You are on page 1of 11

Social Behavior as Exchange

Author(s): George C. Homans


Source: American Journal of Sociology, Vol. 63, No. 6, Emile Durkheim-Georg Simmel,
1858-1958 (May, 1958), pp. 597-606
Published by: The University of Chicago Press
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2772990
Accessed: 08-03-2018 05:29 UTC

REFERENCES
Linked references are available on JSTOR for this article:
http://www.jstor.org/stable/2772990?seq=1&cid=pdf-reference#references_tab_contents
You may need to log in to JSTOR to access the linked references.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
http://about.jstor.org/terms

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and
extend access to American Journal of Sociology

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
SOCIAL BEHAVIOR AS EXCHIANGE

GEORGE C. HOMANS

ABST RACT

To consider social behavior as an exchange of goods may clarify the relations among four bodies of the-
ory: behavioral psychology, economics, propositions about the dynamics of influence, and propositions
about the structure of small groups.

THE PROBLEMS OF SMALL-GROUP RESEARCH what happens in elementary social be-


havior, even though we may not be able to
This essay will hope to honor the memory
explain why the propositions should take
of Georg Simmel in two different ways. So
the form they do. A great amount of work
far as it pretends to be suggestive rather
has been done, and more appears every day,
than conclusive, its tone will be Simmel's;
but what it all amounts to in the shape of
and its subject, too, will be one of his. Be-
a set of propositions from which, under
cause Simmel, in essays such as those on
specified conditions, many of the observa-
sociability, games, coquetry, and conversa-
tional results might be derived, is not at all
tion, was an analyst of elementary social
clear-and yet to state such a set is the
behavior, we call him an ancestor of what
first aim of science.
is known today as small-group research.
For what we are really studying in small The third job is to begin to show how the
propositions that empirically hold good in
groups is elementary social behavior: what
happens when two or three persons are in small groups may be derived from some set
a position to influence one another, the sort of still more general propositions. "Still
more general" means only that empirical
of thing of which those massive structures
propositions other than ours may also be
called "classes," "firms," "communities,"
and "societies" must ultimately be com- derived from the set. This derivation would
posed. constitute the explanatory stage in the
science of elementary social behavior, for
As I survey small-group research today,
explanation is derivation.' (I myself sus-
I feel that, apart from just keeping on with
pect that the more general set will turn out
it, three sorts of things need to be done. The
to contain the propositions of behavioral
first is to show the relation between the re-
psychology. I hold myself to be an "ulti-
sults of experimental work done under
mate psychological reductionist," but I can-
laboratory conditions and the results of
not know that I am right so long as the re-
quasi- anthropological field research on
duction has not been carried out.)
what those of us who do it are pleased to
call "real-life" groups in industry and else- I have come to think that all three of
these jobs would be furthered by our adopt-
where. If the experimental work has any-
ing the view that interaction between per-
thing to do with real life-and I am per-
suaded that it has everything to do-its sons is an exchange of goods, material and
propositions cannot be inconsistent with non-material. This is one of the oldest
those discovered through the field work. theories of social behavior, and one that we
But the consistency has not yet been demon- still use every day to interpret our own be-
strated in any systematic way. havior, as when we say, "I found so-and-so
rewarding"; or "I got a great deal out of
The second job is to pull together in some
him"; or, even, "Talking with him took a
set of general propositions the actual re-
great deal out of me." But, perhaps just be-
sults, from the laboratory and from the
field, of work on small groups-propositions 1 See R. B. Braithwaite, Scientific Explanation
that at least sum up, to an approximation, (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1953).

597

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
598 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY

cause it is so obvious, this view has been he is interested in what determines changes
much neglected by social scientists. So far in the rate of emission of learned behavior,
as I know, the only theoretical work that whether pecks at a target or something else.
makes explicit use of it is Marcel Mauss's The more hungry the pigeon, the less
Essai sur le don, published in 1925, which is corn or other food it has gotten in the re-
ancient as social science goes.2 It may be cent past, the more often it will peck. By the
that the tradition of neglect is now chang- same token, if the behavior is often re-
ing and that, for instance, the psychologists inforced, if the pigeon is given much corn
who interpret behavior in terms of trans- every time it pecks, the rate of emission will
actions may be coming back to something fall off as the pigeon gets satiated. If, on the
of the sort I have in mind.3 other hand, the behavior is not reinforced
An incidental advantage of an exchange at all, then, too, its rate of emission will
theory is that it might bring sociology closer tend to fall off, though a long time may pass
to economics-that science of man most ad- before it stops altogether, before it is ex-
vanced, most capable of application, and, tinguished. In the emission of many kinds of
intellectually, most isolated. Economics behavior the pigeon incurs aversive stimula-
studies exchange carried out under special tion, or what I shall call "cost" for short,
circumstances and with a most useful built- and this, too, will lead in time to a decrease
in numerical measure of value. What are in the emission rate. Fatigue is an example
the laws of the general phenomenon of of a "cost." Extinction, satiation, and cost,
which economic behavior is one class? by decreasing the rate of emission of a par-
In what follows I shall suggest some ticular kind of behavior, render more prob-
reasons for the usefulness of a theory of so- able the emission of some other kind of
cial behavior as exchange and suggest the behavior, including doing nothing. I shall
nature of the propositions such a theory only add that even a hard-boiled psycholo-
might contain. gist puts "emotional" behavior, as well as
such things as pecking, among the uncondi-
AN EXCHANGE PARADIGM
tioned responses that may be reinforced in
I start with the link to behavioral psy- operant conditioning. As a statement of the
chology and the kind of statement it makespropositions of behavioral psychology, the
about the behavior of an experimental ani- foregoing is, of course, inadequate for any
mal such as the pigeon.4 As a pigeon ex- purpose except my present one.
plores its cage in the laboratory, it happens We may look on the pigeon as engaged
to peck a target, whereupon the psycholo- in an exchange-pecks for corn-with the
gist feeds it corn. The evidence is that it psychologist, but let us not dwell upon that,
will peck the target again; it has learned the for the behavior of the pigeon hardly de-
behavior, or, as my friend Skinner says, the termines the behavior of the psychologist at
behavior has been reinforced, and the all. Let us turn to a situation where the ex-
pigeon has undergone operant conditioning. change is real, that is, where the determina-
This kind of psychologist is not interested tion is mutual. Suppose we are dealing with
in how the behavior was learned: "learning two men. Each is emitting behavior re-
theory" is a poor name for his field. Instead, inforced to some degree by the behavior of
2Translated by I. Cunnison as The Gift (Glen- the other. How it was in the past that each
coe, Ill.: Free Press, 1954). learned the behavior he emits and how he
8 In social anthropology D. L. Oliver is working learned to find the other's behavior re-
along these lines, and I owe much to him. See also inforcing we are not concerned with. It is
T. M. Newcomb, "The Prediction of Interpersonal
enough that each does find the other's be-
Attraction," American Psychologist, XI (1956),
575-86. havior reinforcing, and I shall call the re-
'B. F. Skinner, Science and Human Behavior inforcers-the equivalent of the pigeon's
(New York: Macmillan Co., 1953). corn-values, for this, I think, is what we

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
SOCIAL BEHAVIOR AS EXCHANGE 599

mean by this term. As he emits behavior, tivities of the group. Festinger and his col-
each man may incur costs, and each man leagues consider two kinds of reinforcing
has more than one course of behavior open activity: the symbolic behavior we call "so-
to him. cial approval" (sentiment) and activity
This seems to me the paradigm of ele- valuable in other ways, such as doing some-
mentary social behavior, and the problem ofthing interesting.
the elementary sociologist is to state prop- The other variable they work with they
ositions relating the variations in the values call communication and others call interac-
and costs of each man to his frequency dis- tion. This is a frequency variable; it is a
tribution of behavior among alternatives, measure of the frequency of emission of
where the values (in the mathematical valuable and costly verbal behavior. We
sense) taken by these variable for one man must bear in mind that, in general, the one
determine in part their values for the other.5 kind of variable is a function of the other.
I see no reason to believe that the prop- Festinger and his co-workers show that
ositions of behavioral psychology do not ap- the more cohesive a group is, that is, the
ply to this situation, though the complexity more valuable the sentiment or activity the
of their implications in the concrete case members exchange with one another, the
may be great indeed. In particular, we mustgreater the average frequency of interaction
suppose that, with men as with pigeons, of the members.6 With men, as with pigeons,
an increase in extinction, satiation, or aver- the greater the reinforcement, the more
sive stimulation of any one kind of behavior often is the reinforced behavior emitted.
will increase the probability of emission of The more cohesive a group, too, the greater
some other kind. The problem is not, as it the change that members can produce in the
is often stated, merely, what a man's values behavior of other members in the direction
are, what he has learned in the past to find of rendering these activities more valuable.7
reinforcing, but how much of any one value That is, the more valuable the activities
his behavior is getting him now. The more that members get, the more valuable those
he gets, the less valuable any further unit of that they must give. For if a person is emit-
that value is to him, and the less often he ting behavior of a certain kind, and other
will emit behavior reinforced by it. people do not find it particularly rewarding,
these others will suffer their own production
THE INFLUENCE PROCESS
of sentiment and activity, in time, to fall off.
We do not, I think, possess the kind of But perhaps the first person has found their
studies of two-person interaction that sentiment and activity rewarding, and, if
would either bear out these propositions or he is to keep on getting them, he must make
fail to do so. But we do have studies of his own behavior more valuable to the
larger numbers of persons that suggest that others. In short, the propositions of behav-
they may apply, notably the studies by ioral psychology imply a tendency toward
Festinger, Schachter, Back, and their associ- a certain proportionality between the value
ates on the dynamics of influence. One of tn AthArc .of the. hAhn%;1'ir n mnn CilyPc
the variables they work with they call co-
hesiveness, defined as anything that attracts 6K. W. Back, "The Exertion of Influence through
people to take part in a group. Cohesive- Social Communication," in L. Festinger, K. Back, S.
ness is a value variable; it refers to the de- Schachter, H. H. Kelley, and J. Thibaut (eds.),
Theory and Experiment in Social Communication
gree of reinforcement people find in the ac- (Ann Arbor: Research Center for Dynamics, Uni-
versity of Michigan, 1950), pp. 21-36.
5Ibid., pp. 297-329. The discussion of "double
contingency" by T. Parsons and E. A. Shils could 'S. Schachter, N. Ellertson, D. McBride, and D.
easily lead to a similar paradigm (see Toward a Gregory, "An Experimental Study of Cohesiveness
General Theory of Action [Cambridge, Mass.: and Productivity," Human Relations, IV (1951),
Harvard University Press, 1951], pp. 14-16). 229-38.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
600 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY

and the value to him of the behavior they latter often appear to be in practical equi-
give him.8 librium, and by this I mean nothing fancy.
Schachter also studied the behavior of I do not mean that all real-life groups are
members of a group toward two kinds of in equilibrium. I certainly do not mean that
other members, "conformers" and "devi- all groups must tend to equilibrium. I do
ates."9 I assume that conformers are people not mean that groups have built-in antidotes
whose activity the other members find valu- to change: there is no homeostasis here.
able. For conformity is behavior that co- I do not mean that we assume equilibrium.
incides to a degree with some group stand- I mean only that we sometimes observe it,
ard or norm, and the only meaning I can that for the time we are with a group-and
assign to norm is "a verbal description of it is often short-there is no great change
behavior that many members find it valu- in the values of the variables we choose to
able for the actual behavior of themselves measure. If, for instance, person A is inter-
and others to conform to." By the same acting with B more than with C both at the
token, a deviate is a member whose behavior beginning and at the end of the study, then
is not particularly valuable. Now Schachter at least by this crude measure the group is
shows that, as the members of a group come in equilibrium.
to see another member as a deviate, their Many of the Festinger-Schachter studies
interaction with him-communication ad- are experimental, and their propositions
dressed to getting him to change his behav- about the process of influence seem to me to
ior-goes up, the faster the more cohesive imply the kind of proposition that empiri-
the group. The members need not talk to the cally holds good of real-life groups in prac-
other conformers so much; they are relative- tical equilibrium. For instance, Festinger et
ly satiated by the conformers' behavior: they al. find that, the more cohesive a group is,
have gotten what they want out of them. the greater the change that members can
But if the deviate, by failing to change his produce in the behavior of other members.
behavior, fails to reinforce the members, If the influence is exerted in the direction
they start to withhold social approval from of conformity to group norms, then, when
him: the deviate gets low sociometric choice the process of influence has accomplished all
at the end of the experiment. And in the the change of which it is capable, the propo-
most cohesive groups-those Schachter calls sition should hold good that, the more co-
"high cohesive-relevant"-interaction with hesive a group is, the larger the number of
the deviate also falls off in the end and is members that conform to its norms. And it
lowest among those members that rejected does hold good.10
him most strongly, as if they had given him Again, Schachter found, in the experiment
up as a bad job. But how plonking can we I summarized above, that in the most co-
get? These findings are utterly in line with hesive groups and at the end, when the ef-
everyday experience. fort to influence the deviate had failed,
members interacted little with the deviate
PRACTICAL EQUILIBRIUM
and gave him little in the way of sociometric
At the beginning of this paper I suggestedchoice. Now two of the propositions that
that one of the tasks of small-grouphold research
good most often of real-life groups in
was to show the relation between the results practical equilibrium are precisely that the
of experimental work done under labora- more closely a member's activity conforms
tory conditions and the results of field re- to the norms the more interaction he re-
search on real-life small groups. Now the ceives from other members and the more
8 Skinner, op. cit., p. 100. liking choices he gets from them too. From

'S. Schachter, "Deviation, Rejection, and Com- 0 L. Festinger, S. Schachter, and K. Back, Social
munication," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psy- Pressures in Informnal Groups (New York: Harper
chology, XLVI (1951), 190-207. & Bros., 1950), pp. 72-100.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
SOCIAL BEHAVIOR AS EXCHANGE 601

these main propositions a number of others same frequencies as he did at the beginning,
may be derived that also hold good.-' the group is for that period in equilibrium.
Yet we must ever remember that the truth Let us then ask why any one member's be-
of the proposition linking conformity to lik- havior should persist. Suppose he is emit-
ing may on occasion be masked by the truth ting behavior of value Al. Why does he not
of other propositions. If, for instance, the let his behavior get worse (less valuable or
man that conforms to the norms most close- reinforcing to the others) until it stands at
ly also exerts some authority over the group, Al - AA? True, the sentiments expressed
this may render liking for him somewhat by others toward him are apt to decline in
less than it might otherwise have been.12 value (become less reinforcing to him), so
Be that as it may, I suggest that the labo- that what he gets from them may be Si
ratory experiments on influence imply prop- - AS. But it is conceivable that, since
ositions about the behavior of members of most activity carries cost, a decline in the
small groups, when the process of influence value of what he emits will mean a reduc-
has worked itself out, that are identical with tion in cost to him that more than offsets
propositions that hold good of real-life his losses in sentiment. Where, then, does
groups in equilibrium. This is hardly sur- he stabilize his behavior? This is the prob-
prising if all we mean by equilibrium is that lem of social control.'3
all the change of which the system is, under Mankind has always assumed that a per-
present conditions, capable has been ef- son stabilizes his behavior, at least in the
fected, so that no further change occurs. short run, at the point where he is doing the
Nor would this be the first time that statics best he can for himself under the circum-
has turned out to be a special case of dy- stances, though his best may not be a "ra-
namics. tional" best, and what he can do may not
be at all easy to specify, except that he is
PROFIT AND SOCIAL CONTROL
not apt to think like one of the theoretical
Though I have treated equilibrium as an antagonists in the Theory of Games. Before
observed fact, it is a fact that cries for ex- a sociologist rejects this answer out of hand
planation. I shall not, as structural-func- for its horrid profit-seeking implications, he
tional sociologists do, use an assumed equi- will do well to ask himself if he can offer any
librium as a means of explaining, or trying other answer to the question posed. I think
to explain, why the other features of a social he will find that he cannot. Yet experiments
system should be what they are. Rather, designed to test the truth of the answer are
I shall take practical equilibrium as some- extraordinarily rare.
thing that is itself to be explained by the I shall review one that seems to me to
other features of the system. provide a little support for the theory,
If every member of a group emits at the though it was not meant to do so. The ex-
end of, and during, a period of time much periment is reported by H. B. Gerard, a
the same kinds of behavior and in much the member of the Festinger-Schachter team,
" For propositions holding good of groups inunder the title "The Anchorage of Opinions
practical equilibrium see G. C. Homans, The Hu- in Face-to-Face Groups."''4 The experiment-
mnan Group (New York: Harcourt, Brace & Co.,er formed artificial groups whose members
1950), and H. W. Riecken and G. C. Homans, met to discuss a case in industrial relations
"Psychological Aspects of Social Structure," in G.
Lindsey (ed.), Handbook of Social Psychology and to express their opinions about its prob-
(Cambridge, Mass.: Addison-Wesley Publishing able outcome. The groups were of two kinds:
Co., 1954), II, 786-832. high-attraction groups, whose members were
2See Homans, op. cit., pp. 244-48, and R.told F. that they would like one another very
Bales, "The Equilibrium Problem in Small Groups,"much, and low-attraction groups, whose
in A. P. Hare, E. F. Borgatta, and R. F. Bales
(eds.), Small Groups (New York: A. A. Knopf, '3 Homans, op. cit., pp. 281-301.
1953), pp. 450-56. H Human Relations, VII (1954), 313-25.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
602 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY

members were told that they would not find to have been interested only in the differ-
one another particularly likable. ences in the sums of the rows, which show
At a later time the experimenter called that there is more shifting toward the group,
the members in separately, asked them and less shifting toward the paid partici-
again to express their opinions on the out- pant, in the high-attraction than in the low-
come of the case, and counted the number attraction condition. This is in line with a
that had changed their opinions to bring proposition suggested earlier. If you think
them into accord with those of other mem- that the members of a group can give you
bers of their groups. At the same time, a much-in this case, liking-you are apt to
paid participant entered into a further dis- give them much-in this case, a change to
cussion of the case with each member, al- an opinion in accordance with their views-
ways taking, on the probable outcome of or you will not get the liking. And, by the
the case, a position opposed to that taken same token, if the group can give you little
by the bulk of the other members of the of value, you will not be ready to give it
group to which the person belonged. The much of value. Indeed, you may change your
opinion so as to depart from agreement even
TABLE 1 further, to move, that is, toward the view
PERCENTAGE OF SUBJECTS CHANGING TOWARD held by the paid participant.
SOMEONE IN THE GROUP So far so good, but, when I first scanned
Mild Strong these tables, I was less struck by the differ-
Agree- Disagree- Disagree- ence between them than by their similarity.
ment ment ment
The same classes of people in both tables
High attraction.... 0 12 44
Low attraction... . 0 15 9 showed much the same relative propensities
to change their opinions, no matter whether
the change was toward the group or toward
TABLE 2 the paid participant. We see, for instance,
PERCENTAGE OF SUBJECTS CHANGING TOWARD that those who change least are the high-
THE PAID PARTICIPANT attraction, agreement people and the low-
Mild Strong attraction, strong-disagreement ones. And
Agree- Disagree- Disagree- those who change most are the high-attrac-
ment ment ment
tion, strong-disagreement people and the
High attraction.... 7 13 25
Low attraction. .. . 20 38 8 low-attraction, mild-disagreement ones.
How am I to interpret these particular re-
experimenter counted the number of per- sults? Since the experimenter did not discuss
sons shifting toward the opinion of the paid them, I am free to offer my own explana-
participant. tion. The behavior emitted by the subjects
The experiment had many interesting re- is opinion and changes in opinion. For this
sults, from which I choose only those behavior they have learned to expect two
summed up in Tables 1 and 2. The three possible kinds of reinforcement. Agreement
different agreement classes are made up of with the group gets the subject favorable
people who, at the original sessions, ex- sentiment (acceptance) from it, and the ex-
pressed different degrees of agreement with periment was designed to give this reinforce-
the opinions of other members of their ment a higher value in the high-attraction
groups. And the figure 44, for instance, condition than in the low-attraction one.
means that, of all members of high-attrac- The second kind of possible reinforcement
tion groups whose initial opinions were is what I shall call the "maintenance of one's
personal integrity," which a subject gets by
strongly in disagreement with those of other
members, 44 per cent shifted their opinion sticking to his own opinion in the face of dis-
later toward that of others. agreement with the group. The experimenter
In these results the experimenter seems does not mention this reward, but I cannot

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
SOCIAL BEHAVIOR AS EXCHANGE 603

make sense of the results without something ment people, and, like them, they are prone
much like it. In different degrees for differ- to change their opinions, in this case, more
ent subjects, depending on their initial posi- toward the paid participant. The subjects
tions, these rewards are in competition with in the other two cells, who have medium
one another: they are alternatives. They are profits, display medium propensities to
not absolutely scarce goods, but some per- change.
sons cannot get both at once. If we define profit as reward less cost, and
Since the rewards are alternatives, let me if cost is value foregone, I suggest that we
introduce a familiar assumption from eco- have here some evidence for the proposition
nomics-that the cost of a particular course that change in behavior is greatest when per-
of action is the equivalent of the foregone ceived profit is least. This constitutes no di-
value of an alternative'5-and then add the rect demonstration that change in behavior
definition: Profit = Reward - Cost. is least when profit is greatest, but if, when-
Now consider the persons in the corre- ever a man's behavior brought him a balance
sponding cells of the two tables. The be- of reward and cost, he changed his behavior
havior of the high-attraction, agreement away from what got him, under the circum-
people gets them much in the way of accept- stances, the less profit, there might well come
ance by the group, and for it they must give a time when his behavior would not change
up little in the way of personal integrity, for further. That is, his behavior would be sta-
their views are from the start in accord with bilized, at least for the time being. And, so
those of the group. Their profit is high, and far as this were true for every member of
they are not prone to change their behav- a group, the group would have a social or-
ior. The low-attraction, strong-disagreement ganization in equilibrium.
people are getting much in integrity, and I do not say that a member would stabil-
they are not giving up for it much in valu- ize his behavior at the point of greatest con-
able acceptance, for they are members of ceivable profit to himself, because his profit
low-attraction groups. Reward less cost is is partly at the mercy of the behavior of
high for them, too, and they change little. others. It is a commonplace that the short-
The high-attraction, strong-disagreement run pursuit of profit by several persons often
people are getting much in the way of in- lands them in positions where all are worse
tegrity, but their costs in doing so are high, off than they might conceivably be. I do not
too, for they are in high-attraction groups say that the paths of behavioral change in
and thus foregoing much valuable accept- which a member pursues his profit under the
ance by the group. Their profit is low, and condition that others are pursuing theirs too
they are very apt to change, either toward are easy to describe or predict; and we can
the group or toward the paid participant, readily conceive that in jockeying for posi-
from whom they think, perhaps, they willtion
getthey might never arrive at any equi-
some acceptance while maintaining some in- librium at all.
tegrity. The low-attraction, mild-disagree-
DISTRIBUTIVE JUSTICE
ment people do not get much in the way of
integrity, for they are only in mild disagree- Yet practical equilibrium is often ob-
ment with the group, but neither are they served, and thus some further condition may
giving up much in acceptance, for they are make its attainment, under some circum-
members of low-attraction groups. Their re- stance, more probable than would the indi-
wards are low; their costs are low too, and vidual pursuit of profit left to itself. I can
their profit-the difference between the two offer evidence for this further condition
-is also low. In their low profit they re- only in the behavior of subgroups and not
semble the high-attraction, strong-disagree- in that of individuals. Suppose that there
are two subgroups, working close together
1" G. J. Stigler, The Theory of Price (rev. ed.;
New York: Macmillan Co., 1952), p. 99. in a factory, the job of one being somewhat

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
604 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY

different from that of the other. And


be higher too. suppose
This last is the theory of no-
that the members of the first complain and blesse oblige, which we all subscribe to,
say: "We are getting the same pay as they though we all laugh at it, perhaps because
are. We ought to get just a couple of dol- the noblesse often fails to oblige. To put the
lars a week more to show that our work is matter in terms of profit: though the re-
more responsible." When you ask them wards and costs of two persons or the mem-
what they mean by "more responsible," bers of two groups may be different, yet the
they say that, if they do their work wrong, profits of the two-the excess of reward over
more damage can result, and so they are cost-should tend to equality. And more
under more pressure to take care.16 Some- than "should." The less-advantaged group
thing like this is a common feature of indus- will at least try to attain greater equality, as,
trial behavior. It is at the heart of disputes in the example I have used, the first group
not over absolute wages but over wage dif- tried to increase its profit by increasing its
ferentials-indeed, at the heart of disputes pay.
over rewards other than wages. I have talked of distributive justice.
In what kind of propostion may we ex- Clearly, this is not the only condition deter-
press observations like these? We may say mining the actual distribution of rewards
that wages and responsibility give status in and costs. At the same time, never tell me
the group, in the sense that a man who takes that notions of justice are not a strong in-
high responsibility and gets high wages is fluence on behavior, though we sociologists
admired, other things equal. Then, if the often neglect them. Distributive justice
members of one group score higher on re- may be one of the conditions of group
sponsibility than do the members of another, equilibrium.
there is a felt need on the part of the first
EXCHANGE AND SOCIAL STRUCTURE
to score higher on pay too. There is a pres-
sure, which shows itself in complaints, to I shall end by reviewing almost the only
bring the status factors, as I have called study I am aware of that begins to show in
them, into line with one another. If they are detail how a stable and differentiated social
in line, a condition of status congruence is structure in a real-life group might arise out
said to exist. In this condition the workers of a process of exchange between members.
may find their jobs dull or irksome, but they This is Peter Blau's description of the be-
will not complain about the relative position havior of sixteen agents in a federal law-
of groups. enforcement agency.17
But there may be a more illuminating way The agents had the duty of investigating
of looking at the matter. In my example I firms and preparing reports on the firms'
have considered only responsibility and pay, compliance with the law. Since the reports
but these may be enough, for they represent might lead to legal action against the firms,
the two kinds of thing that come into the the agents had to prepare them carefully, in
problem. Pay is clearly a reward; responsi- the proper form, and take strict account of
bility may be looked on, less clearly, as a the many regulations that might apply. The
cost. It means constraint and worry-or agents were often in doubt what they should
peace of mind foregone. Then the proposi- do, and then they were supposed to take the
tion about status congruence becomes this: question to their supervisor. This they were
If the costs of the members of one group are reluctant to do, for they naturally believed
higher than those of another, distributive that thus confessing to him their inability
justice requires that their rewards should be to solve a problem would reflect on their
higher too. But the thing works both ways: competence, affect the official ratings he
If the rewards are higher. the costs should
17 Peter M. Blau, The Dynamics of Bureaucracy
16 G. C. Homans, "Status among Clerical Work-(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1955), 99-
ers," Human Organization, XII (1953), 5-10. 116.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
SOCIAL BEHAVIOR AS EXCHANGE 605

made of their work, and so hurt their chances of that advice, the cost lying precisely in the
for promotion. So agents often asked other foregone value of time to do his own work.
agents for help and advice, and, though this Blau suggests that something of the same
was nominally forbidden, the supervisor sort was true of an agent who went to a
usually let it pass. more competent colleague for advice: the
Blau ascertained the ratings the supervi- more often he went, the more costly to him,
sor made of the agents, and he also asked in feelings of inferiority, became any further
the agents to rate one another. The two request. "The repeated admission of his in-
opinions agreed closely. Fewer agents were ability to solve his own problems ... under-
regarded as highly competent than were mined the self-confidence of the worker and
regarded as of middle or low competence; his standing in the group."20
competence, or the ability to solve technical The result was that the less competent
problems, was a fairly scarce good. One or agents went to the more competent ones for
two of the more competent agents would not help less often than they might have done if
give help and advice when asked, and so the costs of repeated admissions of inferi-
received few interactions and little liking. ority had been less high and that, while
A man that will not exchange, that will not many agents sought out the few highly com-
give you what he has when you need it, will petent ones, no single agent sought out the
not get from you the only thing you are, in latter much. Had they done so (to look at
this case, able to give him in return, your the exchange from the other side), the costs
regard. to the highly competent in interruptions to
But most of the more competent agents their own work would have become exorbi-
were willing to give help, and of them Blau tant. Yet the need of the less competent for
says: help was still not fully satisfied. Under these
circumstances they tended to turn for help
A consultation can be considered an exchange
to agents more nearly like themselves in
of values: both participants gain something,
competence. Though the help they got was
and both have to pay a price. The questioning
agent is enabled to perform better than he not the most valuable, it was of a kind they
could otherwise have done, without exposing his could themselves return on occasion. With
difficulties to his supervisor. By asking for such agents they could exchange help and
advice, he implicitly pays his respect to the liking, without the exchange becoming on
superior proficiency of his colleague. This either side too great a confession of inferi-
acknowledgment of inferiority is the cost of ority.
receiving assistance. The consultant gains pres-
The highly competent agents tended to
tige, in return for which he is willing to devote
enter into exchanges, that is, to interact with
some time to the consultation and permit it to
many others. But, in the more equal ex-
disrupt his own work. The following remark of
an agent illustrates this: "I like giving advice. changes I have just spoken of, less compe-
It's flattering, I suppose, if you feel that others tent agents tended to pair off as partners.
come to you for advice.'8 That is, they interacted with a smaller num-
ber of people, but interacted often with these
Blau goes on to say: "All agents liked few. I think I could show why pair relations
being consulted, but the value of any one of in these more equal exchanges would be more
very many consultations became deflated for economical for an agent than a wider dis-
experts, and the price they paid in frequent tribution of favors. But perhaps I have gone
interruptions became inflated."19 This im- far enough. The final pattern of this social
plies that, the more prestige an agent re- structure was one in which a small number
ceived, the less was the increment of value of highly competent agents exchanged ad-
of that prestige; the more advice an agent vice for prestige with a large number of
gave, the greater was the increment of cost others less competent and in which the less
`8 ]bid., p. 108. l Ibid., p. 108. 20 Ibid., p. 109.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms
606 THE AMERICAN JOURNAL OF SOCIOLOGY

competent agents exchanged, in pairs and to others try to get much from them, and
in trios, both help and liking on more nearly
persons that get much from others are under
equal terms. pressure to give much to them. This process
Blau shows, then, that a social structure of influence tends to work out at equilibrium
in equilibrium might be the result of a proc- to a balance in the exchanges. For a person
ess of exchanging behavior rewarding and engaged in exchange, what he gives may be
costly in different degrees, in which the in- a cost to him, just as what he gets may be a
crement of reward and cost varied with the reward, and his behavior changes less as
frequency of the behavior, that is, with the profit, that is, reward less cost, tends to a
frequency of interaction. Note that the be- maximum. Not only does he seek a maxi-
havior of the agents seems also to have satis- mum for himself, but he tries to see to it
fied my second condition of equilibrium: the that no one in his group makes more profit
more competent agents took more responsi- than he does. The cost and the value of what
bility for the work, either their own or he gives and of what he gets vary with the
others', than did the less competent ones, quantity of what he gives and gets. It is sur-
but they also got more for it in the way of prising how familiar these propositions are;
prestige. I suspect that the same kind of it is surprising, too, how propositions about
explanation could be given for the structurethe dynamics of exchange can begin to gen-
of many "informal" groups. erate the static thing we call "group struc-
ture" and, in so doing, generate also some of
SUMMARY the propositions about group structure that
students of real-life groups have stated.
The current job of theory in small-group
In our unguarded moments we sociologists
research is to make the connection between
find words like "reward" and "cost" slipping
experimental and real-life studies, to con-
into what we say. Human nature will break
solidate the propositions that empirically
in upon even our most elaborate theories.
hold good in the two fields, and to show how
But we seldom let it have its way with us
these propositions might be derived from a and follow up systematically what these
still more general set. One way of doing this words imply.2' Of all our many "approach-
job would be to revive and make more rigor- es" to social behavior, the one that sees it
ous the oldest of theories of social behavior as an economy is the most neglected, and
-social behavior as exchange. yet it is the one we use every moment of our
Some of the statements of such a theory lives-except when we write sociology.
might be the following. Social behavior is an
HARVARD TUNIVERSITY
exchange of goods, material goods but also
'The White-Collar Job (Ann Arbor: Survey
non-material ones, such as the symbols of
Research Center, University of Michigan, 1953),
approval or prestige. Persons that give much pp. 115-27.

This content downloaded from 141.132.64.206 on Thu, 08 Mar 2018 05:29:17 UTC
All use subject to http://about.jstor.org/terms

You might also like