You are on page 1of 8

5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

Musical analysis
Musical  analysis "is the means of answering directly the question 'How does it
work?'."(Bent 1987, 5) The method employed to answer this question, and indeed
exactly what is meant by the question, differs from analyst to analyst, and according to
the purpose of the analysis. According to Ian Bent (1987, 6), "its emergence as an
approach and method can be traced back to the 1750s. However it existed as a scholarly
tool, albeit an auxiliary one, from the Middle Ages onwards." Adolf Bernhard Marx was
influential in formalising concepts about composition and music understanding
towards the second half of the 19th century (Pederson 2001).

The principle of analysis has been variously criticized, especially by composers, such as
Edgard Varèse's claim that, "to explain by means of [analysis] is to decompose, to mutilate the spirit of a work" (quoted
in Bernard 1981, 1).

Contents
Analyses
Techniques
Discretization
Composition
Analytical situations
Compositional analysis
Perceptual analysis
Analyses of the immanent level
Nonformalized analyses
Formalized analyses
Intermediary analyses
Divergent analyses
See also
References
Further reading
External links

Analyses
Some analysts, such as Donald Francis Tovey (whose Essays  in  Musical  Analysis are among the most accessible
musical analyses) have presented their analyses in prose. Others, such as Hans Keller (who devised a technique he
called Functional Analysis) used no prose commentary at all in some of their work.

There have been many notable analysts other than Tovey and Keller. One of the best known and most influential was
Heinrich Schenker, who developed Schenkerian analysis, a method that seeks to describe all tonal classical works as
elaborations ("prolongations") of a simple contrapuntal sequence. Ernst Kurth coined the term of "developmental
motif". Rudolph Réti is notable for tracing the development of small melodic motifs through a work, while Nicolas
Ruwet's analysis amounts to a kind of musical semiology.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 1/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

Musicologists associated with the new musicology often use musical analysis (traditional or not) along with or to
support their examinations of the performance practice and social situations in which music is produced and that
produce music, and vice versa. Insights from the social considerations may then yield insight into analysis methods.

Edward Cone (1989,) argues that musical analysis lies in between description and prescription. Description consists of
simple non-analytical activities such as labeling chords with Roman numerals or tone-rows with integers or row-form,
while the other extreme, prescription, consists of "the insistence upon the validity of relationships not supported by the
text." Analysis must, rather, provide insight into listening without forcing a description of a piece that cannot be heard.

Techniques
Many techniques are used to analyze music. Metaphor and figurative description may be a part of analysis, and a
metaphor used to describe pieces, "reifies their features and relations in a particularly pungent and insightful way: it
makes sense of them in ways not formerly possible." (Guck 1994, 71) Even absolute music may be viewed as a,
"metaphor for the universe," or nature as, "perfect form" (Dahlhaus 1989, 8, 29 cited in Bauer 2004, 131).

Discretization
The process of analysis often involves breaking the piece down into relatively simpler and smaller parts. Often, the way
these parts fit together and interact with each other is then examined. This process of discretization or segmentation is
often considered, as by Jean-Jacques Nattiez (1990), necessary for music to become accessible to analysis. Fred
Lerdahl (1992, 112–13) argues that discretization is necessary even for perception by learned listeners, thus making it a
basis of his analyses, and finds pieces such as Artikulation by György Ligeti inaccessible (Lerdahl 1988, 235) while
Rainer Wehinger (1970) created a "Hörpartitur" or "score for listening" for the piece, representing different sonorous
effects with specific graphic symbols much like a transcription.

Composition
Analysis often displays a compositional impulse while compositions often "display an analytical impulse" (BaileyShea
2007, [8]) but "though intertextual analyses often succeed through simple verbal description there are good reasons to
literally compose the proposed connections. We actually hear how these songs [different musical settings of Goethe's
Nur  wer  die  Sehnsucht  kennt] resonate with one another, comment upon and affect one another [...] in a way, the
music speaks for itself" (BaileyShea 2007, [7]). This analytic bent is obvious in recent trends in popular music
including the mash-ups of various songs [see (BaileyShea 2007, [8])].

Analytical situations
Analysis is an activity most often engaged in by musicologists and most often applied to western classical music,
although music of non-western cultures and of unnotated oral traditions is also often analysed. An analysis can be
conducted on a single piece of music, on a portion or element of a piece or on a collection of pieces. A musicologist's
stance is his or her analytical situation. This includes the physical dimension or corpus being studied, the level of
stylistic relevance studied, and whether the description provided by the analysis is of its immanent structure,
compositional (or poietic) processes, perceptual (or esthesic) processes (Nattiez 1990, 135–36), all three, or a mixture.

Stylistic levels may be hierarchized as an inverted triangle:

universals of music

system (style) of reference

style of a genre or an epoch

style of composer X

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 2/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

style of a period in the life of a composer

work

(Nattiez 1990, 136, who also points to Nettl 1964, 177, Boretz 1972, 146, and Meyer)

Nattiez outlines six analytical situations, preferring the sixth:

Poietic Immanent structures Esthesic


processes of the work processes
1 ♦
Immanent analysis
2 ♦ ← ♦
Inductive poietics
3 ♦ → ♦
External poietics
4 ♦ → ♦
Inductive esthesics
5 ♦ ← ♦
External esthesics
6 ♦ ←→ ♦ ←→ ♦
Communication between the three levels

(Nattiez 1990, 140)

Examples:

1. "...tackles only the immanent configuration of the work." Allen Forte's musical set theory
2. "...proceed[s] from an analysis of the neutral level to drawing conclusions about the poietic." Reti (1951, 194–206),
analysis of Debussy's la Cathédrale engloutie
3. The reverse of the previous, taking "a poietic document—letters, plans, sketches— ... and analyzes the work in
the light of this information." Paul Mie (1929), "stylistic analysis of Beethoven in terms of the sketches"
4. The most common, grounded in "perceptive introspection, or in a certain number of general ideas concerning
musical perception ... a musicologist ... describes what they think is the listener's perception of the passage"
Meyer (1956, 48), analysis of measures 9–11 of Bach's C minor fugue in Book I of the Well-Tempered Clavier
5. "Begins with information collected from listeners to attempt to understand how the work has been perceived ...
obviously how experimental psychologists would work"
6. "The case in which an immanent analysis is equally relevant to the poietic as to the esthesic." Schenkerian
analysis, which, based on the sketches of Beethoven (external poietics) eventually show through analysis how the
works must be played and perceived (inductive esthesics)

Compositional analysis
Jacques Chailley (1951, 104) views analysis entirely from a compositional viewpoint, arguing that, "since analysis
consists of 'putting oneself in the composer's shoes,' and explaining what he was experiencing as he was writing, it is
obvious that we should not think of studying a work in terms of criteria foreign to the author's own preoccupations, no
more in tonal analysis than in harmonic analysis."

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 3/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

Perceptual analysis
On the other hand, Fay (1971, 112) argues that, "analytic discussions of music are often concerned with processes that
are not immediately perceivable. It may be that the analyst is concerned merely with applying a collection of rules
concerning practice, or with the description of the compositional process. But whatever he [or she] aims, he often fails
-- most notably in twentieth-century music -- to illuminate our immediate musical experience," and thus views analysis
entirely from a perceptual viewpoint, as does Edward Cone (1960, 36), "true analysis works through and for the ear.
The greatest analysts are those with the keenest ears; their insights reveal how a piece of music should be heard, which
in turn implies how it should be played. An analysis is a direction for performance," and Thomson (1970, 196): "It
seems only reasonable to believe that a healthy analytical point of view is that which is so nearly isomorphic with the
perceptual act."

Analyses of the immanent level


Analyses of the immanent level include analyses by Alder, Heinrich Schenker, and the "ontological structuralism" of
the analyses of Pierre Boulez, who says in his analysis of The Rite of Spring (Boulez 1966, 142), "must I repeat here that
I have not pretended to discover a creative process, but concern myself with the result, whose only tangibles are
mathematical relationships? If I have been able to find all these structural characteristics, it is because they are there,
and I don't care whether they were put there consciously or unconsciously, or with what degree of acuteness they
informed [the composer's] understanding of his conception; I care very little for all such interaction between the work
and 'genius.'"

Again, Nattiez (1990, 138–39) argues that the above three approaches, by themselves, are necessarily incomplete and
that an analysis of all three levels is required. Jean Molino (1975a, 50–51) shows that musical analysis shifted from an
emphasis upon the poietic vantage point to an esthesic one at the beginning of the eighteenth century (Nattiez 1990,
137).

Nonformalized analyses
Nattiez distinguishes between nonformalized and formalized analyses. Nonformalized analyses, apart from musical
and analytical terms, do not use resources or techniques other than language. He further distinguishes nonformalized
analyses between impressionistic, paraphrases, or hermeneutic readings of the text (explications  de  texte).
Impressionistic analyses are in "a more or less high-literary style, proceeding from an initial selection of elements
deemed characteristic," such as the following description of the opening of Claude Debussy's Prelude to the Afternoon
of a Faun: "The alternation of binary and ternary divisions of the eighth notes, the sly feints made by the three pauses,
soften the phrase so much, render it so fluid, that it escapes all arithmetical rigors. It floats between heaven and earth
like a Gregorian chant; it glides over signposts marking traditional divisions; it slips so furtively between various keys
that it frees itself effortlessly from their grasp, and one must await the first appearance of a harmonic underpinning
before the melody takes graceful leave of this causal atonality" (Vuillermoz 1957, 64).

Paraphrases are a "respeaking" in plain words of the events of the text with little interpretation or addition, such as the
following description of the "Bourée" of Bach's Third Suite: "An anacrusis, an initial phrase in D major. The figure
marked (a) is immediately repeated, descending through a third, and it is employed throughout the piece. This phrase
is immediately elided into its consequent, which modulates from D to A major. This figure (a) is used again two times,
higher each time; this section is repeated" (Warburton 1952, 151).

"Hermeneutic reading of a musical text is based on a description, a 'naming' of the melody's elements, but adds to it a
hermeneutic and phenomenological depth that, in the hands of a talented writer, can result in genuine interpretive
masterworks.... All the illustrations in Abraham's and Dahlhaus's Melodielehre (1972) are historical in character;
Rosen's essays in The  Classical  Style (1971) seek to grasp the essence of an epoch's style; Meyer's analysis of
Beethoven's Farewell Sonata (1973: 242-68) penetrates melody from the vantage point of perceived structures." He

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 4/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

gives as a last example the following description of Franz Schubert's Unfinished Symphony: "The transition from first
to second subject is always a difficult piece of musical draughtsmanship; and in the rare cases where Schubert
accomplishes it with smoothness, the effort otherwise exhausts him to the verge of dullness (as in the slow movement
of the otherwise great A minor Quartet). Hence, in his most inspired works the transition is accomplished by an abrupt
coup de théâtre; and of all such coups, no doubt the crudest is that in the Unfinished Symphony. Very well then; here is
a new thing in the history of the symphony, not more new, not more simple than the new things which turned up in
each of Beethoven's nine. Never mind its historic origin, take it on its merits. Is it not a most impressive moment?"
(Tovey 1978, 213–1990, 162–163).

Formalized analyses
Formalized analyses propose models for melodic functions or simulate music. Meyer distinguishes between global
models, which "provide an image of the whole corpus being studied, by listing characteristics, classifying phenomena,
or both; they furnish statistical evaluation," and linear models which "do not try to reconstitute the whole melody in
order of real time succession of melodic events. Linear models ... describe a corpus by means of a system of rules
encompassing not only the hierarchical organization of the melody, but also the distribution, environment, and context
of events, examples including the explanation of "succession of pitches in New Guinean chants in terms of
distributional constraints governing each melodic interval" by Chenoweth (1972, 1979), the transformational analysis
by Herndon (1974, 1975), and the "grammar for the soprano part in Bach's chorales [which,] when tested by computer
... allows us to generate melodies in Bach's style" by Baroni and Jacoboni (1976,).

Global models are further distinguished as analysis by traits, which "identify the presence or absence of a particular
variable, and makes a collective image of the song, genre, or style being considered by means of a table, or
classificatory analysis, which sorts phenomena into classes," one example being "trait listing" by Helen Roberts (1955,
222), and classificatory analysis, which "sorts phenomena into classes," examples being the universal system for
classifying melodic contours by Kolinski (1956). Classificatory analyses often call themselves taxonomical. "Making the
basis for the analysis explicit is a fundamental criterion in this approach, so delimiting units is always accompanied by
carefully defining units in terms of their constituent variables." Nattiez (1990, 164)

Intermediary analyses
Nattiez lastly proposes intermediary models "between reductive formal precision, and impressionist laxity." These
include Schenker, Meyer (classification of melodic structure in Meyer 1973, chapter 7), Narmour, and Lerdahl-
Jackendoff's "use of graphics without appealing to a system of formalized rules," complementing and not replacing the
verbal analyses. These are in contrast to the formalized models of Babbitt (1972) and Boretz (1969). According to
Nattiez, Boretz "seems to be confusing his own formal, logical model with an immanent essence he then ascribes to
music," and Babbitt "defines a musical theory as a hypothetical-deductive system ... but if we look closely at what he
says, we quickly realize that the theory also seeks to legitimize a music yet to come; that is, that it is also normative ...
transforming the value of the theory into an aesthetic norm ... from an anthropological standpoint, that is a risk that is
difficult to countenance." Similarly, "Boretz enthusiastically embraces logical formalism, while evading the question of
knowing how the data—whose formalization he proposes—have been obtained" (Nattiez 1990, 167).

Divergent analyses
Typically a given work is analyzed by more than one person and different or divergent analyses are created. For
instance, the first two bars of the prelude to Claude Debussy's Pelléas et Mélisande:

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 5/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

Debussy Pelleas et Melisande prelude opening.  Play 

are analyzed differently by Leibowitz (1971), Laloy, van Appledorn, and Christ (1966). Leibowitz analyses this
succession harmonically as D minor:I-VII-V, ignoring melodic motion, Laloy analyses the succession as D:I-V, seeing
the G in the second measure as an ornament, and both van Appledorn and Christ (1966,) analyses the succession as
D:I-VII.

Nattiez (1990, 173) argues that this divergence is due to the analysts' respective analytic situations, and to what he calls
transcendent principles (1997b: 853, what George Holton might call "themata"), the "philosophical project[s]",
"underlying principles", or a prioris of analyses, one example being Nattiez's use of the tripartitional definition of sign,
and what, after epistemological historian Paul Veyne, he calls plots.

Van Appledorn sees the succession as D:I-VII so as to allow the interpretation of the first chord in measure five, which
Laloy sees as a dominant seventh on D (V/IV) with a diminished fifth (despite that the IV doesn't arrive till measure
twelve), while van Appledorn sees it as a French sixth on D, D-F♯-Ab-[C] in the usual second inversion. This means
that D is the second degree and the required reference to the first degree, C, being established by the D:VII or C major
chord. "The need to explain the chord in measure five establishes that C-E-G is 'equally important' as the D-(F)-A of
measure one." Leibowitz (1971,) gives only the bass for chord, E indicating the progression I-II an "unreal" progression
in keeping with his "dialectic between the real and the unreal" used in the analysis, while Christ explains the chord as
an augmented eleventh with a bass of B♭, interpreting it as a traditional tertian extended chord.

Debussy's Pélleas et Mélisande prelude, measures 5–6.  Play 

Not only does an analyst select particular traits, they arrange them according to a plot [intrigue].... Our sense of the
component parts of a musical work, like our sense of historical 'facts,' is mediated by lived experience." (176)

While John Blacking (1973, 17–18), among others, holds that "there is ultimately only one explanation and ... this could
be discovered by a context-sensitive analysis of the music in culture," according to Nattiez (1990: 168) and others,
"there is never only  one  valid musical analysis for any given work." Blacking gives as example: "everyone disagrees

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 6/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

hotly and stakes his [or her] academic reputation on what Mozart really meant in this or that bar of his symphonies,
concertos, or quartets. If we knew exactly what went on inside Mozart's mind when he wrote them, there could be only
one explanation". (93) However, Nattiez points out that even if we could determine "what Mozart was thinking" we
would still be lacking an analysis of the neutral and esthesic levels.

Roger Scruton (1978, 175–76), in a review of Nattiez's Fondements, says one may, "describe it as you like so long as you
hear it correctly ... certain descriptions suggest wrong ways of hearing it ... what is obvious to hear [in Pélleas et
Mélisande] is the contrast in mood and atmosphere between the 'modal' passage and the bars which follow it." Nattiez
counters that if compositional intent were identical to perception, "historians of musical language could take a
permanent nap.... Scruton sets himself up as a universal, absolute conscience for the 'right' perception of the Pélleas et
Mélisande. But hearing is an active symbolic process (which must be explained): nothing in perception is self­evident."

Thus Nattiez suggests that analyses, especially those intending "a semiological orientation, should ... at least include a
comparative critique of already-written analyses, when they exist, so as to explain why the work has taken on this or
that image constructed by this or that writer: all analysis is a representation; [and] an explanation of the analytical
criteria used in the new analysis, so that any critique of this new analysis could be situated in relation to that analysis's
own objectives and methods. As Jean-Claude Gardin so rightly remarks, 'no physicist, no biologist is surprised when
asked to indicate, in the context of a new theory, the physical data and the mental operations that led to its
formulation' Gardin (1974, 69). Making one's procedures explicit would help to create a cumulative  progress  in
knowledge." (177)

See also
List of music software (Section: Music analysis software)

References
Babbitt, Milton. 1972. "Contemporary Music Composition and Music Theory as Contemporary Intellectual History".
In Perspectives in Musicology: The Inaugural Lectures of the Ph. D. Program in Music at the City University of
New York, edited by Barry S. Brook, Edward Downes, and Sherman Van Solkema, 270–307. New York: W. W.
Norton. ISBN 0-393-02142-4. Reprinted, New York: Pendragon Press, 1985. ISBN 0-918728-50-9.
BaileyShea, Matt (2007). "Filleted Mignon: A New Recipe for Analysis and Recomposition (http://mto.societymusic
theory.org/issues/mto.07.13.4/mto.07.13.4.baileyshea.html#FN3REF)". Music Theory Online 13, no. 4
(December).
Bauer, Amy (2004). "'Tone-Color, Movement, Changing Harmonic Planes': Cognition, Constraints, and Conceptual
Blends in Modernist Music", in The Pleasure of Modernist Music: Listening, Meaning, Intention, Ideology, edited by
Arved Ashby, 121–52. Eastman Studies in Music 29. Rochester: University of Rochester Press; Woodbridge:
Boydell and Brewer, Ltd. ISBN 1-58046-143-3.
Bent, Ian (1987). Analysis. London: McMillan Press. ISBN 0-333-41732-1.
Bernard, Jonathan. 1981. "Pitch/Register in the Music of Edgar Varèse." Music Theory Spectrum 3:1–25.
Blacking, John (1973). How Musical Is Man?. Seattle: University of Washington Press. Cited in Nattiez (1990).
Boretz, Benjamin. 1969. "Meta-Variations: Studies in the Foundationbs of Musical Thought (I)". Perspectives of
New Music 8, no. 1 (Fall–Winter): 1–74.
Boretz, Benjamin. 1972. "Meta-Variations, Part IV: Analytic Fallout (I)". Perspectives of New Music 11, no. 1 (Fall–
Winter): 146–223.
Chailley, Jacques. 1951. La musique médiévale, with a preface by Gustave Cohen. Les grands musiciens 1.
Paris: Coudrier.
Chenoweth. 1972..
Christ, William (1966), Materials and Structure of Music (1 ed.), Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall, ISBN 0-13-
560342-0, OCLC 412237 (https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/412237) LCC MT6 M347 1966 (https://catalog.loc.gov/vw
ebv/search?searchCode=CALL%2B&searchArg=MT6+M347+1966&searchType=1&recCount=25). Cited in
Nattiez (1990).
Cone, Edward. 1989. "Analysis Today". In Music: A View from Delft, edited by, 39–54. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press. ISBN 978-0-226-11470-5; ISBN 978-0-226-11469-9. Cited in Satyendra.
Dahlhaus, Carl. 1989. The Idea of Absolute Music, translated by Roger Lustig. Chicago and London: University of
Chicago Press.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 7/8
5/11/2018 Musical analysis - Wikipedia

Guck, Marion A. (1994). "Rehabilitating the incorrigible", Theory, Analysis and Meaning in Music, ed. Anthony
Pople. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press:57-74.
Laloy, L. (1902). "Sur deux accords", Revue musicale. Reprinted in La musique retrouvée. Paris: Plon, 1928,
pp. 115–18. Cited in Nattiez (1990).
Lerdahl, Fred (1988/1992). Cognitive Constraints on Compositional Systems. Contemporary Music Review 6, no.
2:97–121.
Leibowitz, René. (1971). "Pelléas et Mélisande ou les fantômes de la réalité", Les Temps Modernes, no. 305:891–
922. Cited in Nattiez (1990).
Marx, Adolf Bernhard. 1837–47. Die Lehre von der musikalischen Komposition I–IV.Leipzig: Breitkopf & Härtel.
Meyer. 1973..
Molino Jean. 1975a..
Molino Jean. 1975b..
Nattiez, Jean-Jacques 1990. Music and Discourse: Toward a Semiology of Music, translated by Caroline Abbate.
Princeton: Princeton University Press. ISBN 0-691-02714-5. French original: Musicologie générale et sémiologue,
Paris:, 1987.
Nettl, Bruno. 1964..
Pederson, Sanna. 2001. "Marx, (Friedrich Heinrich) Adolf Bernhard [Samuel Moses]". The New Grove Dictionary
of Music and Musicians, second edition, edited by Stanley Sadie and John Tyrrell. London: Macmillan Publishers.
Reti, Rudolph. 1951. The Thematic Process in Music..
Rosen, Charles. 1971. The Classical Style..
Satyendra, Ramon. "Analyzing the Unity within Contrast: Chick Corea's 'Starlight'". Cited in Stein (2005).
Scruton, Roger. 1978..
Stein, Deborah (2005). Engaging Music: Essays in Music Analysis. Oxford and New York: Oxford University
Press. ISBN 0-19-517010-5.
Tovey, Donald Francis. 1978..
Van Appledorn, M.-J. (1966). "Stylistic Study of Claude Debussy's Opera Pelléas et Mélisande". Ph.D. Diss.,
Rochester: Eastman School of Music. Cited in Nattiez (1990).
Vuillermoz. 1957..
Warburton. 1952..
Wehinger, Rainer. 1970..

Further reading
Cook, Nicholas (1992). A Guide to Musical Analysis. ISBN 0-393-96255-5.
Hoek, D.J. (2007). Analyses of Nineteenth- and Twentieth-Century Music, 1940-2000. ISBN 0-8108-5887-8.
Kresky, Jeffrey (1977). Tonal Music: Twelve Analytic Studies. ISBN 0-253-37011-6.
Poirier, Lucien, ed. (1983). Répertoire bibliographique de textes de presentation generale et d'analyse d'oeuvres
musicales canadienne, 1900-1980 = Canadian Musical Works, 1900-1980: a Bibliography of General and
Analytical Sources. ISBN 0-9690583-2-2

External links
Example Musical Analyses showing the relationship between voice leading and chord progression patterns
Harmony.org.uk (http://www.harmony.org.uk/book/musical_analysis.htm)
Benoit Meudic, IRCAM, Musical Pattern Extraction: from Repetition to Musical Structure (http://recherche.ircam.fr/
equipes/repmus/RMPapers/CMMR-meudic2003.pdf)

Retrieved from "https://en.wikipedia.org/w/index.php?title=Musical_analysis&oldid=839285034"

This page was last edited on 2 May 2018, at 13:11.

Text is available under the Creative Commons Attribution-ShareAlike License; additional terms may apply. By using
this site, you agree to the Terms of Use and Privacy Policy. Wikipedia® is a registered trademark of the Wikimedia
Foundation, Inc., a non-profit organization.

https://en.wikipedia.org/wiki/Musical_analysis 8/8

You might also like