You are on page 1of 18

Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213 – 230

Aggregation and deliberation in valuing environmental


public goods:
A look beyond contingent pricing

M. Sagoff *
Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy, Room 3111, 6an Munching Hall, Uni6ersity of Maryland, College Park,
MD 20742, USA

Abstract

Starting from a distinction between Kantian (principle-based) and utilitarian (preference-based) approaches in
political theory, this essay argues that we may understand normative judgments individuals make about policy to
express principled views of the public interest or purpose not private preferences about their own consumption
opportunities. These judgments, in other words, state opinions about what we ought to do as a society rather than
report preferences about what I want as a utility-maximizer. This essay then argues that contingent valuation can take
into account these kinds of judgments—which dominate public discourse about the environment — only if it moves
toward a deliberative, discursive, jury-like research method emphasizing informed discussion leading toward a
consensus based on an argument about the public interest. © 1998 Elsevier Science B.V.

Keywords: Environmental goods; Environmental services; Contingent pricing; Aggregation; Deliberation

1. Introduction contingent valuation methodology (CVM) (Car-


son et al., 1994). The second research program is
This essay seeks to bring together and thus philosophical and analyses the kinds of decisions
contribute to two programs of research. The first individuals reach by democratic political processes
comprises socioeconomic experiments designed to rather than by market transactions. This research
measure the value individuals attach to environ- is associated with a large literature concerning
mental goods and services that markets fail to discursive and deliberative approaches to the for-
price. This effort, which often uses surveys to mation of public values enacted in legislation
elicit individual willingness to pay (WTP) for pub- (Fishkin, 1995).
lic goods, is associated with the vast literature on These two fields of research are moving toward
a common interest in processes of group learning,
* Tel.: +1 301 4054753; e-mail: ms2@umail.umd.edu discourse and consensus-building. The purpose of

0921-8009/98/$19.00 © 1998 Elsevier Science B.V. All rights reserved.


PII S 0 9 2 1 - 8 0 0 9 ( 9 7 ) 0 0 1 4 4 - 4
214 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

this paper is to suggest that each research pro- alternatives ‘‘by evaluating their consequences in
gram may learn from the other and that their terms of prior preferences’’. The contemporary
differences may be less important than the direc- utilitarian believes that social well-being or wel-
tion they share in common. fare, construed in terms of the satisfaction of the
This essay is organized into the following sec- preferences ranked by WTP, constitutes the prin-
tions. The first section presents the familiar dis- cipal goal of environmental policy. ‘‘The basic
tinction between ‘consumer’ and ‘citizen’ premises of welfare economics are that the pur-
preferences in the context of the even more vener- pose of economic activity is to increase the well-
able distinction between utilitarian and deonto- being of the individuals that make up the society
logical approaches in political theory. This section and that each individual is the best judge of how
describes the problem citizen preferences pose for well-off he or she is in a given situation’’ (Free-
CVM insofar as it presupposes a connection be- man, 1993).
tween preference satisfaction and individual wel- When they adopt the deontological framework,
fare or well-being. The second section describes decision makers ‘‘pursue a logic of appropriateness,
the pervasive influence citizen preferences exert on fulfilling identities or roles by recognizing situations
CV surveys and on other ‘stated preference’ meth- and following rules that match appropriate behav-
ods of socioeconomic research. ior to the situations they encounter’’ (March, 1994).
In the third section, the essay proposes that the In this context, individuals typically do not ask,
two strategies economists initially adopted to deal ‘what situation will most benefit me as an individ-
with citizen preferences, i.e. either denying their ual?’ but, ‘what do we believe is appropriate for us
existence or connecting them to psychic income, as a society, given our shared principles, beliefs and
have failed. The fourth part of the essay explains commitments?’ Political institutions provide the
that an emerging strategy which emphasizes the context in which citizens debate and legislate con-
constructive as distinct from the diagnostic aspect ceptions of the common good bounded by civil,
of CVM may succeed in accounting for these political, and property rights.
values. The next two sections argue that a con- These two conceptions of collective choice dif-
structive, deliberative, and discursive turn also fer in the way they interpret disagreement among
goes a long way toward resolving technical prob- members of society. The contemporary utilitarian
lems that have vexed CV research. The paper understands disagreement in terms of competition
concludes by suggesting that developments in po- for the use of scarce resources. In a society with-
litical theory lend support to the use of CVM as a out resource constraints, all preferences may be
constructive, deliberative and discursive instru- satisfied. The Kantian analyzes disagreement in
ment in estimating the value of public environ- terms of the logical opposition of moral or politi-
mental goods. The result is a useful convergence cal beliefs (Kant, 1959). In answering the question
between contemporary moral philosophy and so- ‘what do we stand for as a nation?’ individuals
phisticated methods of socioeconomic research. may state logically opposing views of social policy
rather than make competing private claims on
scarce resources. In this framework for collective
2. An introductory distinction choice, the reasoning process ‘‘is one of establish-
ing identities and matching rules to recognized
Possibly the most venerable — and surely the situations’’ (March, 1994).
most familiar—distinction in political theory is These alternative approaches in political theory
drawn between utilitarian and deontological (or introduce an equally familiar distinction between
Kantian) conceptions of rational choice. March consumer and citizen preferences. Consumer pref-
(1994) in his A Primer on Decision-Making, lays erences, for example, to buy Pepsi rather than
out a standard theoretical understanding of these Coke, reflect what the individual thinks is good
two points of view. When decision makers adopt for her or him. Citizen preferences, in contrast,
the utilitarian approach, they choose among given reflect principles the individual believes are im-
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 215

plicit in the character, commitments, or identity zens have defended as approaches to regulation.
of the community as a whole. While the words ‘I Other views are also worth considering. For ex-
want’ are likely to introduce a consumer prefer- ample, libertarians regard pollution as a form of
ence, a statement that begins with ‘society coercion and thus as a violation of rights
should…’ is likely to express a citizen preference. (Machan, 1984). They argue that society should
Environmental economists, as citizens and as minimize pollution as a form of trespass or tort
scientists, argue that society should allocate re- rather than optimize it as an economic externality.
sources to those willing to pay the most for them Libertarians may approve policies, therefore, that
in order to maximize aggregate social well-being. require society to reduce or minimize pollution far
This view expresses an objective policy position, more than is economically efficient. Libertarians
not a consumer preference. Like any policy posi- believe it is more important to protect personal
tion, it is to be supported by argument and analy- and property rights against trespass than to bal-
sis. One would not assess its objectivity or validity ance benefits and costs.
by assessing the WTP of its advocates. Members of the Noah movement believe that
The same distinction between subjective desires humanity has a moral obligation to respect and
and objective beliefs applies to virtually every preserve species even at some cost to itself (Nor-
controversy. Earlier this century, those who op- ton et al., 1995). Preservationists in the tradition
posed child labor, for example, sometimes did so of John Muir have kept magnificent landscapes
for self-serving reasons. For the most part, how- from development by making aesthetic, religious
ever, citizens fought against child labor on objec- and cultural rather than economic arguments.
tive moral grounds. They believed that in our These and other groups saw to it that ‘‘the corner-
stones of environmental policy in the United
society, as in any society, children should go to
States’’, such as the Clean Air, Clean Water and
school rather than to the mines. Similarly, when
Endangered Species Acts, ‘‘explicitly prohibited
advocating any policy position, whether about
the weighing of benefits against costs in the set-
campaign reform, the sale of marijuana, abortion,
ting of environmental standards’’ (Cropper and
or assisted suicide, individuals call on others to
Oates, 1992).
agree with their views or, if they disagree, to
Environmental economists have developed
explain why. Those who oppose the death
careful and sophisticated analyses of the ways
penalty, for example, usually seek nothing for environmental policy can handle consumer prefer-
themselves; they protest capital punishment be- ences, i.e. those that reflect judgments individuals
cause they believe it is useless and barbaric, not make about what benefits them. In discussion or
because they themselves fear being hanged. debate about environmental policy, however, citi-
To summarize, consumer preferences reflect zen preferences loom much larger, since people
conceptions of the good life individuals seek for nearly always argue in terms of what society
themselves, while citizen preferences reflect con- ought to do rather than in terms of what is good
ceptions of the good society offered for the con- for them. How, then, should policy makers take
sideration and agreement of others. Consumer citizen preferences into account?
preferences, having the form ‘I want p,’ are associ- As a kind of default strategy, theorists could
ated with gains in individual welfare WTP may simply leave it to the individual to act simulta-
measure. Citizen preferences, having the form ‘we neously within market and political institutions to
ought to…’ or ‘society should…’, express views pursue these different sorts of values. On the
the individual holds as one of us about what we other hand, since markets often fail and since
stand for. He or she expects other members of the political processes, let us say, are not always
political community to agree or, if they disagree, poetry-in-motion, social scientists have every mo-
to explain why. The debate proceeds without ref- tivation for trying to design experimental and
erence to personal well-being. surrogate instruments and procedures by which
Welfare and therefore environmental these different kinds of values might be expressed,
economists offer one among many positions citi- revealed and measured.
216 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

In response to this challenge, economists, soci- choice associated with welfare economics. Tradi-
ologists, and others who seek to strengthen CVM tionally, advocates of this view have held that the
are bringing to the conduct of experiments discur- ‘invisible hand’ of the market ideally performs
sive, information-rich, and deliberative research both the function of eliciting preferences and of
methods to enable subjects to construct informed aggregating welfare. As Kneese and Bower wrote
values or preferences in relation to public environ- in 1972, economic theory ‘‘developed on the pre-
mental goods (Keeney, 1992; Renn et al., 1995a,b; sumption that virtually everything of value is
Webler et al., 1995). Political theorists and stu- suitable for private ownership with little or no
dents of democratic processes, in turn, have begun ‘spillover’ to other persons, households and firms
to emphasize deliberation and consensus-forma- when the private property is put to use by its
tion, as distinct from the aggregation of individu- owner’’. Kneese and Bower (1972) added: ‘‘of
als’ willingness to pay, as the appropriate path to course, it was realized that sometimes adjustments
the evaluation of public goods in a democracy had to be made for ‘market failure’, but these
(Buell, 1996). These theorists, whether in the so- were implicitly, if not explicitly, regarded as minor
cial or political sciences, are drawn to some of the with respect to the overall allocation’’.
same kinds of experiments in their attempts to Kneese and Bower observed that by the 1960s,
understand political deliberation in democratic economists began to recognize that market fail-
decision-making. By analyzing similar processes ures were pervasive and ubiquitous, especially
of social learning, exchange and identification, with respect to public goods that possess aes-
economic analysts and political theorists are de- thetic, spiritual, or cultural significance, such as
veloping parallel conceptions of the function of endangered species and old-growth forest. As
democratic institutions in resolving social conflicts more and more of nature took on historical and
(Elster, 1989; Shklar, 1991; Fishkin, 1995; Sun- cultural value, Kneese and Bower wrote, it be-
stein, 1996). came clear ‘‘that the pure private property con-
This essay will propose, in the context of recent cept applies satisfactorily to a progressively
work both in socioeconomic research and political narrowing range of natural resources and eco-
theory, that individuals, rather than serving sim- nomic activities’’. If environmental resources are
ply as locations or channels where consumer pref- to be allocated efficiently, they argued, non-mar-
erences are found, may participate in a social ket mechanisms are needed to allocate them.
process in which they construct collective judg- Economists urged the government to employ ex-
ments as citizens about the value of a public perts from their profession to ‘correct’ market
environmental good. The opportunity for social prices for public environmental goods and ser-
learning, since it informs consumer and citizen vices. ‘‘Private property and market exchange’’,
choice, could strengthen CV research. Researchers Kneese and Bower concluded, ‘‘have little appli-
are beginning to structure the CV experiment as a cability to their allocation, development and con-
kind of focus group or jury that might reflect servation’’.
views of the larger society. The outcome of delib- If market failure provides ‘‘the most important
eration may then depend less on the addition of argument for governmental intervention’’
individual utilities than on the force of the better (Cowen, 1992) where issues of social equity are
argument about the public interest (Habermas, secondary, economists must play a central role in
1982). policy making. Their expertise is needed to quan-
tify in monetary terms—or attach ‘shadow’ or
‘surrogate market’ prices to—environmental
3. The pervasiveness of citizen preferences goods and services that are not traded under
perfectly competitive conditions. This presents a
From the 1950s to the 1970s, socioeconomic comparatively easy task with respect to common
approaches to the evaluation of public goods property resources, such as wild fish stocks, that
generally adopted the conception of collective produce the kinds of commodities, such as fish,
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 217

markets ordinarily price. It is harder to assign unpublished). The results of one study ‘‘provide
shadow prices to the kinds of environmental an assessment of the frequency and seriousness of
goods most relevant to this essay, those with these non-economic considerations: They are fre-
moral, aesthetic and cultural significance, such as quent and they are significant determinants of
visibility in the Grand Canyon or wildlife in WTP responses’’ (Schkade and Payne, 1993).
Prince William Sound. These moral or spiritual Researchers found a large range of strategies
assets enlist our political views more than our for constructing stated WTP that had little or
consumer interests. To allocate (or to preserve) nothing to do with respondents’ expected utilities
these assets, we traditionally rely on political (Schkade and Payne, 1994). Edwards (1986)
rather than market institutions and processes. points out with respect to ‘bequest’ value that
As economists Cropper and Oates (1992) point choices ‘‘motivated entirely out of an unselfish
out, economists responded in two ways to the interest in the well-being of others’ fail to reflect
need to attach shadow prices to public environ- personal welfare’’. A group of economists con-
mental goods. First, they developed methods ‘‘to clude: ‘‘Whatever CV surveys may be measuring,
infer the value of improved environmental ameni- they are not measuring consumers’ economic pref-
ties from the prices of the market goods to which erences over environmental amenities. Thus they
they are, in various ways, related’’. Second, they do not represent values that should be used in
‘‘turned to an approach regarded historically with cost-benefit analysis or for measuring compensa-
suspicion in our profession: the direct questioning tory damages’’ (Diamond et al., 1993).
of individuals about their valuation…’’. The recently issued Global Biodiversity Assess-
This essay is concerned not with methods by ment acknowledges that non-use or ‘existence’
which economists ‘impute’ prices to public envi- value ‘‘is almost entirely driven by ethical consid-
ronmental goods, but with instruments erations precisely because it is disinterested value’’
economists have developed to elicit the stated (Perrings et al., 1995). This study notes that ‘‘exis-
preferences of individuals with respect to the pro- tence value has been argued to involve a moral
tection of the natural environment. These surveys ‘commitment’ which is not in any way all self-in-
generally seek to elicit WTP for public goods with terested’’ (Perrings et al., 1995, citing Sen, 1977).
aesthetic or spiritual significance individuals be- The Assessment explains that ‘‘commitment can
lieve society ought to protect. Individuals report be defined in terms of a person choosing an act
that they base their WTP for these goods on their that he believes will yield a lower level of personal
concerns as citizens more than on their wants as welfare to him than an alternative that is also
consumers. Respondents seem affected less by available to him’’ (Perrings et al., 1995). If the
considerations of their own well-being than by satisfaction of ‘existence’ values lowers welfare,
‘‘ethical concerns, altruism, or the desire to do on which side of the cost-benefit equation should
their ‘fair share’— concerns that indicate they they be entered? The individual does not want less
used decision-making processes inconsistent with welfare per se, but ‘‘adherence to one’s moral
the neoclassical paradigm’’, insofar as it seeks to commitments will be as important as personal
maximize individual welfare or well-being welfare maximization and may conflict with it’’
(Stevens et al., 1993). (Perrings et al., 1995).
Reviewing several CV protocols, three
economists concluded that ‘‘responses to CV
questions concerning environmental preservation 4. Citizen preferences and individual well-being
are dominated by citizen judgments concerning
social goals and responsibilities rather than by The pervasive influence of citizen preferences
consumer preferences’’ (Blamey et al., 1993, un- has posed a theoretical problem for CV research.
published). These responses often reveal ‘‘social The problem arises in establishing the relevance of
or political judgments rather than preferences WTP, insofar as it measures individual welfare, to
over consumer bundles’’ (Blamey et al., 1993, citizen preferences, which by definition concern
218 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

goods or goals other than individual welfare. message across, or that their audience is per-
They also reflect values individuals typically pur- versely predisposed against their ideas’’ (Schelling,
sue through civic and political association, not 1983).
through actual or hypothetical market transac- The ambiguity of the term ‘satisfaction’ sug-
tions. gests a second way of dealing with the problem of
Economists have responded to this problem in citizen preferences. In a logical sense, to ‘satisfy’ a
two distinct ways. Some welfare economists have preference is to meet or fulfill its terms; this is also
ruled citizen preferences (other than their own the sense in which equations and conditions are
theory) out of consideration. Freeman (1993) ‘satisfied’. In a psychological sense, to ‘satisfy’ a
states flatly that society ‘‘should make changes in preference or a person refers to a mental state of
environmental resource allocations only if the re- pleasure or contentment. These two senses of the
sults are worth more in terms of individuals’ word ‘satisfy’ are easily blurred. This being so, it
welfare than what is given up by diverting re- is easy to slide from the logical to the psychologi-
sources and inputs from other uses’’. Economists cal meaning of ‘satisfaction’.
Stokey and Zeckhauser (1978) similarly believe In the late 1960s, economists at Resources for
that ‘‘the purpose of public decisions is to pro- the Future, for example, observed that individuals
mote the welfare of society’’. They add that ‘‘the experience psychological satisfaction when they
welfare levels of the individual members of society forego material well-being to support policies they
are the building blocks for the welfare of society’’. believe are intrinsically right. ‘‘There are many
Stokey and Zeckhauser (1978) solve the problem people who obtain satisfaction from the mere
of citizen values by assuming there are none, i.e.
knowledge that part of wilderness North America
that the individual will be motivated only by
remains’’, Krutilla (1967) wrote, ‘‘even though
considerations of personal subjective utility. ‘‘In
they would be appalled by the prospect of being
the United States we usually take the position
exposed to it’’. Building on Krutilla’s theoretical
that it is the individual’s own preferences that
insight, economists developed many concepts—
count, that he is the best judge of his own wel-
including ‘existence’, ‘vicarious benefit’, ‘bequest’
fare’’.
and ‘stewardship values’—to capture in welfare
If individuals are to judge only their own wel-
fare —if they are motivated only by private con- terms amounts people are willing to pay for poli-
sumer preferences— who is to provide objective cies of which they strongly approve but from
views about public policy? Who is to engage in which they do not directly benefit.
political deliberation as distinct from actual or Economists seeking to measure these ‘non-use’
hypothetical market transactions? Presumably, or ‘non-consumption’ values sometimes supposed
only those in the scientific vanguard, who under- that WTP correlated with the ‘warm glow’ indi-
stand the economic foundations of environmental viduals expected to obtain in supporting a worthy
policy, can discuss it objectively. According to cause, for example, the protection of a wilderness
this presumption, which Leonard and Zeckhauser area they would never visit. This strategy presup-
(1986) have made explicit, ‘‘consent and the cost- posed what had to be proved, namely, that WTP
benefit criterion are equivalent and… cost-benefit for wilderness preservation ‘really’ sought to buy
analysis can be thought of as a form of ‘hypothet- psychic satisfaction, avoid feelings of guilt or
ical’ consent by the community’’. What shall we angst and the like. Krutilla and others assumed
say, then, of individuals who express views of that whatever the individual said he wanted to
environmental policy inconsistent with the princi- buy, the actual object must be his or her own
ples of welfare economics? These citizen prefer- well-being. They thought that individuals, by sat-
ences may influence their replies to CV surveys. isfying their preferences in a logical sense, primar-
Some welfare economists would dismiss such be- ily intended to satisfy themselves in a
liefs as irrational. They have concluded that envi- psychological sense and thus to achieve a higher
ronmental economists ‘‘have failed to get their level of utility.
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 219

When citizens say that they are willing to pay The 19th-century Utilitarian John Stuart Mill
for the existence of visibility over the Grand understood that pleasures that are inappropriate
Canyon, whether they will visit it or not, what do to their objects, are reprehensible. He wrote that
they think they are buying? Is it clean air or ‘‘it is better to be Socrates dissatisfied than a pig
psychic satisfaction? Surveys that investigate ‘non- satisfied’’. Parents know this. They socialize chil-
use’ values never ask how much individuals would dren to enjoy what is valuable rather than to
pay for the psychic satisfaction or ‘warm glow’ value what is enjoyable. Among those who are
they expect to experience as a result of various socialized, pleasure follows moral judgment and
policies. Instead, these surveys inquire about does not substitute for it. If we enjoy what is
WTP for the policy itself, e.g. wilderness protec- evil—for example, racism or genocide—that does
tion or the preservation of a species. Wilderness not make it better. It only makes us worse.
protection and psychic satisfaction are different The literature of environmental economics sug-
goods that may be provided separately. For each, gests only two approaches to citizen preferences:
therefore, WTP must be separately surveyed. to dismiss them as irrational or to conflate them
To understand this, it is helpful to distinguish with consumer preferences. Some economists,
between pleasure or satisfaction as, (1) the end, such as Zeckhauser and Leonard, by supposing
object, or goal of an action or choice and, (2) the that their theory of public policy has the hypo-
means or mental faculty by which people perceive thetical consent of all citizens, would ignore con-
or appreciate the aesthetic, moral and other nor- trary views (and legislation consistent with them)
mative properties of objects and events. As an as perverse or irrational. Like Marxists and others
object or end of experience, pleasure may be whose science teaches them the truth, they dismiss
understood as a response to a stimulus, for exam- dissent as ignorance or as willful irrationality.
ple, the relief addicts experience when they get Other economists in the tradition of Krutilla as-
their next ‘fix’. The entire value of the stimulus, sume that whatever reasons citizens offer for their
say, morphine, consists in the pleasure or relief WTP, whatever object they describe, and however
from pain it gives. Narcotics, prostitution, gam- surveys are worded, the real object of desire must
bling and other addictive pursuits, in view of the be psychic income or satisfaction. This assump-
ferocity of the appetites they feed upon, may tion ties preference satisfaction to expected well-
deliver the greatest amount of pleasure as a com- being and thus magically transforms views
modity at the lowest cost, at least in the short run. opposed to welfare economics into data for cost-
Surgery may also offer a lot of pleasure for the benefit analysis.
dollar—a nice lobotomy, for instance. These
kinds of pleasures, such as the ignorance that is
bliss, have no worth. They rob people of their 5. A third strategy to account for citizen
humanity and often make them slaves of their preferences
desires.
On the other hand, pleasure may function cog- Economists need not dismiss citizen preferences
nitively to inform us about good and evil. Plea- out of hand, however, nor invoke a special sort of
sure (or pain) in this context is not the end but the psychic income to explain them. A third strategy
means—the faculty — by which we perceive the for interpreting citizen preferences may be more
moral and aesthetic qualities of the world. The promising. This approach builds on social choice
quiet satisfaction a person takes when contem- theory by employing WTP simply to rank or
plating an accomplishment, for example, is a way measure preferences relative to one another. No
of perceiving its value, but it is not what gives it claim is made about the relation of these prefer-
value. If pleasure or satisfaction itself were the ences to welfare or well-being in a substantive or
goal, a good biochemist or hypnotist could psychological sense.
provide it at little cost and the Big Lie would be This strategy begins by asserting that the rela-
better than the hard truth. tionship between WTP, well-being, and prefer-
220 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

ence-satisfaction is a logical, stipulative, or formal and ‘preference satisfaction’ are logically equiva-
one. In other words, this strategy makes no psy- lent, rather than causally related, the proposition,
chological claims. Having no psychological di- ‘society should satisfy preferences to maximize
mension, WTP simply orders preferences in welfare’ asserts exactly the same thesis as ‘a= a’.
relation to each other rather than in relation to It cannot be refuted because it expresses a stipu-
some external quantity, such as happiness. If ‘wel- lated identity. The old adage that ‘you get what
fare’ or ‘utility’ is construed as a formal ordering you pay for’ is necessarily true in this instance.
relation among preferences, as it is in social ‘Well-being’ is what you always pay for by defini-
choice theory, rather than a measure of subjective tion, it has no independent meaning and no con-
well-being, the distinction between consumer and nection with happiness as it is ordinarily
citizen preferences loses its significance. One could understood.
rank preferences without regard to the kinds of One might argue, then, that because WTP
preferences they are (Keeney and Raifa, 1980). refers to or correlates with no substantive, i.e.
This strategy may overcome a familiar criticism moral or psychological, conception of well-being,
of the thesis that links the satisfaction of prefer- it provides a formal, ordering metric to establish
ences to welfare or well-being. Study after study the relative weight individuals place on their pref-
has shown that after basic needs are met, happi- erences. To speak crudely, to assess WTP is to ask
ness or contentment do not vary with income and people to put their money where their mouths are.
thus with the ability to satisfy preferences (for To express the same thought more politely, WTP
reviews of the literature, see Kahneman and serves as a metric to identify the trade-offs indi-
Varey, 1991; Easterlin, 1995). Studies relating viduals would make between what they want for
wealth to perceived happiness have found that themselves and for society as a whole. As a way
‘‘rising prosperity in the USA since 1957 has been to rank preferences—consumer or citizen, self-re-
accompanied by a falling level of satisfaction. garding or other-regarding —WTP may provide a
Studies of satisfaction and changing economic suitable economic measure.
conditions have found overall no stable relation- Researchers may establish a ranking of social
ship at all’’ (Argyle, 1986). ‘‘And this is virtually policies by asking individuals after discussion and
inevitable because the faster preferences actually deliberation for their WTP for them. For exam-
are met, the faster they escalate’’ (Rescher, 1980). ple, researchers could explain the concept of an
The thesis that preference satisfaction correlates efficient allocation to a survey group and ask
with welfare is immune to this kind of empirical them how much society ought to pay to achieve
refutation as long as economists define ‘welfare’ in efficiency in the allocation of environmental
terms of WTP and abandon the attempt to corre- goods. In view of the pervasiveness of market
late WTP with any conception of well-being, not failure, efficiency is expensive to achieve. (The
simply defined in terms of it. Many commentators current deontological approach to policy, since it
have observed that sophisticated welfare is based more on rules than on outcomes, may not
economists use WTP as a formal measure to order incur the same information costs.) The costs in-
preferences without making any inferences about volved in determining the ‘correct’ shadow price
human happiness. As Posner (1981) points out, for every environmental good and service can be
the ‘‘most important thing to bear in mind about high, especially if everyone’s moral and political
the concept of value — in the welfare economist’s beliefs must be taken into account. The price of
sense —is that it is based on what people are CV surveys is not small and it increases when
willing to pay for something rather than the hap- opposing sides to a controversy each commission
piness they would derive from having it’’. their own experiments.
We should understand, then, that in contempo- For example, public officials must pay large
rary welfare economics, ‘welfare’ and ‘well-being’ amounts to fund contingent valuation studies to
are not causally related to ‘preference satisfaction’ assess natural resource damage, such as that
but are proxies or stand-ins for it. Since ‘welfare’ caused by the Exxon Valdez incident. This does
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 221

not include the large sums various interested policy makers more as a recommendation than as
parties invest in commissioning their own studies a kind of evidence. Just as the opinion of a jury
or in litigating the validity of the studies commis- about the guilt or innocence of a defendant is
sioned by their opponents. Exxon has spent vast supposed to be legitimate because of the informed
sums hiring experts to refute damage estimates deliberation that produces it, so, too, the process
based on reported willingness to pay for an un- of informed deliberation may add weight to the
fouled environment. When pockets are deep and judgments individuals render about the value of
the political atmosphere is charged, there is no public goods.
theoretical limit on the amount society may have One could imagine the possibility that citizen
to pay to achieve closure about the true, scientific, groups might convene as ‘juries’ to work out
or objective value of a sea otter, much less larger through informed deliberation a value or ‘price’
public goods. The Exxon corporation was willing for particular public goods. Several such juries
to pay huge amounts to many of the nation’s best given the same evidence and information might
economists to take its side in the Valdez contro- reach roughly the same judgment. If so, could we
versy (Hausman, 1993); other litigants were able say that this consensus represents a kind of
to attract non-Nobel laureates at somewhat lower knowledge citizens can reach if provided the ap-
prices. More generally, solving technical problems propriate context for thought and reflection? The
in CVM has become a growth industry, and one design of these panels might draw upon the
may wonder how much of its wealth society must strengths of jury processes (Kalven and Zeisel,
invest to achieve agreement among economists. 1966; Hastie and Pennington, 1983; Hans and
Vidmar, 1986; Abramson, 1994). One might also
learn from the history of citizen participation in
6. Diagnostic and constructive elements in CV deliberative groups resolving environmental confl-
research icts (Fiorino, 1990) and from work on ‘grass
roots’ deliberation on national issues (Mathews,
Traditionally, economists have used CV surveys 1994) and international development (Annis and
and other instruments for diagnostic purposes. Hakim, 1988).
The purpose of these experiments has been to Many political theorists believe that delibera-
elicit preexistent preferences for public goods. tion about conceptions of the public interest, as
This method of eliciting and aggregating individ- distinct from the articulation and satisfaction of
ual utilities parallels a conception of democracy as individual subjective utilities, is a defining charac-
‘‘a kind of social welfare function which goes teristic of a democratic political process. This
from individual preferences to a social preference view, associated with Rousseau and his contem-
that embodies the greatest level of preference sat- porary followers (Cohen, 1986, 1989), regards
isfaction for the whole population’’ (Christiano, ‘‘the democratic process as an attempt to formu-
1995). In this context, discursive group processes late and reliably choose a conception of the com-
may be useful in part because they allow individu- mon good with which to guide society’’
als to reflect in an informed and more critical way (Christiano, 1995). In this context, individuals
on their preexisting preferences. might be asked to deliberate not so much about
Recently, social scientists, in response to some the welfare effect of an environmental policy on
of the criticisms restated here, have revised their them individually as about its appropriateness or
approach in CV research to treat informed group desirability for society as a whole, in view of a
deliberation as serving not so much a diagnostic ‘price tag’ that is attached to it. Their individual
as a constructive purpose. The function of this WTP may represent a conception of their ‘fair
kind of group process is not to plumb more share payment’, not a measure of their own wel-
reliably the pre-existing preferences of the respon- fare loss or gain.
dents but to work through evidence and argument A deliberative and constructive framework for
to reach a considered judgment, which may guide CV research responds to the difficulty for eco-
222 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

nomic theory emphasized in this essay, the pen- might influence or bias the response (Samuelson,
chant of individuals to take concerns other than 1947). The data collected could not then be con-
their own welfare into account when putting hy- sidered exogenous to—but might be an artifact
pothetical values on public goods. One might of—the methods used to collect them. Critics
imagine an experiment in which individuals are often describe CV surveys as unreliable, for exam-
asked for estimates of WTP based simply on a ple, because responses vary with the way a survey
policy’s effects on their own expected welfare or question is focused or framed. According to these
utility and, secondly, based on their moral, reli- critics, CV surveys can achieve reliable results
gious, or political beliefs and commitments. It only under the condition that individuals possess
would be an interesting result if the sign (plus or ‘‘a set of coherent preferences for goods, including
minus) of the estimates were different, for exam- non-market goods such as clean air and nice
ple, if people thought that protecting the kanga- views’’ and that ‘‘these preferences can be recov-
roo rat would affect their own welfare negatively, ered’’ by appropriate survey methods (Kahneman,
if at all, but nevertheless were willing as a matter 1986).
of religious scruple or moral principle to bear a Contrary to this requirement, ‘‘people tend not
share of the societal cost of maintaining a popula- to have previously well-defined values’’ about
tion of that endangered creature. In that event, a non-marketed goods (Cummings et al., 1986;
CV study could offer the policy maker two esti- Mitchell and Carson, 1989). Accordingly, they
mates, one related to social welfare, the other to ‘‘must construct their responses at the time they
views of social responsibility. are asked an elicitation question, rather than re-
The often-heard objection that cost-benefit ap- trieve a previously formed value’’ (Schkade and
proaches are antidemocratic would not seem to Payne, 1993 citing Slovic Griffin and Tversky,
apply to research on value formation in a con- 1990). Schkade and Payne (1993) point out: ‘‘if
structive and deliberative setting. Deliberative and responses to CV questions are indeed constructed,
discursive processes now being studied may corre- we would expect them to be highly sensitive to
spond with similar processes that characterize features of the task and context that would influ-
value formation in civil society as well as in ence the process of construction’’. Preference-for-
consumer markets (Stern and Fineberg, 1996). mation does not seem to take place exogenously
Accordingly, methods of sociological research to the survey but is endogenous to it (Hanemann,
now being developed to measure public values by 1994).
providing opportunities for deliberation may both Experimental results confirm this expectation.
enlighten and be understood in relation to emerg- The order in which questions are asked, for exam-
ing conceptions of public choice in a democracy ple, appears to influence the amounts respondents
(Stern and Dietz, 1994). bid (Samples and Hollyer, 1990), as does the
information the survey provides (Samples et al.,
1986). Preference-reversals are observed across
7. Technical problems besetting CV experiments different response modes, such as WTP, ranking
and rating (Slovic and Lichtenstein, 1983). Re-
This paper has proposed that CV research, by searchers have also found that willingness to ac-
adopting a more deliberative, discursive and con- cept compensation to forego an environmental
structive approach to evaluating environmental improvement is paradoxically many times greater
public goods, may resolve the objection that CV than willingness to pay for that same improve-
experiments can deal only with consumer but not ment (Bishop and Heberlein, 1979; Rowe et al.,
with citizen preferences. The move toward group 1980). Various studies (Kahneman and Knetsch,
deliberation may also go far toward resolving 1992; Desvousges, 1993) demonstrate the ‘embed-
certain technical problems that vex ‘stated prefer- ding’ effect, a tendency to state much the same
ence’ methods of valuation. Critics have worried, WTP for a part of a resource as for the whole.
for example, that the survey vehicle or protocol Respondents ‘‘react to an amenity’s symbolic
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 223

meaning instead of to the specific levels of provi- Surveys are intended to function like dipsticks
sion described’’ (Mitchell and Carson, 1989; see measuring the depth of well-defined preferences in
also Kahneman and Knetsch, 1992). These transparent circumstances. A respondent to a sur-
anomalies suggest that individuals, lacking rele- vey may have a different choice in mind, however,
vant preference maps, construct them on the spot than the one the researcher ascribes to her or him.
(Fischhoff and Furby, 1988; Fischhoff, 1991; Gre- He or she may engage in all kinds of strategic or
gory, Lichtenstein and Slovic, 1991). Two ‘gaming’ behavior. ‘‘In reality’’, Oppenheim
economists conclude that ‘‘a fundamental as- (1966) has written, ‘‘questioning people is more
sumption underlying the use of CV, that people like trying to catch a particularly elusive fish, by
have well-articulated values for non-market hopefully casting different kinds of bait at differ-
goods, is simply wrong’’ (Schkade and Payne, ent depths, without knowing what is going on
1993). beneath the surface’’.
Another technical problem that vexes CV sur- This problem shows up in CV research because
veys has to do with the ambiguity of survey data data from surveys, no matter how carefully col-
with respect to preferences. This problem arises lected, must be interpreted. This requires the so-
because preferences are not observable objects. cial scientist to make assumptions about the
One might think of them as private mental states reasons that led subjects to respond as they did.
or, more accurately, as conceptual constructs of People may overstate WTP for environmental im-
microeconomic theory (Sagoff, 1994). Preference provements, for example, since ‘‘there is no cost
must be inferred from behavior. Yet behavior is to being wrong and therefore no incentive to
not self-describing; rather, a person’s motions or
undertake the mental effort to be accurate’’ (Free-
actions have to be interpreted. To interpret these
man, 1979). The researcher, therefore, is left to
motions or actions as a choice, one must already
figure out what the respondent may have had in
ascribe a preference to the agent. Without the
mind, in other words, to infer the nature of the
ascription of such a motive, the bodily motions
behavior (‘strategic bidding’) by making an as-
would make no sense. An obvious circularity
sumption about the underlying preference (‘to
arises. There are as many ways one may describe
skew the survey results’). In other words, choice is
behavior as there are preferences one may want to
infer from it. in fact inferred from preference as much as the
Respondents who are asked to state their WTP other way round.
to protect a species, for example, might be
thought to choose between its ‘existence’ value
and other goods they might buy. In fact, they may 8. The deliberative turn in CV research
frame the opportunity set differently and thus
their response may indicate a different kind of The deliberative turn in CV research may meet
choice. They may ‘purchase’ a clear conscience these kinds of objections. Consider, first, the ob-
(Kahneman and Knetsch, 1992) or the approval jection that individuals often do not possess well-
of the questioner (Bishop et al., 1986). Alterna- articulated preference orderings for public goods
tively, the same expressed WTP may indicate will- but must construct them in response to a survey
ingness to contribute to a worthy cause (Daum, instrument. This will be a problem if the survey
1993; Guagnano et al., 1994), to defray a ‘fair purports to reveal a preexisting, well-articulated
share’ of society’s cost (Stevens et al., 1991), to preference ordering. It might be an advantage,
improve the lot of future generations, or ‘‘to however, if the research instrument sought a dif-
avoid violating the rights of others, including ferent result, for example, to help respondents
non-human species’’ (Opulach and Grigalunas, construct value judgments. Even if individuals do
1992). Commentators note that CV surveys can not have well-articulated preference orderings to
easily misrepresent WTP ‘‘for a good cause as begin with, they may nonetheless reach legitimate
benefits associated with the specific commodity and reliable value choices in circumstances appro-
being described’’ (Opulach and Grigalunas, 1992). priate to making public choices. These are circum-
224 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

stances in which individuals ideally make choices conflict-resolution and group dynamics and be-
generally, i.e. as a result of deliberation, reflection havior (Whyte, 1991). The extensive literature
and social learning (Estlund, 1990). concerning focus groups, for example, should be
To put the same point differently: Socioeco- surveyed for its relevance to new methods and
nomic researchers can make a virtue of necessity developments in CV research (Morgan, 1993).
by acknowledging that the values that surveys The deliberative turn helps to resolve the prob-
elicit are to some extent artifacts of the survey lem that arises because a person’s observable be-
method. Rather than attempt to eliminate the havior can be interpreted to embody any number
artifact by ever more refined and subtle controls, of possible choices. A deliberative approach to
they may recognize that the ‘elicitation’ of prefer- CV surveys leaves it to the respondents to clarify
ence is inevitably a constructive process. Even if among themselves explicitly what they are valuing
elicited preferences are to some extent artifacts or and why. If it is a particular species or landscape,
products of the methods used to elicit them, how- for example, the deliberative group can pin down
ever, they can be stable and coherent, if these for itself precisely which aspects of the ‘public
methods enable individuals to arrive at informed good’ it values and how much; it can also set up
and well-considered value judgments. comparative valuations with the appropriate ref-
The objection that preferences are in some way erence classes, i.e. other species and other land-
endogenous to the research vehicle loses some of scapes. This provides a richer and more
its force, in other words, if the vehicle is condu- meaningful record for the policymaker. The dis-
cive to reliable and well-considered preference cursive approach also avoids ambiguity in survey
formation. Researchers may seek ways, therefore, questions. The public good and the shadow price,
to create fair and open processes of group deliber- as it were, together become the objects of determi-
ation, processes which have been thoroughly stud- nation through deliberation.
ied in other contexts (Gunderson, 1995). The use More difficult questions, which require sus-
of these processes may produce results which, tained philosophical analysis, arise concerning the
being more fully considered, are more robust and structure of deliberative methods used in the eval-
less susceptible to semantic manipulation, for ex- uation of public environmental goods. Should the
ample, to ‘framing’, ‘focus’, and ‘embedding’ ef- group as a whole strive toward a consensus valua-
fects. tion or vote on alternatives? Should the group
The recognition that deliberative and discursive seek to determine how much an environmental
processes will enable individuals in groups to con- good is worth to them, or should they try to
struct values rather than express prior preferences estimate how much society as a whole should be
may relieve economists of an unnecessary burden, willing to pay, given some idea of a ‘fair share’
the attempt to elicit responses that are not an payment? Still more questions arise if the group is
artifact of the survey process. Instead they may to consider ‘equity’ considerations, for example,
examine how the dynamics of group deliberation the question of who should pay for reducing
can generate well-considered and informed value pollution or protecting wetlands. The amount
choices (Stern, 1991). Plainly, normative, concep- people are willing to pay may vary with their
tual, and theoretical issues must be resolved if beliefs about who ought to pay, for example, for
practitioners are to succeed in introducing partici- protecting species or reducing pollution. These
patory, discursive, and deliberative techniques moral issues are relevant to socioeconomic re-
into socioeconomic experimental protocols used search.
to measure the value of public environmental
goods. Perhaps the easiest of these problems con-
cerns the rules that govern free and equal discus- 9. The relevance of democratic theory
sion in the context of group decision making.
These rules—along with appropriate institutional Alexander Hamilton, writing in Federalist Pa-
contexts—have been studied in the context of per no. 71, declared ‘‘the republican principle
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 225

demands that the deliberative sense of the com- function of the kind famously discussed by Arrow
munity should govern’’. Socioeconomic experi- (1951). In this conception, ‘‘individuals are sup-
ments that bring groups of citizens together to posed to begin with their diverse ends, desires,
deliberate in an informed way over the value of goals, or projects and then to promote them as
environmental improvements may approximate effectively as possible’’ (Estlund, 1993). Democ-
the ideal dynamics of democratic deliberation. racy becomes a special case of instrumental ratio-
Thus, those who design experimental protocols nality (Barry and Hardin, 1982). Many theorists
for eliciting environmental values may have much of this school recognized, of course, that a ratio-
to learn from the literature about democratic nal person will form his or her own choices in the
processes of group decision making. light of those that others are likely to make, so
During the past decades political theorists and that this approach to political theory can empha-
philosophers have engaged in a lively debate over size cooperation, not just competition. Harsanyi
what is meant by ‘the deliberative sense of the (1982), for example, has argued that social moral-
community’ and how it may come to control the ity arises in this context as a result of rational,
government. In this debate, two conceptions of utility-maximizing behavior. In strategic or plural-
democracy oppose each other. One treats ‘the istic conceptions of democracy, deliberation, con-
deliberative sense of the community’ simply as the sultation, cooperation, learning, and morality all
totality of the preferences of its individual mem- may figure prominently. These virtues matter,
bers. On this approach, the appropriate function however, insofar as they help individuals to deter-
of government is to aggregate these preferences, a mine their own best interests and society to serve
task for which voting is a familiar if somewhat those interests as fully as resources and technol-
inefficient mechanism. The opposing position con- ogy allow.
tends that a ‘sense of the community’ lies in the Since the 1980s, many political theorists have
considered judgments of its members about the moved away from the ‘strategic’ model toward an
common good. What is central to this conception ideal of democracy as a deliberative and coopera-
of democracy is not the act of voting so much as tive enterprise (Elster, 1986; Sunstein, 1988; Es-
the deliberative process that leads up to it, in tlund, 1993). This emphasis on deliberative,
which citizens construct and refine their judgment discursive and collegial processes of collective
about the common will in dialogue with each choice draws inspiration and support from many
other. sources, including communications theories asso-
In the 1950s and 1960s, political scientists and ciated with the Frankfurt School of sociology
theorists generally adhered to the first conception (Apel, 1980; Habermas, 1979, 1996). A second
of democracy, a ‘pluralist’ or ‘strategic’ model of source is found in the ‘civic republican’ literature
political choice based on conceptions of the indi- centering in American law schools (Michelman,
vidual found in welfare economics (Dahl, 1956; 1989; Sunstein, 1993b, 1996). A third tradition
Downs, 1956; Black, 1958; Buchanan and Tul- emphasizes ‘civic engagement’ in participatory
lock, 1962). According to this approach, ‘‘man is democracy (Putnam, 1993; Mathews, 1994;
an egoistic, rational, utility maximizer’’ (Mueller, Fishkin, 1995) and ‘civic virtue’ (Will, 1992).
1979) and possesses preference orderings which, if These positions agree in rejecting the view that
rational, conform to certain well-known formal political processes fundamentally aggregate prior
conditions (Sen, 1970). As Dietz (1994), has writ- preferences.
ten, under this rational actor model, ‘‘people try In the models of ‘civic republicanism’ or ‘par-
to maximize the benefits they receive relative to ticipatory democracy’ that oppose strategic or
the costs they bear. That is, all actors are using pluralistic approaches, citizens engage in delibera-
the same rule in deciding what action to take — tion not so that each can determine or refine his
self-interested utility maximization’’. or her own interests, but so that together they can
At its simplest, the strategic conception models discover a good that is not simply a function of
collective choice on the idea of a social welfare their individual utilities. Theorists who claim
226 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

James Madison as the American founder of this them adequate and appropriate information and
tradition cite his defense of a representational encourages them to engage in discussion and de-
system as necessary to ‘‘refine and enlarge the liberation to determine their WTP for a public
public views by passing them through the medium policy choice (Dietz, 1987, 1988, 1994). (What
of a chosen body of citizens, whose wisdom may counts as ‘adequate and appropriate’ information
discern the true interest of their country’’. Invok- is a big question and plainly requires a paper in
ing this tradition, Sunstein (1993a) writes that the itself.) Such a discursive or deliberative approach
goal of a constitutional democracy ‘‘is to ensure may have the same purpose as more conventional
discussion and debate… in a process through survey methods, i.e. to elicit WTP in order to
which reflection will encourage the emergence of quantify the value of public environmental goods
general truths’’. in monetary terms. It may be more reliable, how-
Current research in the theory of democracy ever, because individuals have the opportunity to
suggests that in voting, citizens and their represen- review their preferences in collaborative discus-
tatives may perform a cognitive task rather than sion with others.
an arithmetic one. Instead of simply aggregating Viewed in the context of the contemporary
their individual interests, they vote on a common theory of democracy, moreover, groups of in-
view of their collective interest. In other words, formed citizens convened to deliberate about the
the policy chosen is the one that a majority be- value of public goods could serve to guide public
lieves expresses the will of the community as a policy in another way. They could function not as
whole. Those who vote against a resolution are informants about their personal utilities but as
still bound by it, because they participated in the citizen-juries reaching judgments about environ-
process by which it was chosen. Participation in a mental values on the basis of argument and evi-
political community would then involve a kind of dence. Deliberative bodies of citizens could render
moral commitment to the public interest which a judgment, for example, about the value of pub-
participation in a market does not. This accounts lic environmental goods not simply to them but to
for the obligation citizens feel to obey even those society as a whole, along with a statement of the
statutes they oppose. As long as their views are ‘fair share’ they would pay as members of the
heard on the merits, rather than balanced on the community to protect those goods. Individuals
basis of WTP, citizens retain the ‘voice’ option of joined in groups to consider matters of public
a democracy rather than only the ‘exit’ option of policy, in other words, need not stop at stating
a market (Hirschman, 1981). their WTP as individuals for particular environ-
mental goods or services. They might also explain
or express their WTP in terms of a collective
10. Contingent valuation and democracy judgment (from which some, of course, may dis-
sent) about the value society ought to place on
Economists and other social scientists initially certain resources and the extent to which society
brought group discussion and deliberation into as a whole should invest in those goods rather
CVM as ways to overcome problems, such as than other public goods and services. In address-
‘framing’ and ‘embedding’ effects, that beset con- ing these questions, socioeconomic research may
ventional survey methods (Webler, 1993; Stern draw from a recent model of practical rationality,
and Dietz, 1994). These researchers soon recog- which gives social deliberation a critical role in
nized an additional benefit of deliberative meth- resolving conflicts among values (Sherman, 1989).
ods, namely, that they are more consistent with This approach takes the view that practical
the larger democratic institutions and processes choice, (1) involves a diversity of competing goods
by which society actually and legitimately makes and commitments that lack a (metric) commen-
political trade-offs. surability, (2) depends on context-sensitive per-
The deliberative and discursive turn in CV re- ception of what is normatively salient in the
search convenes individuals into groups, gives particular circumstances (Murdoch, 1970) and (3)
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 227

requires social deliberation and learning in the mation and the advice, suggestions, and
choice of ends and means-to-ends, as well as in experience of others. If this kind of social learning
the distribution of costs and benefits (Sen, 1985, conditions preference formation in markets, there
1987; Richardson, 1994; Nussbaum, 1990, 1995). seems no a priori reason to exclude it from socioe-
This approach sees group deliberation not merely conomic research into environmental values in
as an evidentiary tool or as a mechanism for experimental contexts.
collective decision making, but as a basic feature
of practical rationality. It highlights the impor-
tance of group processes for environmental policy Acknowledgements
making, suggesting a convergence between con-
temporary moral philosophy and sophisticated The author acknowledges with gratitude the
empirical research. generous support of the National Science Foun-
Economists and others involved in CV research dation, Grant No. SBR-9613495, for this re-
have responded to the concerns identified here in search. The Pew Charitable Trusts provided
a variety of ways. Many have developed sophisti- additional support under a generous grant to the
cated survey protocols, some favoring a dichoto- Institute for Philosophy and Public Policy to
mous-choice question format (Hanemann, 1986), study issues related to civic renewal in America.
others open-ended question formats (Desvousges, The views expressed in this paper are those of the
1993), referenda methods (Carson et al., 1986; author alone and not necessarily of any funding
Cameron and Huppert, 1991), bidding games and agency.
auctions (Cummings et al., 1986), and other vari-
ants in protocol design and analysis (Mitchell and
Carson, 1989; Loomis, 1990). While many of
these refinements are well worth pursuing, this References
essay has focused on one methodological innova-
Abramson, J., 1994. We, the Jury: the Jury System and the
tion that might benefit most from normative and Ideal of Democracy. Basic Books, New York.
conceptual analysis— the introduction of discur- Annis, S., Hakim P. (Eds.), 1988. Direct to the Poor: Grass-
sive and deliberative methods of valuation. roots Development in Latin America. Rienner, Boulder,
The possibility that the dynamics of group dis- CO.
Apel, Karl-Otto, 1980. Towards a transformation of philoso-
cussion and deliberation — as well as access to
phy; translated by Glyn Adey and David Frisby. London;
information—might improve the reliability of so- Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
cioeconomic research into environmental values Argyle, M., 1986. The Psychology of Happiness. Methuen,
draws on a large body of established theory in New York.
social psychology (Delbecq et al., 1975; Haber- Arrow, K.J., 1951. Social Choice and Individual Values. Wi-
ley, New York.
mas, 1984), social learning (Bandura, 1971), pub-
Bandura, A., 1971. Social Learning Theory: Motivational
lic participation (Fiorino, 1990; Laird, 1993), and Trends in Society. General Learning Press, Morristown,
group decision making processes (Burns and NY.
U8 berhorst, 1988; Clarke, 1989) in relation to envi- Barry, B., Russell, H. (Eds.), 1982. Rational Man and Irra-
ronmental problems. The introduction of a more tional Society? Sage, Beverly Hills, CA.
Bishop, G.F., Tuchfarber, A.J., Oldendick, R.W., 1986. Opin-
discursive approach to value elicitation also
ions on fictitious issues: the pressure to answer survey
makes intuitive sense. If individuals do not come questions. Public Opin. Q. 50, 240 – 250.
to CV surveys with predetermined preferences but Bishop, R.C., Heberlein, T.A., 1979. Measuring values of
must construct them, then the process of con- extramarket goods: are indirect measures biased? Am. J.
struction may legitimately involve social learning, Agric. Econ. 61, 926 – 930.
Black, D., 1958. The Theory of Elections and Committees.
since this is precisely what occurs in other con-
Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
texts in which people work out their values. In Buchanan, J.M., Tullock, G., 1962. The Calculus of Consent,
markets, for example, individuals construct pref- Logical Foundations of Constitutional Democracy. Uni-
erences for goods over time in response to infor- versity of Michigan Press, Ann Arbor, MI.
228 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

Buell, J., Sustainable Democracy: Individuality and the Poli- Dietz, T., 1988. Social impact assessment as applied human
tics of the Environment. Sage, Thousand Oaks, CA. ecology: integrating theory and method. In: Borden, R.,
Burns, T.R., U8 berhorst, R., 1988. Creative Democracy: Sys- Jacogs, J., Young, G.R. (eds.) Human Ecology: Research
temic Conflict Resolution and Policymaking in a World of and Applications. Society for Human Ecology, College
High Science and Technology. Praeger, New York. Park, MD, pp. 220 – 227.
Cameron, T.A., Huppert, D.D., 1991. Referendum contingent Dietz, T., 1994. What should we do? Human ecology and
valuation estimates: sensitivity to the assignment of offered collective decision making. Human Eco. Rev. 1 (2), 301 –
values. J. Am. Stat. Assoc. 86, 910–918. 309.
Carson, R.T., Hanemann, W.M., Mitchell, R.C., 1986. Deter- Downs, A., 1956. An Economic Theory of Democracy. Harper
mining the Demand for Public Goods by Simulating Refer- and Row, New York.
endums at Different Tax Prices (manuscript). University of Easterlin, R., 1995. Will raising the incomes of all increase the
happiness of all? J. Econ. Behav. Organ. 27, 35 – 48.
California, San Diego, CA.
Edwards, S.F., 1986. Ethical preferences and the measurement
Carson, R.T. et al., 1994. A Bibliography of Contingent
of existence values: does the neoclassical model fit? North-
Valuation Studies and Papers, Natural Resource Damage
eastern J. Agric. Resource Econ. 15, 145 – 159.
Assessment, Inc., La Jolla, CA.
Elster, J., 1986. The Market and the Forum: Three Varieties of
Christiano, T., 1995. Voting and democracy. Can. J. Philos. 25
Political Theory. In: Elster J., Hylland A. (Eds.), Founda-
(3), 395 – 414. tions of Social Choice Theory. Cambridge University
Clarke, L., 1989. Acceptable Risk? Making Decisions in a Press, New York. pp. 111 – 112.
Toxic Environment. University of California Press, Berke- Elster, J. 1989. Solomonic Judgments: Studies in the Limita-
ley, CA. tions of Rationality. Cambridge University Press, Cam-
Cohen, J., 1986. An epistemic conception of democracy. Ethics bridge.
97, 27 – 40. Estlund, D., 1990. Democracy without preference. Philos. Rev.
Cohen, J., 1989. Deliberation and Democratic Legitimacy. In: 99 (3), 397 – 423.
Hamlin, A., Pettit, P. (Eds.). In: The Good Polity: Norma- Estlund, D., 1993. Who’s afraid of deliberative democracy.
tive Analysis of the State. Blackwell, Oxford. Tex. Law Rev. 71, 1437 – 1477.
Cowen, T., 1992. Introduction. Public Goods and Market Fiorino, D., 1990. Making Environmental Policy. University
Failures. Transaction, New Brunswick, NJ. of California Press, Berkeley, CA.
Cropper, M.L., Oates, W.E., 1992. Environmental economics: Fischhoff, B., 1991. Value elicitation: is there anything in
a survey. J. Econ. Lit. 30, 675–740. there? Am. Psychol. 46, 835 – 847.
Cummings, R.G., Brookshire, D.S., Schultze W.D. (Eds.), Fischhoff, B., Furby, L., 1988. Measuring values: a conceptual
1986. Valuing Environmental Goods: A State of the Arts framework for interpreting transactions with special refer-
Assessment of the Contingent Method. Roman and Allan- ence to contingent valuation of visibility. J. Risk Uncer-
held, Totowa, NJ. tain. 1, 147 – 184.
Dahl, R., 1956. A Preface to Democratic Theory. University Fishkin, J.S., 1995. The Voice of the People: Public Opinion
of Chicago Press Chicago, IL. and Democracy. Yale University Press, New Haven, CT.
Daum, J., 1993. Some legal and regulatory aspects of contin- Freeman, A.M., III. 1979. The benefits of environmental
gent valuation. In Hausman, J.A. (Ed.), Contingent Valua- improvement: theory and practice. Resources for the Fu-
tion: A Critical Assessment. North Holland, Amsterdam, ture. Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD.
pp. 389 – 416. Freeman, A.M., III. 1993. The Measurement of Environmen-
tal and Resource Values. Resources for the Future. Wash-
Delbecq, A.L., van de Ven, A.H., Gustafson, D.H., 1975.
ington, DC.
Group Techniques for Program Planning: A Guide to the
Gregory, R., Lichtenstein, S., Slovic, P., 1991. Valuing Envi-
Nominal Group and Delphi Process. Scott-Foresman,
ronmental Resources: A Constructive Approach, Journal
Glenview, IL.
of Risk and Uncertainty, 7(2), October 1993, 177 – 197.
Desvousges, W.H., Reed Johnson, F., Dunford, R.W., Boyle,
Guagnano, G.A., Dietz, T., Stern, P.C., 1994. Willingness to
K.J., Hudson, S.P., Wilson, K.N., 1993. Measuring natural pay: a test of the contribution model. Psychol. Sci. 5,
resource damages with contingent valuation: tests of valid- 411 – 415.
ity and reliability. In: Hausman, J.A. (Ed.), Contingent Gunderson, A.G., 1995. The Environmental Promise of Dem-
Valuation: A Critical Assessment. North Holland, Amster- ocratic Deliberation. University of Wisconsin Press,
dam, pp. 91 – 164. Madison, WI.
Diamond, P.A., Hausman, J.A., Leonard, G.K., Denning, Habermas, J., 1979. Communication and the Evolution of
M.A., 1993. Does contingent valuation measure prefer- Society. Beacon Press, Boston.
ences? Experimental evidence. In: Hausman, J.A. (Ed.), Habermas, J., 1982. Critical Debates. Thompson J.B., Held D.
Contingent Valuation: A Critical Assessment. North Hol- (Eds.). MIT Press, Cambridge, MA.
land, Amsterdam, pp. 41–90. Habermas, J., 1984. The Theory of Communicative Action,
Dietz, T., 1987. Theory and method in social impact assess- vol. 1 Reason and the Rationalization of Society. Beacon
ment. Sociol. Inq. 57, 54–69. Press, Boston.
M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230 229

Habermas, J., 1996. Justification and Application: Remarks on Machan, T., 1984. Pollution and political theory. In: Tom
Discourse Ethics (C. Cronin, Trans.). MIT Press, Cam- Regan (Ed.), Earthbound: New Introductory Essays in
bridge, MA. Political and Social Philosophy. Random, New York, pp.
Hanemann, W.M., 1986. Implications from Biometrics for the 74 – 106.
Design of Dichotomous Choice Contingent Valuation March, J.G., 1994. A Primer in Decision Making. The Free
Markets. Paper presented at the United States Department Press, New York.
of Agriculture Conference of Research Issues in Resource Mathews, D., 1994. Politics for People: Finding a Responsible
Decisions Involving Marketed and Nonmarketed Goods, Public Voice. University of Illinois Press, Urbana, IL.
San Diego, California. Michelman, F., 1989. Conceptions of democracy in American
Hanemann, W.M., 1994. Valuing the environment through constitutional argument: the case of pornography regula-
contingent valuation. J. Econ. Perspect. 8, 19–43. tion. Tenn. Law Rev. 56, 293 – 294.
Hans, V.P., Vidmar, N., 1986. Judging the Jury. Plenum, New Mitchell, R.C., Carson, R.T., 1989. Using Surveys to Value
York. Public Goods: The Contingent Valuation Method. Re-
Harsanyi, J., 1982. Morality and the theory of rational behav- sources For the Future, Washington, DC.
ior. In: Sen, A., Williams, B., (Eds.), Utilitarianism and Morgan, D. (Ed.), 1993. Successful Focus Groups: Advancing
Beyond. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge. the State of the Art. Sage, Newbury Park, CA.
Hastie, R., Penrod, S., Pennington, N., 1983. Inside the Jury. Mueller, D., 1979. Public Choice. Cambridge University Press,
Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. New York.
Hirschman, A.O., 1981. Exit, Voice and Loyalty: Responses to Murdoch, I., 1970. The Sovereignty of the Good. Routledge
Decline in Firms, Organizations and States. Harvard Uni- and Kegan Paul, London.
versity Press, Cambridge, MA. Norton, B.G., Hutchins, M., Stevens, E.F., Maple, T.L.
Hausman, J.A. (Ed.), 1993. Contingent Valuation: A Critical (Eds.), 1995. Ethics on the Ark: Zoos, Animal Welfare and
Assessment. North Holland, Amsterdam. Wildlife Conservation. Smithsonian Institute, Washington,
Kahneman, D. 1986. Comments. In: Cummings, R.G., Brook- DC.
shire, D.S., Schulze, W.D. (Eds), Valuing Environmental Nussbaum, M., 1990. The Discernment of Perception: An
Goods: An Assessment of the Contingent Valuation Aristotelian Conception of Private and Public Rationality.
Method. Rowman & Allanheld, Totowa, NJ. In: Nussbaum, M. (Ed.), Love’s Knowledge: Essays on
Kahneman, D., Varey, C., 1991. Notes on the psychology of Philosophy and Literature. Oxford University Press, New
utility. In: Elster, J., Roemer, J. (Eds.), Interpersonal Com- York.
parisons of Well-Being. Cambridge University Press, New Nussbaum, M., 1995. Poetic Justice. Beacon Press, Boston.
York, pp. 127 – 163. Oppenheim, A.N. 1966. Questionnaire Design and Attitude
Kahneman, D., Knetsch, J.L., 1992. Valuing public goods: the Measurement. Basic Books, New York.
purchase of moral satisfaction. J. Environ. Econ. Manag. Opulach, J.J., Grigalunas, T.A., 1992. Ethical Values and
22, 57 – 70. Personal Preference as Determinants of Non-use Values:
Kalven, H., Zeisel, H., 1966. The American Jury. Little, Implications for Natural Resource Damage Assessments.
Brown, Boston, MA. Department of Resource Economics Staff Paper. Univer-
Kant, I., 1959. Foundations of the Metaphysics of Morals sity of Rhode Island.
(L.W. Beck, Trans.). Bobbs-Merrill, Indianapolis, IN. Perrings, et al., 1995. Economic Values of Biodiversity. In:
Keeney, R.L., Raifa, H., 1980. Decisions with Multiple Objec- Heywood, V.H. (Ed.). Global Biodiversity Asssessment.
tives: Preferences and Value Tradeoffs. Wiley, New York. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp. 823 – 914.
Keeney, R.L., 1992. Value-Focused Thinking: A Path to Cre- Posner, R., 1981. The Economics of Justice. Harvard Univer-
ative Decision Making. Harvard University Press, Cam- sity Press, Cambridge, MA.
bridge, MA. Putnam, R.D., Leonardi R., Nanetti, R., 1993. Making
Kneese, A.V., Bower, B.T., 1972. Introduction. In: Kneese, Democracy Work: Civic Traditions in Modern Italy.
A.V., Bower B.T., (Eds.), Environmental Quality Analysis. Princeton University Press, Princeton, NJ.
Johns Hopkins Press, Baltimore, MD. Renn, O., Webler, T., Wiedemann, P. (Eds.), 1995. Fairness
Krutilla, J., 1967. Conservation reconsidered. Am. Econ. Rev. and Competence in Citizen Participation: Evaluating Mod-
57 (4), 777 – 786. els for Environmental Discourse. Kluwer, Dordrecht.
Laird, F., 1993. Participatory analysis, democracy and techno- Renn, O., Webler, T., Wiedemann, P., 1995. Novel Ap-
logical decision making. Sci. Technol. Human Values 18, proaches to Public Participation in Environmental Deci-
341 – 361. sion Making. Kluwer, Amsterdam.
Leonard, H., Zeckhauser, R., 1986. Cost-benefit analysis ap- Rescher, N., 1980. Unpopular Essays on Technological Pro-
plied to risks: its philosophy and legitimacy. In: MacLean, gress, University of Pittsburgh Press, Pittsburgh.
D. (Ed.), Values at Risk. Rowman & Littlefield, Totowa, Richardson, H.S., 1994. Practical Reasoning About Final
NJ, pp. 31 – 48. Ends. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge.
Loomis, J.B., 1990. Comparative reliability of the dichoto- Rowe, R.D., d’Arge, R.C., Brookshire, D.S., 1980. An experi-
mous choice and open-ended contingent valuation tech- ment on the economic value of visibility. J. Environ. Econ.
niques. J. Environ. Econ. Manag. 18, 78–85. Manage. 7, 1 – 19.
230 M. Sagoff / Ecological Economics 24 (1998) 213–230

Sagoff, M., 1994. Should preferences count? Land Econ. 70 Slovic, P., Griffin, D., Tversky, A., 1990. Compatibility effects
(2), 127 – 144. in judgment and choice. In: Hogarth, R.M. (Ed.), Insights
Samples, K., Dixon, J., Gowen, M., 1986. Information disclo- in Decision Making: A Tribute to Hillel J. Einhorn. Uni-
sure and endangered species evaluation. Land Econ. 62, versity of Chicago Press, Chicago.
306 – 312. Stern, P.C., 1991. Learning through conflict: a realistic ap-
Samples, K. Hollyer, P., 1990. Contingent valuation of wildlife proach to risk communication. Policy Sci. 24, 99 – 119.
resources in the presence of substitutes and complements. Stern, P.C., Dietz, T., 1994. The value basis of environmental
In: Johnson, R.L., Johnson, G.V. (Eds.), Economic Valua- concern. J. Social Issues 50, 65 – 84.
tion of Natural Resources. Westview Press, Boulder, CO, Stern, P.C., Fineberg, H.V. (Eds.), 1996. Understanding Risk:
pp. 177 – 192. Informing Decisions in a Democratic Society. National
Samuelson, P., 1947. Foundations of Economic Analysis. Har- Academy Press, Washington, DC.
vard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Stevens, T.H., Echeverria, J., Glass, R.J., Hager, T., Moore,
Schelling, T.C., 1983. Preface. In: Schelling, T.C. (Ed.), Incen- T.A., 1991. Measuring the existence value of wildlife: what
tives for Environmental Protection. MIT Press, Cam- do CVM estimates really show? Land Econ. 67, 390 – 400.
bridge, MA. Stevens, T.H., More, T.A., Glass, R., 1993. Measuring the
Schkade, D.A., Payne, J.W., 1993. Where do the numbers existence value of wildlife: reply. Land Econ. 69, 309 – 312.
come from? how people respond to contingent valuation Stokey, E., Zeckhauser, R., 1978. A Primer for Policy Analy-
questions. In: Hausman, J.A. (Ed.), Contingent Valuation: sis. Norton, New York.
A Critical Assessment. North Holland Press, Amsterdam, Sunstein, C., 1988. Beyond the republican revival. Yale Law J.
pp. 271 – 304 97, 1539 – 1570.
Schkade, D.A., Payne, J.W., 1994. How people respond to Sunstein, C., 1993a. The Partial Constitution. Harvard Uni-
contingent valuation questions: a verbal protocol analysis versity Press, Cambridge, MA.
of willingness to pay for an environmental regulation. J. Sunstein, C., 1993b. Democracy and the Problem of Free
Environ. Econ. Manage. 26, 88–109. Speech. The Free Press, New York.
Sen, A., 1970. Collective Choice and Social Welfare. Holden- Sunstein, C., 1996. Earl Warren is dead. New Repub. May 13,
Day, San Francisco. 35 – 39.
Sen, A., 1977. Rational fools: a critique of the behavioral Webler, T., 1993. Habermas put into practice: a democratic
foundations of economic theory. Philos. Public Affairs 6 discourse for environmental problem solving. In: Crossing
(4), 327 – 344. Boundaries: New Directions in Human Ecology. Society
Sen, A., 1985. Well-being, Agency and Freedom: The Dewey for Human Ecology, Salt Lake City, UT.
Lectures 1984. J. Philos. 82. Webler, T., Kastenholz H., Renn, O., 1995. Public Participa-
Sen, A., 1987. On Ethics and Economics. Blackwell, Oxford. tion in Impact Assessment: A Social Learning Perspective,
Sherman, N., 1989. The Fabric of Character: Aristotle’s The- Environ. Impact Assess. Rev.15, 443 – 463.
ory of Virtue. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Whyte, W.(Ed.), 1991. Participatory Action Research. Sage,
Shklar, J., 1991. American Citizenship: The Quest for Inclu- Newbury Park, CA.
sion. Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA. Will, George. 1992. Restoration: Congress, Term Limits and
Slovic, P., Lichtenstein, S., 1983. Preference reversals: a the Recovery of Deliberative Democracy. The Free Press,
broader perspective. Am. Econ. Rev. 73, 596–605. New York.

You might also like