On law and justice (Stob. F1. 43.132).
ployed both types of proportions, the geometric and arith- 20 Fritz has shown that "in spite of the hierarchic
metic, as symbols of social justice; however, we take ex- tendencies of the [Pythagorean] order the strongest oppo-
ception to his generalizations about and prejudiced treat- sition [to I'ythagoreanism] came from those among the
ment of the Pythagoreans "doing lip-service to equality." aristocrats who looked upon themselves as the preservers
Archytas map serve as a n example of a Pythagorean of the old tradition" (op. cit., 98).
VOL. 96, NO. I, 1952] ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 57

a just government. We select two fragments, Delatte already has pointed out the parallel
both ascribed t o Archytas but definitely not of between the political and economic reforms of
his authorship. Both bear a striking resemblance Archytas a t i'arentum and Archytas' theory of
to Aristotle's argumentation and may have served proportion. The above cited fragment shows,
him as a model. The one says that Archytas has according to Delatte, how the theory of propor-
called the Spartan State a balanced constitution tions can be adapted to meet social needs and
because the Spartans have applied the rule of new conditions which arise in political pra~tice.~3
"reciprocal proportionality" to their political Here, the fundamental c o n c e ~ t of Aristotle
lifesZ1 This reference discloses that the term takes shape: to establish social order means to
"reciprocal proportionality,"which ,lristotle took find the right proportions and to apply them to
over from the Pythagoreans, has been regarded the life of the community. Then the rich and
as an expression of Archytas. The other the poor "will have that which is fair and equal"
fragment deals with the connection between -distributive justice-and "it stops those who
-
proportion and justice in contracts and business know how to calculate before thev commit
- injustice" in contracts-corrective justice.
transactions. is also attributed to Archvtas
himself but comes probably from one of- his Aristotle must have been very receptive to
disciples. I t says: such ideas. The political strife between the
landed aristocracy and the commercial classes
C o r r e c t calculation w h e n found p u t s a n e n d t o in Athens resembled the social and political
civil strife a n d increases concord. F o r w h e n this developments in the Tarentum of Archytas.
t a k e s place greed disappears a n d e q u a l i t y prevails, The commercial classes of Athens fought as
because b y m e a n s of calculation w e c o m e t o agree- much for imperialistic expansion and monetary
m e n t o v e r c o n t r a c t s (avvahhayphrwv). Because of
commercialism as for political democracy; the
i t t h e poor receive f r o m t h e powerful a n d t h e rich
privileged or formerly privileged classes fought
give those in need, b o t h in confidence t h a t t h r o u g h
i t t h e y will h a v e t h a t which is fair a n d equal. T h u s for landholdings and oligarchic rule. Plato,
a s t h e rod a n d check of evildoers, it s t o p s those who the scion of a family belonging to the old
k n o w how t o calculate before t h e y c o m m i t injustice, aristocracy, took passionately the side of
persuading t h e m that t h e y will n o t b e a b l e t o escape oligarchy and landed aristocracy. He built up
detection w h e n t h e y c o m e u p a g a i n s t i t ; those w h o his own version of oligarchic government, and
c a n n o t calculate i t restrains f r o m injustice b y show- it seems not unjustified to assume that in
i n g t h e m t h a t in t h i s v e r y f a c t t h e y a r e c o m m i t t i n g devising his rule of the learned philosophers he
injustice.?? was thinking of Archytas, the great sage and
successful s t a t e ~ m a n . ~In~ the Laws (744 B),
21 This statement of pseudo-Archytas is to be found in
the commentary of Alexander of Aphrodisias, the most
the aged Plato was willing to concede political
important commentator of Aristotle's works in antiquity power to the wealthy apart from the born
(ca. 200 A.D.), on Aristotle's Metaphysics, 985b, 26. I t is aristocrats and the virtuous. Aristotle remained
quoted by Stewart, op. cit. 1 : 445. Even if the term uncompromising toward the commercial classes;
"reciprocal proportionality" was not used by Archytas he was not prepared to give political power to
himself-and it seems unlikely t h a t Archytas should have
looked upon the Spartan state as a n exemplary govern- those whose wealth was derived from commercial
ment-Alexander's remark indicates t o us that the concept profits. In the Politics he has drawn a strict
might have formed a part of Pythagorean political specu- line between the accumulation of wealth for
lation. \Ve cite Alexander as a source of information the sake of the "noble" life and the limitless
about Pythagoreanism in the belief that in his time
Pythagorean literature was still well known and because hunt for money as an end in itself. Commercial
Alexander was a sober scholar "holding aloof from the life, the exchange in the market, was to be
mystical tendencies of the Academics of his time." J. E. subjected to a principle that insured "exchange
Sandys, A history of classical scholarship, 1 : 340-341, 3rd
ed., Cambridge Univ. Press, 1921.
of equivalents" and excluded "profits" and the
22 We take this translation of fragment 47 B 3 in Diels' accumulation of wealth from profits. He thought -
Vorsokratiker, 273, from Minar, op. cit., 91. We have it not proper for the "citizen" to get wealthy in
changed only Minar's translation of the term o v v a X X b r p a r a
which he renders with "mutual problems." Diels trans- term X o y ~ u p 6 s ,i.e., "correct calculation," might be equiva-
lated "gegenseitige Handelsverpflichtungen" (mutual busi- lent to "establishing proportions."
ness obligations) and Mullach "contractus" (Fragmenta 23 A. Delatte, Essai sur la politipue pythagoricienne, 259,
Philosophorum Graecorum, 1 : 562, Paris, Didot, 1875). Liege, Vaillant-Carmanne, 1922, as quoted by Minar,
I t is the same expression Aristotle uses in describing those op. cit., 91-92.
transactions which are subject to corrective justice. The 24 SO Popper, op. cit., 172.
58 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC. AMER. PHII,. SOC.

this manner. On the other hand, the trader, Aristotle made the terms of a proportion to
too, was to be prevented from becoming rich mean either men or things. In the geometric
a t the expense of the non-commercial citizen. proportion of distributive justice the first and
'I'he solution of the problem lay in the application the second terms represent the two partners of a
of "particular justice" to the distribution of partnership and the third and the fourth terms
wealth and to business transactions; it was their respective shares in the common fund.
the rule of proportion. The identification of men and things with
rlristotle adopted from the "so-called" Pythag- numbers or terms of a proportion, however, is
oreans, besides such principles as the correspond- merely an analogy (Met., N. 6, 1093b, 11-16).
ence of proportions and political justice, some of The word "term" "was transferred by Aristotle
his most fundamental concepts and procedures. from Mathematics to Logic."29 "Moreover.
The "mean," the measure of justice, is a Pythag- *Aristotle compares his procedure to that oi
orean doctrine and was expounded as such by those who bring numbers into figures (aXtjpara)
Plato in the Philebus; from there it found its like the triangle and the square."30 The square
wa> into Aristotle's E t h i ~ s . The ~ ~ mean as a arrangement of persons and things in his pattern
measure, however, was an analog>- Aristotle of "proportional reciprocit!." to be discussed
introduced into his philosophy a t a later stage presently is an illustration of this procedure
of his development. "In his earl]. works as in which he admittedll- has taken over from the
the Platonic Protreptikos, he had stated: 'The Pythagoreans.
Good is the exactest measure'; in the Ethics How lively the tradition of rlrchytas has been
of his mature period, the 'mean,' the 'mesotes,' in the Peripatetic School is testified b>- the
is merely an analog! ( ~ a 6 '2~aarov)and is the writings of Aristoxenus of Tarentum (cn. 318
opposite of e x a c t n e ~ s . " ~Another
~ use of math- B . c . ) , a pupil of ,Aristotle who was originall>.
ematical terms (ijPot) as purell. logical analogies trained in P~~thagorean philosophy a t Tarentum
can be seen in Aristotle's application of the and later became a member of the Peripatetic
old Pythagorean numerical symbol of justice. School. Aristoxenus wrote, among other bio-
"Aristotle tells distinctly that the Pythagoreans graphical studies, a life of ~ r c h y k sand con-
explained only a few things by means of numbers tinued Archytas' research on harmony in a
(,Vet., 11. 4, 1078b)" and "that according to celebrated work on music which made him the
them . . . justice was four."?' In Aristotle's leading authority in the ancient world on the
philosophy this sj-mbolic number, rooting in theory and history of music. He endeavored
old m>.stical beliefs, takes on a new rationalistic in his writings to synthesize P>-thagorean and
meaning. If justice is essentially a proportion Aristotelian views on ethics and music. *Aristotle
and every proportion involves four terms, two induced him, in particular, to inquire not solely
people and two things, then the number four into general theories but also to examine empir-
evpresses a logical relation. ical evidence for his theories. The character of
.Aristotle also agreed expressly with the those of -\ristoxenus' treatises which are still
Pythagoreans if they presented the relation extant appears to support our contention that
between things as numerical ratios (Met. N. 3, Aristotle and his pupils, following the master's
1090a, 20-23). He reports on the authority of example, attempted to harmonize the teachings
,Ar~hytas?~ that the P>thagorean Eurytos "used of -\rchytas and the doctrines of the Peripatetic
to give the number of all sorts of things, such as School and to combine abstract reasoning with
horses and men, and that he demonstrated empirical research.
these b>- arranging pebbles in a certain way"
(Met., N. 5,1092b, 10-11). In the same manner,
Alristotle'stheory of exchange was an attempt
25 John Burnet, Early Greek philosophy, 112, n. 2 , 4th to expound a rule by which the exchange of goods
ed., London, A. & C. Black, 1930. can be established as an exchange of equal values.
2Warold Schilling, Das Ethos der IIesotes, 14. Eine Then each one receives what is "due to him" and
Studie zur Nikomachischen Ethik des Aristoteles. Heidel-
berger Abhandlungen zur Philosophie ~ ~ ihrer
n d Geschichte. justice prevails. The solution of this problem
No. 22. Tuebingen, Mohr, 1930. presupposes the answer to two questions: first,
27 Burnet, op. czt., 107-108.
28 Burnet, ibzd., 100, n. 2 Burnet reports that it is 29 Burnet, The Ethics of Aristotle, 126.
made clear by Theophrastus' commentary on the Meta- 30 Burnet, Early Greek philosophy, 100; the passage re-
physics that Archytas was the source of this statement. ferred to is dfet., N. 5, 1092b.
VOL. 96, NO. I , 19521 ARISTOT1,E'S THEORY OF EXCHrlNGE 59

what "is due" to each of the two parties to the A D and BC as diagonal lines.32 Now, Aristotle
exchange, and, secondly, how can things of calls on us to effect a "diagonal conjunction"
different quality which are exchanged exactly (4 ~ a s d~ L ~ ~ E T PU ~O{ EVU [ L S ) , i.e., to place in conjunc-
because of their qualitative difference be com- tion A and D and B and C. Whereas in dis-
pared with each other and thus be "equalized"? tributive justice the conjunction ( u b { e u [ i s ) is one
For example: between A and C and B and D , or between one
man and his own good and the other man and
L e t A b e a builder, B a s h o e m a k e r , C a house, D
his own good, the conjunction in "proportionate
a shoe. T h e builder, t h e n , m u s t g e t f r o m t h e shoe-
m a k e r t h e l a t t e r ' s w o r k , a n d m u s t himself g i v e h i m reciprocity" ( h v r i a e s o v 0 6 s ) is that between A and
in r e t u r n his own. If, t h e n , first t h e r e is a propor- D and B and C or between one man and the
t i o n a t e e q u a l i t y of goods, a n d t h e reciprocal action other man's good and vice versa.
t a k e s place, t h e result will b e "equality." If n o t , The term "proportionate reciprocity" has
t h e bargain is n o t e q u a l , a n d d o e s n o t hold; for t h e r e been defined by Euclid thus: "Two magnitudes
i s n o t h i n g t o p r e v e n t t h e w o r k of t h e o n e being are said t o be reciprocally proportional to two
b e t t e r t h a n t h a t of t h e o t h e r ; t h e y m u s t therefore
be e q u a t e d (Eth. Nic., V, 5 , 1133a, 7-14).
others when one of the first is to one of the
other magnitudes as the remaining one of the
The \vay to equate goods is "proportionate last two is to the remaining one of the first."33
reciprocity." "Proportionate reciprocitj-" exists This definition, as Heath has remarked, requires
if "the number of shoes exchanged for a house that the magnitudes shall be all of the same
. . . corresponds to the ratio of builder to kind.34 The formula of "proportionate rec-
shoemaker." As every other form of particular iprocity" can be transcribed as following:
justice, "commutative justice" involves four
terms: the two persons who exchange their goods
and the two goods, their "works," which they
exchange.
- The mathematical or quasi-math-
ematical pattern underlying "commutative jus- "Proportionate reciprocity" is, therefore, a geo-
tice," however, is more differentiated than either metric proportion not between four terms but
that of geometric or arithmetic proportion. It rather between four ratios. If we call the ratios
consists of a "figure," a "scheme," and a propor-
tion between the four terms of the figure.
The figure -\ristotle was thinking of must have
heen the following: 32 The diagram is presented a s a parallelogram, among
others, by Alexander Grant, T h e ethics of Aristotle 2 : 118,
4th ed., London, Longmans, Green, 1885; D. P. Chase,
The Aricomachean ethics, 112, Everyman's Library, No.
547, London, J . M. Dent & Sons, n.d.; Adolf Stahr,
Aristotles' A'ikomackische Ethik, 171, Stuttgart, Krais &
Hoffmann, 1863; Stahr draws only one diagonal.
33 Sir Thomas L. Heath, The thirteen books of Euclid's
elements, 2 : 189, 2nd ed., Cambridge, Univ. Press, 1926.
The definition as given by Euclid, Book \'I, 2, is not
In this figure A is a builder, B a shoemaker, C a intelligible. Therefore, Heath has used the transcription
of this definition as proposed by Robert Simon in his
house, and D a shoe. English edition of T h e elements of Euclid (1756). Euclid's
In presenting the diagram as above, we are own wording of the definition stresses that the relation
following Burnet's procedure3' which appears between "reciprocally related figures" [ d v r r x e ~ o v O 6 ~ax+
a

to us more convincing than the conventional /.~ara] is one of ratios. \-arious mathematicians have
interpolated into the text of Euclid "terms of ratios"
geometrical square, where AB, BD, DC and C A which would support our transcription. In Euclid's Ele-
are presented as the four sides of a square and ments, this definition is "insular"; Euclid has never applied
it to parallelograms. For this reason Heath suggested
:" Burnet, T h e Ethics of Aristotle, 225. However, we that it has been later interpolated by Heron of Alexandria
deviate from Burnet in that he interprets the conjunction (150 B.c.?) who has it, too.
of the four terms-A, B , C, D-as a n arithmetic propor- 31 Heath, ibid. Proportional reciprocity requires equal-
tion in which the sum of the extremes equals the sum of ity of the four magnitudes, A , B , C, D ; that is exactly
the middle terms such as A D = B+ +
C, whereas we what Aristotle demands. In fact, A and B are no magni-
hold t h a t it is a conjunction of the alternando type of a tudes but "terms" by way of analogy; they are "equalized"
geometric proportion, viz., A :D: :B : C. if C and D which are magnitudes are "equal."
60 JOSEF

then e:f : :g: h. In this proportion the ratios equally, t h e r e would b e e i t h e r n o exchange o r n o t
e:f and g:h are equal. As in a geometric t h e s a m e exchange) (Eth. Nic., V, 5, 1133a, 25-28).34a
proportion the first term (ratio) can be conjunc- The equating factor is "need." The word
tive with the third, and the second with the 4 x p ~ i a has been persistently translated with
fourth term. Then e :g : :f : h. "demand." Although Aristotle has been con-
So much to the formula. What does it mean scious of the interrelation between need and
to the problem as posed by the exchange of demand, i.e., the need backed up by purchasing
goods? power, here he meant unequivocally "need"
First of all, if exchange is to take place, the only. However, he failed to differentiate
two goods have to be "equalized." The equal- between this and another aspect of the word
ization has to be effected prior to the exchange "need." Need is what makes people desire a
and precedes the square arrangement between certain good but it is a specific quality of goods
persons and their goods. This postulate raises which makes them desirable to people. This
three questions: (1) What does Aristotle under- quality inherent in products of a specific skill
stand by the "inequality" of goods? (2) Why consists in their capacity to offer "want satisfac-
have the persons who exchange to be equated, tion." The term "need" has thus two aspects:
too? (3) \$'hat is the equating factor? "want" and "want satisfaction," the one if
T o answer questions (1) and (2) properly we seen from the point of the person who wants
have to recall what we have said earlier about the good and the other if seen from the point of
Xristotle's general view on economics. Aristotle the good which gives what is wanted.
could not conceive of goods as such but merely The builder's work is as much needed by the
of goods in relation to persons, be it as products shoemaker as the shoemaker's work by the
of human skill or as media of want satisfaction. builder. But the "want satisfaction" offered
Now, the fundamental "inequality" of goods by the builder's product exceeds that of a
consists in their being products of diyerent skills. pair of shoes by 100 times. The builder's skill
"For it is not two doctors that associate for exceeds by that much the shoemaker's skill.
exchange, but a doctor and a farmer, or in That, in Aristotle's mind, has nothing to do
general people who are different and unequal" with the time involved in building a house or
(Eth. Nic., V, 5 , 1133a, 17). Skill is what creates making a pair of shoes. "Labor" in the ab-
"inequality" among people but it is this inequal- stract, the labor-time of the Political Economy,
ity, the outgrowth of specialization, that leads is alien to Aristotle's thinking; he never mentions
to exchange. IVe recognize here the "natural it or implies it in his deductions.
inequality" of which Plato has spoken in the Yet he was very much concerned with the
Republic and which he has regarded as the "value" of a skill. This value can be measured
economic basis of the city-state. Equation of
by the quantity of products of other skills for
goods is thus identical with the equation of the
which it can be exchanged. "A man's fortune,"
skills whose products they are. "The number
of shoes exchanged for a house . . . must wrote Adam Smith, "is greater or less, in
therefore correspond to the ratio of builder to proportion . . . to the quantity . . . of the
shoemaker." But what is the ratio between produce of other men's labor which it enables
the skills of the builder and the shoemaker? him to purchase or command."35 When Adam
Suppose it is like 1 : 100. Then, one unit of Smith formulated what he thought to be a
the housebuilder's work would be equal to 3" In the above passage Ross translates i-vi rrvr with
100 units of the shoemaker's work. The propor- "unit." Taken literally the two words mean "a some-
tion would read-Builder : Shoemaker : :one house thing" and we like t o retain the original meaning of this
: l o 0 pairs of shoes. How do we know that term. Aristotle explains later in the chapter what the
this is the ratio between the skills? This is nature of this "something" is, viz., a "representative of
want" n the form of money. I t helps t o illuminate
LAristotle'sanswer : Aristotle's way of exposition t o reproduce his intentionally
colorless and general term. Rudolf Kaulla made refer-
T h i s proportion will n o t b e effected unless t h e
ence to this phrasing of Aristotle's statement-a phrasing
goods a r e somehow equal. All goods m u s t therefore designed to prepare the reader for a problem: the search
be measured by some o n e thing. .. . Now this unit for "the something" which makes goods comparable. Cf.
[something] is in t r u t h d e m a n d [need, i.e., rj xpeia], Kaulla's sentence quoted a t the end of this essay.
which holds all things together (for if m e n d i d n o t 35 Adam Smith, The wealth of nations, 1 , chap. 5 : 31,
need o n e a n o t h e r ' s goods a t all, o r d i d n o t need t h e m Modern Library edition. N. Y., Random House, 1937.
VOL. 96, K O . 1, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE

"labor theory of valueu-but what in fact is a into the wax, so the craftsman confers his
"value theory of labor"-he expressed very craftsmanship on his work. He would cease
eloquently what Aristotle must have had in to do it if he were not assured of receiving the
mind. And here lies the interconnection between equivalent for what his craft seems worth to him.
"need1' and "demand": the more valuable a Before diagonal conjunction takes place, the
man's skill is than that of other men, the greater proportion reads A : C: :B :D. The exchange
will be the quantity of products of other skills ratio of C to D--one house to 100 pairs of
he can "command." The purchasing power, shoes-equals the ratio of A to B or A's skill to
the "demand," follows from the value of the B's skill. Expressed in ratios between A and
skill; what makes people want a product and the product of his skill and B and the product of
what enables them to afford it are two different his skill, the proportion is e :f . Geometric
things. Of these two, the primary, in Aristotle's proportion of skills and the products of skills
eyes, is the "need." is one of the two factors which determine the
Xristotle has expressed this thought in a exchange ratio of two goods. The whole
metaphoric phrase which has been obscured proportion which regulates exchange, however,
unnecessarily by the commentators of the involves four ratios, viz. e :f : :g: h, i.e., the ratio
Ethics. After he has discussed the equaliza- of skills t o their products equals the ratio of A's
tion of products of different skills that must be product (C) to B , and B's product (D) to A.
effected "to prevent the work of the one being The problem is now to equate A :D and B : C.
better than that of the other," he says: The one side of the proportion expressing
( A n d this is t r u e of o t h e r a r t s [besides house-
"proportionate reciprocity" has rid the goods of
building a n d shoemaking] also; t h e y would h a v e their incommensurability qua products of differ-
been destroyed if w h a t t h e p a t i e n t suffered [ w h a t ent skills. They are now commensurable qua
t h e w o r k received f r o m t h e c r a f t s m a n ] h a d n o t media of want satisfaction. The other side of
been j u s t w h a t t h e a g e n t d i d [ w h a t t h e c r a f t s m a n d i d the proportion is designed to divest them of their
t o it], a n d of t h e s a m e a m o u n t a n d kind.) (Eth. Nic., incommensurability as media of flarticular satis-
V, 5 , 1133a, 14-16.) faction. A house fills a need unlike that filled
The metaphoric language-the "agent" and by a pair of shoes. But both goods can be
the "patientn-can well be juxtaposed with commensurable if looked upon not as satisfying
another less abstract metaphor that Stewart this or that need but satisfying needs in general.
has chosen:36 as the seal imprints its picture "Now in truth it is impossible that things
differing so much should be commensurate
Stewart, op. cit., 455-458. Translation and interpre- but with reference to want satisfaction they
tation of this passage depends on the way in which the
terms "agent" ( r b noroirv) and "patient" ( r b ?rbaXov) are may become so sufficiently" (Eth. Nic., V, 5 ,
interpreted. As Stewart has shown, with reference t o 1133b, 18-22). The geometric proportion of
Plato's Thaetetus, 157A, and Aristotle's De Anima, 111. goods received in exchange qua media of want
5, 430a, the meaning of these terms is a purely logical one, satisfaction is expressed in the reciprocal ratio
There are two interpretations of "agent" and "patient"
possible. Either the two terms denote the relation be- of the builder to shoes and the shoemaker to the
tween the craftsman and his work. This is Stewart's housk. I t is the formula of "diagonal cross-
version which we accept in principle. He translates the coniunctionl'-A :D : :B : C. Want satisfaction
sentence thus: '. . . The arts would perish, unless, as the der&ed from the possession of one house must
active element put forth action in each case t o such and he equal to that derived from the possession of
such extent and in such and such a mode, the passive
element received the impression of this action conformably 100 pairs of shoes.
in each case to the extent and to the mode." Stewart's Here is then the total "proportionate rec-
elaboration of this connection, however, fails to meet the iprocity" :
meaning of it in concreto and misses the application of
this sentence to the economic argument.
Or the two terms refer to the relation between the one
producer and the other as parties to the exchange. This
interpretation is offered, e.g., by H. Rackham in his The ratios e and g express the want satisfaction
edition of the A7icomacheanEthics, 282, n. b, Loeb Classical
Library, Cambridge, Harvard Univ. Press, 1936. "The and that makes this interpretation appear rather unlikely.
phrases 'active element' and 'passive element' seem to We mention this alternative, because Rackham's reading
mean producer and consumer." However, in exchange seems to be the same as Thomas Aquinas' which might
as conceived by Aristotle both parties are simultaneously have caused the latter's fateful interpretation of this pas-
producers and consumers, or rather givers and recipients, sage (see p. 65).
JOSEF SOUDEK

or utility of their own skills and their products bjr the judge, the personified justice. Who is
to the ones who offer the products of their skill to be the judge in exchange?
in the market, i.e., the amount of the produce -
In exchange the terms of the arithmetic
of other skills they receive in exchange for their proportion are the want satisfactions derived by
own. The ratios f and h reflect the utility of the exchanging parties from the possession of
the products of other skills to the ones who give each other's goods. What else could the mean-
away their own. ing of A :D and B: C be? We are confronted
.Aristotle realized a t once the difficulty in with two ratios-A :D = g and B : C = h. These
applying his concept to this particular instance two ratios are of the same nature and thus the
of exchange. The one who wants a house, the want satisfactions are "equated." This happy
shoemaker, can give only 100 pairs of shoes in coincidence does not occur automatically; it has
exchange but that might not be what the to be established through an arithmetic propor-
housebuilder wants. For this reason &Aristotle tion as is used in corrective justice.
shifted his argument in two ways: First, he The ratios g and h are not only a proportion
compared two producers whose valuation of want in themselves; they are ~imultaneously inter-
satisfaction is easier to demonstrate, viz., a mediates in a proportion of four differing
shoemaker and a farmer. Secondl!, he intro- estimations of want satisfactions. The shoe-
duced into his reasoning money: the house- maker might assume that a pair of shoes should
builder in exchange for his produce might get be equal to three bushels of wheat whereas the
something that would bring him into possession farmer might think that one bushel of wheat
not of a quantit3- of just one particular product should be enough payment for one pair of shoes.
but of an assortment of various goods the total Therefore, an intermediate has to be found
value of which would he equal to the value of between the three bushels in the shoemaker's
his own product. \I'e shall discuss the function estimation of the "value" or utility of his shoes
of money as "the representative" of "need" and the one bushel of wheat, the farmer's
later; the understanding of the function of estimation of the "value" of one pair of shoes.
mone) requires, in addition to the analysis of The proportion would then be
an exchange without "the double coincidence of 3 bushels - 2 bushels = 2 bushels - 1 bushel.
want," a clarification of the "equalization" of
"~vantsatisfactions." How can the want satis- riristotle has to say this about corrective
faction of a pair of shoes and n specified amount justice in exchange :
of food he equalized (Aristotle fails to give an These names, both loss and gain, have come from
example; he just mentions "food")? voluntary exchange; for to have more than one's own
Suppose a pair of shoes equals two bushels of is called gaining, and to have less than one's original
wheat. That means to sa) that a pair of shoes share is called losing, e.g. in buying and selling and
gives the farmer the same want satisfaction as in all other matters in which the law has left people
two bushels of wheat give the shoemaker. How free to make their own terms; but when they get
do we know that these two want satisfactions, neither more nor less but just what belongs to them-
the two "utilities," are of identical intensity? selves, they say t h a t they have their own and t h a t
they neither lose nor gain (Eth. Nit., V, 4, 1132b,
Here enters the arithmetic proportion of the 11-18).
"corrective justice."
.Arithmetic proportion applies where things If exchanging goods, the parties make their
or people being equal in qualit). or supposed to own terms. They form their own estimations
be equal are related to each other. In the of what they think belongs to them, i.e., what
case of "voluntary" transactions such as sale, want satisfaction they derive from the goods
purchase, or lending, the terms compared are they get in exchange for their own produce.
expressed in quantities of an identical object Consequently, they themselves have to deter-
such as mane!.. The intermediate is of the mine what the intermediate is between their
same nature as the two extremes. The formula respective estimations. How do they do it?
of arithmetic proportion is A - B = B - C. I t has been suggested that L4ristotle was
The intermediate, the proper price of the house thinking of bargaining in the market. That
in our previous example, is equally distant from appears not unreasonable. In bargaining people
the two moneJ- claims of the seller and the formulate their own terms of exchange and
purchaser. The intermediate has been found correct whatever discrepancies there might
VOL. 96, NO. I , I ~ S Z ] ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 63

exist between their valuations of goods. They tions: it equalizes skills and want satisfactions,
arrive a t an exchange ratio by taking in account and not, as Smith assumed, merely equates skills.
of what service things are to them and the The intermediate or the mutually determined
craftmanship required for their production. ratio between the two estimations of want
Adam Smith has given a lively description of this satisfactions will then be a c c e ~ t e das the ex-
process and, again, he has expressed what change ratio of the two goods. The intermediate
Aristotle's idea must have been. His reference obviously must be found before exchange takes
to "equality" thus established indicates a more place, otherwise the ratio is not mutually
than accidental similarity of his reasoning to satisfactory. AAristotle emphasized that in the
that of Aristotle. That Smith manoeuvered following passage: "But we must not bring them
himself into difficulties and contradictions with [the parties to the exchange] into a figure of
his own supposed "labor theory" does not matter proportion when they have already exchanged
here; that he means "skill and dexterity" of (otherwise one extreme will have both excesses),
labor when he just speaks of "labour" becomes but when they still have their own goods" (Eth.
obvious from the context. He writes: ,'Vie., V, 5, 1133b, 2). RIuch wit has been wasted
on the interpretation of this indeed fundamental
... I t is often difficult t o ascertain t h e propor-
sentence.38 Seen within its proper context, it
tion between two different quantities of labour. T h e
time spent in two different sorts of u o r k will not should not be too difficult to understand its
a l u a y s alone determine this proportion. T h e dif- meaning. The shoemaker estimates the value
ferent degrees of hardship endured, and of ingenuity of his Gork in terms of wheat and the farmer
exercised, must likewise be taken into account. his work in terms of shoes. The one who gives
There may be more labour in a n hour's hard ~ o r k away his product, according to .Aristotle, will
than in t \ \ o hours easy business; or in a n hour's value it higher, a t least for the sake of bargaining,
application t o a trade which i t cost ten j e a r s labour than the one who desires it. And the one who
t o learn, t h a n in a month's industry a t a n ordinary desires it will attach a -greater value to a ~ r o d u c t
and obvious emplojment. B u t i t is not easy t o
when he wants it than a t the time when he has it.
find a n y accurate measure either of hardship or
ingenuity. In exchanging indeed t h e different pro- Thus, prior to bargaining, the value of goods is
ductions of different sorts of labour for another, some distorted in opposite directions bj- both parties.
allowance is commonly made for both. I t is a d - Bargaining sets the proper valuation of- goods,
justed, however, -not b) a n y accurate measure, b u t both from the ~ o i n tof view of the seller and
by the higgling and bargaining of t h e market, accord- that of the buyer. If that were not so, the one
ing t o t h a t sort of rough equality which, though not who would get away with his own estimation,
exact, is sufficient for c a r r j i n g on t h e business of for instance the seller, would have "both
common life.37 excesses" in the sense of corrective justice.
Smith apparently followed Aristotle in his Aristotle has made this point in Book IX, chapter
discussion of the exchange ratio of goods qua 1 (1164b, 12-21) of the Ethics where he deals
products of different skills. But Aristotle went with reciprocity of services and feelings among
further than Smith. .According to his theory friends in analogy to reciprocity in exchange.
There he says:
the exchange ratio of goods is determined by
38 Grant has interpreted the admittedly "not clear"
two ratios: the ratio of skills and the ratio of
phrase 6 ~ a Cv X X C f u v r a r as meaning this: ".-\fter an exchange
want satisfactions. As long as the problem is has been made, . . . it is no longer time to talk of 'equality
that of reducing skills to want satisfaction for of labor' or for either side to claim an advantage on this
the sake of establishing equality, distributive account. If he did, he would have 'both superiorities'
reckoned to him, i.e., his own superiority over the other
justice is a t work. If it then comes to the producer, and the superiority of his product over that of
problem of establishing a ratio of want satisfac- the others. . . . It seems unnecessary to say that the
tions, the principle of corrective justice has to value of a thing is not settled after it is sold. Rather it is
after the goods have come to the market, and had a market
be applied. This, too, is being done in bargain- price put on them, that considerations of their production
ing. Thus, bargaining operates in both direc- must cease" (op. cit., 120). The misinterpretation of
Burnet is even more surprisi~lgafter his candid explana-
37 Wealth of nations, 1 , chap. 5: 31. Edwin Cannan, the tion of the working of "corrective justice." He writes:
editor of Smith's work, noted that Smith made no further "The work of the cobbler must not be equated with that
reference of this discussion on the adjustment of different of the builder, otherwise the farmer will have not only his
skills in chapter 10 on "Inequalities of Wages and Profits" own excess over the cobbler, but the excess of the builder
(p. 31, n. 5). over the cobbler as well" (op. cit., 228).
64 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC.AMER. PHIL. SOC.

We see this [discrepancy in reciprocity] happening


goods, the exchange ratio of the goods reflects
too with things put up for sale, and in some places
the worth of each other's skill. The quantity
there are laws providing t h a t no actions shall arise
of goods each party gives and receives is in
out of voluntary contracts, on the assumption t h a t
conformity with the value of each party's work.
one should settle with a person to whom one has
The purchasing power, the ability to "demand"
given credit, in the spirit in which one bargained
other people's work, stands thus in proportion
with him. T h e law holds t h a t i t is more just t h a t
the person to whom credit \%-as given should fix to the quality of one's own productive effort.
the terms than the person who gave credit should do.The "measure of value" is utility, to be sure.
But utilities as such are not measurable.
For most things are not assessed a t the same value
by those who have them and those who want them; Aristotle has realized that. Therefore, he did
each class values hichlv what is its own and what it
u 2
not compare the utility of one kind of goods to
is offering; yet the return is made on the terms fixed
one person with the utility of the same goods to
by the receiver. But no doubt the receiver should another person but rather did he compare the
assess a thing not a t what i t seems n o r t h when he
ratio of the utilities of two products to one
has it, but what he assessed it a t before he had it.
person with the ratio of the utilities of two other
Bargaining prevents a violation of the arith- products to another person. They have to be
metic proportion. If the seller would set the identical if exchange of goods is to be an ex-
price on his own, he would, in addition to change of equivalents.
obtaining the quantit~.of goods or money that Equalization of want satisfaction is ordinarily
is "due" to him, make a "gain." The purchaser, facilitated by the use of money but it is not
because he gets less than is due to him, u~ould determined by money. What role money plays
incur a "loss." The difference between what he in this process and what significance it has for
receives and the quantitl- which he should have the exchange will be explained later. First we
received has been added to the seller's income. want to investigate how and why Aristotle was
This is the "double excess" of the "one extreme" so frequently misunderstood.
meaning the extreme in an arithmetic proportion
(a - b = b - c ; a and c are the extremes).
If that happened, "voluntary transaction" Aristotle's theory of exchange is of the type
would, in fact, become an "involuntary trans- of pre-"marginal" utility theory. In spirit, if
action" such as theft or robbery. If in market not in form, it belongs to the tradition of French
exchange the purchaser is in dire need of some- utility theory of the late eighteenth century.
thing and thus unable to bargain or if the seller Its counterparts in modern times are the theories
holds a monopolistic position, then what appears of Condillac, Turgot, and Say. Yet many
on the surface as a "voluntary transaction" influential interpreters, particularly in English
is distorted in spirit and perverted into factual speaking countries, saw in it an unsatisfactorily
"extortion." Aristotle has distinguished these developed labor theory of value, if it merited the
two types of transactions, partly with this status of a "theory" a t all. The statement of
thought in mind. The character of corrective James Bonar, quoted in the opening of our essay,
justice as a free agreement between equals may serve as an example for the low opinion in
stands out the more clearly against the back- which it was held.
ground of involuntary transaction. The history of the interpretation of Aristotle's
Now, the circle of market exchange is closed. economic views in the fifth book of the Ethics,
It has started with the "need" of the people in for the greater part, is a history of misinterpre-
the city-state for each other's products. To tations. This trend seems to have been initiated
satisfy it in a just manner, first "diagonal by the Scholastic philosopher Albertus Magnus
cross-conjunction" has to be effected, i.e., (1 193-1280). In his commentary on the Ethics,
equality of "want satisfactions" has to be estab- he interpreted the obscure phrase concerning
lished. This is being done by way of bargaining. the equality of the "agent" and the "patient"
Each party will be assigned the same amount of (Eth. ~ i c . V,, 5 , 1133a, 14-16) in a novel way.
want satisfaction. Then, and only then, the We have discussed this sentence earlier and
exchange of equivalents takes place. Since the found it to express the equality of two goods qua
degree of want satisfaction depends on the products of skills or the equalization of goods
degree of skill involved in the production of the through equalization of the respective skills
VOL. 96, NO. 1, I ~ S Z ] ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 65

whose products they are. Albertus Magnus the reciprocity of exchange) is clearer to moderns
rendered the meaning- of this sentence thus: if we make our standard one hour of labor of
each workman instead of the man himself. The
Equal amounts of labor and expenses must be
exchanged for each other if each productive effort is of commodities is thus
to receive its equivalent. If the carpenter does not according to Aristotle, upon an estimate of the
receive as much in quantity and quality as corre- labor or cost of production in each case. Stewart
sponds to his own effort then he will discontinue to (notes to N. Eth., I , p. 499) suggests that this
produce beds; thus the profession of the carpenter gives what the economists call "natural value,"
will be destroyed. . . .39 but that the market value oscillates from this
because of supply and demand." We quote this
His pupil, Thomas Aquinas remarked in his
passage from A History of Greek Economic
commentary on the Ethics40 that equality in
Thought by Albert ,4. T r e ~ e to r ~ give
~ a vivid
exchange meant equality in "labor and expenses''
impression of the naive nonchalance with which
although he realized that want (or utility) was
Aristotle's theory was fashioned to the preference
the real measure of value. T o have brought
of the day. What was originally used as a
labor and expense into the discussion of
device "to make clearer to moderns" what
Aristotle's theory was an error, although a
Aristotle meant by equalization of skills, became
fruitful one. "The true descendant of the
by the turn of the century the explanation of
doctrine of Aquinas is the labor theory of value,"
exchange ratio "according to Aristotle." Trever
says R. H. T a ~ n e y . ~ l
himself wrote in his learned essay: "It is not
Scholastic exegesis thus introduced a new
merely equal wants that are considered, as he
element into Aristotle's theory that was alien
to the original concept. I t stood there unamal- states, but equal costs as well. . . . I t is clear
then, from this passage in the Ethics, that
gamated besides Aristotle's genuine theory of
"want" as the regulator of exchange. The Aristotle understood that economic value is de-
termined by demand, as measured in money, and
modern interpreters smuggled it into their
presentation of the philosopher's views, not by by labor invested or cost of p r ~ d u c t i o n . " ~ ~
accident but with a definite purpose in mind. W. D. Ross, in his translation of the Ethics,
They tried desperately to bring Aristotle's published in 1925, followed the procedure of
concept or what they considered his "value Grant and Stewart who were understandably
theory" in harmony with the classical labor impressed by the authority of J. St. Mi11 in
theory as formulated by Ricardo and J. St. matters of economic theory. Between 1885
Mill. Grant, Stewart and, to a lesser degree, and 1892, the years in which Grant and Stewart
Burnet borrowed from the labor theory of value published their works, and 1925 the classical
what seemed to be necessary to explain the value theory was utterly defeated, in England
equalization of skills in proportionate reciprocity. as elsewhere, and the need to make Aristotle
The "value" of one house equals the "value" of a conform to the official teachings of economists
certain amount of shoes, they concluded, if the had disappeared. This change of thought-
amount of labor time contained in both goods is crucial for a correct interpretation of Aristotle's
the same. That Aristotle compared skills and ideas-has found no echo in a translation as
not abstract labor spent on the production of authoritative as that of Ross. He remarks in
goods, did not occur to them. "As observed by a footnote to Eth. Nic., V: 5, 1133a, 5 :
R i t ~ h i eand
~ ~ H. R . S e ~ a 1 1the
~ ~proportion (in T h e working of "proportionate reciprocity" is
not very closely described by Aristotle, but seems
39 Ethicorum lib. V , tract. 11, c. 7, Quoted from Rudolf
Kaulla, Die geschichtliche Entwicklung der modernen Wert-
to be as follows. A and B are workers in different
theorien, 53, Tuebingen, H . Laupp, 1906. trades, and will normally be of different degree of
40 Commentarii i n X libros ethicorum Aristotelis. Lib. \', "worth." Their products, therefore, will also have
lectio 7 and 9. Kaulla, ibid. unequal worth, i.e. (though Aristotle does not ex-
41 Religion and the rise of capitalism, 38-39, K. Y . , pressly reduce the question to one of time) if
Penguin Books, 1947. A - nB, C (what A makes, say, in a n hour) will be
42 LArticle"Aristotle" in Palgrave's Dictionary of political
economy, 1: 53-55, London, Macmillan, 1923-26. where we should think of their services as productive
43 T h e theory of value before A d a m Smith. Amer. Econ. agents."
Assoc. Publ., Ser. 3, 2 (3): 3, K. Y., Macmillan, 1901. 44 Chicago, Univ. of Chicago Press, 1916, p. 83. Italics
Trever, incidentally, misrepresented Sewall who observed are ours.
correctly that "Aristotle thinks of the persons themselves 45 Ibid., 84.
JOSEF SOUDEK

worth n times as much a s D (what B makes i n a n the truth than their antagonists. The Russian
hour). A fair exchange will then take place if A economist Wladimir Gelesnoff has given the
gets D and B gets 1 C; i.e., if A gives what i t takes explanation for the "discovery" of the Austrians:
him a n hour t o make, in exchange for what i t takes B
n hours t o make."4G Aristotle's economic theorizing is so dissimilar
from the economic theory of A. Smith, Ricardo,
Ross' interpretation has already been adopted J. St. hlill with which the people of the 19th century
by an historian of economic thought as a genuine were familiar t h a t the modern learned interpreters
presentation of Aristotle's views on exchange4' of Aristotle were puzzled b j some of his statements.
and is likely to slip into the works of other And only the marginal utility school has exentually
historians who consult the "original" in a widely given t h e key t o t h e Aristotelian economic s l stem.
accepted translation. Economists of today do . . . [In Aristotle's theory] t h e goods are valued
not read the old masters in the original Greek exclusively by their destination, i.e., by their utility.
and Latin as their teachers have done only one . . . \\'hen, many centuries later, the question of
or two generations ago. utility a s a factor of economic ~ a l u a t i o ncame t o t h e
,At the turn of the century economists put up fore-and with no less sharpness and bias-the
resistance against this misinterpretation of theoreticians of l a l u e have had to break away force-
fully from the consideration of the labor process.
Aristotle's teachings. The reason for this
countermovement is obvious. I t was as much ... '10

dictated by the general trends in economic Gelesnoff agreed with the ,Austrians that for
theorizing as by opposition to the older gen- Aristotle labor was not the economic ground of
eration which claimed the authorit!, of the explanation for the exchange of equivalents.
philosopher for the Classical Political Economy. Equality in exchange "has nothing to do with the
The movement did not start in France where it equality of quantities of human labor which
could have been expected to begin. In France, are incorporated in the exchanged commodities
the cradle of the studies in the history of eco- ,ind in the amounts of mane!. mediating the
nomic thought and until today its most affec- exchange. . . . If Aristotle spedks of equality
tionate home, Aristotle was not regarded wit11 in exchange, then . . . he means equalit!. of the
too much respect by the generation of the great contracting parties."jl Gelesnoff offered two
historians of economic doctrines, Dennis, Gide, reasons for Aristotle's one-sided point of view on
and Rist. At the end of the last centurl-, economic problems: one is Aristotle's general
August Suchon wrote in his history of economic philosophy and the other his valuation of
theories in ancient Greece that "no one of us physical labor. Economic valuation is a special
is indebted to Plato and rlristotle for their case of valuation in general which is rooted in
insights into economics."~8 The new trend man's psychological ability to choose and to
originated with the AAustrian marginal utility select the desirable. Physical labor, in Aristotle's
theoreticians, the pupils of hlenger and Wieser. opinion, has or is no value in itself. Karl hIarx
Johann Zmavc and Oskar Kraus "discovered" had pointed that out when discussing Aristotle's
triumphantly that Aristotle was a predecessor theory of exchange; Alarx maintained that
of the modern uti1it~--theoryof value and not, Aristotle did not consider labor as a measure of
as has been claimed, of the classical labor-theory value because labor \\as known to him as slave-
of value.4g And the!- were, indeed, closer to
totelische LVerttheorie in ihren Beziehungen zu den Lehren
46 1132b, footnote 1; italics are ours. cler modernen Psychologenschule, Ztschr. fuer die gesamte
4i E. Whittacker, A history of economic ideas, 408, S . Y . Staatswissenschaften, 61 : 573-592, 1905.
Longmans, Green, 1943. j0 Die oekonomische Gedankenwelt des r\ristoteles,
48 Les thdories t4conomiques duns la Gre'cc antique, 7, Paris. Archizt fuer Sozialwissenschaft und Sosialpolitik, 50: 1-33,
Librairie de la societe du recueil general des lois and des 1923, a t pp. 2 and 19. This essay, a translated summary
arr&ts, 1898. Souchon's judgment was a reaction to the or excerpt from the first part of Gelesnoff's History of
high praise of Aristotle as the "creator of political econ- Economic Thought, puhlished by the Moscow Scientific
omy" by J. B. Saint-Hilaire in the preface to his transla- Institute in 1917, is by far the most profound and most
tion of the Politics, 1837. Cf. Trever, op. cit., 81. n. 2. stimulating interpretation of .4ristotle1s views on economics
4 9 J . Zmavc, Die Werttheorie bei Xristoteles und Thomas we have encountered. Gelesnoff has not dealt with the
v. Aquino, Archio fuer die Geschichte der Philosophie, 1 2 : theory of exchange in such detail as has been done here;
407-433, 1899; the same, Die Geldtheorie und ihre Stellung but he is the only economist we know of who has taken
innerhalb der wirtschafts- und sozialwissenschaftlichen Aristotle's mathematical treatment of the theory of ex-
Anschauungen des Aristoteles. Ztschr. fuer die gesanzte change very seriously. Ibid., 24.
.Staatsulissenschaften, 58: 48-79, 1902; 0. Kraus, Die aris- 5l Ibid., 29.
VOL.96, YO. I, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 67

labor only and therefore valueless.52 Gelesnoff text is 0bjectionable,5~he takes it under consider-
accepted Marx's thesis. However, he added that ation. Then he proposes an alternative explana-
in ancient Greece goods were not produced by tion: not the exchange of equal amounts of
slaves exclusively but by free men as well. labor constitutes equality but a ratio between
Yet physical labor of any sort degraded man and quantities of goods in conformity with the
made him unfit for the nobler tasks in the life "social standing" of the exchanging producers.
of the citizen. Aristotle wrote: S o w , the ratio "as the builder is to the shoe-
maker" contains no reference to their respective
T h e necessary people a r e either slaves w h o min-
ister t o t h e w a n t s of t h e individuals, o r t h e mechanics
"social position" (as it may have been in the
a n d labourers w h o a r e t h e s e r v a n t s of t h e com- mouth of a Scholastic philosopher) but to their
m u n i t y . . . . [ B u t ] n o m a n c a n practice v i r t u e w h o respective skills. Finally, the two mutally exclu-
is living t h e life of a mechanic o r labourer (Pol., sive opposites-labor contained in the exchanged
111, 5 , 1278a, 11-13; 20-21). goods and the "social positionH-are regarded
as one determinant and want as the other
The marginal utility theorists, although better
determinant of the value of the goods to be
equipped than their adversaries to grasp the
exchanged. Beer's treatment of Aristotle's
intention of Aristotle's theory, were still not
doctrine is a regrettable slip but it does not
able to free themselves from Thomas Aauinas'
impair the main thesis of his valuable book:
interpolation. Oskar Kraus wrote that
that ;iristotlels economic teachings formed a
Aristotle's theory of just exchange "culminates u

perpetual source of inspiration for the develop-


in the sentence that the producer's return, ment of pre-classical economic thought in
all other things equal, shall be proportionate to
England.
the effort of labor and sacrifice^."^^ He referred
.Aristotle's theory of exchange is rarely a
expressly to Thomas Aquinas as the authority
topic in current books on the history of economic
for his interpretation. -4ristotle's theory of
exchange appeared to him, therefore, less -
doctrines. His general views on economics. if
discussed a t all, are c o r r e c t l ~characterized as a
satisfactory than the master's general explana-
type of utility theory and no claim is made
tion of economic intercourse as being regulated
that his theory of exchange fits either into the
by want.
classical or utility theory of value.56 Bewildered
The authority of Thomas Aquinas played a
55 He noted on p. 166: "St. Thomas Aqui~las, in his com-
fateful role again in a more recent presentation
mentary on Aristotle's Ethics (book V) interpreting the
of *qristotle's theory. In his pioneering work on philosopher, remarked that equality of exchange meant
Early British Economics,hI. Beer wrote : also equality 'in labore et in expensis.' None the less, he
came finally to the conclusio~~-or rather gave way t o the
T w o theories of value a r e r u n n i n g in Aristotle's
authoritative view of Aristotle-that want (utility) was
reasoning: w a n t , d e m a n d o r use a s t h e real s t a n d a r d , the real measure of value."
while t h e l a b o u r a n d social s t a n d i n g of t h e c r a f t s m a n 56 Lewis H . Haney, Hisfory of economic thought, 4th ed.,
a r e likewise considered, b u t n o t a d h e r e d to. . .. In X. Y., hlacmillan, 1949, states on page 65: "AII exchange
Aristotle's t e x t t h e r e is s o m e u n c e r t a i n t y w h e t h e r is just, when each gets exactly as much as he gives the
only t h e v a l u e of t h e goods m u s t b e first ascertained other; yet this equality does not mean equal costs, but
b y t h e labor embodied in t h e m o r also b y t h e social equal wants. If men want the cobbler's product more than
s t a n d i n g of t h e producer, s o t h a t t h e s a m e a m o u n t the husba~ldma~l's, more grain must be given for shoes."
of a builder's l a b o u r m a y , b y reason of his social The first sentence is correct and Thomas -4quinas' inter-
position, be m o r e valuable t h a n t h a t of a shoe- pretation is well rejected. The second sentence has 110
bearing on Aristotle's theory whatever; it explai~lschanges
m a k e r o r farmer.54 of exchange ratios in the market without reference
There are no less than three inconsistencies in to the exchanging parties themselves-a problem with
x hich Aristotle has not dealt a t all. Eric Roll, A history
this analysis. First, the author presents Thomas of economzc thought, revised ed., N. Y., Pren~ice-Hall,1942,
Aquinas' interpretation of exchange as the gives a very valuable a~lalysisof Aristotle's treatment of
exchange of equal amounts of labor. Although exchange (pp. 26-27). Roll denies that Aristotle has de-
he realizes that St. Thomas' reading of the veloped a theory of exchange value, a statement which is
acceptable o111y if one follows, as Roll does, the classical
62 Capital. Vol. 1. chap. 1, sect. 3, p. 68, hlodern Library distinction betxeen use-and exchange value. He writes:
edition, N. Y., Random House, n.d. ". . . although it is true that he [Aristotle] regards ex-
" Op. cit., 591. change as ultimately based on wants, he lever the less con-
54 Early British economics from the X I I I t h to the middle of siders 'proportionate equality' prior to exchange as essen-
the X V I I I t h century, 231 and 230, London, George Allen & tial. He is thus definitely on the side of those who regard
Enwin, 1938. exchange-value as existing apart from price and prior t o
68 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC.AMER.
PHIL. SOC.

by the variety of interpretations and unaware psychological nature and not directly measurable.
that so differently looking value theories as that However, the degree of want satisfaction can be
of Political Economy and the various versions expressed indirectly by something that is objec-
of the utility school are all offsprings of the tive in appearance and quantitative in nature.
same father, the historian of economic doctrines viz., money. If an individual is willing to pa)- a
takes the easy way out of a dilemma that appears certain amount of money for particular goods.
to him insoluble and not too "relevant" a t that he indicates the "worth" of those goods to him;
-he simply ignores it. the want satisfaction he derives from their posses-
sion is as great as that of any other goods which
he can buy with the same amount of mane!,.
The analysis of the exchange of goods reveals Aristotle put it thus:
the true nature of money, as Aristotle under- . . . all things t h a t are exchanged must be some-
stood it. Money is neither a "standard of how comparable. I t is for this end t h a t money has
value" nor wealth; it is a medium of exchange, been introduced. .. .
. .All goods must . . be meas-
designed to facilitate it. From this function ured by some one thing. . . . Now this [something]
two others are derived: money acts also as a is in t r u t h [want satisfaction], which holds all things
"unit of account" and as a "store of value." together . . . ; b u t money has become by con-
We do not plan to go into a lengthy discussion vention a sort of representative of [want satisfac-
tion] (Eth. Nic., V, 5 , 1133a, 17-31).
of Aristotle's theory of money. I t is the one
part of his economic doctrines that has attracted X few sentences later he rephrases his thought
more attention and has met with warmer acclaim and calls the monetary expression of the ex-
than any other part of his views on economic change ratio the "price" of things. He then
matters. Rightly so. "Great as the deficiencies goes on to illustrate how prices help to formulate
of Aristotle's theory of money are," Gelesnoff the exchange ratio of goods. He says:
has observed, "it has to be acknowledged
unreservedly . . . that . . . his formulation of .
. . Kow in t r u t h it is impossible t h a t things
the problem of the value of money is astounding differing so much should become commensurate,
b u t with reference t o \%-antthey may become so
and-a parallel phenomenon is not very easy to sufficiently. There must, then, be a unit, a n d t h a t
find even among modern economists."57 Here, fixed by agreement (for which reason i t is called
we are interested exclusively in one aspect of money); for i t is this t h a t makes all things com-
his views on money: how do they fit into the mensurate, since all things are measured b y money.
general philosophical and methodological con- Let A be a house, B ten minae, C a bed. A is half
cepts which underlie his analysis of the market of B, if the house is worth five minae or equal t o
exchange? t h e m ; the bed, C, is a tenth of B; i t is plain, then,
hour many beds are equal t o a house, viz., five
Money facilitates exchange by transforming
(Eth. IITic., V, 5 , 1133b, 18-26).
subjective, qualitative phenomena into objective,
quantitative ones. Want satisfaction is of a In exchange goods are made comparable qua
media of want satisfaction. An exchange ratio
any particular act of exchange. He did not, however,
develop a theory of the factors determining that exchange-
of goods is established if a certain amount of
value." Roll's contention that equality and exchange- one product gives the same want satisfaction as
value are to be determined prior to exchange is correct; a certain amount of another product, or to be
but he is not right if he claims that Aristotle did not explain more exact: if the ratios of two utilities are
the factors determining this equality and thus the "ex- equal to both parties. The degree of want
change-value" of goods (the term "exchange-value" as
Roll uses it cannot possibly be applied to Aristotle s satisfaction, the "value" of one unit of a product,
theory as it is derived from classical theory which, in turn, may also be expressed as the ratio of this product
is diametrically opposed to Aristotle's "utility" theory). to a certain amount of money. Aristotle calls
In Aristotle's opinion, wants form the basis of exchange this ratio a "price" and so do we. A modern
and serve as a measure of the "value" of the goods ex- economist would formulate a price as follows:
changed. A critical appraisal of Roll's analysis, inspired
by Marx's presentation of Aristotle's theory of exchange, I n every transaction, whether for barter or money,
would require a discussion of Marx's general interpretation
each person gives something up a n d receives some-
of the Greek philosopher's doctrines which cannot be done
here; Gelesnoff has done that in a definitive manner (op. thing in exchange. If 5 apples a r e traded for 25
cit., 29). nuts, t h e price of apples in terms of n u t s is 25 t o 5 ,
57 Op. cit., 29. .
or, briefly, 5 t o 1; . . Similarly, if 5 apples sell
VOL. 96, NO. 1, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY OF EXCHANGE

for 25 cents, then t h e price of apples in terms of V, 5, 1133a, 19-22). The exchange ratio of
money is 5 cents. one pair of shoes to two bushels of wheat can
Every price is really a price ratio involving a also be said to be as
numerator and a denominator. Each depends upon
the way in which the two quantities are measured; one pair of shoes :2 drachmae

... 58 : : two bushels of wheat : 2 drachmae.

The exchange ratio of two products can be The market price of one pair of shoes, i.e., two
expressed in monetary terms like this: as the drachmae, has been found by way of bargaining.
ratio of one unit of a product is to a fraction of It is the intermediate between two exchange
one unit of money, so is the ratio of one unit of ratios which, in turn, are formulated as money
another product to another fraction of the same prices such as
unit of money. This is Aristotle's example:
if 10 minae (B) is the "unit of money," the price 3 drachmae - 2 drachmae
of one house (A) is 5 minae ($B) and the price = 2 drachmae - 1 drachma.
of one bed is 1 mina (&B), then The market price of two drachmae for a pair of
1 house ( A ):5 minae (+B) shoes would be the intermediate between the
: : 1 bed (C) : 1 mina (&B). two extremes, the price demanded by the
shoemaker and the price offered by the farmer.
In this geometric proportion the first term can The market price thus corresponds to the "proper
be connected with the third term, and the price" as established in corrective justice by the
second term with the fourth (alternando). judge. In this way Aristotle has fit the concept
Then the proportion reads: of money into the pattern of corrective justice.
The modern economist has no place in his
A : C : :$B:&B
theory for this argument of Aristotle which, in
or
1 house : 1 bed : :5 minae : 1 mina. a way, elaborates his earlier thesis that money
functions as a "unit of account." Aristotle, as
T h e exchange ratio of 1 house, one unit of the we shall show presently, pursued a definite
housebuilder's produce of skill and 1 bed, one purpose in enlarging on this point. However,
unit of the carpenter's produce, is like 5 minae the modern economist would agree with him to
to 1 mina, or 5 : 1. Money has changed merely the extent that money provides a more conven-
the form of the exchange ratio but not its ient expression for the exchange ratio of any two
character; it has transcribed it in other, viz. goods.
numerical terms. Aristotle says ". . . T h a t If we relied completely on barter, we should have
exchange took place before there was money is to keep in mind a great number of price ratios-as
plain; for it makes no difference whether it is many as the number of pairs t h a t could be formed
five beds that exchange for a house, or the mathematically from the number of commodities.
money value of five beds" (Eth. Nic., V, 5, Thus, for only 5 different goods there would be 10
1133b, 26-27). Money is thus clearly a "unit different price ratios to remember. . . .
of account" and not a "standard of value." By use of the elementary axiom t h a t things equal
The advantage of using this "unit of account," to the same thing are equal t o each other, the reader
according to Aristotle, is twofold: money makes can convince himself that, once he knows the price
ratio of all goods in terms of one good, he can easily
it easier to correct deviations from the proper get the price ratio between any two goods by divi-
exchange ratio and it relieves us of the necessity sion. . . .59
of the "double coincidence of want" as required
in barter. The other advantage of the use of money
The first advantage was described by ,4ristotle consists in the fact that one of the two parties
somewhat obscurely thus: ". . . Money. . . to the exchange may prefer money to other
becomes in a sense an intermediate; for it goods either because the buyer has nothing to
measures all things, and therefore the excess offer that the seller needs or because the seller
and the defect-how many shoes are equal to a wants to postpone the exchange until a later
house or to a given amount of food" (Eth. N c . , date. The point was very well taken by
Aristotle :
58 Paul A. Samuelson, Economics. A n introductory
analysis, 58, N . Y . , McGraw-Hill, 1948. 59 Samuelson, ibid., 5 6 5 7 .
70 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC. AMER.
PHIL. SOC.

And for the future e x c h a n g e t h a t if we d o not would have undermined his contention that
need a thing no\\; we shall have it ever we do need i t money "exists not by nature."
-money is as i t were our surety; for it must be 1, another context, ~ ~ i ~employed t ~ t la ~
possible for us to get what we want by bringing the theory about the origin of money which, too, was
money. Now the same thing happens to money
itself as to goods-it is not always worth the same;
definitely in contradiction to the "conventional-
yet it tends to be the steadier. This is why all ist" theory as offered in the Ethics. In the
goods must have a price set on them; for then there "Politics," he traced the use of metallic money
willalwaysbeexchange . . . (Eth. ,Vic.,V,5, 1133b, backtothegeneralusefulnessof themetalsout
10-16). of which money is coined. He wrote:
The description of the role of money as a store . . . men agreed to employ in their dealings with
of value can hardl?. be better. Money permits each other something which was intrinsically useful
us to divide exchange into two transactions, and easily applicable to the purpose of life, for ex-
selling and buying, and to effect these two ample, iron, silver and the like. Of this the value
transactions a t different times. This division was a t first measured simply by size and weight,
but in the process of time they p u t a stamp upon it,
obviates the necessity of the "double coincidence
to save the trouble of weighing and to mark the
of want" in barter, i.e., that exchange can take
value (Pol., I , 9, 1257a, 35-41).
place only if one party has to offer what the
other needs and vice versa. The only "proof" he ever suggested in support
How did money ever acquire its three func- of his conventionalist theory of money is the
tions, that of a medium of exchange, a unit of fable of Midas (Pol., I, 9, 1257b, 15-16). But
account and a store of value? R/Ioney, says if everything that Jlidas touched would have
Aristotle, has become the "representative of been transformed into something else than gold
want" by "agreement" or "lawH-"because it and something that had "utility" such as bread
exists not by nature but b ~ law - (nomos) and or clothing, would JIidas' fate have been
it is in our power to change it and to make it different? ,Aristotle thought the JIidas fable to
useless" (Eth. -2iic., V, 5, 1133a, 30-31). His be enough support for that school which con-
thesis is not as conclusive as it may appear a t sidered Inone>- but a "sham" in contrast to
the first glance. The fact that we can change the the other school which believed money to be
value of the monetary unit through debasement real wealth. In discussing these two schools of
or completel1. demonetize Inonel., does not thought, he indicated a definite preference for
imply, as Aristotle wants us to believe, that the former; this is in harmony with his theor)- in
the concrete form of money-a certain amount the Ethics but a t variance with the above quoted
of precious metal-has no value in itself. The passage from the same chapter of the Politics.
question remains: why, in the first place, did \Ye like to suggest an explanation why, in
people select a certain precious metal to act as this particular place in the Ethics -Aristotle
a representative of need? .And furthermore, presented the "conventionalist" theor!, of mane\.
does gold or silver lose its utilit?. completel!., without reservations. Exchange of goods is
once it loses its function as "money"? rooted in the natural "inequalit?" of the
Aristotle came very close to an answer to exchanging parties but is conducted strict11 in
these questions. In the Rhetoric ( I , 7, 1364a, the spirit of "equality." Once the naturally
24-26), he pointed out that things are more or unequal skills are equalized, the parties to the
less valuable depending on whether they are exchange are treated as equals. "\fTant satis-
rare or plentiful. "Thus, gold is a better thing faction" equalizes the goods and their producers
than iron, though less useful: it is harder to get, and money takes over the function of want,
and therefore more worth getting." Aristotle a t least on the surface and for all practical
never followed up rarity as a basis of value; purposes. Seen in this aspect, the role of
he might have arrived a t different results regard- moneS- becomes very similar to that of the
ing the worth of skills or goods in general. judge in corrective justice.60 \Yhen he discussed
The concept of rarity as an explanation of value
6 o Stewart, op. cit., 1: 416 has noted that "it is in the
would have heen in no contradiction to his
institution of vburapa that the pri~lciple of Corrective
general utility theor!.; in fact, it would have Justice is most largely and effectively embodied. . . ."
lent it additional support. The rarity of gold Stewart also referred to one of the medieval (eleventh
as a ground of explanation of its value, however, re~ltury) Byzantine commentators of Aristotle, Michael
VOL. 96, NO. 1, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE

the working of corrective justice, Aristotle into the Ethics. Plato and X e n o ~ h o n had
made the point that "in bul~ingand selling and mentioned it already and there exist good
in all matters in which the law left people free reasons to assume that the conventionalist theory
to make their own terms" (Eth. Nic., V, 4, 1132b, of money goes back to the early Cynics.62 The
15-16), they act so to sa) as their own judges, Cynical School, in turn, was closely related to
preventing "loss" and "gain" and making sure the S o ~ h i s t s . The founder of the school.
that each one gets what is due to him. *And Antisthenes, was a pupil first of the Sophist
shortly before he formulated his thesis that Gorgias and later of Socrates. The Sophists
money exists not by nature but by law, he made were the ones who developed the theory that
the obscure remark: "money . . . becomes in a the government was a creation of a social contract
sense an intermediate, for it measures all things, and they stressed the principle of "corrective
and therefore the excess and the defect."61 justice" in contrast to the "distributive justice"
-4ristotle thought that money was not merel>- of their antagonists. The interpretation of
instrumental in expressing price relations in money as another institution of convention,
general but, more important, in enabling the man-made and thus subject to change a t the
exchanging parties to arrive a t the proper will of man, suits well the intellectual climate of
exchange ratio. That is why he divided the Sophistic reasoning. Plato probably adopted it
function of money as a common denominator of from them when he spoke in the Republic
different goods into tivo subordinate functions: (371 B) and in the Laws (742 A , B ; 918 B) of
moneq acts as a "unit of account" and also as money as a "symbol of exchange."
a measure of the correct exchange ratio. MTe However, Aristotle did not accept uncritically
have shown why a modern economist cannot Plato's version of the conventionalist theory of
accept Xristotle's distinction. The use of mone! monel-. He agreed in principle with Plato's
as a common denominator is more economical thesis that money "equalizes" goods but he
than exchange ratios between pairs of specified denied that the trader, who puts monel- to this
goods in barter because it provides one price use, has any part in the functioning of money as
ratio from which other ratios are easily derived. the common denominator. Plato wrote:
The exchange ratio which eventually becomes
Retail t r a d e in a c i t y is n o t b y n a t u r e i n t e n d e d t o
the market price constitutes only one among
d o a n y h a r m , b u t q u i t e t h e c o n t r a r y ; for is n o t he a
many possible ratios; it is not money that benefactor w h o reduces ineoualities a n d incommen-
brings it about but bargaining or, in modern surabilities of goods t o e q u a l i t y a n d c o m m o n meas-
parlance, the play of the market forces. u r e ? A n d this is w h a t t h e power of m o n e y accom-
Aristotle was furthermore motivated by an plishes, a n d t h e m e r c h a n t m a y be said t o be a p -
intellectual tradition to link up the conventional- pointed for this purpose. T h e hireling a n d t h e
ist theory of money with the working of correc- tavern-keeper, a n d m a n y o t h e r occupations, s o m e
tive justice. Both theories grew out of the same of t h e m more a n d o t h e r s less seemly-alike have
this object;-they seem t o satisfy o u r needs a n d
general social philosophy, viz., the convention- equalize o u r possession^.^^
alism of the Sophists. The theory that money is
a creation of law or convention, and the etl-mo- W. L. Newman, The Politics of Aristotle, 2 : 187-188,
logical explanation of its nature contained in the Oxford, Clarendon Press, 1887, has quoted a n impressive
fact that the name for money (nomisma) has list of references which all point in this direction. New-
man believes that Aristotle in the Politics, I , 9, 1257b was
been derived from the word "law" (nomos), was discussing the attitude of the early Cynics toward money.
of old standing when Aristotle incorporated it 63 This is Jowett's translation of this somewhat obscure
passage in book X I , 918, of the Laws. B. Jowett, The
of Ephesus, who pointed to this analogy between money dialogties of Plato, 2 : 657, N. Y., Random House, 1937.
and the judge. Ibid., 462. We realize that Jowett's rendition is open to discussion.
61 The Greek equivalent of what Ross translates with The English Plato-scholar Taylor translates as follows:
"excess" and "defect," J?rcpox$v and ZXXei$iv, respectively, ". . . Internal retail trade, when one considers its essen-
can also be rendered with "superior and inferior value," tial function, is not a mischievous thing, but much the
as, e.g., Rackham has done in his translation (op. cit., reverse. Can a man be other than a benefactor if he
283). The context seems to us to suggest a reference to effects the even and proportionate diffusion of anything
the two extremes and the intermediate of the arithmetic in its own nature so disproportionately and unevenly
proportion in corrective justice. In the preceding analysis, diffused as commodities of all sorts? This, we should
the producers and their goods have been equalized already; remind ourselves, is the very result achieved by a currency,
what remains to be done is the determination of the market and this, as we should recognize, the function assigned t o
price as the resultant of the two estimated prices. the trader. Similarly the wage-earner, the tavern-keeper,
72 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC.A MER. PHIL. soc.

Plato thus assigned the function of money to rather he always fought any claim of the com-
"equalize goods" to the trader as much as to mercial class to this source of its wealth. Aristotle
money or to mone5- if in the hands of the trader. found a way out of this dilemma, created by
Although Plato himself spoke in a quite uncom- Plato, if it ever was one to him: he retransferred
plimentary manner about trade in general in the function of "equalization," i.e., the faculty
the introduction to the above quoted passage of to make goods commensurable and thus to
the Laws, he felt compelled to acknowledge that facilitate mutual want satisfaction, from the
the trader is a "benefactor" to the community trader to the impersonal mediator, money. And
-
as lone as he adheres to the rules of his trade. money, Aristotle said clearly enough, is "barren";
Aristotle despised trade in every form and it cannot "by nature" produce children-
particularly "retail trade," and he was as little "profit" and "interestH-to the trader and
inclined to make any concession to the merchant money lender (Pol., I, 10, 1258b, 2-8).
class as the younger Plato in the Republic.
The afore mentioned theory of trade represents VII
the view of the aged Plato, the author of the Aristotle's theorl- of exchange has never been
Laws, who had made his peace with moneymak- accepted in its totality bq- any philosopher or
ing and p l u t ~ c r a c y while
, ~ ~ -4ristotle never gave economist in modern history. The complexity
up his opposition to this class (see Pol., 1, 9, of the ~ h i l o s o ~ h i c aframework
l within which
1257b, 1-10). Xristotle saw quite well the Alristotleexpounded his ideas and the peculiar
implication of Plato's views: the trader, because methodological approach prevented its accept-
he ~ e r f o r m sas useful a role as Plato ascribes to ance even among scholars well versed in Alristotle
him, is entitled to some sort of reward. That is exegesis. Elements of his theory, however,
exactll- what Alristotledisputed; he was unable such as want as the measure of value, the role
to detect an)- justification of commercial "profit," of monel- in exchange, and the principle of
and other callings, some more and some less reputable, all exchange of equivalents have entered the
have the common function of meeting various demands meditations on the nature of exchange of
with supply and distributing commodities more evenly.
.. ." (.A. E. Taylor, The laws of Plato, 31 1, London, J . M. post-scholastic modern philosophers until the
Dent & Sons, 1934). knd of the eighteenth century. The founders
The difference in translation hinges on the words d p a h j v of the utilitv theory of value in the France of the
and r 6 p p e ~ p o v . Taylor follows the tradition of interpreting second half.of the-eighteenth century employed
the term ot5ppsrpov with "even and proportionate diffusion concepts that bear the stamp of Aristotelian
of anything." E. B. England in his edition of the Laws,
2: 521, Manchester, Univ. Press, 1921, gives the less reasoning. I t is hard to believe that they
equivocal equivalent of dvhpaXov as "inequality in the dis- should have happened on them without knowl-
tribution of stock throughout the community." We pre- edge of the originator. As an example of the
fer Jowett's translation; it seems to meet the meaning of similarity between their theor)- and that of the
this passage better. But regardless of which one of the
two interpretations one accepts, in one point the intention
Greek philosopher we like to quote a passage
of Plato's thesis is clear: money performs its function in from A. R. J. Turgot's Re$ections on the Forma-
the hands of the trader and the trader has a function in tion and Distribution of JVealth. In this famous
society which qualifies him for some reward. And this work, Turgot wrote:
contention Aristotle refuted. An interesting examination
of Plato's view on this topic which had a n immeasurable S o long a s we consider each exchange a s isolated
influence on medieval speculation about the role of the a n d s t a n d i n g b y itself, t h e v a l u e of each of t h e
trader in society is presented by Barker, op. cit., 324-325. things exchanged h a s n o o t h e r measure t h a n t h e
Barker, too, sides with Jowett in the interpretation of the need o r t h e desire a n d t h e m e a n s of t h e c o n t r a c t i n g
above passage. I t is regrettable that Barker has not parties, balanced o n e a g a i n s t t h e o t h e r , a n d i t is
brought out this difference between Plato and .lristotle fixed b y n o t h i n g b u t t h e a g r e e m e n t of their
when he investigated the debt of iiristotle to the Laws,
380-382. This tradition and the power of Aristotelian
64 In another passage cf the L a w , Plato stated this rule
concerning the distribution of power and wealth in the
ideas was partll- destroyed or a t least over-
state: "Political offices, arid contributions, as well as dis- shadowed by the tremendous impact of the
tribution of bounties, should be proportional to the value English classical school of economics, particu-
of a citizen's wealth. And they should depend not only larly in the form it was given it by Ricardo
on his virtue or that of his ancestors or on the size and and J. St. Mill. The more surprising it is that
attractiveness of his body, but also upon his wealth or his --
poverty" (Laws, V,744 B ) . Cf. also Popper, op. cit., n. 20 66 Quoted from Jlasterworks of economics, ed. by L. D.
to chap. 6 , p. 219. Abbott, 53, N. Y., Doubleday, 1948.
VOL. 96, NO.1, 19521 ARISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 73

one of the fathers of the modern marginal goods. Aristotle was concerned exclusively with
-utility school of economics, W. St. Jevons, the goods given away and received whereas
should have developed a theory of exchange Jevons, motivated by his general value theory,
which in spirit and form, in premise and con- compared the goods exchanged with the amounts
clusion, provides the most amazing parallelism of goods retained by the parties. Another
to Aristotle's doctrine in the history of economic dissimilarity arises from the way in which
thought. His ideas as presented in the Theory Jevons formulated mathematically the relation
of Political Economy66 read like a modern between persons and goods. Aristotle, we
paraphrase of the fifth book of the Ethics. remember, expressed it as a proportion; the
Jevons was not a t all aware of it; on the con- relation of the housebuilder, A , to the product
trary, he believed that with his novel ideas on of his skill, C, appeared to him as the ratio A : C.
economics he had broken away from a tradition Jevons conceived of it as a function, and that is
hostile, as he thought, to the progress of no doubt a superior way of expressing it. Thus,
economic thinking and from the authority the relation of the farmer A to his corn a is
of their representatives among whom he counted described by Jevons as f (a) ; this function denotes
Aristotle. "I protest against deference for any the degree of utility to A of the total amount of
man," he wrote, "whether John Stewart Mill, corn in his possession before the exchange takes
or Adam Smith, or Aristotle, being allowed to place. Furthermore, Jevons was thinking in
check i n q ~ i r y . " ~ ' The irony of his judgment terms of "marginal" (he called it "final")
of Aristotle, however, is excusable if we remember utility, i.e. the utility of an infinitely small
how Aristotle's teachings were presented to quantity of a commodity-a notion unfamiliar
English economists in the middle of the to Aristotle. According to his general theory of
nineteenth century. value, Jevons regarded the utility of the total
The mathematical treatment of its theories, amount of corn as not measurable; he concerned
Jevons held, would give economics the character himself only with the degree of utility of one
of a science. T h a t applied particularly to the fraction of it such as the amount of corn A
theory of the exchange of goods. The correct exchanges, or the degree of utilitj- of the differ-
solution of the problem involved in exchange, ence between the amount A possessed before
Jevons maintained, required the recognition of the exchange, a , and the amount he possesses
its mathematical nature. He formulated it as after the exchange, a - x. The exchange of
follows: "As there must be two parties and two goods involves, in the view of Jevons, therefore
quantities to every exchange, there must be two four functions:
equations" (p. 101). Here are the four terms of (1) the utility to A of the amount of corn he
the proportion, Aristotle has spoken of: two
retains (a - x) or (a - x),
persons and two products which, if in proper
(2) the utility to A of the goods he receives (y)
proportion, assure equality in exchange. Jevons,
then, set forth the relation between the persons or $1 Y,
(3) the utility to B of the amount of beef he
and the goods. "Let us now suppose that the retains (b - y) or $2 (b - y), and
first body, A , originally possessed the quantity
(4) the utility to B of the corn he receives (x)
a of corn, and that the second body, B , possessed
or 4~x.
the quantity b of beef. As the exchange consists
in giving x of corn for y of beef, the state of "Let 41 (a - x) denote the final degree of
things after exchange will be as follows: utility of corn to A , and 42 x the corresponding
function for B. Also let $1 y denote A's final
A holds a - x of corn, and y of beef

degree of utility for beef and $2 (b - y) B's


B holds x of corn, and b - y of beef" (p. 99).

similar function" (p. 99).


Thus far, there is no difference between The problem is now this: There must be
Aristotle's and Jevons' approach t o the problem. established a ratio between the two products
The deviation of Jevons from Aristotle sets in exchanged-y:x-which will bring about two
with the formulation of the character of the new ratios: one between the utility to A of the
relation between the exchanging parties and the amount of his goods he retains (a - x) after
68 Fourth edition, London, Macmillan, 1911. Chap. IV,
exchanging x for y and the utility of the amount
pp. 75-166. of the commodity he receives (y) from B, and
67 Ibid., 276-277. another one between the utility to B of the
74 JOSEF SOUDEK [PROC. AMER. PHIL. SOC.

amount of his goods he retains (b - y) after The ratio of exchange of two products is the
exchanging y for x and the utility of the amount reciprocal of the ratio of the utilities of what A
of the commodity (x) he receives from A . The gives away to what he receives, and conversely
Y
to what B gives away to what he receives.
ratio - is the price. There must be an equality Aristotle as well as Jevons recognized the
x
Y difficulty of finding a common denominator for
between - and the first ratio pertaining to A , and the utilities of identical goods to different per-
x

sons. He, too, introduced therefore a ratio but


another equality between and the ratio per- it was one between the utility of what one
.T
desires for consumption and the utility of one's
taining to B.
own product of skill; both utilities, however, he
The exchange ratio of the two products
stated differently from Jevons, in terms of ab-
exchanged will be inversely related to the ratio
solute rather than marginal utility.
of the final degrees of utility of the amount of
Jevons was bound to arrive a t the same con-
goods retained by the exchanging parties. -qs
clusion as Aristotle because he started out from
Jevons put it:
two sets of assumptions identical with those of
T h e ratio of exchange of a n y two commodities the philosopher and employed an almost identical
will be the reciprocal of the ratio of the final degree methodological approach. \Ye have discussed
of utility of the quantities of commodity available the parallelism in methodology and now want
after the exchange is completed (p. 95). to add a few remarks as to the general philosoph-
We arrive, then, a t the conclusion, t h a t whenever ical concepts underlying both theories. Jevons'
two commodities are exchanged for each other . . .
the quantities exchanged satisfy two equations,
theory of value, based on Bentham's hedonism,
which may be thus stated in a concise form- is practically the same as A r i s t ~ t l e ' s . ~Both
~
believe that satisfaction of wants motivates man
&(a - x) - -
y - "P(X ((p. 100). in his economic endeavors and, therefore con-
J.~(Y) .2: J.z(b - y ) stitutes the objective in the exchange of goods.
The ratio of the marginal utility of what A Both assume, furthermore, that some equality
retains to what he receives is thus equal to the guides the conduct of exchange and this equality
ratio of the marginal utility of what B retains to must be one of want satisfaction.
what he receives. Jevons introduced a ratio The theory of exchange of both men met with
of "final degree of utilitl-" in the conviction little success. Aristotle's theory was never
that final utility as such cannot be measured and fully understood and bore the odium of queer-
need not be measured for two reasons: first, ness. Jevons' theory was rejected by modern
every mind is inscrutable to every other mind economists, to a lesser part on account of its
and no common denominator for utilities can philosophical character, but mainly because of
be found, and secondly, the parties to the ex- the inherent inability to explain social exchange,
change compare the relative utility of what they the exchange in the market. Carl Menger has
desire with the relative utility of what they retain refuted the validity of every theory which aims
and these ratios provide a homogeneous basis for to prove that exchange of equivalents constitutes
comparison. the motivation and objective of exchange of
Aristotle, on the other hand, compared the goods.69 For reasons which we cannot investi-
A Oskar Kraus has revealed the links of philosophical
utility of what A gives away, - with what he @

C' tradition which tie Aristotle's value theory as presented


A in the ni'comachean Ethics with Bentham's hedonism
receives, - and the corresponding utilities to B , and via Bentham with Jevons' economics (op. cit., 574
D' and more detailed in his book Z u r Theorie des Wertes,
and stipulated the following two equations : Halle, Max Xiemeyer, 1901). But Kraus concerned him-
self exclusively with the general philosophical ideas under-
lying the value theories of .Xristotle and Jevons, respec-
tively, xvithout entering into a detailed analysis of the
theories of exchange as we have done here.
or if A : C = e, B : D = f, A:D = g, and B : C 69.%-ticle "Geld," Handwoerterbuch der Staatswissen-
= h, then schaften, 3: 730-757, 1st ed., Jena, G. Fischer, 1892.
hIenger investigated primarily Aristotle's theory of money
e - -C- -
- f but took occasion to go into this aspect of Aristotle's
g-D-h' general philosophy of exchange. \I:hile he misunderstood
VOL. 96, NO. I, 19.521 -4RISTOTLE'S THEORY O F EXCHANGE 75

gate here, hIengerls dictum seems to have been natural prices, i.e., the exchange ratio of goods re-
generally accepted by all schools of modern gardless of their monetary expression. Further-
economics. The more serious criticism leveled more, Aristotle looked a t goods not merely as
a t Jevons' equation, and the one which sealed media of want satisfaction but as products of
its fate, consists in the fact that Jevons' theory human skill as well-an aspect which has given
clarifies a t best individual exchange, but not rise to so many misunderstandings of his
social exchange, i.e. the exchange of goods thoughts. The modern economist neglects pur-
between many sellers and many buyers whose posely this aspect as it is apt to lead him into a
actions constitute the forces of the market as a labor theory of value; the partiality of the
whole. Turgot, in his above quoted statement, modern economist a t once simplifies his task
proved to be a keener analyst than Jevons. He and lends greater consistency to his theorizing.
realized that his and, by implication, Aristotle's Yet Aristotle's approach opens broader vistas
theor\- applied only "so long as we consider each to the science of economics as he realized the
exchange as isolated and standing by itself." dual role of the exchanging parties in the market,
Jevons was not aware of that and thought that viz. the identity of producers and consumers.
his deductions would hold for the simultaneous We see J . B. Say's Law of the Jfarkets faintly
exchange of all parties in the market as well. shaping up; but even its simplest implication
IVicksell and Edgeworth, though generally in would have been incomprehensible to the philos-
sympathy with Jevons' undertaking, have shown opher himself.
that he has wrongly assumed that all parties in The potentialities of Aristotle's theory are, and
the market would be motivated by exactly the in history have proven to be, immense. Their
same degree of marginal utility and has thus impact on the development of economic doc-
trines, manifestly and implicitly, is not easy to
described in a complicated manner nothing
appraise. The theory of exchange, though
else than free c ~ m p e t i t i o n . ~ ~
consistent in itself, does not form the central
Aristotle had no such ambitions as Jevons. part of a comprehensive and coherent theory
He confined himself to individual exchange as is of economics which could have been taken over
to be expected in a work on the ethics of individ- in toto by any school of thought; yet historically
ual behavior. Social economics were outside it broke fertile ground on which a systematic
the scope of the Ethics;he treated them in the theory could thrive. Rudolf Kaulla was there-
Politics. But he dealt with two asDects of the fore fully justified in opening his study of the
exchange of goods which, in turn, were outside development of modern value theories with an
the scope of Jevons' reasoning: he implemented enlightened though brief summary of Aristotle's
into his theory an explanation of money prices theory of exchange. As to its historical signifi-
where Jevons stopped a t the vindication of cance, he came to the following conclusion:
Aristotle's theory of money, misled by the misinterpreta- .\ristotle has brought into the world the thought
tions prevailing in his time, he had a good insight into the which was t o insure his influence on the philosophy
ethical postulates of Aristotle's theory of exchange; how- of economics u p t o t h e most recent times: t h a t t h e
ever, he refuted them as much as the theories "of most comparability of values of different economic goods
economic theoreticians" following -4ristotle in respect to has a s its condition a something which is common
the princ~pleof the "exchange of equivalents." t o t h e magnitudes t o be ~ o m p a r e d . ~ '
7 0 Wicksell's and Edgeworth's arguments are satis-
factorily discussed by Roll, op. czt., 420-421. 7L Op. cit., 52.

You might also like