You are on page 1of 9

medical education in review

Professionalism: a framework to guide medical


education
Howard Brody1,2 & David Doukas3

CONTEXT Despite considerable advances in RESULTS The key precepts needed for a
the incorporation of professionalism into the robust presentation of professionalism can be
formal curriculum, medical students and resi- grouped under two headings: Professionalism
dents are too often presented with a mechani- as a trust-generating promise (representing
cal, unreflective version of the topic that fails commitment to patients interests, more than
to convey deeper ethical and humanistic aspi- a mere business, a social contract, a public
rations. Some misunderstandings of profes- and collective promise, and hard work), and
sionalism are exacerbated by commonly used Professionalism as application of virtue to
assessment tools that focus only on superfi- practice (based on virtue, deeper attitudes
cially observable behaviour and not on moral rather than mere behaviour, and requiring of
values and attitudes. practical wisdom).

METHODS Following a selective literature CONCLUSIONS These key precepts help stu-
review, we engaged in philosophical ethical dents to avoid many common, unreflective
analysis to identify the key precepts associated misunderstandings of professionalism, and
with professionalism that could best guide the guide faculty staff and students jointly to
development of an appropriately reflective address the deeper issues required for success-
curriculum. ful professional identity formation.

Medical Education 2014: 48: 980987


doi: 10.1111/medu.12520

Discuss ideas arising from the article at


www.mededuc.com discuss

1
Institute for the Medical Humanities, University of Texas Medical Correspondence: Howard Brody, Institute for the Medical
Branch, Galveston, Texas, USA Humanities, University of Texas Medical Branch, 301 University
2
Department of Family Medicine, University of Texas Medical Boulevard, Galveston, Texas 77555-1311, USA.
Branch, Galveston, Texas, USA Tel: 00 1 409 772 9386/2376; E-mail: habrody@utmb.edu
3
Division of Medical Humanism and Ethics, Department of
Family and Geriatric Medicine, University of Louisville, Louisville,
Kentucky, USA

980 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987
Professionalism: a framework

education research is compounded. Knowing how


INTRODUCTION properly to assess and measure professionalism
requires the contributions of more disciplines than
A Year 3 medical student turned in to one of us (HB) are usually brought to bear, especially ethical and
a required essay that began When I hear the word philosophical perspectives. Although the sociology
professionalism, my first reaction is Yuk! In the of the professions teaches us important lessons that
resultant small-group discussion, several students have major ethical import, viewing professionalism
concurred with the writer: they too had come away as a concept to be explained solely by sociological
from their previous professionalism teaching sessions models is inadequate.17 As valuable as it may be to
with negative opinions. They had somehow gotten measure behaviour, if professionalism is more than
the impression that professionalism as presented in behaviour, all such assessment tools will fall short.
their curriculum had taught them merely prohibi- We concur with the observation of Cruess and Cru-
tions of behaviour. When asked what they thought ess: As situated learning theory suggests, a balance
professionalism ought to mean, they described a con- must be struck between teaching the cognitive base
cept which, in the instructors view, matched well with explicitly and providing opportunities where learn-
the core ethical ideas the term is intended to convey: ing can occur in an authentic context.18 For exam-
dedication to the priority of the patients interests. ple, one thoughtful study of unprofessional
behaviour among students (passing examination
Our joint experience in teaching about ethics and information to their fellows) correctly identified the
professionalism for a number of years reinforces culture of assessment as a background condition
our concern that medical educators too often trans- affecting the behaviour. The authors, however,
mit to students and residents an unreflective, failed to ask how assessing professionalism itself
mechanical view of professionalism. This concern might create problems for teaching the concept cor-
was voiced by Coulehan1 and subsequently sup- rectly.19
ported by empirical studies.26 One possible flaw in
this teaching is that the concept and practice of pro- This paper proposes a keep it simple approach to
fessionalism may not be sufficiently grounded in the cognitive base of professionalism that conveys
either ethics or humanities. Such teaching can be a the most critical and central ideas in a way that
reduction of behaviours into a list of Do Nots learners can readily grasp and value. This presenta-
based on superficial appearance and comportment, tion, moreover, naturally leads to further inquiry
evaluated by checklists. The resultant negative per- that prompts deeper ethical reflection. Our goal is
ception of professionalism in many students stems to clarify this core set of ideas for use in profession-
from their impression that they are being asked to alism pedagogy, and thus indirectly to guide future
memorise a list of rules that seems detached from educational assessment and research. This paper
their intended ethical role as a healer.2,4,6,7 Instead, does not propose a detailed professionalism curricu-
we assert that professionalism ought to resonate pos- lum because such curricula will necessarily vary
itively with the ethical aspirations of learners and depending on the teaching setting and resources.20
prompt them to reflect more deeply.8 The key precepts required to convey this core set of
ideas are grouped under two interrelated headings:
Some educators attribute the problem of how to Professionalism as a trust-generating promise, and
teach professionalism to the lack of scholarly con- Professionalism as application of virtue to practice.
sensus over the definition of professionalism, or to
other problems of a conceptual nature.7,916 We
support continued scholarly inquiry, but disagree PROFESSIONALISM AS A TRUST-GENERATING
that this is where the pedagogic problem lies. We PROMISE
believe that, at present, we possess for teaching pur-
poses sufficient consensus on the most important The first set of precepts leads to the idea that pro-
core ideas that ground professionalism. Overcoming fessionalism entails making a promise that ideally
professionalisms negative impression requires that builds public trust and can be very challenging to
we focus more on the aspirational signal and less on fulfil. Once students see how challenging this task
the deleterious noise. is, they are better prepared for the second set of
precepts, which address the character formation
If we are presently unclear on how best to teach necessary to live up to such a promise over a profes-
professionalism, the problem with respect to sional lifetime.

2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987 981
H Brody & D Doukas

Professionalism as a commitment to the interests of consulting the list.1,2,4,6,7 We suggest instilling in stu-
the patient dents the core of what professionalism is and then
helping them to see how the core logically gener-
Professionalism represents a commitment to placing ates the list. It is still helpful to share the list with
the interests of the patient ahead of those of the students, but ideally as a set of illustrations with
professional. which to expand the core precept.

Most definitions agree that the goal of the profes- Professionalism means that health care can never be
sional interaction is the benefit of the patient and merely a business
only secondarily the benefit of the physician.
(Although a technical term for this attribute is self- In a world in which all human relationships tend to
abnegation, we will use the more widely under- be recast as business arrangements, it is worth stat-
stood, if less precise, term altruism.21) Such a ing this key precept explicitly, even if it is merely a
claim may seem both self-evident and vacuous, but restatement of the first.24 If health care were pri-
it is actually quite pregnant with important issues marily a business, making a profit could be seen as
that students and residents need to discuss. its first principle, thereby contradicting the precept
that the good of the patient comes before the good
At what point, for example, do the professionals of the professional. Health care in todays world is
own interests have a legitimate claim in patient indeed a business: professionals are not indepen-
care? How much is the professional expected to dently wealthy, and someone must pay the rent and
sacrifice to benefit the patient? When do lifestyle keep the lights on. However, health care should
issues or moral commitments owed to other indi- never be viewed merely or primarily as a business. The
viduals supersede ones obligations to the patient? commercialisation and commodification of medi-
These are issues with which students and residents cine are among the most important threats to pro-
should grapple under faculty guidance and thus it fessionalism today,25 and students are immersed in
is helpful that this key precept stimulates such a world that views every aspect of human life as
questions. occurring in a marketplace.26,27 This aspect of pro-
fessionalism therefore deserves emphasis. For exam-
Placing the patients interests first entails a list of ple, Hafferty and Castellanis proposal that
related behaviours entrepreneurial professionalism and lifestyle pro-
fessionalism merely represent further recognition
Placing the patients interests first logically entails a of professionalisms complexities in todays world
list of related professional behaviours and obliga- requires a greater examination of their ethical foun-
tions. Contrary to the perception of the medical stu- dations and implications.14
dent described in the Introduction, definitions of
professionalism can also assume the form of lists Professionalism is derived from the verb to
of desirable behaviours.22 For example, many defini- profess, which means to promise
tions grant technical competence equal status with
giving priority to the patients interests.23 However, In a classic article, Pellegrino stated that the verb
when learners understand that professionalism in form was more informative than the noun.28 This
practice must be guided by the patients best inter- key precept relates the other precepts to the impor-
est, they readily see that this beneficence-based duty tant goal of public trust. Medicine requires public
requires the physician to be technically competent in trust, a concept that embraces the patients trust in
order to truly be able to serve. Similarly, the priority the individual practitioner. Patients will not give an
of the patients interests implies other professional honest, exhaustive medical history, or allow their
behaviours, such as respecting confidentiality, truth- bodies to be examined and probed, without this
fulness and shared decision making. trust, but without the information thus gleaned
from patients, practitioners will be helpless to com-
When professionalism is presented as a laundry list plete their tasks. Why should patients trust practitio-
of behaviours (whether positive or negative), stu- ners, including those they have never previously
dents equate the learning of professionalism with encountered? The answer this key precept offers is
the memorising of such a list, which implies that that health professionals have promised the commu-
whether a behaviour is professional or unprofes- nity at large to place the interests of the patient
sional can be determined by mechanically foremost.

982 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987
Professionalism: a framework

The promise suggested by to profess is both a A public, collective promise to dedicate oneself to
public and a collective promise putting the patients interests first suggests on
reflection that the physician has undertaken a very
Why should patients find this promise compelling? challenging task. Humans are probably pro-
What makes professionals worthy of the trust they grammed to be altruistic on occasions when, for
expect? In the end, professionals actual behaviour example, those with whom they feel close ties of
will establish their trustworthiness. Yet most patients kinship are threatened by physical danger. By con-
are nevertheless willing at least provisionally to trust trast, it is difficult to put someones interests ahead
practitioners. This trust is driven by the sense that of our own when we feel tired or threatened. It is
the promise made by practitioners to the commu- even harder to prioritise the interests of those with
nity is both public and collective. whom we feel no natural identity, and towards
whom we may even feel animosity. Yet the promise
Medical students best grasp this key precept when of professionalism requires that all such patients, in
they consider the ceremony at which a physicians all such circumstances, receive our best care, predi-
oath is sworn upon graduation. Firstly, the ceremony cated on our diligence in knowledge and skill acqui-
is public; the class does not retreat behind closed sition, our directed efforts towards the patients
doors to recite the oath. Secondly, swearing the oath benefit, and our public trust.30 Larson and Yao
is a collective action of the entire class; it is a promise make a similar point about empathy and point out
to the public and to each other. Individual students are that bringing ones deeper attitudes into congru-
not asked whether or not they wish to recite the oath, ence with surface behaviours requires considerable
or whether they would like to alter the wording to cre- emotional labour.31
ate their own versions. All participants take for
granted that the ceremony will lack meaning unless Admitting that keeping the promise of professional-
all students swear the same oath at the same time. ism is difficult accomplishes three critical pedagogic
tasks. Firstly, it establishes the importance of a pro-
The precept of a public, collective promise may be fessionalism curriculum and justifies time and
a challenging one to convey to students in a society energy devoted to the topic. Secondly, it takes the
so wedded to the ideal (or myth) of individualism. faculty member off the pedestal and opens up real
Students may initially resist the idea that they are dialogue with students as all reflect together upon
bound by a collective promise that they did not ways to deal with predictable challenges to profes-
individually negotiate. Reflection, however, will sional behaviour. Finally, understanding how hard
show them that if the promise is not both public professionalism is leads naturally to the next set of
and collective, patients will have little reason to key precepts that identify professionalism with vir-
trust a physician who happens to be on duty in the tue. Virtue comprises our positive aspirations for
emergency department and whom the patient has character that will achieve the goods of health care
never previously met. One pedagogic technique by translating our deeper values, attitudes and
that nicely bridges individualism with the precept beliefs into effective behaviours.
of the collective promise involves having students
write their own oaths or codes.29 The notion of a Professionalism as an implied contract between
public, collective promise leads directly to the fur- society and the profession
ther precept of professionalism as a social contract,
which we address below. Professionalism can be viewed as an implied con-
tract between society and the medical profession, in
Professionalism, properly understood, is hard work which mutual benefits are conferred, and which can
be renegotiated if conditions change.
A further problem with unreflective assessment
tools, in which professionalism is equated with the At first glance the sociological literature on the pro-
checking by faculty staff of boxes that refer to obser- fessions might appear to be distinct from an ethical
vable behaviours, is that they create the impression approach, as sociology attempts a descriptive
that meeting the minimum threshold is easy and account, whereas ethics addresses the ought rather
that only learners with serious ethical flaws will be than the is.14,32 The notion of a social contract,
deficient in professionalism. This undermines the however, provides an important meeting ground
important message that professionalism is an aspira- between sociological and ethical accounts. Cruess
tional goal which even the best physicians must and Cruess have reminded us that the idea of the
struggle to attain. social contract can usefully frame the way in which

2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987 983
H Brody & D Doukas

professionalism is taught.18,33 For example, without tue perspective, students may wonder why they are
the social contract, students will be unable to under- being asked to adopt this seemingly idiosyncratic
stand the ethical importance and context of ade- approach when addressing professionalism.
quate physician self-regulation.
Students will best understand a virtue approach
The concept of the social contract reminds the stu- when they are reminded of how hard it is to keep
dent that trust involves a two-way relationship. Ide- ones public promise to put the interests of patients
ally, trust exists on the patients side and trust- first, as the maintenance of public trust requires. To
worthiness on the physicians. A dedication to profes- do this not only on good days, but also on bad days
sionalism, viewed as character, establishes the condi- when we are tired and irritable and no-one is watch-
tions for trustworthiness. ing, requires more than simple rules; it requires that
we devote ourselves to becoming certain sorts of persons.
Students often focus only on the dyadic nature of If students engage in honest reflection, they will
the physicianpatient relationship and need to be agree that little in their previous lives has taught
reminded of social context. This key precept them to be the sorts of persons who routinely put the
reminds students that the benefits conferred by soci- interests of others first, even if to do so requires
ety on physicians, which include a comfortable level some significant sacrifice. If students see that profes-
of income that is sufficient to pay off student loans, sionalism, properly understood, requires them to
are conditional upon societys belief that it is receiv- grow into the sorts of persons who not only engage
ing the hoped-for benefits from the profession. If in that hard work, but who do so willingly and
society decides that caregivers have strayed from the cheerfully, they then understand what character and
path of virtue and are no longer trustworthy, the virtue have to do with their education.3638
privileges and authority now granted to health pro-
fessionals may be withdrawn. Furthermore, if society Virtue is sometimes misunderstood because of a
makes it difficult for professionals to provide care focus on the listing of specific virtues, such as altru-
according to the appropriate ethical standards as ism, compassion and honesty, as if these, too, could
happened most dramatically in Nazi Germany the be understood separately and memorised as a list of
professionals ought to demand that the contract be desirable behaviours. We recommend instead focus-
renegotiated and may refuse to assume their ing on the core idea of virtue as it relates to lifelong
assigned social roles. character formation.

Virtue as transcending behaviour


PROFESSIONALISM AS APPLICATION OF VIRTUE TO
PRACTICE The virtuous person behaves in certain ways that can
be observed and measured, but virtue transcends
Professionalism as a subset of health care ethics behaviour. This key precept may be less important
for trainees than for faculty staff and those involved
Professionalism is a subset of health care ethics and in assessment and accreditation, but students still
represents an application of virtue to the health need a sense of it if they are to understand the com-
professions. plex relationship between professionalism and com-
monly employed lists of professional behaviours.
Professionalism is a question of ethics, but much of
ethics today is addressed through rules and princi- In one sense, virtue is ultimately about behaviour.
ples.34 Rules and principles may be highly useful There would be little point in saying that altruism is
tools for ethical deliberation, but they have a major a virtue if the virtuous person never actually
weakness: they ignore the question of what sort of behaved altruistically, but merely entertained noble
person is deciding or performing the action. The ideas. One goal of learning and improving ones
approach to ethics that focuses on what sort of per- own virtues is to be confident that when faced with
son one is becoming, or moral character, is com- typical stresses and crises, one will default to the
monly called virtue.35 As Pellegrino stated, virtue- right way to behave and will not be led astray by
based ethics is a system that concentrates on the temptation or fear.
moral agent and the kind of person he or she
ought to be, rather than on the acts themselves, the By contrast, part of the reason why the develop-
circumstances, or the consequences they pro- ment of these virtues is indeed a lifelong commit-
duce.23 As so little of ethics education reflects a vir- ment derives from the fact that merely behaving

984 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987
Professionalism: a framework

in certain ways is never enough. Albeit that get- Being virtuous requires more than having incul-
ting trainees to behave in accord with a list of cated good values; it means having the practical wis-
professional attributes is a good way to start the dom to discern precisely how the virtuous
process of character development, it is not the professional should respond to any given concrete
intended moral destination. Making virtuous situation.41 As one aspect of good character, this
behaviour ones default requires that virtuous atti- practical wisdom is a skill that must be cultivated
tudes percolate deep into ones being. An ongo- over a lifetime.
ing challenge for evaluators is to use behavioural
measures of professionalism appropriately, with Students can understand these aspects of basic vir-
full awareness of their limitations, and not to tue ethics by reflecting on their own experiences.
employ them in ways that send the wrong message For example, Year 1 medical students struggle with
to students and residents. the basic skills of history taking and physical exami-
nation. They often ignore the patient while focusing
Cohen seems to advocate restricting the domain of on their memorised checklist of tasks. Yet they
professionalism solely to observable behaviour, rele- understand that, with further practice, they will be
gating deeper values and attitudes to the realm of able to perform a smooth, competent history and
humanism.24 However, Cohen immediately adds: physical examination, while also attending fully to
In the absence of humanistic grounding, profes- the patients words and feelings. Faculty staff can
sionalism lacks authenticity; it is a thin veneer. . .24 make an analogy between this experience and how
As Cohen clearly calls for both professionalism and the practitioners approach to the patient in a mor-
humanism as he defines them, we think it better to ally complex situation improves with practice.
require a professionalism curriculum that addresses
both observable behaviours and deeper attitudes, Even students who have had no experience with
and find in virtue the required integration among clinical mentors in school have probably encoun-
these concepts. Medical education must do more tered practitioners in their own and their familys
than teach to the test of expected behaviours, and lives, and have seen both positive and negative role
must also promote the cultivation of virtue as a life- models. Getting students to focus on their own
long quest in the face of numerous challenges.39 vision of the sort of practitioner they most wish to
resemble in their future career, and the sort of prac-
Virtue requires integrating a set of values, attitudes titioner they most wish to avoid becoming, allows
and behaviours them to reflect upon the importance of practical
mentoring in the development of the virtuous pro-
Virtue in professionalism requires integrating a set of fessional.
values, attitudes and behaviours into the core of ones
being, and applying practical wisdom to determine These key precepts about virtue help to immunise
how the virtuous professional would respond to a students to two common misuses of professional-
given clinical situation; this is the sort of wisdom one ism, which unfortunately feed cynicism rather than
ordinarily gains from observing trusted mentors. professional development.2 One misuse is that of
professionalism as a bludgeon, a term that refers
If professionalism is applied virtue ethics, and most to the use of professionalism as a threat or
students have not been introduced to virtue ethics, weapon with which to punish students who dont
a short course in virtue is required as a part of pro- follow the administrations rules. The other misuse
fessionalism education. This key precept represents involves reducing professionalism merely to a req-
the essentials that students must grasp. Being a vir- uisite competency that can be exhaustively evalu-
tuous professional requires doing the right thing ated solely according to a checklist of concrete
(whatever puts the patients interests first and fore- behaviours.1,7 Unfortunately, professionalism in
most) in the right way and with the right attitude, education must do double duty.42 A small number
and doing so consistently and reliably as an expres- of trainees will indeed behave in grossly unprofes-
sion of deeply formed character; it requires getting sional ways and must (according to the social con-
medical virtues like altruism right into the marrow tract) either be remediated or terminated for the
of ones moral bones. However, the virtuous physi- safety of the community. For this group, profes-
cian is more than altruistic; he or she also exempli- sionalism must serve as a minimal threshold of
fies those aspects of character that promote the acceptable behaviour. However, this message com-
patients best interests (such as compassion, perse- municates the wrong view of professionalism to
verance, integrity and practical wisdom).40 the much larger group that ideally will see

2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987 985
H Brody & D Doukas

professionalism as a positive, aspirational goal and REFERENCES


not as a minimal threshold. The double duty and
the aspirational ideal must both be explained to 1 Coulehan J. Viewpoint: todays professionalism:
students so that the messages sent by the school engaging the mind but not the heart. Acad Med 2005;
remain clear. 80:8928.
2 Brainard AH, Brislen HC. Viewpoint: learning
professionalism: a view from the trenches. Acad Med
CONCLUSIONS 2007;82:10104.
3 Goldie J, Dowie A, Cotton P, Morrison J. Teaching
The key precepts we propose for education in medi- professionalism in the early years of a medical
cal professionalism may be summarised as: (i) pro- curriculum: a qualitative study. Med Educ 2007;41:6107.
4 Baernstein A, Oelschlager AMEA, Chang TA, Wenrich
fession is a public, collective promise providing the
MD. Learning professionalism: perspectives of
basis for trust, based on an implied social contract preclinical medical students. Acad Med 2009;84:57481.
committed to the patients best interests, and (ii) 5 Karnieli-Miller O, Vu TR, Holtman MC, Clyman SG,
professionalism involves hard work that implicitly Inui TS. Medical students professionalism narratives:
requires knowledge and technical competence, but, a window on the informal and hidden curriculum.
more importantly, requires the application of virtue Acad Med 2010;85:12433.
ethics. 6 Monrouxe LV, Rees CE, Hu W. Differences in
medical students explicit discourses of
A professionalism curriculum that emphasises these professionalism: acting, representing, becoming. Med
precepts, we suggest, will resonate more effectively Educ 2011;45:585602.
with medical trainees and will help to prevent a 7 Wear D, Kuczewski MG. The professionalism
movement: can we pause? Am J Bioeth 2004;4 (2):110.
number of common misunderstandings that cur-
8 McGarry K, Landau C. Enhancing medical
rently hamper the effectiveness of professionalism professionalism through interactive seminars. Med
teaching. The precepts also ought to guide educa- Educ 2012;46:5234.
tional research to ensure that the right attributes 9 Liaison Committee on Medical Education. Standards
and outcomes are assessed, and that the assessment of accreditation of medical education programs
instruments do not inadvertently teach students the leading to the MD degree. 2012. http://www.lcme.org/
wrong message about professionalism by stressing functions.pdf. [Accessed 21 March 2013.]
superficial behaviours over deeper character devel- 10 Accreditation Council for Graduate Medical
opment. Education. Communication, interpersonal skills, and
professionalism evaluation form. http://www.acgme.
A great many important concerns about the ethics org/acgmeweb/Portals/0/430_RadOnc_360_IP2.pdf.
[Accessed 21 March 2013.]
and history of professionalism remain to be
11 Joint Commission. Leadership in healthcare
addressed. We wish by proposing our list of key pre- organisations: a guide to Joint Commission leadership
cepts to foreclose none of that ongoing scholarly standards. 2009. http://www.jointcommission.org/
exploration. We merely wish to indicate how a robust assets/1/18/WP_Leadership_Standards.pdf.
curriculum for medical students and residents, suffi- [Accessed 21 March 2013.]
cient to cover the basic concept of professionalism 12 Swick HM. Toward a normative definition of medical
and to warn of some common misuses of the concept, professionalism. Acad Med 2000;75:6126.
can be constructed out of material already available, 13 Arnold L, Stern DT. What is medical professionalism?
while the deeper inquiry continues. In: Stern DT, ed. Measuring Medical Professionalism.
New York, NY: Oxford University Press 2006;1537.
14 Hafferty FW, Castellani B. The increasing
Contributors: both authors made substantial contributions complexities of professionalism. Acad Med 2010;85:
to the conception, design and writing of this paper. Both 288301.
authors participated in the review and critical revision of 15 Chandratilake M, McAleer S, Gibson J. Cultural
the various drafts and approved the final manuscript for similarities and differences in medical
publication. professionalism: a multi-regional study. Med Educ 2012;
Acknowledgements: none. 46:25766.
Funding: none. 16 Inui TS. A Flag in the Wind: Educating for
Conflicts of interest: DD is president and chief executive Professionalism in Medicine. Washington, DC:
officer of the Academy for Professionalism in Health Care. Association of American Medical Colleges 2003.
HB is a past chairman of its board of directors. 17 Graham C, de Leeuw S, Markless S. Widening debates
Ethical approval: not applicable. about medical professionalism. Med Educ 2013;47:33941.

986 2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987
Professionalism: a framework

18 Cruess RL, Cruess SR. Teaching professionalism: 31 Larson EB, Yao X. Clinical empathy as emotional
general principles. Med Teach 2006;28:2058. labour in the patientphysician relationship. JAMA
19 McCourt C, Johnston JL, Cooper S, Gormley GJ. The 2005;293:11006.
level playing field: the impact of assessment practice 32 Freidson E. Professionalism Reborn: Theory, Prophecy and
on professional development. Med Educ 2012;46:766 Policy. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press 1994.
76. 33 Cruess RL, Cruess SR. Expectations and obligations:
20 Doukas DJ. The medicalsocial education compact professionalism and medicines social contract with
and the medical learner. In: Kenny N, Shelton W, society. Perspect Biol Med 2008;51:57998.
eds. Lost Virtue: Professional Character Development and 34 Beauchamp TL, Childress JC. Principles of Biomedical
Medical Education. Philadelphia, PA: Elsevier 2006; Ethics, 6th edn. New York, NY: Oxford University
185209. Press 2009.
21 Pellegrino ED, Thomasma DC. (eds). Self-effacement. 35 Doukas DJ. Where is the virtue in professionalism?
In: The Virtues in Medical Practice. New York, NY: Camb Q Healthc Ethics 2003;12:14754.
Oxford University Press 1993;14461. 36 Doukas DJ. Returning to professionalism: the re-
22 Medical Professionalism Project. Medical emergence of medicines art. Am J Bioeth 2004;4 (2):
professionalism in the new millennium: a physicians 189.
charter. Lancet 2002;359 (9305):5202. 37 Rhodes R, Cohen D, Friedman E, Muller D.
23 Pellegrino ED. Professionalism, profession and the Professionalism in medical education. Am J Bioeth
virtues of the good physician. Mt Sinai J Med 2002; 2004;4 (2):202.
69:37884. 38 Lee WT, Schulz K, Witsell D, Esclamado R.
24 Cohen JJ. Viewpoint: linking professionalism to Channelling Aristotle: virtue-based professionalism
humanism: why it matters. Acad Med 2007;82:102932. training during residency. Med Educ 2012;46:112930.
25 Rothman DJ. Medical professionalism focusing on 39 Antiel RM, Kinghorn WA, Reed DA, Hafferty FW.
the real issues. N Engl J Med 2000;342:12836. Professionalism: etiquette or habitus? Mayo Clin Proc
26 Sandel M. What Money Cant Buy: The Moral Limits of 2013;88:6512.
Markets. New York, NY: Farrar, Straus & Giroux 2012. 40 Pellegrino ED, Thomasma DC. (eds). In: The Virtues
27 Brody H. The Golden Calf: Economism and American in Medical Practice. New York, NY: Oxford University
Policy. Amazon/CreateSpace 2011. Press 1993.
28 Pellegrino ED. Toward a reconstruction of medical 41 Kinghorn WA. Medical education as moral formation:
morality: the primacy of the act of profession and the an Aristotelian account of medical professionalism.
fact of illness. J Med Philos 1979;4:3256. Perspect Biol Med 2010;53:87105.
29 Cohn F, Lie D. Mediating the gap between the white 42 Hafferty F. Measuring professionalism: a commentary.
coat ceremony and the ethics and professionalism In: Stern DT, ed. Measuring Medical Professionalism.
curriculum. Acad Med 2002;77:1168. New York, NY: Oxford University Press 2006;281306.
30 Doukas DJ, McCullough LB, Wear S, Lehmann LS,
Nixon LL, Carrese JA, Shapiro JF, Green MJ, Kirch Received 29 January 2014; editorial comments to author 4
DG. The challenge of promoting professionalism March 2014, accepted for publication 7 May 2014
through medical ethics and humanities education.
Acad Med 2013;88:16249.

2014 John Wiley & Sons Ltd. MEDICAL EDUCATION 2014; 48: 980987 987
Copyright of Medical Education is the property of Wiley-Blackwell and its content may not
be copied or emailed to multiple sites or posted to a listserv without the copyright holder's
express written permission. However, users may print, download, or email articles for
individual use.

You might also like