You are on page 1of 9

Article Number: LALI: 04157

History of Psycholinguistics 1

a0005 History of Psycholinguistics


G Altmann, University of York, York, UK Plato was possibly the earliest to write at length on p0015

! 2006 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved. language (where others may have spoken, but not
written). Certainly, his writings were the most influ-
ential with respect to the philosophy of language
p0005 Our faculty for language has intrigued scholars for and the question ‘what does a word mean?’ Plato, in
centuries. Yet most textbooks assume that psycho- his Republic, considered the meaning of words in
linguistics has its origins in the late 1950s and 1960s, his Allegory of the Cave (as well as in Cratylus). In this
and that nothing of note contributed to its evolution allegory, a group of prisoners have been chained all
before then. In some respects this is true, in that it their lives within a cave. All they see are the shadows
was only then that psycholinguistics began to prolif- of objects cast upon a wall by the flames of a fire.
erate as an identifiable discipline within the psychol- They experience only those shadows (in much the
ogy literature. This proliferation was marked by the same way that we can only experience the results of
founding in 1962 of the Journal of Verbal Learning our sensory percepts), and their language similarly
and Verbal Behavior (which subsequently, in 1985, describes only those shadows. Plato noted that when
became the Journal of Memory and Language). Why using a word, the prisoners would take it to refer to
the original journal was so titled, and why its title the shadows before them, when in fact (according to
presents us with a historical paradox, will become Plato), they would refer not to objects in the shadow

F
clearer as this review unfolds. The review’s purpose world, but (unbeknown to the prisoners) to objects in
is to consider how the present-day state of the art the real world. Thus, for Plato (and a host of more

O
evolved. In so doing, it will touch briefly on ancient contemporary philosophers, from Frege to Puttnam),
Greek philosophy, 19th century neuroscience, 20th the true meaning of a word—its reference—is exter-
century psycholinguistics, and beyond. It will consid- nal to the person who, by using the word, is attribut-

O
er approaches to the brain as practiced in both an- ing meaning to it. But why should it matter what a
cient Egypt and modern neuroscience. It will be word refers to?
necessarily selective, in order to make some sense of The psycholinguistic endeavor is to uncover the p0020
PR
the historical developments that contributed to psy- mental processes that are implicated in the acquisi-
cholinguistic science. tion, production, and comprehension of language.
Just as psychology is the study of the control of
s0005 From the Ancient Egyptians to the Greek behavior, so psycholinguistics is the study of the con-
Philosophers trol of linguistic behavior. A part of any psycholin-
guistic theory of mental process is an account of what
p0010 The earliest to write about language and the brain constitutes the input to the mental process—that is,
ST

were the ancient Egyptians—the first to write about what information is operated upon by those process-
anything at all. A catalog of the effects of head injury es. While Plato was of course correct that the form of
(and injuries lower down the body also) exists in what the real-world object dictates the form of the sensory
is now referred to as the Edwin Smith Surgical Papy- image presented to the allegorical prisoner, the mental
rus, written about 1700 b.c. The writer (believed to processes involved in that prisoner’s use of language
R

have collected together information spanning per- can operate only on mental derivatives of that sensory
haps another 1000 years before) referred there to image. There may be properties of the real-world
what is presumed to be the first recorded case of object (such as color, texture, and density) that are
FI

aphasia—language breakdown following brain trau- not represented in their shadow-forms, and thus men-
ma. However, the Egyptians did not accord much tal processes that might otherwise (outside the cave)
significance to the brain, which unlike the other develop sensitivity to those properties need never de-
organs of the body, was discarded during mummifi- velop such sensitivities if constrained to living a life
cation (it was scraped out through the nose). They inside the cave. But while the shadows would not
believed instead that the heart was the seat of the soul permit the distinction between, say, a tennis ball and
and the repository for memory, a view largely shared an orange, the contexts in which the shadows were
by the Greek philosopher Aristotle (384–322 b.c.)— experienced, or their names heard, would distinguish
a somewhat surprising position to take given that between the two—mental sensitivities would develop,
he was a student at Plato’s Academy and that Plato but they would not necessarily be grounded in the
(427–347 b.c.) believed the brain to be the seat of perceptual domain. These distinctions, between the
intelligence.
Article Number: LALI: 04157

2 History of Psycholinguistics

actual world and our experience of the world, and The 19th Century Emergence of the s0015

between an object or word and the context in which Cognitive Neuropsychology of Language
that object or word might occur, led other philoso-
phers, most notably Wittgenstein in his Philosophical The first systematic studies of the relationship between p0030

Investigations, to propose that the meaning of a word language and brain were conducted in the 19th cen-
is knowledge of its use in the language—that is, tury. This is probably the earliest point in the history
knowledge of the contexts in which it would be ap- of psycholinguistics from when a progression of stud-
propriate to utter that word, where such knowledge is ies can be traced, with one author building a case on
shaped by experience. We return to this theme when the basis of earlier studies coupled with newer data.
we consider in more detail the more recent history The protagonists at this time were Gall, Boulliard,
(and possible future) of psycholinguistics. Aubertin, Broca, Wernicke, and Lichtheim, to name a
few. None of them would be described as ‘psycholin-
guists,’ but to the extent that their work (like modern-
s0010 The Earliest Empirical Studies day cognitive neuroscientists) informed accounts of
p0025 The pre-history of psycholinguistics (up until the the relationship between brain and language, they are
19th century) was dominated by philosophical con- no less a part of the history of psycholinguistics than
jecture. The term dominated is used loosely here, as are the linguists, philosophers, psychologists, and cog-
there was no systematic and ongoing questioning of nitive scientists who have influenced the field through

F
the relationship between mind and language, or in- their own, sometimes radically different, perspectives.
deed, brain and language—there was no community Franz Gall is perhaps better known for his work on p0035

phrenology, but he believed that language function

O
of researchers asking the questions. But modern-day
psycholinguistics is dominated not by philosophy (al- was localized in the anterior parts of the brain. His
though it had its moments), but by experimental in- student Jean Boulliard collected clinical evidence in
support of Gall’s theory, and in turn, Boulliard’s stu-

O
vestigations that measure reaction times, monitor eye
movements, record babies’ babbles, and so on. Its pre- dent Ernest Aubertin did the same. It was at a meeting
history lacks such experimentation. This is not to say in April of 1861 that Aubertin made his beliefs plain:
If a case of speech loss could be found that was not
PR
that no experiments were performed. Certainly, there
were isolated cases, generally of a kind that would not accompanied by a frontal lesion, he would give up his
be tolerated in the modern age. Indeed, one of the (and his intellectual forbearers’) belief in the localiza-
most widely replicated studies (if one is to believe the tion of language. In the audience was Paul Broca,
historians) is a study that was carried out on at least after whom are named Broca’s aphasia and, within
three and possibly four independent occasions be- the left frontal lobe, Broca’s area. Broca was struck by
tween the 7th Century b.c. and the 16th Century a.d. Aubertin’s empirical challenge, but at the same time
ST

In each case, some number of babies were apparently realized that craniology (Gall’s lasting influence on
brought up in isolation (except for carers who were his students) could not provide the proof that was
either mute, or instructed not to speak), with the aim required to establish a link between language loss
of the experiment being to discover what language, if and cerebral localization—only anatomical inspec-
any, the children would grow up speaking. The results tion of the brain could do that. Coincidentally, within
R

varied. The Egyptian Pharaoh Psamtik (7th c.b.c.) a few days he was presented with a patient suffering
was credited by Herodotus with discovering that they from speech loss who died a few days after that.
spoke Phrygian. The Roman emperor and German Broca’s postmortem analysis of this patient’s brain
FI

king Frederick II (1194–1250 a.d.) carried out a sim- (and the damage to what is now referred to as Broca’s
ilar study, but all the infants died. King James IV area), coupled with earlier observations made by Marc
(1473–1513 a.d.) is supposed to have performed a Dax (on right hemiplegia and its correlation with
similar experiment on the island of InchKeith, al- speech loss), but published at the same time, established
though it is likely that this study never in fact took the anatomical validity of the localizationzz hypothe-
place (the fact that the children are reported to have sis. About 10 years later (in 1874), Carl Wernicke
emerged from their isolation speaking Hebrew is one published his work on ‘sensory aphasia’ (deficits in
reason to doubt the truth of the story). And finally, the comprehension of language). This work was con-
Akbar the Great (1542–1605), the grandfather of siderably enhanced by Wernicke’s student Ludwig
Shah Jahan who built the Taj Mahal, similarly failed Lichtheim who, in 1885, produced a schematic (cf.
to discover man’s ‘natural language’ (although there a ‘model’) of how three interlinked centers in the
is some suggestion that in this case, the infants ac- brain are implicated in aphasia: Broca’s (the ‘center
quired a form of signed language inherited, in part, of auditory images’), Wernicke’s (the ‘center of motor
from the infants’ carers). images’), and a diffusely located ‘concept center.’
Article Number: LALI: 04157

History of Psycholinguistics 3

Lesions to each of these areas, or to the connections structures to a laborious set of taxonomic procedures,
between them, produce different kinds of aphasias. starting with the smallest element of language—the
Most interesting of all, his schematic enabled him to phoneme. In doing so, Bloomfield firmly aligned
predict disorders that had not yet been described. This the linguistics of the day with behaviorism. And
ability of a conceptual ‘model’ to make as yet untested just as behaviorism eschewed mental states in its
predictions is a theme we shall return to. study of psychology, so the Bloomfieldian tradition
eschewed psychology in its study of language. The
s0020 The Early 20th Century Influence of study of language was firmly caught between the
proverbial rock and a hard place—between behavior-
Behaviorism
ism on the one hand and taxonomy on the other.
p0040 By the end of the 19th century, the study of language Mental states were, the argument went, irrelevant—
began to change, as did the study of psychology whether with respect to psychological or linguistic
more generally. Interest in the psychology (as op- inquiry.
posed to philosophy) of language shifted from being The behaviorist tradition culminated (with respect p0050

primarily (or even solely) concerned with its break- to language) with B. F. Skinner’s publication in 1957
down to being concerned also with its normal use. of Verbal Behavior. Here, Skinner sought to apply
Wilhelm Wundt in Die Sprache (published in 1900) behaviorist principles to verbal learning and verbal
stressed the importance of mental states and the behavior, attempting to explain them in terms of

F
relationship between utterances and those internal conditioning theory. Verbal behavior (and Verbal
states. William James similarly (at least early on) Behavior) proved to be the final battleground on

O
saw the advantages of introducing mental states into which the classical behavorists and the mentalists
theories of language use (see his 1890 Principles of would clash.
Psychology, in which several contemporary issues in

O
psycholinguistics are foreshadowed). But the early
The Mid-20th Century and the Chomskyan s0025
20th century was a turbulent time for psycholinguis-
Influence
tics (as it was for psychology): J. B. Watson argued
PR
that psychology should be concerned with behavior In 1959, Chomsky published a review of Skinner’s p0055

and behavioral observation, rather than with cons- Verbal Behavior. He argued that no amount of condi-
ciousness and introspection (the Wundtian approach). tioned stimulus-response associations could explain
And whereas Wundt had argued that a psychology the infinite productivity or systematicity of language.
of language was as much about the mind as it was With Chomsky, out went Bloomfield, and in came
about language, behaviorists such as J. R. Kantor mental structures, ripe for theoretical and empirical
argued against the idea that language use implicated investigation. Chomsky reintroduced the mind, and
ST

distinct mental states. For Kantor, the German men- specifically mental representation, into theories of
talist tradition started by Wundt was simply wrong. language (although his beliefs did not amount to a
Even William James turned away from Wundtian theory of psychological process, but to an account of
psychology. Thus, the behaviorist tradition took hold. linguistic structure). So whereas Skinner ostensibly
p0045 The late 19th and early 20th centuries were a time eschewed mental representations, Chomsky appar-
R

of great change in linguistics, too. The 19th century ently proved that language was founded on precisely
had seen the emergence of the Neogrammarians, a such representation. Some later commentators took
group that studied language change. They were inter- the view that the Chomskyan revolution threw out
FI

ested in how the sounds of different languages were the associationist baby with the behaviorist bathwa-
related, and how within a language, the sounds ter. Behaviorism was founded on associationism. Be-
changed over time. They were less interested in what haviorism was ‘out,’ and with it, associationism.
a language ‘looked like’ at a particular moment in Symbolic computation was ‘in,’ but with it, uncer-
time. This changed at the beginning of the 20th tainty over how the symbolic system was acquired.
century when Ferdinand de Saussure brought struc- It was not until the mid-1980s that a new kind of
ture into the study of language. He introduced the revolution took place, in which the associationist
idea that every element of language could be under- baby, now grown up, was brought back into the fold.
stood through its relation to the other elements (he The intervening 20 years were typical teenage years—
introduced syntactic distinctions that are still cen- full of energy, punctuated by occasional false hopes
tral to contemporary linguistics). In the 1930s, the that nonetheless proved essential to the maturation
Bloomfieldian school of linguistics was born, with the process.
publication in 1933 of Leonard Bloomfield’s Lan- Two years before his review of Verbal Beha- p0060

guage. Bloomfield reduced the study of language vior, Chomsky had published Syntactic Structures, a
Article Number: LALI: 04157

4 History of Psycholinguistics

monograph devoted to exploring the notion of ab- research effort in the early 1960s to validate the
stract grammatical rules as the basis for generating psychological status of syntactic processing (the con-
sentential structure. According to Blumenthal in his struction of representations encoding the dependen-
1970 account of the history of psycholinguistics, cies between the constituents of a sentence). Many
Chomsky’s departure from the Bloomfieldian school of these studies attempted to show that perceptual
was too radical for an American publisher to want to complexity, as measured using a variety of different
publish a lengthy volume that Chomsky had written tasks, was related to linguistic complexity (the so-
outlining the new approach, and only Mouton, a called Derivational Theory of Complexity). However,
European publisher (and presumably more sympa- whereas the syntactic structures postulated by trans-
thetic to the tradition that Chomsky was advocating) formational grammar did have some psychological
would publish a shorter monograph based on an reality, the devices postulated for building those struc-
undergraduate lecture series he taught at MIT. In tures (e.g., the transformations that formed a part of
fact, this is not quite accurate (N. Chomsky, personal the grammatical formalism) did not. It soon became
communication); Chomsky had indeed written a lon- apparent that the distinction between competence
ger volume (subsequently published in 1975), and it and performance was far more important than origi-
is true that initial reactions to the manuscript were nally realized—the linguists’ rules, which formed a
negative (but, according to Chomsky, not unreason- theory of competence, did not make a theory of psy-
able), but Syntactic Structures was not a compromise chological process.

F
brought about through Chomsky’s search for a pub- Subsequently, the emphasis shifted toward exami- p0075

lisher; he had not, in fact, intended to publish it. nation of the psychological, not linguistic, mechan-

O
Instead, Cornelis van Schooneveld, a Dutch linguist isms by which syntactic dependencies are determined
and acquaintance of Chomsky’s who was visiting (a process referred to as parsing). In a seminal paper
MIT and happened to edit a series for Mouton, sug- published in 1970, Thomas Bever pointed out that in

O
gested that Chomsky write up his class notes and cases of ambiguity, when more than one structure
publish them. This he did, and modern linguistics (i.e., dependency relation) might be permissible, there
was born. Psycholinguistics became caught up, al- appear to be consistent preferences for one interpre-
PR
most immediately, in its wake. tation rather than another. This consistency appeared
p0065 Chomsky’s influence on psycholinguistics cannot to hold not only across different examples of the same
be overstated. He drew an important distinction kind of ambiguity, but across different people, too.
between ‘competence,’ or the knowledge we have Thus, despite the grammaticality of ‘the horse raced
about a language, and ‘performance,’ the use of that past the barn fell’ (cf. ‘the car driven past the garage
language (a distinction that was reminiscent of Saus- crashed’), the preference to interpret ‘raced’ as a main
sure’s earlier distinction between langue and parole). verb (instead of as a past participle equivalent to
ST

Both, he claimed, arise through the workings of the ‘driven’) is so overwhelming that the sentence is
human mind—a mind, which furthermore is innately perceived as ungrammatical (and the preference is
enabled to learn the structures of human language then said to induce a ‘garden path’ effect). Evidently,
(although not everyone agreed with the arguments grammaticality and processability are distinct mental
for a language acquisition device akin to a mental phenomena.
R

organ—a concise summary of the counterarguments


was written by Bates and Goodman (1999)). It is
On the Influence of the Digital Computer s0035
perhaps surprising that against the backdrop of
FI

Syntactic Structures and Chomsky’s Review of The 1970s saw enormous growth in psycholinguis- p0080

Skinner’s Verbal Behaviur, a new and influential tics. Advances were made across a wide range of
journal dedicated to research into the psychology of phenomena, including the identification of both
language should nonetheless, in 1962, give itself a printed and spoken words, the reading process, sen-
title (the Journal of Verbal Learning and Verbal tence comprehension (with much of the emphasis on
Behavior) that firmly placed it in the behaviorist the resolution of ambiguities of the ‘garden path’
tradition. kind), and the mental representation of texts. Wheth-
er there was a ‘spurt’ in the number of publications
is contentious, because although there undeniably was
s0030 From Linguistic Competence to
such a spurt, the whole of psychology experienced
Psychological Performance
the same rapid growth. It would be wrong, however,
p0070 Chomsky’s theories of grammar were theories of to attribute all this advancement to the influence of
competence, not performance. And yet, his work on Chomsky. The demise of behaviorism played a part
transformational grammar initiated a considerable (and certainly Chomsky played a part in that demise),
Article Number: LALI: 04157

History of Psycholinguistics 5

but so did the advent in the 1950s of the digital emerged in the mid -980s, apparently eschewing
computer. The ‘mind-as-computer’ metaphor had a symbolic computation and modularity.
subtle but pervasive influence on both psycholinguis-
tics and the study of cognition generally. Computer The Late 20th Century Emergence of s0040
programs worked by breaking down complex beha- Connectionism: Statistical Approaches to
viors into sequences of simpler, more manageable
Language
(and hence more understandable) behaviors. They
relied on symbol manipulation and the control of In 1986, David Rumelhart and Jay McClelland pub- p0090

information flow. They distinguished between differ- lished Parallel Distributed Processing. This edited
ent levels of explanatory abstraction (the high-level volume described a range of connectionist, or neural
programming language, the assembly code, and the network, models of learning and cognition, and
flow of electrical currents around the hardware). And marked a ‘coming of age’ for connectionism. It was,
perhaps most important of all to the empirical psy- for many researchers in psycholinguistics, their first
chologist, they enabled novel predictions to be made introduction to a wide range of research in this emer-
that might not otherwise have been foreseen had the ging field. Of particular interest were the facts that
‘model’ not been implemented in full; complex inter- ‘knowledge’ in connectionist networks is encoded as
actions among the components of a program were not patterns of connectivity distributed across the neural-
easy to foresee. like units, and ‘processing’ is manifest as spreading

F
p0085 The influences of the digital computing revolution patterns of activation. These networks can learn
were felt in different ways. Some were direct, with complex associative relations largely on the basis of

O
researchers building computer simulations of mental simple associative learning principles (based primari-
behavior (in the growing field of Artificial Intelligence, ly on work published in 1949 by Donald Hebb, a
several language ‘understanding’ programs were writ- student of Lashley’s). Various algorithms exist to set

O
ten, some of which are still relevant 35 years later— the ‘strengths’ of the connections between the units
e.g., Terry Winograd’s SHRDLU program written in automatically, so that a given input pattern of activa-
1968–1970). Other influences were indirect, coming tion across some set of units will spread through the
PR
to psycholinguistics via philosophy. One such exam- network and yield a desired output pattern across
ple was Jerry Fodor’s Modularity of Mind hypothe- some other set of units. Indeed, multiple input-output
sis (from 1983). One simplified interpretation of this pairings can be learned by the same network. Impor-
hypothesis (it was interpreted in different ways by tantly, and in contrast to the ideals of the behaviorist
different researchers) was that there are two alterna- traditions, neural networks can develop internal
tive ways of theorizing about the mind: One is to representations.
assume it is incredibly complex and that multiple Several connectionist models had profound effects p0095
ST

sources of information interact in multiple ways, and on developments in psycholinguistics. TRACE, for
the other is to assume that it can be broken down into example, developed by McClelland and Jeff Elman
a number of modules, each of which performs some in the 1980s, was a model of spoken word recogni-
particular function and is ‘blind’ to the workings of tion that formed the focus of empirical research for
the other modules (perhaps taking as input the output a good 20 years after its inception. But TRACE did
R

of one or more of those other modules). Fodor argued not learn anything—it was hardwired. An extremely
that certain aspects of cognition were modular (the influential model that did learn by itself was de-
input systems), and certain others were not (central scribed by Elman (1990), who showed how a partic-
FI

processes). This hypothesis had considerable influence ular kind of network could learn the dependencies
in psycholinguistics, and for a time (the mid-1980s that constrain the sequential ordering of elements
to early 1990s), hypotheses were evaluated accord- (e.g., phonemes or words) through time. In effect, it
ing to whether they were modular or not. There seemed learned which kinds of word could follow which
little agreement, however, on where one drew the other kinds of word (hence, it was a statistical model,
boundaries (for example, was spoken language recog- because it encoded the statistics of the language it
nition a part of an input system? If it was, how could was trained upon). Interestingly, it developed internal
‘higher-level’ knowledge of the context in which representations that appeared to resemble gram-
the language was being interpreted influence the mod- matical knowledge; words that occurred in similar
ular and encapsulated recognition process? —Some sentential contexts came to evoke similar internal
argued it could not, while others argued it could). representations (that is, internal patterns of activity
It was about this time, in seeming opposition to when the word was presented to the network) —and
the trend toward symbolic computation, that a new because words of the same grammatical category tend
computationally motivated approach to cognition to occur in the same sentential contexts, different
Article Number: LALI: 04157

6 History of Psycholinguistics

‘clusters’ of words emerged, with each cluster repre- innate constraints on learning and neural structure
senting a different category of word. might be an important component of human lan-
p0100 Not surprisingly, the entire connectionist enterprise guage acquisition (Elman, 1996).
came under intense critical scrutiny from the linguis- Neural networks can be criticized for being (among p0110

tics and philosophy communities, not least because it other things) too unconstrained—they can, in princi-
appeared to reduce language to a system of statistical ple, do more than might be humanly possible—but
patterns, was fundamentally associationist, nonmod- the opposite criticism, that they are too small and do
ular, and eschewed the explicit manipulation of sym- not necessarily ‘scale up’ is another criticism that is
bolic structures (because the internal representations often heard. Neural networks as currently implemen-
that emerged as a result of the learning process were ted are just the ‘medium’ on which are offered up the
not symbolic in the traditional sense). Within the statistics. To misuse a common adage, the proof will
context of the symbolic-connectionist debate there be in the pudding, not in the plate that serves it up.
developed what became perhaps one of the longest There is little doubt, from the historical perspective,
surviving disputes in contemporary psycholinguistics; that although the emergence of connectionism has
between those that believe that word formation (e.g., offered a powerful theoretical tool, its emergence
the formation of ‘walked’ from ‘walk,’ ‘ran’ from has also polarized sections of the psycholinguistic
‘run,’ and ‘went’ from ‘go’) is driven by knowledge community, between ‘connectionists’ on the one hand,
of rules and exceptions to those rules, and those who and ‘symbolists’ on the other. This polarization is not

F
believe it is driven by statistical regularity (which can unique to psycholinguistics, however, but pervades
apparently capture, in the right model, both the regu- the study of cognition more broadly. And as if to

O
larly and irregularly formed words). The debate further muddy the theoretical waters, the beginning
shows little sign of abating, even 20 years later. of the 21st century has seen renewed interest in yet
p0105 Critics notwithstanding, statistical approaches to another (no less controversial) paradigm—one that

O
language (both with respect to its structure and its grounds language (and cognition) in action.
mental processing) are becoming more prevalent,
with application to issues as diverse as the ‘discovery’ The Early 21st Century and the Grounding s0045
PR
of words through the segmentation of the speech
of Language in Action and the Brain
input, the emergence of grammatical categories, and
even the emergence of meaning as a consequence of Traditional theories in cognition suppose that the job p0115

statistical dependencies between a word and its con- of the perceptual system is to deliver to the cognitive
text (cf. Wittgenstein’s views on the meaning of system a representation of the external world. The job
words). Empirically also, the statistical approach of the cognitive system is then to reconstruct, mental-
has led to investigation of issues ranging from infants’ ly, that external world. This reconstruction subse-
ST

abilities to segment speech and to induce grammar- quently forms the basis for ‘commands’ sent to, for
like rules to adult sentence processing. The reason example, the motor system. Cognition thus med-
that such approaches have proved so appealing is iates between perception and action. An alternative
that statistics are agnostic as to the nature of the approach, termed ‘embodied cognition,’ is that cog-
real-world objects over which the statistics are nition and action are encoded within the same repre-
R

calculated—thus, the fundamentally same algorithm sentational medium. Cognition is thus rooted in the
can be applied to sequences of phonemes, words, or same motoric and sensory representations that sup-
sentences. Their implementation within a neural net- port interaction with the external world. Or, put an-
FI

work is similarly agnostic—the same network and other way, cognition is grounded in the same neural
the same algorithms that enable that network to substrates that support sensory-motoric interaction
induce the appropriate statistics can be applied to with the external world. One consequence of this
many different domains. Connectionism opened up view is that language, a component of cognition,
experience-based learning to a range of psychological should, like the other components of cognition, be
domains, not just the linguistic domains. And experi- studied in the context of (i) the interactions it causes
ence-based learning was attractive not least because it between the hearer and the world, and (ii) the neural
required fewer assumptions about the existence of substrates that support those interactions. Coinciden-
innately specified domain-specific faculties (and in a tally, the 1990s saw a boom in research into the neural
multi-authored volume published in 1996, Jeff Elman substrate of language, in part due to the increased
teamed up with a variety of developmental psycholo- availability of neuroimaging technologies (predomi-
gists to argue that connectionism was attractive pre- nantly PET and fMRI, with EEG and more recently
cisely because it enabled a new perspective on how MEG also proving influential). It also saw increased
Article Number: LALI: 04157

History of Psycholinguistics 7

research into the relationship between language and away from a response button. A range of studies,
action. Taken together, these two streams of research some involving TMS (Transcranial Magnetic Stimu-
provided increasing evidence for embodied cognition. lation—a method for either temporarily stimulating
p0120 With respect to imaging, a variety of studies or suppressing a part of the brain, such as parts of
demonstrated what Lichtheim had alluded to a cen- motor cortex) have confirmed this motoric compo-
tury earlier—that concepts are not represented in nent to language comprehension.
some discrete location within the brain, but are It is noteworthy, with respect to the embodiment p0130

distributed across different regions. For example, approach to cognition, that some of its basic tenets
words whose meanings implicate tool use (e.g., ‘ham- have been around since the earliest days of (contem-
mer’) activate regions of the brain responsible for porary) psycholinguistics. Winograd’s SHRDLU pro-
controlling motoric action (during the use of the gram, for example, viewed the meaning of a word
tool) and other regions involved in the recognition such as ‘place’ or ‘lift’ as that part of the program that
of object form (during perception of the tool). Color caused placing or lifting—language comprehension
words (e.g., ‘yellow’) and words referring to non- within that program was grounded in sensory-motoric
manipulable artefacts (e.g., ‘house’) do not activate representation—and as such, SHRDLU followed in
motoric areas to the same extent, but they do activate the Wittgenstinian tradition of treating meaning as
regions close to those implicated in form perception use. Similarly, it is noteworthy that although most of
and, for color words, color perception. Importantly, the neuroimaging of language has been carried out

F
there is no single region that is primarily active; rath- independently of theories of embodied cognition,
er, words and concepts activate complex patterns much of the work converges on the same theme—

O
of activity that are distributed and overlapping that aspects of language are represented in the same
within different parts of the brain that are known representational substrates that control our sensory-
to have (other) motoric and sensory functions. The motoric interactions with the external world.

O
meanings of (at least some) words do appear, then, to
be grounded in those neural substrates that support
Epilogue s0050
sensory-motoric interaction.
PR
p0125 About the same time that increased attention was And that, broadly speaking, is where the field is p0135

focusing on neuroimaging, new techniques for study- now. In the space available, it is impossible to docu-
ing language and its effects on action were also being ment all the trends that have influenced contempo-
developed. One of these involved the monitoring rary psycholinguistics, and which have influenced
of eye movements as participants listened to com- not just what kinds of language behavior we study
mands to manipulate objects in front of them, or as (e.g., language breakdown, normal language use,
they listened to descriptions of events that might ambiguity resolution, and so on), but also how we
ST

unfold within the scene before them (one can view study those behaviors (through aphasia, neuroimag-
language-mediated eye movements as central to the ing, language-mediated eye movements, and so on).
relationship between language and action, because And we have still to see the full influences of connec-
eye movements signal overt shifts in attention, and tionism, statistical learning, embodied cognition, and
because attention to something necessarily precedes the neuroscience of language. What we can be sure of
R

(deliberate) action upon it). It was found that eye is that the boundaries between the study of language
movements were closely synchronized with processes and the study of other aspects of cognition are wear-
implicated in both spoken word recognition and sen- ing thinner (the eye movement research mentioned
FI

tence processing, and that much could be gleaned above is at the interface of language and vision, for
about what kinds of information were recruited at example). No doubt there are already developments
what point during a word or sentence in order to in ‘neighboring’ fields of study (e.g., the computation-
interpret the unfolding language with respect to the al sciences and non-cognitive neurosciences) that
scene in front of the participant (it is not without will also have an impact, but have yet to emerge as
some irony that in L. N. Fowler’s famous Phrenology quantifiable influences on psycholinguistics. For ex-
bust, from about 1865, the faculty for language is ample, researchers are already using computational
located just below the left eye). Another technique techniques coupled with detailed neuroanatomical
involved measuring motoric responses to different research on the neural structure of the brain to at-
kinds of linguistic stimuli—for example, words or tempt to understand the kinds of ‘computation’ that
sentences referring to movements toward or away distinct parts of the brain may be capable of. Such
from the body were found to interfere with responses research promises greater understanding of the brain’s
in a judgment task (e.g., ‘does this sentence make ability to learn, represent, and deploy language. And
sense?’) that involved moving a finger toward or although the history of psycholinguistics is relevant to
Article Number: LALI: 04157

8 History of Psycholinguistics

understanding where the field is today, perhaps of emergence of language. Mahwah, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum
greater interest is where the field will be tomorrow. Associates. 29–80.
Blumenthal A L (1970). Language and psychology: Histor-
ical aspects of psycholinguistics. New York: John Wiley
Acknowledgments & Sons.
Bever T G (1970). ‘The cognitive basis for linguistic struc-
This article is a substantially expanded version of a
tures.’ In Hayes J R (ed.) Cognition and the development
short, 1500-word section on the history of psycholin- of language. New York: John Wiley and Sons.
guistics that appeared as part of a broader review of Chomsky N (1957). Syntactic structures. Mouton.
issues in psycholinguistics (Altmann, 2001). The Chomsky N (1959). ‘Review of Skinner’s Verbal Beha-
reader is referred to this paper for in-depth review viour.’ Language 35, 26–58.
of (some of) the topics that constitute the field of Elman J L (1990). ‘Finding structure in time.’ Cognitive
psycholinguistics. The author would like to thank Science 14, 179–211.
the publishers of this article for donating his fee Elman J L, Bates E A, Johnson M H, Karmiloff-Smith A,
to the charity Medecins sans Frontieres, and Silvia Parisi D & Plunkett K (1996). Rethinking innateness:
Gennari for advice on topics ranging from Plato to A connectionist perspective on development. Cambridge,
neuroimaging. Mass: MIT Press/Bradford Books.
Fodor J A (1983). Modularity of mind. Cambridge, Mass:
MIT Press.

F
See also: Cognitive science (an overview) (00856); Con- Marcus G F (2003). The algebraic mind. Cambridge, Mass:
nectionist models of human language processing (00858); MIT Press/Bradford Books.
Early discussions of speech disorders (02403); fMRI Martin A & Chao L L. ‘Semantic memory and the brain:

O
(02399); Language, visual cognition and motor action structure and processes.’ Current Opinion in Neurobiol-
(00865); Modularity of mind and language (00859); Psy- ogy 11, 194–201.
cholinguistics: Overview (00788); Sentence Processing McClelland J L & Elman J L (1986). ‘The TRACE model of

O
(00789); Symbolic models of human language processing speech perception.’ Cognitive Psychology 18, 1–86.
(00857); Transcranial magnetic stimulation (02402). Price C J (1999). ‘The functional anatomy of word compre-
hension and production.’ Trends in Cognitive Sciences
2(8), 281–288.
PR
Bibliography Rumelhart D E & McClelland J L (eds.) (1986). Parallel
distributed processing: Explorations in the microstruc-
Altmann G T M (1997). The ascent of Babel: An explora- ture of cognition. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
tion of language, mind, and understanding. Oxford: Saffran E M (2000). ‘Aphasia and the relationship of lan-
Oxford University Press. guage and brain.’ Seminars in Neurology 20(4), 409–418.
Altmann G T M (2001). ‘The language machine: Psycholin- Skinner B F (1957). Verbal behavior. New York: Appleton-
guistics in review.’ British Journal of Psychology 92, Century-Crofts.
ST

129–170. Winograd T (1972). ‘Understanding natural language.’


Bates E & Goodman J C (1999). ‘On the emergence of Cognitive Psychology 3(1), 1–191.
grammar from the lexicon.’ In MacWhinney B (ed.) The
R
FI
Article Number: LALI: 04157

Non-Print Items

Abstract:
Psycholinguistics is the empirical and theoretical study of the mental processes that enable linguistic behavior. This
article reviews the history of psycholinguistics, from the time of the ancient Egyptians. Its aim is to highlight past,
present, and emerging trends that either have defined, or will define, the field. It is not a systematic review of issues or
topics within the field but a historical overview of how the field developed and how its development looks set to
proceed.

Biography:
Gerry Altmann received his Ph.D. from the University of Edinburgh in 1986. After a postdoctoral position in the
Department of Linguistics, he moved to a lectureship at the University of Sussex. He moved to the University of York
in 1995 where he is a Professor of Psychology. His introductory text on psycholinguistics (Altmann, 1997) won the
British Psychological Society’s Book Award in 2000. Aside from many published articles on the psycholinguistics of
sentence processing, he has edited a number of books on spoken language understanding, as well as a six-volume
collection of key articles in psycholinguistics (published by Routledge). His early research was on issues in syntactic
parsing (the relationship between syntactic ambiguity resolution and prior context). More recently, he has focused on
the study of language-mediated eye movements. He has two children, whose movements are rarely mediated by his
language. His portrait occasionally hangs in the National Portrait Gallery, London.

Keywords: aphasia, behaviorism, brain, Broca, Chomsky, cognition, connectionism, eye movements, learning,
neuroimaging, Plato, psycholinguistics, Wernicke

Author Contact Information:


Gerry Altmann
Department of Psychology
University of York
York, YO10 5DD, UK
g.altmann@psych.york.ac.uk

You might also like