You are on page 1of 9

Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31

Contents lists available at ScienceDirect

Studies in History and Philosophy


of Modern Physics
journal homepage: www.elsevier.com/locate/shpsb

Principle theories, constructive theories, and explanation in modern physics


Wesley Van Camp
Department of Philosophy, The George Washington University, Washington, DC 20052, USA

a r t i c l e i n f o abstract

Article history: Clifton, Bub, and Halvorson’s paper, ‘‘Characterizing Quantum Theory in terms of Information-Theoretic
Received 12 September 2009 Constraints’’ (2003) invokes the theoretical significance of principle theories in contrast with constructive
Received in revised form theories. However, a more thorough discussion of the merits of principle theories and constructive
22 November 2010
theories is required to justify this approach towards quantum mechanics. Looking at Einstein’s original
Accepted 12 December 2010
Available online 22 January 2011
use of the distinction to characterize special relativity, this paper argues that it is best understood in
terms of explanatory preferences. The distinction depends fundamentally on the kinds of scientific
Keywords: explanation the respective types of theories provide. This conceptual clarification can shed light on
Explanation principle theory approaches to quantum mechanics by delineating both the specific strengths of
Constructive/Principle theories
principle theories and pinpointing the explanatory motivation guiding this strategy. The aim of this
Quantum mechanics
paper is to establish the broad philosophical justification for a principle theory approach to interpreting
quantum mechanics.
& 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.

When citing this paper, please use the full journal title Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics

1. Introduction an interpretational advantage over existing interpretations of


quantum mechanics. One argument for this seems to rely on
Clifton, Bub, and Halvorson’s paper, ‘‘Characterizing Quantum the interpretational success of the special and general theories of
Theory in terms of Information-Theoretic Constraints’’ (CBH, relativity as seen through the lens of Einstein’s own statements
2003) shows that the fundamental elements of a quantum theory regarding these theories as principle theories. Specifically, regard-
can be deduced from three information-theoretic principles. This ing quantum mechanics and the CBH approach, Bub (2005, 2004)
theoretical result motivates the claim that quantum mechanics argues that the information-theoretic approach is the only viable
can be viewed as a principle theory. The primary inspiration for option for the foundations of quantum theory.
thinking that quantum mechanics should be viewed as a principle There is no doubt that the CBH result is very theoretically
theory comes from a direct analogy with Einstein’s insight into his interesting and novel. CBH take it to show that quantum mechanics
own theories of relativity, combined with their apparent lack of can be represented as a principle theory, one that postulates ‘‘that
need for interpretation as perceived by the physics and philoso- we live in a world in which there are certain constraints on the
phical communities. In a later iteration of this program, Bub acquisition, representation, and communication of information’’
(2005) argues that from a foundational perspective, ‘‘this amounts (CBH, 2003, p. 1562). However, that quantum mechanics can be
to treating quantum mechanics as a theory about the representa- represented as a principle theory does not imply that this repre-
tion and manipulation of information constrained by the possibi- sentation provides a more satisfying interpretational basis for
lities and impossibilities of information transfer in our worldy quantum mechanics. The aim and scope of this paper is a relatively
rather than a theory about the ways in which nonclassical waves modest one. For CBH, there is a great deal riding on the foundational
and particles move’’ (Bub, 2005, p. 557). significance of principle theories versus constructive theories. What I
The CBH result, with Halvorson’s (2004) addendum, shows hope to show is that the existing discussion regarding the relative
that quantum mechanics can be successfully represented as a set merits of principle theories and constructive theories misses, or fails to
of constraints, or principles, on the transfer, manipulation, and emphasize, the central characteristic of this distinction. This is that
representation of information. It is at least implicitly argued that a the distinction depends fundamentally on the kinds of scientific
physical theory which is based on a small set of principles offers explanation the respective types of theories provide. Constructive
theories are grounded in their ability to offer causal-mechanical
explanations of phenomena, a type of scientific explanation most
E-mail address: wvancamp@gmu.edu prominently advocated by Salmon (1984).

1355-2198/$ - see front matter & 2011 Elsevier Ltd. All rights reserved.
doi:10.1016/j.shpsb.2010.12.002
24 W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31

Principle theories are also explanatory. The primary function  the impossibility of perfectly broadcasting the information
of a principle theory is tied to the explanatory role it plays contained in an unknown physical state; and
through unification. The theory of explanation as unification  the impossibility of unconditionally secure bit commitment
was first advanced by Friedman (1974) and has been developed (CBH, 2003, p. 1562).
since by Kitcher (1989). While principle theories may often offer
this kind of explanation, principle theories can also do explana- Roughly, these mean that there can be no superluminal signaling,
tory work by establishing the very explanatory framework for that it is impossible to identically clone or copy an arbitrary system,
empirical theories by way of conceptual clarification. This is and that it is impossible to be guaranteed of a secure commitment
distinct from the kind of unification of phenomena described by to a particular value by another party where that value is hidden
Friedman and Kitcher. As will be discussed, the two are connected from you. If these three principles are imposed on the world, it will
and this constitutive role played by principle theories provides an be a world with quantum characteristics.
equally important kind of explanatory function. A brief summation of the CBH argument is that, first, a classical
This clarification of the distinction can shed light on the discus- theory is equivalent to a commutative C*-algebra. A quantum
sion of approaches like that of CBH by delineating both the specific theory must be non-commutative. Furthermore, non-commutivity
strengths of principle theories and pinpointing the explanatory mathematically entails non-local entanglement, but only the
motivation that should be guiding this strategy, while exposing mathematic possibility, not that it must exist. Non-commutivity
the source of the perennial weaknesses of standard interpretations entails the impossibility of broadcasting information, since the
of quantum mechanics. The aim of this paper is to establish the possibility of broadcasting is shown to imply a commutative
broad philosophical justification for a principle theory approach to framework, as is the reverse, that commutivity entails the possi-
interpreting quantum mechanics. If a principle theory approach is to bility of broadcasting. The impossibility of superluminal informa-
succeed interpretationally, it must successfully play the explanatory tion transfer is shown to be equivalent to kinematic independence.
role expected of a principle theory. It must establish the possibility Finally, no bit commitment is shown to guarantee the existence of
of unification which gives a principle theory explanatory merit, or non-local entanglement. CBH are only able to motivate the entail-
establish the conceptual framework necessary for clear empirical ment of no bit commitment from non-local entanglement, but this
understanding. To be clear, the goal of this paper is not to evaluate entailment is proved in Halverson (2004). Thus, CBH have shown
the specific merits of any particular version of this approach, that their three information-theoretic principles are equivalent to
including CBH, but merely to clarify the justification behind the their characterization of quantum mechanics. For our purposes, the
strategy and define the terms of its success or failure.1 technical features of this derivation detailed in CBH are only of
passing interest. What is relevant is the question about what
would it mean, philosophically, if quantum mechanics can be
2. Informational constraints as principles of quantum shown to be formally equivalent to a small number of informa-
mechanics tion-theoretic principles or constraints on information transfer in
our world. CBH argue that this means that quantum mechanics
CBH developed a theory of quantum mechanics from simple ought to be characterized as an information-theoretic principle
information-theoretic principles. CBH begin with the very general theory, a significant departure from other understandings of the
framework of the abstract C*-algebra, a mathematical framework theory.
broad enough to include all of the various physical theories that
are available to modern physics, including both classical and
quantum classes of theories. The work is done by placing restric- 3. Principle and constructive theories
tions on this abstract structure, which divide it into those theories
that are classical in nature and those that are quantum mechan- Central to the CBH argument is the distinction between
ical. First, the authors define the physical characteristics that are principle theories and constructive theories—a distinction raised
characteristic of a general quantum theory as opposed to a by Einstein (1954) regarding his own theories of special relativity
classical one. These are: and general relativity. The CBH program explicitly compares itself
with that of Einstein, who formulates his special theory of
 that the algebras of observables pertaining to distinct physical relativity from the two principles that (1) physics in any inertial
systems must commute, usually called microcausality or kine- frame is the same and that (2) the speed of light is constant for all
matic independence; observers. Regarding this theory, Einstein invokes a distinction
 that any individual system’s algebra of observables must be between two conceptually distinct types of theories – principle
nonabelian, i.e., non-commutative; theories and constructive theories – in ‘‘What is the Theory of
 that the physical world must be nonlocal, in that space-like Relativity’’, saying,
separated systems must at least sometimes occupy entangled
We can distinguish various kinds of theories in physics. Most
states (CBH, 2003, p. 1563).
of them are constructive. They attempt to build up a picture of
the more complex phenomena out of the materials of a
CBH claim that there are three information-theoretic princi-
relativity simple formal scheme from which they start outy
ples that are entailed by these characteristics and which likewise
Along with this most important class of theories there exists a
entail them. These equivalent information-theoretic principles
second, which I will call ‘principle-theories.’ These employ the
are:
analytic, not synthetic, method. The elements which form their
basis and starting-point are not hypothetically constructed but
 the impossibility of superluminal information transfer between empirically discovered ones, general characteristics of natural
two physical systems by performing measurements on one
processes, principles that give rise to mathematically formu-
of them;
lated criteria which the separate processes or the theoretical
representations of them have to satisfyy
The advantages of the constructive theory are completeness,
1
For an analysis of the CBH approach specifically see Van Camp (2009). adaptability, and clearness; those of the principle theory are
W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31 25

logical perfection and security of the foundations (Einstein, of these arguments is the more explicit, and it is basically that
1954, p. 228). other formally quantum interpretations (as defined by the CBH
principles) are in principle empirically underdetermined (i.e. can-
For Einstein, paradigmatic examples of these contrasting types not provide empirical evidence for their account of measurement
of physical theories are represented in the kinetic theory of gases, devices beyond that of orthodox quantum mechanics). Therefore, a
which is a solidly constructive theory, and thermodynamics, measurement device must be viewed as a black box – that is, as an
which is a principle theory. The kinetic theory of gases is a theory information source. The only rational recourse we have is the CBH
that begins with, or makes primary, the physical, molecular position, a claim about what information-theoretic constraints
constituents and their interactions. It is from these constituents hold in our world.
and the physical properties of these bodies, that the more general The second argument, the positive one and the focus of this
theory is built up or constituted. In contrast to this, thermody- paper, is less explicit, as it seems to rely on an appeal to the
namics does not depend on there being any such constituents; authority and the success of Einstein’s methodology. Einstein’s
rather, thermodynamics begins with a small set of principles. distinction, at least for those theories he discusses (thermodynamics,
From these broad constraining principles, which are supposed to the kinetic theory of gases, relativity theory), is quite a plausible
apply in all physical situations, one can deduce all aspects of distinction to make. That each type of theory exemplifies its
thermodynamic phenomena. Einstein’s aim in ‘‘What is the respective strengths is likewise convincing. Moreover, by arguing
Theory of Relativity’’ to explain the special theory of relativity that special and general relativity are principle theories, Einstein
and general relativity as principle theories. For special relativity, bolsters the idea that principle theories are particularly well suited
the light postulate and the principle of relativity are principles to give foundational security to a physical theory. The theories of
which allow the deduction of the consequences of relativity special and general relativity are both powerful fundamental phy-
theory. This is a fundamentally different type of theorizing from sical theories. Within the professions of physics or philosophy, there
Lorentzian mechanics, special relativity’s predecessor and chal- is not the general perception that relativity theory requires some
lenger, which represents a distinctly constructive theory of the further interpretation to justify or make sense of it.
same phenomena, depending as it does on the contraction of The same cannot be said to have been the case with quantum
physical bodies moving through the medium of the aether. In this mechanics. To a large extent – more for philosophers than physicists
approach, the phenomena are explained by hypothesizing perhaps – there are ongoing programs to provide such an interpreta-
mechanical interactions, which describe in a causal manner that tion for quantum mechanics, or to explain why no such interpretation
which is observed. is required2. The more prominent among these might arguably be
One may reasonably ask, what is the connection between the seen as more constructive theories. The Bohmian hidden variable
type of theory that was presented and which theory was approach explicitly postulates definite particle positions guided by
accepted. That is, what is the relationship between the type of the wavefunction to explain quantum phenomena. GRW collapse
theory and its success, particularly for a fundamental theory for theories also postulate a mechanism, the stochastic collapse of a real
physics? On the one hand, one could argue that it was Einstein’s wavefunction, to account for the classical characteristics of macro-
use of principles which allowed for his success and that this systems and quantum phenomena.
shows that principle theories were better suited to meet the In the Everettian many-worlds interpretation of quantum
problem in this case, as well as in other fundamental theories mechanics, there is no collapse of the wavefunction. The wave-
such as thermodynamics and Newtonian mechanics. As Einstein function of the universe plays an ontological role, as it is taken to
notes, however, constructive theories are not without substantial be a complete and real description of the universe. A number of
merit. If one is looking for completeness and a greater level of things require explanation. The first is the appearance of collapse,
understanding, then constructive theories are better suited to this or according to this view, the splitting of the world into non-
purpose. interfering branches. The second is an explanation of the decom-
On the other hand, principle theories have their own strengths. position into the preferred basis that we observe. The third is the
One of these is the security of their foundations. The very general Born rule and the appearance of quantum probabilities in a
principles are generalizations extrapolated from empirical condi- universe where all measurement outcomes actually occur. In
tions which have been found to hold without exception. They are recent formulations3, the explanations for all of these employ
then elevated to the status of postulates. In making such princi- the mechanism of decoherence, involving the large number of
ples postulates of the theory, they function logically as more than degrees of freedom of particles making up the composite macro-
very strong empirical generalizations. They become principles system of the object being measured, the measuring instrument,
whose truth is basically no longer in question, and which can only and the environment. The many-worlds interpretation takes the
fall should the theory as a whole collapse. The foundational formalism of quantum mechanics at face value, without adding
security Einstein talks about is this analytic formal structure any additional structure, as a complete theory, and instead
founded on essentially irrevisable principles. It is this founda- depends on the ontological role of the wavefunction. However,
tional security of being a principle theory which appears to best to explain some important features of experience, and so to
characterize Einstein’s self-asserted motivation behind using succeed as an interpretation, the current view is that this
principle theories to resolve the fundamental conceptual tensions approach must explicitly appeal to the causal role of decoherence.
between classical electrodynamics and mechanics in the case of The failure of convergence around one interpretation makes it
special relativity, and the conceptual tensions underlying the seem reasonable to think that taking a different tack in the area of
Newtonian notion of gravity in the case of general relativity. quantum mechanics, towards a new principle theory approach, is
CBH take their cue from this prospective insight into theory a smart and innovative strategic move. As Bub and others have
building, appealing to the distinction made by Einstein and apply- argued, other approaches to interpreting quantum mechanics,
ing it to their reformulation of quantum mechanics as a set of which might be viewed as more constructive approaches, as
information-theoretical principles. Bub (2005), appeals to Ein-
stein’s distinction, arguing on two separate grounds that the 2
See Fuchs’ claim based on historical evidence of over 75 years of trying
principle theory approach is not only justified, but preferred and without consensus (2002, pp. 1–3).
perhaps even necessary for there to be any foundational grounding 3
This view is sometimes called the ‘‘Oxford’’ version of many-worlds. See
for quantum mechanics that is philosophically satisfying. The first (Deutsch, 1999; Saunders, 1995, 1998; Wallace, 2002, 2003, 2006).
26 W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31

compared with an information-theoretic principle theory treatment of Lorentz turns out to be unfair4. Nevertheless, a
approach, ultimately seem to fail as widely accepted interpreta- constructive theory might open itself up to being ad hoc in a way
tions, and we have reasons to think that they might never that a principle theory is less prone to according to its nature. The
succeed. Moreover, as suggested by Einstein, principle theories postulation, however well evidenced, of specific mechanisms to
can be an alternative model for success in developing funda- explain phenomena, when those mechanisms themselves cannot
mental theories. yet – or in this case in principle – be empirically verified, leaves
room for accusations of ad hoc theory building. However, this
cannot be a sufficient reason for adopting a principle theory over
4. Understanding the distinction a constructive theory as a matter of principle, even if it might be a
matter of good methodology. One has simply to look to other
But should we conclude that because special relativity is a examples of constructive theories, such as statistical mechanics,
principle theory, it is better or in some sense more fundamental which are more fundamental than the corresponding principle
than Lorentz’s? Why? After all, why should such a causal- theory, thermodynamics, even if their theoretical basis was less
mechanical explanation, such as that offered by Lorentz, not be secure at the outset.
more interpretationally adequate than one, such a special rela- Other philosophers have developed the distinction between
tivity, which requires the entire restructuring of the concepts of the roles which constructive theories and principle theories play
space and time themselves? This section will develop the princi- in physics. Flores (1999) describes three grounds on which
ple/constructive distinction, and, in the process, uncover the role Einstein justifies his distinction between principle theories and
that explanation plays in underwriting both principle theories constructive theories. First, there is an ontological difference.
and constructive theories. This will help us understand the roles Constructive theories are realistic about the existence of entities,
these different types of theories play in physics. or they are concerned with what Flores calls entity realism.
Klein (1967) argues that Einstein, in formulating his special Principle theories cannot offer this type of realism nor are they
theory of relativity, relied heavily on his understanding of the meant to. Principle theories are concerned with nomological
theory of thermodynamics and used it as a model of good theory realism, establishing which scientific principles are true in our
building, among other things. As Klein argues, the primary reason world. The second basis for the distinction is their differing
for this was that thermodynamics was essentially different from epistemological basis. Flores maintains that, for Einstein, principle
other contemporary theories in terms of its basic structure. theories begin with empirically discovered general principles. On
Where most theories of the day were constructive theories, the other hand, we arrive at constructive theories by hypothesiz-
thermodynamics represented a prime example of a principle ing the existence of the entities in question, in order to explain
theory. Einstein says about thermodynamics, some phenomena.
A theory is the more impressive the greater the simplicity of its The third way that types of theories can differ that Flores
considers is the conceptual roles they play, or their function. For
premises is, the more different kinds of things it relates, and the
more extended its area of applicability. Therefore the deep Einstein, principle theories function as universal constraints on
impression that classical thermodynamics made upon me. It is any further application of theory under those principles. Starting
the only physical theory of universal content concerning which I as they do with general empirical principles made into postulates,
am convinced that, within the framework of applicability of its principle theories set the general conceptual and mathematical
basic concepts, it will never be overthrown. (Einstein, 1949, p. 32) constraints imposed by the theory for any physical description
falling under it. This is not the case with constructive theories.
Since thermodynamics does not depend on any particular These are theories whose elements must satisfy these conditions
causal-mechanical model or hypothetical constituents, Einstein set by the overarching principle theory covering it. Constructive
was sure of its security and of its ability to guide him in further theories are, of necessity, developed under conceptual con-
investigations. Historically, this guidance occurred at two levels. straints, delimiting what is off limits. If such a constructive theory
First, the firm grounding of thermodynamic principles quite meets with difficulty, then, methodologically, we first attempt to
literally guided Einstein’s early work in the area of thermody- modify it rather than the structural constraints imposed on it
namics by offering virtually unquestionable axioms, delineating from above. It is only in times of deep theoretical crisis that such a
further avenues of research. Second, the model of thermody- radical move is made. In this way, the two types of theories play
namics as a principle theory served as a philosophical guide, distinct functional roles in science.
influencing Einstein’s ideas about how to develop physical the- According to Flores, the ontological dimension of this distinc-
ories in general, and in developing relativity in particular. tion is primary for Einstein and the other dimensions are only
On later accounts of the development of special relativity, derivative of that difference 5. Flores rejects this, arguing that we
Einstein’s principle theory approach to special relativity has been should emphasize the functional aspect of the distinction, since
contrasted with the other prominent theory of the time, that of there is no clear ontological distinction that applies to all theories.
Lorentz, whose pre-relativistic theory has been portrayed by In some cases it is unclear where the fundamental starting point
Einstein and others as being a constructive theory of the same for a theory is; is it a principle or an underlying entity? Newton’s
phenomena. Therefore, the argument seemed to go, it was not as universal law of gravitation is given as an example (Flores, 1999,
good, primarily because Lorentz’s theory was not as foundation- pp. 127–9), since it cannot be classified without problem as a
ally secure. Lorentz’ theory explains the apparent inconsistencies principle theory or as a constructive theory.
between Newtonian mechanics and Maxwellian electrodynamics Instead, Flores proposes that we focus on the functional roles
with a set of transformations for Maxwell’s equations for different that theories play. In order to more clearly define the distinction
frames relative to the aether. Lorentz accounts for the absence of Einstein raises, Flores revises it, calling the ‘‘upper-level’’ theories
experimental evidence of the aether from experiments such those
by Michelson and Morley (1887) by hypothesizing that the
4
measuring instruments contract as they moved through the For a comprehensive discussion see Janssen (2002).
5
I am not certain Flores’ portrayal does justice to Einstein’s thoughts on this
aether, thus compensating for the null result. Einstein and others issue. Einstein was well aware of the functional role of principle theories and his
accused Lorentzian dynamics of being an ad hoc theory, attempt- philosophy reflects considerable thought about the constitutive nature of this
ing to fit this single experimental result into the theory. This function. See Howard (1994).
W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31 27

‘‘framework theories’’, in lieu of calling them ‘‘principle theories’’, argument for such an explanation-centric understanding of this
because it is the role of these theories to provide the overarching distinction, which is absent in other accounts.
framework by imposing constraints or restrictions on other Second, Flores’ association of principle theories with the
theories. ‘‘The main elements of these ‘upper-level’ theories are Kitcher-style unificationist account of explanation and construc-
general physical principles (typically expressed as ‘laws’) and tive theories with causal-mechanical explanation is incomplete as
definitions of physical terms which are expected to be applicable it stands. Once it has been established that the distinction is best
in the analysis of any physical system’’ (Flores, 1999, p. 126). The understood in terms of explanatory function, it must be recog-
theories that these upper-level theories constrain Flores calls nized that it cannot simply be a matter of causal-mechanical vs.
‘‘interaction theories’’, since they typically involve the interac- Kitcher-style unification. Principle or framework theories can do
tions of various, more elementary constituents (though not something more than this. It is the case that constructive theories
necessarily mechanical ones). Interaction theories ‘‘describe spe- are centrally about providing causal-mechanical explanation. It is
cific physical processes within the constraints imposed by the tempting to lump principle theories into the top-down class of
principles (or one of the consequences) of a framework theory’’ explanation by unification, the most important competing expla-
(p. 129). natory theory, since many, if not all, successful principle theories
This revised distinction sheds light on the nature of scientific do provide such unification. However, functioning as a framework
theorizing in general. What is it a theory is supposed to be doing? is not only about unifying argument patterns. It can also be about
A great deal of literature has been written on the nature of establishing principles constitutive of the conceptual framework.
scientific explanation and Flores’ emphasis on function highlights Before making that argument, it is necessary to look at some
the important role which scientific theories play in providing historical considerations and current arguments regarding the
explanation. As Flores notes, two of the more influential philoso- purpose of scientific explanation and explanatory pluralism.
phical viewpoints regarding explanation now appear ready made
to track this new distinction. One line of analysis of scientific
explanation, represented in Friedman (1974) and Kitcher (1989),
argues that laws are explained through the unification of different
5. Theoretical pluralism in practice
phenomena. Friedman argues for this approach with the basic
idea that ‘‘A world with fewer independent phenomena is, other
A central question of this paper is whether the principle theory
things equal, more comprehensible than one with more’’ (1974, p.
approach to quantum mechanics might hold an advantage over
15). Kitcher is more precise saying, ‘‘Science advances our under-
constructive approaches and why. As this section should make
standing of nature by showing us how to derive descriptions of
clear, it is far from obvious that principle theories are inherently
many phenomena, using the same patterns of derivation again
superior to constructive theories. However, Flores’ considerations
and again, and, in demonstrating this, it teaches us how to reduce
regarding types of scientific theories might be brought to bear on
the number of types of facts we have to accept as ultimate (or
another debate within the philosophy of science, that of explana-
brute)’’ (1989, p. 432). All things being equal, the more descrip-
tion. The different types of theories – principle theories and
tions derivable from an argument pattern, the better an explana-
constructive theories – are in fact theories which center around
tion it is. As Flores notes, this is explanation from the top down,
and exploit different types of scientific explanation. If different
explaining by unifying phenomena within an upper-level theore-
types of scientific explanation are exhibited by different types of
tical structure.
scientific theories, it may not be possible to rectify the unifica-
Contrast this with the bottom-up view most prominently
tionist and causal-mechanical approaches to explanation or settle
expounded by Salmon (1984, 1989). Salmon’s position is that
on one definitive model of scientific explanation. However, one
scientific explanation stems from the ability to provide a causal-
can orient them with their respective type of theory and perhaps
mechanical basis behind physical phenomena. A law is explained
reach the conclusion that both are equally valid in their place.
by detailing the causal mechanisms which make it hold. Like
Instead of competing theories on how scientific explanation
Friedman and Kitcher, Salmon also connects this type of explana-
works, they can be seen as complimentary aims, both with their
tion to a notion of understanding, saying that there are ‘‘intellec-
own merits, but which serve different underlying roles. When we
tual benefits that scientific explanation can confer upon us,
ask for scientific explanation, perhaps there are conceptually
namelyy knowledge of how things in the world work, that is,
distinct kinds of things for which one might be asking, although
of the mechanisms (often hidden) that produce the phenomena
all are tied to the notion of increasing our sense of understanding
we want to understand’’ (1993, p. 15).
about the world. Different types of theories reflect this. The
I do not wish to reject the distinction as Flores describes it, but
notion of explanatory pluralism is of course not a new idea. For
to clarify and expand the functional dimension of the distinction,
example, despite his influence in the area of causal explanation,
and to employ his account as a point of departure. It is imperative
Salmon conjectures that the different types of explanation are not
to investigate the distinction between principle theories and
incompatible, but are complementary (1998, pp. 73–75)7.
constructive theories through the lens of explanatory goals. There
However, Einstein’s distinction between types of theories and
are two points to make. First, it is unclear from Flores’ account
his employment of it can provide an added dimension of histor-
where the emphasis of priority is situated. Is the explanatory
ical analysis to the idea of explanatory pluralism and its role in
connection a derivative property of the functional roles played by
theory development. When we go back and look at Einstein’s
different kinds of theories? Or is the functional role determined
distinction between constructive theories and principle theories,
by explanatory goals? My argument is that the latter is the case.
we can see some degree of ambivalence towards their value on
This is an understanding shared by others6 who have discussed
his part. In some statements, it appears that Einstein prefers the
the principle/constructive distinction in terms of explanatory
constructive approach on the grounds that it provides us with a
aims, although the views differ on which explanatory goal is
deeper understanding. On the other hand, sometimes it seems
most important. In what follows, I hope to give a plausible
that the logical certainty provided by principle theories is the true
aim of our scientific endeavors. Despite the overwhelming

6 7
E.g., Brown (2005), Dieks (2009), and Janssen (2002). See also de Regt (2006) and Dieks (2009)
28 W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31

success of Einstein’s principle theories, on a deeper analysis, it Indeed, Einstein informs us that he first pursued a constructive
turns out that Einstein was not wedded to principle theories. approach to resolving the difficulties presented by the conflict
The distinction between types of physical theories along the between Newtonian mechanics and electrodynamics prior to the
lines of constructive theories and principle theories had been formulation of special relativity.
made prior to Einstein. A similar distinction was noted, interest-
ingly, by Einstein’s contemporary, Lorentz. This connection is the By and by I despaired of the possibility of discovering the true
subject of investigation for Frisch (2005). Lorentz had already laws by means of constructive efforts based on known facts. The
proposed a distinction between types of theories by 1900. One longer and the more desperately I tried, the more I came to the
type of theory begins by postulating ‘‘general principles’’ (1900, conviction that only the discovery of a universal formal princi-
p. 335)8 or ‘‘general laws’’ (p. 336) which express ‘‘generalized ple could lead us to assured results. (Einstein, 1949, p. 53)
experiences’’ (p. 337). There are, however, also theories which
Only after the failure to find a constructive theory did Einstein
postulate a ‘‘mechanism of the appearances’’ (p. 336). Examples of
turn to his principle theory approach to special relativity. Princi-
the first type of theory include the second law of thermodynamics
ple theories serve as guides, or constraints, in theory development
and conservation of energy, while examples of mechanism
by setting parameters in the form of universal laws. For this
theories include the kinetic theory of gases.
purpose, principle theories are ideal, offering a firm foundation
Clearly, Lorentz’s distinction resembles greatly the distinction
due to their generality and security of logical foundations.
between principle and constructive theories made by Einstein,
With this new perspective on Einstein and Lorentz, and their
and it predates Einstein’s distinction, which was discussed at
views on theory construction, the status of principle theories as
length in 1919 in ‘‘What Is the Theory of Relativity.’’ Moreover, if
fundamental theories becomes less certain. It had looked as
we look at Lorentz’s classifications, we can see that there is also a
though perhaps principle theories were the appropriate model
similar distinction between the functional roles played by either
for doing fundamental physics, including quantum mechanics,
type of theory. Principle theories act as constraints, guiding
with the path forged by Einstein himself as a primary example.
further theorizing.
However, it appears that he did not necessarily favor principle
The prevailing view, both historically, and to this day, is that
theories. This does not help resolved the question concerning any
Lorentz anachronistically clung to the mechanistic approach to
interpretational factors which would in principle motivate a
scientific theorizing. Just as Lorentz and Einstein offered compet-
principle theory approach towards quantum mechanics over a
ing theories of what is now considered relativistic phenomena,
constructive approach, or vice versa.
this view contends that they also held competing visions of what
The distinction Flores advocates, emphasizing the functional
an ideal physical theory ought to be like. Einstein was able to
role which different types of theories play – particularly when it
formulate the special theory of relativity because he embraced
comes to explanation – into framework theories and interaction
the principle theory approach over the mechanistic one of
theories, differentiates types of theorizing done in physics, but it
Lorentz. The view that Lorentz was guided by his predisposition
does not favor one over the other. Flores specifically allows that
towards mechanism theories is supported by the historical
there are different roles, satisfied differently, which are involved
resistance Lorentz had towards Einstein’s special theory of rela-
in scientific theorizing. Lorentz, as Frisch notes, was explicitly a
tivity in favor of his own mechanistic theory.
theoretical pluralist, saying that it is a matter of personal
Frisch challenges this view, arguing that the philosophical
preference and not a matter of which type of theory is objectively
views of Lorentz and Einstein in this regard are much closer than
superior or more fundamental to scientific enquiry (Frisch, 2005,
generally thought. Lorentz thought that both principle theories
pp. 669–670). Einstein also seems to have been ambivalent. One
and mechanism theories had a valuable role to play in science,
the one hand, he seems to favor the constructive approach and its
and he did not fail to recognize the benefits of a scientific theory
clear advantage in providing realistic, causal-mechanical explana-
which uses the principle approach. In a view similar to that of
tion and understanding. Yet his greatest contributions to modern
Einstein, who argues that principle theories offer more founda-
physics, special relativity and general relativity, are proudly
tional security, for Lorentz, principle theories offer strong empiri-
offered as principle theories along the lines of thermodynamics,
cal generalizations covering a broad domain of physical
which Einstein touts as a highly successful and paradigmatic
phenomena. Lorentz says, ‘‘‘only when there is absolutely no
model of a principle theory, never to be overturned.
other way out to be found’ scientists will ‘dare to diverge from the
generalized experiences’ embodied in principle-theories’’ (Frisch,
2005, p. 668 quoting Lorentz, 1900, p. 337). Mechanism theories, 6. The role of explanation
in lieu of this security, offer the possibility of greater under-
standing, by postulating the underlying processes which explain I propose that the best way to understand Einstein’s distinc-
scientific phenomena. For Lorentz, a principle theory can say tion and the acceptance of varying theoretical aims is in terms of
‘‘nothing or only very little about the mechanisms of the appear- explanatory preferences and the type of explanation our physical
ances, [thus] lead us to desirable results, but will not show us theories are supposed to be offering, and even notions of what it
much during the trip’’ (1900, p. 355). means to ‘‘understand’’ some phenomena. It seems, through our
What is interesting for our purposes is that Einstein was also analysis, that very important, and what we might call funda-
highly attuned to both the advantages which constructive the- mental, theories in physics are sometimes principle theories and
ories can offer, and the deficiencies of principle theories. In terms sometimes constructive theories. Compared side by side, specific
of explanatory advantage, just as Lorentz thought that mechan- examples demonstrate this. Statistical mechanics is the more
ism theories provide understanding in ways that principle the- fundamental theory, meaning that it, by and large, is taken to
ories cannot, Einstein also recognized that, ‘‘When we say that we explain the principle theory, thermodynamics. Klein says of
have succeeded in understanding a group of natural processes, we Einstein that,
invariable mean that a constructive theory has been found which
covers the processes in question’’ (1954, p. 228). [E]ven in his very early work Einstein was not content to take
thermodynamics only on its own termsy As a ‘theory of
principle’ it had to be intelligible from a more basic point of
8
All translations from the German by Frisch. view. In other words, Einstein also concerned himself with
W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31 29

statistical mechanics as a way of providing that deeper under- This is perhaps a subtle point; nonetheless it is an important
standing of the laws of thermodynamics.’’ (Klein, 1967, p. 510) one. The centrality of explanation in explicating the distinction is
not sufficiently brought to the fore in Flores. That is, explanation
On the other hand, special relativity – a principle theory – has is the sine qua non for understanding the distinction. The dimen-
been adopted over the more constructive theory of Lorentz. sion of most importance which I propose is also a functional one,
The preceding discussion shows us that there are at least two but the function is explicitly an explanatory one. This captures the
distinct kinds of physical theories which differ in their content theoretical unification of principle theories as well as the causal-
and the function they play in our scientific endeavors, in terms of mechanical role played by constructive theories. The branches of
the explanatory structure they can offer. And this makes sense. the distinction may not be mutually exclusive or exhaustive. It
Explanation, on many accounts, is about gaining understanding. may be better to view it as defining ends of a spectrum, within
This is supported by recent developments which explore the which there are theories whose explanatory roles can overlap and
connection between explanation and understanding. Despite the function as hybrids. Nevertheless, we should not lose sight of the
frequent juxtaposition of explanation and understanding, Trout centrality of the types of explanation behind the distinction.
(2002) argues that the subjective psychological ‘‘feeling’’ of We can also clarify the role of explanation played by principle
understanding has no place in scientific explanation, only truth theories a bit further. The most prominent view of unification as
or accuracy. de Regt (2004), subsequently refined by de Regt and scientific explanation is that of Kitcher, and Flores connects his
Dieks (2005), offers a convincing reply to Trout, arguing that notion of a framework theory with this approach. On this view,
while scientific understanding has a pragmatic and contextual something is a better explanation if it is able to unify a wider
component, depending on the particular scientist’s or commu- range of phenomena. Many principle theories participate in this
nity’s skill-set, it also contains an objective component, and that kind of explanation. Newton’s and Einstein’s certainly do. For
understanding is an essential aspect of explanation. This non- instance, Newton’s laws of motion, together with the universal
psychological component is the intelligibility of the theory, law of gravitation, unify celestial and terrestrial phenomena from
defined such that an intelligible theory allows a scientist to planetary orbits, to the tides, to the behavior of objects on earth.
‘‘recognise qualitatively characteristic consequences’’ of the the- However, this type of unification is not the only, nor always the
ory (de Regt & Dieks, 2005, p. 151). A theory can be intelligible by most important, way to understand the role of principle theories
having a number of standards, including, but not limited to, such as special relativity. In some cases, the primary function of
visualisability, causality, unifying power, and/or familiarity. A principle theories is to establish principles which are constitutive
theory can, therefore, promote scientific understanding, given of the very framework of some set of physical concepts. Though
the appropriate context, by having a variety of functional char- Flores refers to the Kitcher program, this constitutivity more
acteristics, and so can explain in a variety of ways. Therefore, closely aligns with what Flores characterizes as a framework
explanatory pluralism is to be expected and not surprising, as theory. This constitutive role is adequately fulfilled only if the
would be theoretical pluralism if it is the case that different types principles successfully establish a coherent conceptual frame-
of theories play distinct explanatory roles as is argued here. work where one had been lacking. As such, theories such as
Again, as Flores describes it, there are three dimensions to the Newton’s and Einstein’s play a fundamental explanatory role by
distinction—ontological, epistemological, and functional. He establishing the explanatory framework itself.
rejects the ontological emphasis, instead emphasizing the func- The constitutive conceptual role played by certain principle
tional dimension. Flores adds that the distinction between types theories has been recognized since Kant, re-interpreted by the
of explanation is derivative of the functional distinction. However, logical positivists, and recently explored by DiSalle (2006). DiSalle
it is the reverse that is true; the principle/constructive distinction argues that some types of theories are necessary as the precondi-
rests on the explanatory motivations behind the particular theory, tions required for defining empirical measurement and hence, the
as seen by looking at both Einstein’s and Lorentz’s views. When preconditions for scientific or empirical explanation. The most
we focus on the upper-level principle (or framework) theories, obvious, and perhaps only clear historical, examples of this are
their functional role comes to the fore. It is their ability to supply found in space-time theories, hence the special relevance of these
an overarching theoretical structure by uniting diverse phenom- theories’ in the history and philosophy of physics. These theories
ena under a single description or by defining its operational are framework theories in Flores’ sense. They establish the frame-
framework. This is one reason why the principle theory approach work within which other theories can be formulated and within
in Newton’s mechanics or special relativity is so explanatorily which questions can be asked with the possibility of getting
successful. However, when we focus on bottom-up constructive empirically meaningful answers. Thus it is necessary that, as both
(or interactionist) theories, it is clearly their powers of causal- Kant and the positivists realized, these theories must have an a
mechanical explanation that makes them attractive. This in turn priori character that is not based strictly on empirical discovery
depends on their ontological basis, their realism about causal- since they actually help define the nature of that empirical
mechanical entities. Therefore, Einstein is wrong to think that it is discovery. Therefore, these theories are constructed in part via a
the ontological characteristics of theories on which the distinction process similar to definition, functioning as principles restricting
is made. Likewise, the way Flores characterizes the functional the meaning of empirical claims. New principles are formed when
aspect of the distinction mischaracterizes the central role played it becomes the case that a new constitutive framework is needed,
by explanatory characteristics. The problem is that if the frame- when the old framework becomes insufficient in light of empirical
work/interaction distinction is prior to the explanatory role, then discoveries that eventually come to be seen as falling outside the
it becomes unclear what particular function it is that interaction scope of that conceptual structure, as happened in the case of
theories are supposed to play or why they are desirable. A special relativity and the concept of simultaneity. Principle
framework theory defines the framework, but an interaction theories of this foundational kind are generated out of a need to
theory, on this dimension, is defined as a non-framework theory, resolve conceptual conflict. ‘‘This interpretive aspect of the laws
a theory which is constrained by some upper-level framework. of physics is the source of their a-priori and seemingly unrevi-
But this fails to capture the importance of the original ontological sable character; their actual revisability reflects what a stringent
emphasis. Being constrained does not imply any causal-mechan- requirement it is upon such a theory, that it be capable of bringing
ical structure. Yet this seems fundamental to how both Einstein the relevant phenomena within its interpretive grasp.’’ (DiSalle,
and Lorentz cash out the notion of a constructive theory. 2006, p. 161) In other words, the crisis arises from conceptual
30 W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31

conflict or lack of coherence, revealed by empirical discovery, and experiment (Einstein, Podolsky, & Rosen, 1935). It might be
this drives the need for conceptual analysis and revision9 . This claimed that Einstein’s powerful objection here was in fact a
also accounts for the foundational security of principle theories way of articulating his frustration that quantum mechanics
which Einstein lauds, stemming as it does from this analytic fundamentally rules out a constructive formulation in its most
character of the principles. rudimentary sense. The incompleteness Einstein was worried
It also allows us clarify the relationship between principle about, stemming from the basic assumptions of separability and
theories and the unificationist program in scientific explanation locality, was an incomplete causal-mechanical explanation for the
of Friedman and Kitcher. Unification by covering the most facts correlations involved.
with the least argument patterns (Kitcher, 1989) is the result of Bell’s later analysis (1964) of the problem illustrates the
bringing more phenomena under one theoretical structure. Prin- impossibility of such a straightforward constructive theory of
ciple theories can offer explanation by unification in this sense. quantum mechanics. The assumptions behind the Bell inequality
Principle theories can also establish the conceptual framework show that quantum mechanics rules out the possibility of there
necessary for a theoretic structure with empirical meaning, by being any common-cause explanation behind the phenomena. As
providing the preconditions for the understanding and explana- such, any constructive theory of quantum mechanics, in its
tion of phenomena that fall under the theory. That is, theories standard sense of providing causal-mechanical explanation, seems
such as this are necessary for any explanation at all because they to be in principle ruled out. At the very least, it is no straightfor-
provide a meaningful conceptual framework. In this way, they are ward task to show how to go about designing or envisioning a
explanatorily motivated by making understanding possible in the constructive theory of quantum mechanics.
most rudimentary sense. That is, if something along the lines of One might reply that other approaches or interpretations do
that proposed by de Regt and Dieks is on the right track, then a attempt this. It has been suggested that Bohm’s approach, which
necessary prerequisite for a theory being intelligible, hence maintains a causal framework and is constructed from quantum
capable of facilitating understanding, is that it offer a coherent particles and waves, does provide a constructive theory and that had
conceptual framework. Theories which can provide this when it is history been different there would be no interpretational qualms
necessary are powerful explanatory tools. surrounding quantum mechanics for that very reason (Cushing,
We can also elaborate on the connection between conceptual 1998). It seems like this might have the appropriate elements
analysis of this sort and explanation by unification. When it of a constructive theory, and proponents of Bohmian mechanics
becomes apparent that a particular framework is in a state of certainly seem to claim that it has the standard advantages of a
crisis, it is because of the emergence of phenomena unanticipated constructive theory: causal-mechanical explanation and under-
by it and which the theory cannot handle. That is, a problem standing. However, as all issues in quantum mechanics seem to
becomes apparent because of disunity at the level of the phenom- encounter, there are roadblocks for this view. If I am right and the
ena, and the intractability of the problem can sometimes point to functional value in a constructive theory stems from its causal-
an underlying conceptual issue. This is what Einstein was able to mechanical explanatory basis, then it will not be successful as a
see. In cases where conceptual problems are resolved, it will often constructive theory unless its causal-mechanical explanatory role is
be that they are noticed because of problems with unification at fulfilled. But by gaining causal determinism, by Bell’s theorem,
the level of the phenomena. Likewise, the resolution of the Bohmian mechanics must be non-local. For Bohmian mechanics,
conceptual issues will often allow the possibility Kitcher-type any change in the environment results in the instantaneous change
unification and explanation of the problematic phenomena. We of the quantum potential everywhere (Cushing, 1998). GRW col-
see this in the special theory of relativity. The necessity of lapse theories must also incorporate non-local factors. The proposed
conceptual revision becomes evident because of the apparent ontology of Bohm and GRW collapse theories both require non-
conflict between Newtonian mechanics and Maxwellian electro- locality10, violating a key assumption behind the EPR problem and
dynamics. Einstein’s analysis establishes the constitutive frame- an assumption contained in the concept of common-cause. As such,
work defining a functioning concept of simultaneity and of the standard notion of causal explanation is violated by these
spacetime. The conceptual analysis allows for the unification of theories. Therefore, they cannot function as constructive arguments
the fields of electrodynamics and mechanical dynamics. unless what it is to be constructive is reinterpreted by reevaluating
what counts as causal explanation. The many-worlds interpretation,
as a constructive theory based upon a particular ontological struc-
ture, does not straightforwardly fail to be a constructive theory. It is
7. On interpretations of quantum mechanics however not unproblematic. One challenge is against the expansive
ontology of postulating the existence of perhaps infinitely many
Before returning to the CBH approach using information-theo- ‘worlds’ and histories in addition to the one we experience. Another
retic principles to create a principle theory of quantum mechanics, is the derivation of quantum probabilities on a theory where all
having explicated the explanatory role intended by such theories, a possible outcomes actually occur with certainty. As an explanation,
few things can be said regarding the role of constructive theories in the interpretation is arguably both ontologically over indulgent and
quantum mechanics. Why would such an approach be appealing? insufficient.
For the same reasons which influenced both Lorentz and Einstein: Therein lies the root of the fundamental disagreements
understandability and explanatory power. A constructive theory between various interpretive schools. Constructive interpreta-
provides mechanisms which in turn provide explanation by tions are attempted, but they are not unequivocally constructive
supplying causal-mechanical understanding. in any traditional sense. There is no consensus among philoso-
By the time quantum mechanics had been developed, Einstein phers. Moreover, as of yet, there appears to be no principled way
famously had serious qualms with the theory. Most notably, to chose between the various interpretations available to us – e.g.
Einstein faced off with Niels Bohr on the adequacy or complete- wavefunction collapse, hidden-variables, or an Everettian world
ness of quantum mechanics. Einstein’s most famous objection to structure – except on the basis of some predilection or preference
quantum mechanics came in the form of the EPR thought

9 10
For a more in depth discussion see DiSalle (2006) and Van Camp (2009, For a discussion on Bohmian mechanics, GRW collapse theories, and non-
pp. 90–135). locality see Maudlin (2008).
W. Van Camp / Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics 42 (2011) 23–31 31

for certain epistemological or metaphysical principles. But insist- theory approach to quantum mechanics such as CBH is to show
ing on one set of such principles means that others must be that quantum mechanics requires conceptual clarification at a
sacrificed. This suggests that there can be no principled reason to foundational level, determine in what respect it is required, and
choose a particular constructive approach that does not contain that its principles are ones which are constitutive of a coherent
some element of arbitrariness based on metaphysical leanings theoretical and conceptual framework whereby meaningful
one way or another. It is difficult to consider these successful explanation is made possible. This is no easy task, but the
constructive theories for the two reasons that any one of them perennial conceptual issues regarding quantum mechanics per-
must give up some part of the standard realist views of causal haps indicate a need, and as this paper shows such a need can be
mechanism and that the particular mechanisms are inherently filled by a well-conceived principle theory.
underdetermined, and so that the force of inference to the best
explanation breaks down. This accounts for the lack of any
References
convergence in the field. The interpretive work that must be done
is less in coming up with a constructive theory and thereby
Bell, J. S. (1964). On the Einstein Podolsky Rosen paradox. Physics, 195–200.
explaining puzzling quantum phenomena, but more in explaining Brown, H. (2005). Physical relativity. Space-time structure from a dynamical
why the interpretation counts as explanatory at all given that it perspective. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
must sacrifice some key aspect of the traditional understanding of Bub, J. (2004). Why the quantum?. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern
Physics, 35, 241–266.
causal-mechanical explanation. Bub, J. (2005). Quantum mechanics is about quantum information. Foundations of
Physics, 35, 541–560.
Clifton, R., Bub, J., & Halvorson, H. (2003). Characterizing quantum theory in terms
8. Conclusion of information-theoretic constraints. Foundations of Physics, 33, 1561–1591.
Cushing, J. T. (1998). Philosophical concepts in physics. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
In this paper, we have been able to demonstrate more de Regt, H. W. (2004). Discussion note: Making sense of understanding. Philosophy
precisely what role a theory, either as a principle theory or as a of Science, 71, 98–109.
constructive theory, plays in physics. Principle theories offer de Regt, H. W. (2006). Wesley Salmon’s complementarity thesis: causalism and
unificationism reconciled?. International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 20,
explanation by unifying phenomena or, relatedly, by supplying a 129–147.
coherent conceptual framework as a precondition of physical de Regt, H. W., & Dieks, D. (2005). A contextual approach to scientific under-
understanding. Constructive theories are best understood as ful- standing. Synthese, 144, 137–170.
Dieks, D. (2009). Bottom-up versus top-down: The plurality of explanation and
filling the role of providing causal-mechanical explanation. The
understanding in physics. In H. de Regt, S. Leonelli, & K. Eigner (Eds.), Scientific
lesson that we can take from this with respect to quantum Understanding: Philosophical Perspectives (pp. 230–248). Pittsburgh: University
mechanics is valuable. By framing the issue in terms of this of Pittsburgh Press.
distinction, we can see why broadly ‘‘constructive’’ approaches to DiSalle, R. (2006). Understanding space-time. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
quantum mechanics, such as Bohm, GRW, or Everett, have Einstein, A. (1949). Autobiographical notes. In P. A. Schilpp (Ed.), Albert Einstein:
remained unsatisfactory interpretations of quantum mechanics Philosopher-scientist. Evanston, IL: Library of Living Philosophers, Inc.
to many, since they have failed to provide a straightforward Einstein, A. (1954). What is the theory of relativity?. In A. Einstein (Ed.), Ideas and
opinions (pp. 227–232). New York: Crown Publishers, Inc.
causal explanation for certain phenomena; indeed quantum Einstein, A., Podolsky, B., & Rosen, N. (1935). Can quantum-mechanical description
mechanics might seem to prohibit such an explanation. This is a of physical reality be considered complete?. Physical Review, 777–780.
failure of the basic strength of a constructive theory. Hence the Flores, F. (1999). Einstein’s theory of theories and types of theoretical explanation.
International Studies in the Philosophy of Science, 13(2), 123–134.
apparent failure of such attempts has led thinkers such as Bohr to
Friedman, M. (1974). Explanation and scientific understanding. Journal of Philoso-
embrace the instrumentalist perspective. It is not my goal to phy, 5–19.
conclusively argue that none of the other interpretations of Frisch, M. (2005). Mechanisms, principles, and Lorentz’s cautious realism. Studies
quantum mechanics are unviable. The literature is replete with in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 36, 659–679.
Fuchs, C. A. (2002). Quantum mechanics as quantum information (and only a little
such arguments, and I need not repeat them here. The point is more). Retrieved from quant-ph/0205039v1.
that these interpretations have, by and large, been constructive Halvorson, H. (2004). Remote preparation of arbitrary ensembles and quantum bit
adjustments to quantum mechanics, and yet, there has been no commitment. Journal of Mathematical Physics, 45, 4920–4931.
Howard, D. (1994). Einstein, Kant, and the Origins of Logical Empiricism. In
consensus regarding such interpretations. This lack of consensus W. Salmon, & G. Wolters (Eds.), Language, Logic, and the Structure of Scientific
can now be explained, since the goal motivating any constructive Theories. Proceedings of the Carnap-Reichenbach Centennial, University of Kon-
theory has not been fulfilled without simultaneously sacrificing stanz, 21–24 May 1991 (pp. 45–105). Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Janssen, M. (2002). Reconsidering a scientific revolution: The case of Einstein
some other feature of a traditional constructive theory. versus Lorentz. Physics in Perspective, 4, 421–446.
So why not develop a principle theory? If there is an inter- Kitcher, P. (1989). Explanatory unification and the causal structure of the world. In
pretational aim for CBH, it seems it must stem from such a P. Kitcher, & W. Salmon (Eds.), Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science,
Vol. 13 (pp. 410–503). Minnesota: University of Minnesota Press.
motivation. What we have seen is that one incentive behind
Klein, M. J. (1967). Thermodynamics in Einstein’s thought. Science, 157, 509–516.
taking a principle theory approach might be that it can provide Lorentz, H. A. (1900). Electromagnetische Theorien physikalischer Erscheinungen.
explanation in the sense of unification. It does not appear that Collected Papers, Vol. VIII. The Hague: Marin Nijhoff.
CBH can offer unification in Kitcher’s sense, nor does it seem that Maudlin, T. (2008). Non-local correlations in quantum theory: how the trick might
be done. In W. L. Craig, & Q. Smith (Eds.), Einstein, Relativity and Absolute
they attempt to. CBH presents information-theoretic principles as Simultaneity (pp. 156–179). New York: Routledge.
having formal equivalence to some general quantum properties of Michelson, A. A., & Morley, E. W. (1887). On the relative motion of the earth and
theories. However, nothing additional has been shown to be the luminiferous ether. American Journal of Science, 34(203), 333–345.
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world.
incorporated into an information-theoretic reformulation of Princeton: Princeton University Press.
quantum mechanics beyond what is contained in quantum Salmon, W. C. (1989). Four decades of scientific explanation. Minneapolis: University
mechanics itself. It is hard to see how it could offer more of Minnesota Press.
Salmon, W. C. (1993). The value of scientific understanding. Philosophica, 51(1),
unification of the phenomena than quantum mechanics already
9–19.
does since they are equivalent, and so it is not offering any Salmon, W. C. (1998). Causality and explanation. New York: Oxford University
explanatory value on this front. Nevertheless, this leaves room for Press, Inc.
conceptual clarification in the foundational framework of quan- Trout, J. D. (2002). Scientific explanation and the sense of understanding.
Philosophy of Science, 69, 212–233.
tum mechanics. This is where the real work is done by Newton Van Camp, W. (2009). Quantum mechanics and quantum information theory.
and by Einstein in relativity theory. The burden for a principle Retrieved from http://hdl.handle.net/1903/9189.

You might also like