You are on page 1of 56

R A D I C A L P H I L O S O P H Y

a journal of socialist and feminist philosophy

83 CONTENTS MAY/JUNE 1997

Editorial collective COMMENTARY


Chris Arthur, Ted Benton, Nadine Cartner,
Andrew Collier, Diana Coole, Peter Dews, Who Are My Peers?
Roy Edgley, Gregory Elliott, The Research Assessment Exercise in Philosophy
Howard Feather, Jean Grimshaw,
Kathleen Lennon, Joseph McCarney, Sean Sayers ................................................................................................... 2
Kevin Magill, Peter Osborne,
Stella Sandford, Sean Sayers, Kate Soper
Issue editor
ARTICLES
Jean Grimshaw Generations of Feminism
Reviews editor Lynne Segal.................................................................................................... 6
Sean Sayers
Contributors
Feminism Without Nostalgia
Sean Sayers teaches philosophy at the Diana Coole .................................................................................................. 17
University of Kent, Canterbury.
Feminist Activism and Presidential Politics:
Lynne Segal is Professor of Gender Theorizing the Costs of the ‘Insider Strategy’
Studies at Middlesex University.
Anne-Marie Smith ....................................................................................... 25
Diana Coole teaches political theory
at Queen Mary and Westfield College, Thinking Naturally
University of London.
John O’Neill ................................................................................................. 36
John OʼNeill teaches philosophy at the
University of Lancaster.
Anne-Marie Smith teaches in the REVIEWS
Department of Government at Cornell
University, Ithaca, NY. Michael J. Sandel, Democracyʼs Discontent
Avishai Margalit, The Decent Society
David Archard............................................................................................... 41
Typing (WP input) by Jo Foster John R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality
Tel: 0181 341 9238
Kevin Magill ................................................................................................. 43
Layout by Petra Pryke
John Keane, Reflections on Violence
Tel: 0171 243 1464
Anthony Arblaster ....................................................................................... 45
Copyedited and typeset by
Robin Gable and Lucy Morton Kevin Anderson, Lenin, Hegel and Western Marxism
Tel: 0181 318 1676 Michael Löwy............................................................................................... 46
Design by Peter Osborne Richard J. Bernstein, Hannah Arendt and the Jewish Question
Anne Seller................................................................................................... 48
Printed by Russell Press, Radford Mill,
Norton Street, Nottingham NG7 3HN Maurice Blanchot, The Most High
Bookshop distribution Julian Cowley .............................................................................................. 49
UK: Central Books, Régis Debray, Media Manifestos
99 Wallis Road, London E9 5LN Hugh Dauncey ............................................................................................. 50
Tel: 0181 986 4854
Simon Critchley and Peter Dews, eds, Deconstructive Subjectivities
USA: Bernard de Boer, 113 East Centre
Street, Nutley, New Jersey 07100, Gideon Calder .............................................................................................. 51
Tel: 201 667 9300; Philip Goodchild, Gilles Deleuze and the Question of Philosophy
Ubiquity Distributors Inc., 607 Degraw Jean-Jacques Lecercle .............................................................................. 52
Street, Brooklyn, New York 11217,
Tel: 718 875 5491;
Fine Print Distributors, 500 Pampa Drive,
Austin, Texas 78752-3028.
NEWS
Tel: 512-452-8709 Forum for European Philosophy
Peter Dews ......................................................................................... 53
Cover: Feminist Mothers, Islington, 1975.
Honouring Levinas
Published by Radical Philosophy Ltd. Robert Vallier ..................................................................................... 54
http://www.ukc.ac.uk/cprs/phil/rp/
XVIIth German Conference for Philosophy
Stephan Meyer .................................................................................. 56
© Radical Philosophy Ltd
COMMENTARY

Who are my peers?


The Research Assessment Exercise
in Philosophy

Sean Sayers

B
ritish universities have just gone through their third Research Assessment
Exercise (RAE). The ʻresearch outputʼ (i.e. publications) of every participat-
ing department has been graded by panels of ʻexpertsʼ on a seven-point scale.
The purpose of this massive operation is to provide a basis for distributing funds for
research. In theory, the idea of allocating these scarce resources according to the
standard of the work produced seems fair and reasonable; but in philosophy, at least,
that is not how things work out in practice.
The assessment process is supposed to be one of ʻpeer reviewʼ. This sounds reassur-
ingly cosy and communitarian; however, it is doubtful whether it operates that way in a
subject as divided as philosophy. What assurance is there that the panel adequately rep-
resents the diversity of contemporary British philosophy and is competent to undertake
a peer review of the field? The short answer is: none. The panel is a quango, with all
the secretive and undemocratic features typical of such bodies. How its members are
chosen is a mystery. Little attempt is made to present them as representative of the
different schools and approaches in the field. It is only a few years since a number of
prominent philosophers opposed the award of a Cambridge honorary degree to Derrida
(see Jonathan Rée, ʻMassacre of the Innocentsʼ, Radical Philosophy 62, Autumn 1992,
pp. 61–2). Are such philosophers suitable to conduct a ʻpeer reviewʼ of the work of the
followers of Derrida? Indeed, what constitutes a ʻpeerʼ group in a subject like phil-
osophy? Questions like these must be answered before the title of ʻpeer reviewʼ can
have any credibility.
The panel, so it is claimed, assessed the work submitted to it objectively and
impartially. In the previous exercises quantitative data were collected. This time the
assessment was purely qualitative. How ʻqualityʼ was judged is shrouded in Kafka-
esque obscurity. The panel does not explain or justify its decisions; nor is there any
appeals procedure. The criteria it employs are specified only in the vaguest fashion.
ʻInternationalʼ and ʻnationalʼ excellence are the key terms. According to one member
of the panel, however, these were not treated as geographical but rather as ʻvalue
conceptsʼ. Assurances are constantly given about the care and scrupulousness with
which the task was undertaken. Nevertheless, at the end of the day, we are simply
required to have faith in the panelʼs judgements. In typically British fashion, we are
expected to defer to the wisdom of authority. And, in typically British fashion, we do.
This extraordinarily opaque and undemocratic system has been accepted with scarcely
a murmur of dissent (though the demoralized state of the universities in Britain has
doubtless contributed).

2 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


The ‘oxygen of competition’
The exercise is designed to inject the ʻoxygen of competitionʼ into philosophy by
rewarding ʻexcellenceʼ wherever it is found. It is most unlikely to have this effect. ʻOf
course, Oxford and Cambridge will get 5sʼ (the top mark), one member of the panel
is reported to have said, even before the submissions were in. Of course they did. Of
course Warwick and Essex (the main centres for ʻcontinentalʼ philosophy) will not
get 5s, he could well have added. Of course they did not. As regards the standards of
ʻinternationalʼ excellence, a colleague was assured: ʻonly the US and Australia count.ʼ
In short, what is regarded as philosophy in Oxford, Harvard and Sydney is the stand-
ard. If you want a high rating, you would be well advised to follow that model.
There can be no doubt that all this will have a deeply conservative impact on the
subject. Instead of promoting ʻexcellenceʼ, it will impose a narrow orthodoxy and stifle
innovation and creativity. Assuming that the RAE is going to be repeated, the system
should be opened up and made publicly accountable.
In the first place, the panel should be selected by an open process with the aim of
representing the diversity of approaches and schools in the subject as a whole. In the
USA this could be achieved through the machinery of the American Philosophical
Association, whose membership covers virtually the whole profession. Unfortunately,
there is no similar organization of philosophers in Britain.
Second, the rating criteria should be specified more precisely, and the reasons for
the panelʼs decisions explained and opened up to appeal. There is nothing particularly
radical in these suggestions. Apart from anything else, they are matters of elementary
justice which simply echo the recommendations of the Nolan Committee on Standards
in Public Life.
Given the divisions within philosophy, however, it is difficult to see how they could
be implemented without taking some account of more objective – that is to say, more
quantitative – standards. Scepticism about the value of these is very widespread, and
not just among defenders of the status quo. Sheer quantity of output – a concern in
previous exercises – is crude and unsatisfactory (and it engenders a deluge of pointless
publications). However, there are other indicators, such as frequency of citation and
even market success, which could help the system respond more fairly to the diversity
of approaches in the subject.
No doubt, as criteria of ʻqualityʼ, these measures are crude too, and I am not sug-
gesting that they should be used mechanically or on their own. No doubt they would
generate their own distortions, as authors would be motivated to cite and be cited rather
than to say anything worth saying. But rating philosophical work on a seven-point scale
is an inherently crude business. At least such criteria offer some objective indication
of academic standing, relatively free of the personal opinions of a few individuals; and
what they reveal is illuminating.
Citations 1981–97
The very idea of consulting citation rates and
Name Humanities Social sciences Total the like is often treated with disdain. According
Derrida, J. 1,867 578 2,445 to Professor Hepburn, reporting on the work of
Habermas, J. 1,493 1,291 2,784 the 1989 panel in philosophy which he chaired,
Gadamer, H.-G. 884 284 1,168
Rorty, R. 720 428 1,148 ʻwe made no use of mechanical aids such as
Levinas, E. 680 93 773 frequency of citation; a notably unsatisfactory
Putnam, H. 647 382 1,029 attempt on a philosophical problem can be cited
Davidson, D. 646 333 979
Quine, W.V. 552 254 806 repeatedly in the early pages of books or articles
Rawls, J. 328 342 670 that aspire to a more adequate theory!ʼ This well
Dummett, M. 284 112 396
Singer, P. 238 364 602 illustrates the complacent amateurism which has
so far characterized the whole exercise. Actual
Source: BIDS ISI Humanities and Social Science Citation Indexes. citation figures tell a very different story. The
most frequently cited philosophers include Rorty,

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 3


Putnam, Davidson; Derrida, Habermas, Gadamer (see Table, previous page). It would
be absurd to suggest that any of these writers has gained his position merely by being
repeatedly refuted. Rather, it is clear that the most cited philosophers are on the whole
the best known and most influential ones.
The high citation rates for ʻcontinentalʼ philosophers like Derrida and Habermas are
striking. There can be no doubt that Derridaʼs work is cited not only by philosophers
but also in literary theory, cultural studies and many other areas, mainly in the humani-
ties. Habermas has a similarly wide influence, though more in the social sciences. To
those who regard philosophy as a narrow and self-contained specialism, such influence
is at best an irrelevance to their standing as philosophers, perhaps even grounds for
suspicion on this score.
Market success arouses similar distrust. To quote Hepburn again, ʻa substantial
published work could be of a semi-popular nature, perhaps summarising the research of
others rather than breaking new ground, and might well not qualify as research at all
in this context.ʼ The concept of ʻresearchʼ at work here may apply well enough in the
sciences, but it is far more debatable in philosophy. The idea that ʻgenuine researchʼ is
written only for a tiny band of specialists, and that the ʻsemi-popularʼ is suspect, has
had a lamentable impact on the style and content of contemporary professional phil-
osophy (of both the analytic and continental varieties); one of the most harmful aspects
of the RAE in its present form is that it enforces this conception of philosophy on the
profession as a whole.
A huge flood of such work has poured forth as a result of the obsession with
ʻresearchʼ dictated by the present system. Much of it is pointless from a philosophical
point of view; its main raison dʼêtre is to gain a research rating and/or promotion. It
remains unread and undiscussed on library shelves; it has no other market. Philosophers
like Derrida and Davidson can scarcely be accused of being ʻsemi-popularʼ. And yet
their work is very widely read and discussed, and sales of their books, I am sure, are
healthy. I do not suggest that frequency of citation or market success alone should
be adopted as measures of research quality. I do suggest that they should not be so
complacently disregarded in the assessment process. For there is every reason to believe
that they provide an indication of ʻqualityʼ less liable to partiality and prejudice than
the personal judgements of panel members.

A dead hand of conformity


To anyone of my generation, the situation in philosophy being fostered by the current
RAE system will be familiar. We have been there before. When I was a student in the
1960s, philosophy in Britain was entirely dominated by the narrow conception of the
subject which then prevailed in Oxford and Cambridge. There were virtually no courses
in British universities on Hegel, Marx, Nietzsche, Heidegger or Freud. Even Sartre, I
was told by one of my teachers at Cambridge, was ʻnot a philosopherʼ. Philosophy was
treated as an entirely distinct and separate subject. The idea that philosophical insights
could fruitfully be derived from, or applied to, other subjects or concrete practical
issues was alien.
It was to combat this situation, and to provide a forum for an alternative and broader
conception of philosophy, that journals like Radical Philosophy were founded. These
attempts to widen the subject were resisted by the established authorities. Mercifully,
this resistance was largely overcome and the subject has broadened very greatly in the
last thirty years, even if such resistance continues, particularly in those departments
rated as most ʻexcellentʼ by the RAE. Oxford and Cambridge remain almost untouched
by these changes.
Elsewhere, the subject has been transformed. New approaches and ideas have been
introduced and taken up. They have won an audience, they are cited in the literature,
they have gained a market. Citation rates and market forces have proved far more

4 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


responsive to innovation and diversity in the subject than the judgements of senior
academics of the sort typically chosen for the RAE panels.
Such indicators demonstrate the reality of the changes that have occurred in phil-
osophy in Britain, and its resulting diversity, in an empirical and objective manner that
cannot plausibly be dismissed. This is their significance in the present context. Until
this diversity is duly recognized, the RAE system, so far from introducing new oxygen,
will impose a dead hand of conformity on the subject and stifle its development. The
sooner it is changed, the better for British philosophy.

Society for European Philosophy

The results of the recent assessment of philosophy de-


partments within the UK clearly demonstrated the mar-
ginalisation of European philosophical traditions. In order
to counter this marginalisation we believe there is a need
for an organisation which would affirm the expanding
influence and vitality of European philosophical traditions.
We therefore propose that a society be
founded to provide a forum in which all
those working within these traditions
– whether within philosophy depart-
ments or not – could meet, further their
own work and defend their common
interests. Dr Christine Battersby,
University of Warwick
Professor Andrew Benjamin,
University of Warwick
In order to found the Society an Professor Geoffrey Bennington,
inaugural conference will be held University of Sussex
Professor Howard Caygill,
at Birkbeck College, Malet Street,
Goldsmiths College, University of London
London WC1 from 10.30am–4.30pm Dr Simon Critchley,
on Saturday June 28. All those inter- University of Essex
ested in participating in the Society Professor Peter Dews,
are invited to attend. University of Essex
Dr Joanna Hodge,
Manchester Metropolitan University
Panels will include: ʻTraditions in
Professor Salim Kemal,
European Philosophyʼ and ʻThe University of Dundee
Philosophical Geography of Europeʼ Dr Peter Osborne,
Middlesex University
Mr Jonathan Rée,
For further information write to: Middlesex University
Dr Kate Soper,
Society for European Philosophy,
University of North London
c/o Department of Philosophy, Professor Margaret Whitford,
University of Warwick, Queen Mary and Westfield College,
Coventry CV4 7AL University of London

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 5


Generations of feminism
Lynne Segal

Politics makes comics of us all. Or we would weep. being overlooked should we fail to keep abreast of new
Sheila Rowbotham1 theoretical fashions; or unable to admit the tensions
and contradictions of past attachments.
I have been thinking for some time now about political
A small band of feminist historians, mostly in
generations.2 Indeed, I began my last book, Straight
the USA, who are trying to recapture the diversity
Sex, with a reflection upon the enduring impact of
of the movement in which they participated, declare
those formative moments which first enable us to
that they cannot recognize themselves, or others, in
make some sense of the world, and our place within
what they see as the distorting accounts of Womenʼs
it – an unjust and shabby world, whatever our personal
Liberation circulating in contemporary feminism.
circumstances. Such moments remain all the more
Rosalyn Baxandall and Linda Gordon, for example,
powerful if, like many of my own generation who
are gathering material for a multi-volume collection
became students in the 1960s, you have hoped – with
of literature from the movement in the United States.
whatever levels of scepticism and self-mockery – to
They are joined by others interested in archiving
participate in the making of history. They leave their
the local histories of Womenʼs Liberation, such as
mark, even as changing times cause one to rethink,
Patricia Romney, documenting a group of fifty women
perhaps even to renounce, oneʼs formative political
of colour based in New York and Oakland, Califor-
presumptions. Yet, what often leaves erstwhile political
nia, who – with other Black activists in the sixties
crusaders with little more than mournful and confus-
and seventies – became the forgotten women who
ing feelings of loss and regret – whatever our capacities
ʻfell down the wellʼ (as Carolyn Heilbrun puts it)
for irony – is the way in which new narratives emerge
in subsequent rewritings of Womenʼs Liberation as
as collective memories fade, writing over those that
exclusively white.3
once incited our most passionate actions.
These historians are aware of the dangers of their
So it has been with Womenʼs Liberation, that second
proximity to their own research, of how memories
wave of feminism which arose out of the upsurge of
are muted or reshaped by subsequent perspectives and
radical and socialist politics in the late 1960s. It grew
interests – whether oneʼs own, or those of younger
rapidly as a mass social movement, peaking in the
recorders. At a recent symposium on the history of
mid-seventies before dissolving as a coherent organiza-
Womenʼs Liberation in the United States, Margaret
tion by the end of that decade. If only indirectly, it
(Peg) Strobel recounted that even when rereading her
affected the lives of millions of women. Now, however,
own diaries and letters she is amazed at their failure
a quarter of a century later, the sparse amount of
to match her current recollections of the events she
thoughtful scholarship analysing the distinctiveness of
has recorded there.4 Reading our histories through
that movement struggles for attention amidst a glut of
texts delineating its contemporary academic progeny the interpretations of others can be more unsettling
– largely scornful of its rougher parent, and the motley again. Contemporary texts reviewing recent feminist
basements, living rooms, workplaces and community history provide sobering examples of how the past is
centres in which it was hatched. This is not just a inevitably read through the concerns of the present,
female Oedipal tale, as disobedient daughters distance often invalidating earlier meanings and projects and
themselves from their mothersʼ passions, seeking rec- erasing their heterogeneity. The displacement of former
ognition for themselves. It is also a sibling affair, as struggles and perspectives, however, is all the more
feminists contend with each other: fearful, perhaps, of disconcerting when contemporary theorists start off

6 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


from a critical fascination with problems of ʻexperi- structuralism” indicates a field of critical practices that
enceʼ, ʻmemoryʼ and the ʻsilencingʼ of other voices, cannot be totalized.ʼ8) Circumspect and equivocal as
alongside a formal abhorrence of binary logics and Butler characteristically is, always preferring the inter-
apparent scepticism about generalization of all kinds. rogative to the more vulnerable affirmative mode, her
Yet, it is precisely the reckless generalization and false influential writing is always read as primarily decon-
contrasts which astonish me when I read accounts of structive, privileging regulatory semiotic or semantic
the distance self-proclaimed ʻninetiesʼ feminism has issues around ʻsubjectivityʼ, ʻidentityʼ and ʻagencyʼ, in
travelled from Womenʼs Liberation, and what now insisting, as she does here, that: ʻTo recast the referent
appears newly homogenized as ʻseventiesʼ feminism. as the signified, and to authorize or safeguard the
category of women as a site of possible resignifications
is to expand the possibilities of what it means to be
Dubious contrasts a woman and in this sense to condition and enable
A recent British collection, edited by Michèle Barrett an enhanced sense of agency.ʼ9 Butler is certainly
and Anne Phillips, Destabilizing Theory, was put right to stress that ʻwhat women signify has been
together to highlight what it refers to as ʻthe gulf taken for granted for too longʼ. But, in calling for
between feminist theory of the 1970s and 1990sʼ. It ʻthe conditions to mobilize the signifier in the service
opens with the conviction: ʻIn the past twenty years of an alternative productionʼ, she delineates a project
the founding principles of contemporary western fem- that is distinctly distanced from the close attention to
inism have been dramatically changed, with previously social structures, relations and practices which an
shared assumptions and unquestioned orthodoxies rel- earlier feminist project prioritized in pursuit of politi-
egated almost to history.ʼ5 Perhaps so. But just what is cal-economic restructuring, and the transformation
being dispatched here? Was it all of a piece? And is it of public life and welfare. Butler even suggests here:
equally anachronistic for contemporary feminists? ʻParadoxically, it may be that only through releasing
ʻSeventiesʼ feminism is criticized for its ʻfalse cer- the category of women from a fixed referent that
taintiesʼ; its search for structural causes of womenʼs something like “agency” becomes possible.ʼ10
oppression (indeed for its very notion of ʻoppressionʼ); Only? However ʻfictitiousʼ or ʻfixedʼ the category
its belief in womenʼs shared interests (and its very of women, feminists did once manage successfully to
attachment to the notion of ʻwomenʼ or ʻwomanʼ); and mobilize them (and not just signifiers) onto the streets
so forth.6 ʻNinetiesʼ feminism, in contrast, has replaced and into campaigns in support of demands for nurser-
what is seen as the naive search for the social causes ies, reproductive rights, education and skill training;
of womenʼs oppression with abstract elaborations of the to assist women fighting discrimination at work, vio-
discursively produced, hierarchical constitution of an lence at home, militarism world-wide; to work within
array of key concepts: sexual difference in particular, Third World development projects; found the womenʼs
binary oppositions in general, and the hetero/sexual- health movement, and so on and so forth: just as if
ized mapping of the body as a whole. However, it does ʻsomething like “agency”ʼ – womenʼs agency – was
tend to have a few generalizations of its own, not least there all along. A feminism that seeks primarily to
its totalizing dismissal of ʻseventiesʼ feminism, and the re-theorize subjectivity is one that is incommensurate
reduction of dissimilar projects to common ground. with, as well as distanced from, the perspectives and
A somewhat similar tension can be found in a paral- practices of Womenʼs Liberation. It is simply not the
lel American collection aiming ʻto call into question same project, however sympathetic to those earlier
and problematize the presumptions of some feminist goals someone like Butler may be. As others have
discourseʼ: Feminists Theorize the Political, edited by noticed, the commitment to heterogeneity, multiplicity
Judith Butler and Joan Scott, which, like the British and difference underlying recent feminist theorizing
text, was published in 1992.7 Its introductory essay can anomalously disguise a hegemonizing dismissal
shows greater caution in drawing comparisons between of theoretical frameworks not explicitly informed by
different phases of feminism, and it is more aware poststructuralism.11 Joan Scott exemplifies this form
that contrasting ʻpostmodernʼ feminism with an earlier of exclusion of theoretical diversity when attacking
ʻmodernistʼ feminism buys into precisely the conceits ʻresistance to poststructuralist theoryʼ as resistance to
of modernity itself, sharing all its enthusiasm for ʻtheoryʼ itself: ʻSince it is in the nature of feminism to
identification with the ʻnewʼ and overconfident renun- disturb the ground it stands on, even its own ground,
ciation of the ʻoldʼ. (Although it is surely a hostage the resistance to theory is a resistance to the most
to fortune to insist, on the opening page, that ʻ“post- radical effects of feminism itself.ʼ12

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 7


Here is the problem. Contemporary feminist theo- she depicts the first wave of feminism as a time
rizing rarely acknowledges the time and the place when women, using a ʻlogic of identificationʼ, pursued
of political ideas. It addresses only abstract theories liberal, egalitarian ends, followed by the emergence
and their refutation. It operates with an idea of the of a militant second phase, which rejected all ʻpatri-
history of feminism as the evolution of academic archalʼ thought and practice, attempting to create
theory and debate. Tellingly, both the British and ʻcounter societiesʼ constructed around mythical notions
North American feminist collections I have mentioned of womanhood. This is the now familiar account of
offer their readers a full index of names – in which, ʻequalityʼ feminism followed by a strictly alterna-
incidentally, extraordinarily few of the influential tive, ʻdifferenceʼ feminism: with women first seeking
feminist names of the 1970s appear – but no index inclusion in, and later exclusion from, the masculine
of topics. In the recent Blackwell textbook Feminist symbolic order. Drawing on Derrida, Kristeva pro-
Thought, by Patricia Clough, dedicated to ʻWomen poses a third generation of feminism which is critical
Around the World Resisting Oppression, Domina- of the binary of sexual difference itself. Yet, as I hope
tion, and Exploitationʼ, there is a context index, but to show, although they never used the rhetoric of
interestingly neither hint nor whisper of abortion or deconstruction, this is precisely where many second-
reproductive rights, housework, childcare, nurseries, generation feminists came in. The contrasts are not as
welfare provision, immigration, marriage, the family, significant as recent re-tellings suggest.
poverty, the state, employment, trade unions, health-
care or violence against women. There is pornography, Rowbotham’s ‘seventies’ feminism
autobiography, film theory, literary criticism, Woman, In my view, the most useful – and perhaps the only
Native, Other. However you cross-reference it, just a meaningful – way to think about the similarities and
few aspects of womenʼs actual resistance ʻaround the differences between different generations of feminism
worldʼ seem to have gone missing.13 Almost no effort is by reflecting upon what defines a political generation
is made in these texts to refer back to the activities and what smashes its hopes and dreams. On an Inter-
and goals of Womenʼs Liberation, only an attempt to national Womenʼs Day march in the early seventies,
contrast theoretical positions as ideal types. Sheila Rowbotham carried a placard that read: ʻEqual
The reason is, of course, that this is an easy way Pay is Not Enough. We Want the Moon.ʼ (File under
to teach feminism as an academic topic. But you equal-rights feminism? Perhaps not. Is the moon here
cannot translate the time of theory and its fashions a symbol of female difference? I think not.) We got
into political history without absurd caricature. Thus neither, as she wrote a decade later; but the radical
early Womenʼs Liberation becomes, for example, a heritage of Womenʼs Liberation continues, she argued,
ʻfeminism of the subjectʼ, when it was not a theory whenever feminists work to realize the dream ʻthat all
about subjectivity at all. It is almost always described human beings can be more than present circumstances
as a theory of equality rather than of difference, allowʼ.14 That vision is not one of equal rights. It was
when it was neither of these things – the one usually called ʻsocialismʼ and it was being reshaped to service
presented as merely an inversion of the other. Both of feminism.
these descriptions miss the point. Womenʼs Liberation I want, for a moment, to focus on Sheila Rowboth-
in its heyday was a theory and practice of social amʼs writing, as she has been one of the most careful
transformation: full of all the embroiled and messy chroniclers (and continuing exponents) of Womenʼs
actions and compromises of political engagement. It Liberation in Britain, in the hope that it may be, as
endlessly debated questions of priorities, organization she puts it, ʻneither falsely valued nor undervaluedʼ, but
and alliances in the attempt to enrich womenʼs lives that feminists might reflect back upon ʻthe hurly-burly
(heatedly discussing the varied – often opposed – inter- of battle, draw clarity from real muddles and learn
ests of different groups of women). In the process, it from our mistakesʼ.15 (Dream on!, one might feel, in
transformed the very concept of the ʻpoliticalʼ, giving these new mean-spirited times.) Since memories only
women a central place within it. find resonance at certain times, Rowbotham adds, if
My sense of the recent history of feminism, in you ʻignore the humdrum you fall into arroganceʼ.16 It
particular of the socialist-feminist strand of Womenʼs was Rowbotham, one of the many inspirational voices
Liberation flourishing in the early seventies, conflicts of seventiesʼ feminism, who proposed the very first
with Julia Kristevaʼs often cited stagist mapping of Womenʼs Liberation conference in Britain at Ruskin
three generations of feminist thought, in her famous College in 1970; importantly for my purposes here, her
essay ʻWomenʼs Timeʼ, first published in 1979. There books were read by tens of thousands of feminists in

8 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


the 1970s. They were hugely influential in the initial Ignorant of ʻpoststructuralismʼ Rowbotham may have
years of Womenʼs Liberation. Rowbotham would be been (writing these words in the early 1970s, in her
criticized, early on, as representing a seventiesʼ femi- mid-twenties), but not so ignorant, I would suggest, of
nism, unformed by psychoanalysis or structuralism.17 the issues it addresses.
Today, of course, her failures would be seen as an inat- She tussles (a favourite word) endlessly with the
tention to poststructuralism or ʻpostmodernityʼ – that problems of relying on direct experience, seeing it as
paradoxical twist of modernity, contrarily repudiating both a strength and a weakness – again not so unlike,
linear narratives while depending on one. but less theoretically fine-tuned than, the recent essay
Joining the game of textual analysis, I recently re- by Joan Scott on the same topic in the collection from
read some of Rowbothamʼs books from the seventies the USA mentioned above.23 She continuously affirms
and early eighties: something I do often to prevent the pointlessness of attempting to pin down the nature
my own long-term memories from dissolving (there of either ʻwomenʼ or ʻmenʼ, adding that, ʻAll revo-
seems nothing to be done about the crashing of short- lutionary movements create their own ways of seeing
term memory). Ironically, what is extraordinary about … But this is a result of great labour.ʼ24 Her writing,
Rowbothamʼs writing is usually quite the reverse of like the forces which drew many women together in
what critics of seventiesʼ feminism imagine. It conveys the early years of Womenʼs Liberation, reflects the
an openness, a chronic lack of certainty, an almost radical Left (largely Marxist) thought of the day: ʻAn
infuriating tentativeness, reiteratively asserting: ʻWhat emergent female consciousness is part of the specific
we have developed through action and ideas has always
sexual and social conjuncture, which it seeks to control
to be subject to reassessmentʼ; or ʻI am too encumbered
and transform.ʼ25 So, while questions of subjectivity
by the particular to move with grace and delicacy
and identity are not ignored (and, when they appear,
between subjective experience and the broad sweep
they are quite as shifting, provisional and contingent as
of social relationships.ʼ18
any postmodernist might desire), the goal is always to
From her earliest reflections, Rowbotham describes
transform society, to make it a better place for all its
the search for the roots of womenʼs subordination as a
members, especially the neediest, and, in her words,
ʻperilous and uncertain questʼ.19 Her texts always stress
ʻgradually accumulate a shared culture of agitationʼ.
what she calls ʻthe differing forms and historically
She writes:
specific manifestations of the power men hold over
women in particular societiesʼ.20 They focus sharply There is democracy in the making of theories which
on the diversity and situational specificity of women: set out to rid the world of hierarchy, oppression and
whether of class, race, employment, domestic situation domination. The act of analysis requires more than
concepts of sex and class, more than a theory of
(although not at first, as she herself soon notes self-
the subject, it demands that in the very process of
critically), sexual orientation: ʻOur own indications are thinking we transform the relations between thinker
only tentative and incomplete … Womenʼs liberation and thought about, theory and experience … Analy-
is too narrow in social composition to comprehend sis is not enough alone, for we enter the beings and
the differences between middle class and working worlds of other people through imagination, and it
class, black and white, young and old, married and is through imagination that we glimpse how these
might change.26
unmarried, country and townswomen.ʼ Moreover, she
writes in 1972, ʻit is clear that most of the isolated Many seventiesʼ feminists have recalled, like Row-
gains we can make can be twisted against women and botham, the imaginative leap when they first began to
that many partial gains are often a means of silencing turn outwards to other women, generating an almost
one group at the expense of another.ʼ21 She emphasizes open-ended desire for solidarity with just those women
the role of language as one of the crucial instruments they had hitherto distanced themselves from: ʻThe
of domination: mainspring of womenʼs liberation was not a generalised
As soon as we learn words we find ourselves out- antagonism to men but the positive assertion of new
side them … The underground language of people relationships between women, sisterhood.ʼ27 Socialist
who have no power to define and determine them- feminists argued that while capitalist societies had
selves in the world develops its own density and changed the relative power and privileges of men,
precision … But it restricts them by affirming their they had also consolidated womenʼs inferior status,
own dependence upon the words of the powerful …
along with that of a multitude of other historically
There is a long inchoate period during which the
struggle between the language of experience and the subordinated groups – predominantly along racialized
language of theory becomes a kind of agony.22 and ethnic lines. So while it was not inconceivable

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 9


that women might gain equality with men in exist- nism, we also need to consider its limitations. But
ing capitalist societies, this would require such deep the precarious presumptions and faltering visions of
levels of cultural, economic and political change that the seventiesʼ feminism I knew have, as I see it, little
they would already have become societies which were to do with dogmatic certitudes, conceptual closure,
fundamentally different from any we have known.28 binary thinking, identity politics or false universalism,
The state, in socialist-feminist analyses like those and much more to do with the floundering fortunes of
of Elizabeth Wilson or Mary McIntosh, was seen as grassroots or movement politics in harsh and unyield-
not strictly ʻpatriarchalʼ, but serving to regulate, and ing times.
occasionally to restructure, the often contradictory and And I am not forgetting the many painful clashes,
conflicting needs of a male-dominated market economy at the turn of the 1980s, as a strengthening Black femi-
and the still intrinsically patriarchal arrangements of nism challenged Eurocentrism in the priorities of much
family life.29 It was from such analyses that they set white socialist-feminist analysis, which privileged
about shaking out and making visible the separate and sexism over racism and ignored the particularities
distinct needs and interests of women (kept hidden by of ethnic difference. But trying to learn to listen to,
familial rhetoric); campaigned against state policies and act upon, Black feminist perspectives was not
and discourses which defined and enforced womenʼs initially a decisive factor in the fading away of social-
dependence on men; demanded an end to social neglect ist-feminism. On the contrary, Black feminists then
of women and children at risk from menʼs violence; occupied the same political spaces, and pursued largely
fought for more and better social provision and com- similar or parallel strategic campaigns for expanding
munity resources – all the while seeking alliances the choice and resources open to Black women and
with other oppressed groups. Strategic priorities were their families. The political limitations they saw in
usually paramount, whether making demands on the what they defined as ʻEuro-Americanʼ feminism, at
state or the trade unions, and even when elaborating that time, as Valerie Amos, Gail Lewis, Amina Mama
utopian visions of communities and workplaces com- and Pratibha Parmar made clear in 1984, was that it
patible with choice and flexibility, where the needs of has ʻcontributed to an improvement in the material
all dependent people would not hidden away in ideal- situation of white middle-class women often at the
ized, yet neglected and isolated, often impoverished, expense of their Black and working class “sisters” …
family units.30 The power of sisterhood stops at the point at which
This socialist-feminist strand of Womenʼs Liber- hard political decisions need to be made and political
ation, chronicled in books like Rowbothamʼs The priorities decided.ʼ32
Past Is Before Us, remained
until the mid-eighties an active
and influential source of ideas
and strategies for promoting
womenʼs interests, usually
working in diverse radical and
reformist coalitions with other
progressive forces.31 However,
the frustration and defeats of
a second term of Conservative
rule (1983–87), which targeted
and weakened precisely those
nooks and crannies in local
government, resource centres
and collective spaces that femi-
nists (and other radicals) had
managed to enter, gradually
exhausted not only the politi-
cal hopes, but even the dreams
of many. In recalling the early
achievements of the womenʼs
movement in re-launching femi-

10 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


The death knell of the seventiesʼ feminism I dwelt adult education into professional status in the univer-
within was not simply the fall-out from internal conflict sities – promoting conceptual uncertainty, political
and divisions, whether over race or sexuality – much indeterminacy and subjective fluidity – opposing
as they turned feminist political spaces into stressful forms of feminist fundamentalism, moral certainty and
combat zones. Rather, coming together as agitators, of psychic essentialism now really were entrenching them-
whatever sex, race or ethnic specificity, to pursue goals selves as the wisdom of the more accessible activist
which require, among other things, a more egalitarian feminism of the eighties. The voices of feminism – like
and caring world, brought us up against a ferocious, if those of Robin Morgan and Andrea Dworkin – which
survived and intensified in the new decade were no
contradictory and erratic, political opponent – some-
longer analysing the specific historical contexts, shifting
thing a new generation of officially licensed theorists,
institutional arrangements, particular social practices
turning inwards rather than outwards, often prefer to
or multiple discourses securing womenʼs inequality
ignore altogether. Over the last two decades, the ever
and marginality. Instead, they denounced the ageless
more deregulated, ever more universalized, interests
dominance of ʻmasculineʼ values over ʻfeminineʼ ones.
of capital have produced deepening social inequali-
A new and complacent romance around the feminine
ties, nationally and internationally. In the process, took precedence as essentially nurturing, non-violent
they have ensured a significant increase in womenʼs and egalitarian; there was an accompanying condemna-
poverty. Meanwhile the fickle, unintended effects of tion of men and masculinity as ineluctably dominating,
market forces and new technologies, alongside the destructive and predatory, rooted in the performance
arduously pursued, intended consequences of feminist of male sexuality.
thought and campaigning, have ensured more paid It was this form of so-called ʻcultural feminismʼ
work, autonomy and choice for other women, at least that I criticized in Is the Future Female? in the late
in the First World (as well as more insecurity for 1980s. The original subtitle of my book, ʻArguments
some men). for Socialist Feminismʼ, was rejected by my publisher,
Twenty years ago it would have been hard to find a Virago Press, as already too unpopular to promul-
single self-respecting feminist in Britain who had not gate, leading to the more neutral ʻTroubled Thoughtsʼ
of its published subtitle.34 Politically, Dworkin and
trekked out to the Grunwick factory in West London,
MacKinnon ushered in the simplistic and reductive
in support of the predominantly Asian women on
anti-pornography campaign as the single most visible
strike, or at least considered such action. In the nine-
and highly funded feminist struggle in recent years.
ties, as Melissa Benn has noted, it would be hard to
The pessimistic corollary of the rejection of historical
find a self-respecting feminist who had even heard of
specificities in this feminist discourse is the dismissal
the predominantly Asian women on strike at Burnsall
of the significance of womenʼs political struggles and
in Birmingham over an almost identical set of issues:
victories: ʻOur status as a group relative to menʼ,
refusal of union recognition, low pay, and the use of MacKinnon declared, ʻhas almost never, if ever, been
dangerous chemicals; or who would have contemplated much changed from what it is.ʼ35 Without buying
supportive action, if they had.33 For sure, Rowbotham into backlash anti-feminism, or the howls of anguish
and like-minded socialist-feminists, working to help we currently hear from and about men, I think we
organize support for women in struggle against the might agree that this is not a very accurate picture
harshest effects of global market forces, had for a of the gender changes and turmoil that have occurred
while a certain naiveté about the nature and potential throughout this century, and especially of the shake-
of ʻrevolutionaryʼ movements. The legacy of seventiesʼ ups over the last three decades. Meanwhile, as the
feminism, seen as a movement of social transformation 1980s progressed, it was either those, like Catharine
aiming to increase the power and self-determination MacKinnon, who offered some version of an increas-
of women everywhere, is contradictory and diverse. ingly totalizing and sanctimonious feminism (clinging
But serious consideration of its full significance is to the moral high ground of womenʼs marginality and
grievously absent in recent appraisals. helplessness), or others, like Camille Paglia, with
Theoretical assaults equally totalizing inversions of this position (caricatur-
There is another twist in this tale of two generations of ing feminism as prudish and puritanical) who found
feminism. In terms of the later writing over of earlier favour with the media. Neither offered any challenge
feminist narratives, the painful irony is that just as to traditional gender discourses.
deconstruction and other forms of poststructuralism It is hard to summarize the illuminations and provo-
imprinted themselves on the academic feminism which cations of academic feminismʼs current embrace of
had graduated from its lowly seventiesʼ birthplace in poststructuralist critiques of universalizing thought

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 11


and emancipatory narratives without courting the ride with its own cheerfully embraced contradictions),
danger of homogenizing contemporary theorizing, once we turn from the academic to the political realm.
much as it has erased the complexities of seventiesʼ As I have argued elsewhere, it is precisely ideas of
feminism. The appropriation of poststructuralist priori- sexual difference encompassing the experiences sup-
ties would inspire what has become known as ʻfeminist posedly inscribing our distinctive ʻfemalenessʼ which
postmodernismʼ – although this conceptually confused most dramatically divide, rather than unite, feminists
and confusing label would not be accepted by all those attempting to fight for womenʼs interests.39 It is easier
placed under its banner. At least three separate strands for women to join forces around issues on the cur-
of thinking are usually lumped together under this rently unfashionable economic front (demanding parity
heading – deriving from Lacan, Derrida and Foucault, in wages and training), or social policy (demanding
respectively – despite their very different implications more and better publicly funded welfare resources),
for feminism. than it has ever been for women to unite around
The first and for a while the most influential post- issues of sexuality and the meanings we attach to
Lacanian strand, often simply called ʻFrench femin- the female body. Creatively exciting as the project of
ismʼ, restricts its focus to the idea of sexual difference re-imagining female corporeality has proved to be to
effaced by the spurious unity or wholeness of the some feminists,40 its neglect of issues of class, race,
Western ʻsubjectʼ (Man): the white, male bourgeois ethnicity and other forms of marginality as equally
subject of history who hides behind the abstract constitutive of womenʼs subjectivity and destiny has
universals of the philosophical tradition. It stresses seemed exclusionary and disempowering to other
the need to fracture the universal or humanist self feminists. Such criticism has been most forcefully
through attentiveness to its repressed or marginalized expressed by Black and ethnic minority feminist theo-
other: ʻfeminineʼ difference. Subversively imagined reticians – from Gayatri Spivak to Barbara Christian
and rewritten as positive, the decentred side of the or Deborah McDowell.41 Some academic feminists like
to quote Gayatri Spivak in support of their view that
silenced and repressed ʻfeminineʼ is thought to enable
women today must ʻtake “the risk of essence” in order
women to ʻforesee the unforeseeableʼ, and escape the
to think really differentlyʼ.42 Spivak herself, however,
dichotomous conceptual order in which men have
has reconsidered her earlier suggestion for a ʻstrategicʼ
enclosed them.36 This new focus upon images of
use of a positive essentialism. Since such a move is
female corporeality has been seen by its exponents
viable only when it serves ʻa scrupulously visible
as presenting a fresh purchase on the old essentialism
political interestʼ, she now warns: ʻThe strategic use
debate, transcending earlier forms of historical, socio-
of essentialism can turn into an alibi for proselytizing
logical or psychoanalytic anti-essentialist arguments.
academic essentialisms.ʼ43 And it has.
The ʻfeminine feminineʼ, Luce Irigaray and Hélène Spivak leads us to the second, more rigorous,
Cixous suggest, can emerge only once women find Derridean strand of feminist poststructuralism, which
the courage to break out of the male imaginary and is critical of the monolithic Lacanian version of differ-
into a female one; once women begin to speak and ence theory. It questions all universalizing or totalizing
write their sexuality, which is always plural, circular theoretical tendencies, deconstructing every discursive
and aimless, in contrast to all existing singular, linear patterning of the self, including that of ʻwomanʼ.44
and phallocentric, masculine forms of symbolization.37 Here, in tune with the input of Black, Third World,
Such feminist reclaiming of the body unfolds here as lesbian, and other feminisms, every generalization
always culturally and psychically inscribed female about women, including the feminist search for the
experience, not anatomical destiny, and is perhaps best causes of womenʼs subordination or any generalized
seen as a form of aestheticized, high modernist, ʻavant- expressions of womenʼs difference – whether seen in
gardismʼ.38 It is nevertheless still narrated in terms of terms of responsibility for child-rearing, reproductive
a universal corporeal subjectivity for women. and sexual experience, menʼs violence, phallogocen-
The attraction of such difference theory, which tric language, a female imaginary, or whatever – is
allows the feminist to speak ʻas a womanʼ, is obvious. regarded with suspicion. This position is summed up
The revaluing of those aspects of womenʼs lives by Donna Haraway:
and experiences previously ignored or demeaned in
There is nothing about being ʻfemaleʼ that naturally
male-centred theorizing was, and remains, crucial
binds women. There is not even such a state as ʻbe-
to feminist research and practice. But there is still ingʼ female, itself a highly complex category con-
a problem which it cannot easily tackle (even if we structed in contested sexual scientific discourses and

12 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


social practices … The feminist dream of a common ʻqueer theoristsʼ have understood Butler to be suggest-
language, like all dreams for a perfectly true lan- ing a type of individual transgressive ʻperformanceʼ
guage, of a perfectly faithful naming of experience, as the most relevant way of undermining existing
is a totalizing and imperialistic one.45
gender dynamics, it is an interpretation she herself
Haraway wants to replace this dream with her own now rejects.50 Meanwhile, some feminists have used
one of ʻa powerful infidel heteroglossia … building Foucault to reject earlier feminist analysis of power in
and destroying machines, identities, categories, relation- relation to key structural and institutional sites. Again,
ships, spaces, storiesʼ, seeking a place for women in a as often noted, the problem here is that it discourages
future ʻmonstrous world without genderʼ.46 Her dream analysis of where and how women are best placed to
is full of playful optimism about the future. For other combat the authority and privilege men commonly
more strictly deconstructive feminists, however, there wield over them – by entering those sites which are
is no theoretically defensible affirmative position, but most expedient or have proved receptive to change, and
only a reminder of the limits of concepts, as Spivak supporting strategies to undermine or transform those
explains: ʻthe absolutely other cannot enter into any which remain most rigid and resistant to change.51
kind of foundational emancipatory projectʼ.47 Such a
deconstructive feminism certainly avoids the perils Political agendas
of generalizations about female subjectivity. But it Poststructuralism, especially in its Derridean and
courts the danger that its own interest in endlessly Foucauldian forms, has provided feminists with fresh
proliferating particularities of difference, and the (if not unique) conceptual tools for problematizing
partial, contradictory nature of womenʼs identities, identities and social differences. It usefully emphasizes
endorses a relativity and indeterminacy which works their hierarchically imposed and coercive nature, and
to undermine political projects. the multiplicity of intertwining, destabilizing and exclu-
The third, Foucauldian, strand of poststructuralist sionary discourses or narratives in which subjectivities
feminism returns us to the body – to its ʻsexualityʼ are historically enmeshed. It suggests the possibility
rather than to sexual difference – but only as a site (however difficult) of categorial re-significations or
or target of ubiquitous technologies of classification, reconfigurations, as well as the need for acceptance of
surveillance and control. Foucaultʼs warning that oppo- paradox and contradiction in conceptualizing change.
sitional discourses are inevitably caught up in the Feminists need to pay heed to the normativities and
relations of domination they resist has been impor- exclusions of discourse, especially as they construct
tant in highlighting the traps facing emancipatory differences between women. But in a world of inten-
movements: of reproducing rather than transcending sifying inequality, any concern with either gender
traditional frameworks of subjection. And his argu- justice or the fate of women overall must also direct
ments about meaning and representation have proved us to issues of redistribution, alongside issues of
particularly productive for lesbian and gay theorists. identity and recognition.52 It is a socialist imaginary,
Here, feminists can learn much from Foucaultʼs combined with feminism, that has always stressed the
insights about the genealogy of discursive regulation, sufferings caused by the material exploitation, depriva-
but next to nothing about how organized resistance tion and social marginalization of women and other
might impinge on such all-encompassing regimes of oppressed groups around the world. These cannot be
power, other than through the discursively disruptive, either superseded or replaced by battles over discursive
micro-political strategies favoured by some lesbian marginalization and invalidation. The two objectives,
theorists. though relatively distinct, are also intricately inter-
Judith Butler, for example, suggests ways of making woven: the one turning feminists outwards towards
ʻgender troubleʼ by subverting the masculine/feminine women in struggle; the other directing us inwards
binary producing sexuality as heterosexuality. Empha- towards refiguring a hitherto abjected ʻfemininityʼ.
sizing the multiplicity of sexual acts which occur in Once we address both sets of issues, then some dif-
a non-heterosexual context can, she concludes, disrupt ferences will matter more than others in generating
and disturb dominant heterosexual/reproductive dis- political interventions.
courses, ʻthrough hyperbole, dissonance, internal con- However plural and irreducibly complex our char-
fusion and proliferationʼ.48 But despite its influence on acterization of the social, any politics seeking the
some feminists, others respond with sheer bewilder- most inclusive transformation of socio-economic and
ment or exasperation at what they see as the staging cultural marginalization must seek to challenge the
of battles at a strictly semiotic level.49 And while some major systems of domination. This means seeking

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 13


to understand just what they are at this historical cance of gender in favour of a plurality of differences.
moment: uncovering why, and how, they persist, as The tenacity of menʼs power over women means that
well as their interaction with whatever specific location feminists must just as tenaciously seek to emphasize
we occupy. Fearful of totalizing generalizations we the diverse and multiple effects of gender hierarchy on
may be, and cautious we must be, but the central global the lives and experiences of women. But if feminism is
axes of economic exploitation and cultural oppression to address the problems of the many women who need
continue to construct and reconstruct themselves in it most, it must see that the specificities of womenʼs
the interrelated terms of ʻgenderʼ (tied in with sexual lives do not reduce to gender, which means working
orientation), ʻclassʼ (tied in with nationality and eth- in alliance with other progressive forces combating
nicity), and ʻraceʼ (tied in with nationality, ethnicity class, racialized, ethnic and other entrenched social
and religion), within what is currently the ever more hierarchies.
totalizing control of a transnational capitalist market. Interestingly, one of the continuing threads between
The invocation of specific differences can only serve seventiesʼ and ninetiesʼ feminisms (and there are
broadly based transformative ends as part of some many such threads, although we may not read about
wider political project seeking to dismantle these basic them in a significant number of ninetiesʼ feminist
structures of domination. texts) is the continuing growth and vision of the
The Anglo-American reception of poststructuralism, international human-rights movements, now often in
with its central place in ninetiesʼ feminist theory, came the form of NGOs.55 Even there, however, as Suzanne
to prominence at a political moment far removed from Gibson and Laura Flanders have described, it has
that which generated the confident hopes Womenʼs proved far easier for women to get their demands
Liberation took to the streets. (Ironically, some expli- taken seriously by the United Nations when they
cations and critiques of ʻpostmodernismʼ present it have addressed gender-specific, apparently fashion-
as responsible for putting feminism on the political able, issues like rape and violence against women,
agenda, as in Eagletonʼs recent The Illusions of Post- than when they have addressed employment rights,
modernism;53 while others would see its influence as illiteracy or poverty.56 Back in Britain, there will be
quite the reverse.) Distrustful, when not dismissive, little significant change in the situation of the women
of traditional forms of collective action and reformist who are worst off until public resources are shifted
political agendas, especially when class-based, femin- to provide far greater welfare provision, without the
ism faces inhibiting dilemmas in describing how either constraints of market considerations. Yet todayʼs
attention to the discursive specificity of ʻfeminineʼ Foucauldian-informed feminists who write about the
difference, or the proliferation of categorial hetero- state reject earlier feminist analysis of its structures
geneity and transgressive display, might ever again and functions, claiming, like Rosemary Pringle and
bring women together in any transformative feminist Sophie Watson, that ʻ[i]n poststructuralist accounts of
project. the state, “discourse” and “subjectivity” rather than
We need to remember that the word ʻfeministʼ has structures and interests become the key terms.ʼ57 But
a history. Sometimes feminists have focused directly such re-theorizing only leads us further away from
on issues of sexual difference; at other times feminism any analysis of the state itself, and the way in which
has been more a movement for the transformation of it has been changing in recent years. The state now
the whole of society. At the close of the nineteenth embraces market forces in most of the areas from
century, ʻfeminismʼ first appeared in English to des- which they were previously excluded, and precisely
cribe the movement of women campaigning for the against the interests of, in particular, women, children
right to vote, but within a few decades the concept and all dependent people.
had expanded to include a variety of different types Britain, like North America, has been moving as
of moral, economic, social and political campaigns fast as it can in quite the opposite direction to that
waged by women. The second wave of Western femi- which might assist those women in greatest need of
nism has similarly drawn upon different meanings, economic and social support. This is why I remain
at times stressing social transformation (especially in a socialist-feminist: still hoping for more dialogue
its early days), at others emphasizing gender-specific than I find at present between different generations
issues.54 The difficulties of generalizing from womenʼs of feminism. Sometimes, as one of my colleagues
experiences (or ʻcorporeal existenceʼ, through whatever writes, recalling his own formative moments in North-
mode of representation) are not hard to document. ern Ireland, you need to have the ʻcourage of your
Nevertheless, it is premature to downplay the signifi- anachronismsʼ.58

14 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Notes limitations in perspectiveʼ (Rowbotham, Dreams and
Dilemmas, p. 59).
1. Sheila Rowbotham, ʻReclaim the Moonʼ, in Dreams and
26. Rowbotham, Dreams and Dilemmas, pp. 74, 208, 218.
Dilemmas, Virago, London, 1983, p. 348.
27. Ibid., p. 83.
2. This is a revised version of a talk given at the Radical
28. Ibid., p. 82.
Philosophy Conference, ʻTorn Halves: Theory and Poli-
29. Elizabeth Wilson, Women and the Welfare State, Tavis-
tics in Contemporary Feminismʼ, London, 9 November
tock, London, 1977; Mary McIntosh, ʻThe State and the
1996.
Oppression of Womenʼ, in Annette Kuhn and AnnMarie
3. Patricia Romney, unpublished notes prepared for round-
Wolpe, eds, Feminism and Materialism: Women and
table discussion, ʻWriting about a Visionary Movement
Modes of Production, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London,
in the “Get Real” World of the ʼ90s: The History of
1978. Some later commentators, though sympathetic to
Womenʼs Liberation in the United Statesʼ, at the 10th
the accounts of the state provided in this writing, would
Berkshire Womenʼs Conference, North Carolina, June
suggest, I think correctly, that they diminished the in-
1996.
trinsically male-dominated structures, practices and
4. Margaret Strobel, in ibid.
discourses of the many differing sectors of the state (S.
5. Michèle Barrett and Anne Phillips, eds, Introduction,
Franzway, D. Court and R.W. Connell, Staking a Claim:
Destabilizing Theory: Contemporary Feminist Debates,
Feminism, Bureacracy and the State, Paladin, London,
Polity Press, Cambridge, 1992, p. 2.
1989).
6. A few years earlier Michèle Barrett had expressed her
30. Michèle Barrett and Mary McIntosh, The Anti-Social
reservations about her own ʻseventiesʼ thinking in Wom-
Family, Verso, London, 1982.
enʼs Oppression Today – in a new preface – indicating
31. Sheila Rowbotham, The Past Is Before Us: Feminism in
(accurately) that recent feminist debate has problem-
Action since the 1960s, Pandora, London, 1989.
atized the notion of ʻwomenʼ and ʻwomanʼ, while sug-
32. Valerie Amos, Gail Lewis, Amina Mama, Pratibha Par-
gesting that the notion of oppression ʻlooks decidedly
mar, Editorial of Many Voices, One Chant: Black Femi-
dated todayʼ.
nist Perspectives, Feminist Review 17, Autumn 1984.
7. Judith Butler and Joan Scott, eds, Feminists Theorize
33. Melissa Benn, ʻWomen and Democracy: Thoughts on
the Political, Routledge, London, 1992.
the Last Ten Yearsʼ, Women: A Cultural Review, vol. 4,
8. Ibid., p. xiii.
no. 3, 1993, p. 237.
9. Butler, ʻContingent Foundationsʼ, in ibid., p. 16.
34. Lynne Segal, Is the Future Female? Troubled Thoughts
10. Ibid.
on Contemporary Feminism, Virago, London, 1987.
11. See, for example, Linda Gordon, ʻReview of Gender and
35. Catharine MacKinnon, ʻPornography, Civil Rights and
the Politics of History by Joan Wallach Scottʼ, Signs 15,
Speechʼ, in Catherine Itzin, ed., Pornography, Women,
Summer 1990.
Violence, and Civil Liberties, Oxford University Press,
12. Joan Wallach Scott, ʻResponse to Gordonʼ, Signs 15,
Oxford, 1992, p. 456.
Summer 1990, p. 859. See also the measured and
36. Hélène Cixous, ʻThe Laugh of the Medusaʼ, in E.
thoughtful account of the erasure of feminist theoreti-
Marks & I. de Courtivron, eds, New French Feminisms,
cal heterogeneity in Susan Stanford Friedman, ʻMak-
Schocken Books, New York, 1981, p. 256.
ing Historyʼ, in Diane Elam and Robyn Weigman, eds,
37. Cixous,ʻThe Laugh of the Medusaʼ; Luce Irigaray, This
Feminism Beside Itself, Routledge, London, 1995.
Sex Which Is Not One, Cornell University Press, Ithaca
13. Patricia Clough, Feminist Thought, Blackwell, Oxford,
NY, 1985, p. 32.
1994.
38. See, for example, Laura Kipnis, ʻLooks Good on Paper:
14. Rowbotham, Dreams and Dilemmas, p. 354, emphasis
Marxism and Feminism in a Postmodern Woldʼ, in Ec-
added.
15. Ibid., pp. x, 351. stasy Unlimited: On Sex, Capital, Gender, and Aesthet-
ics, University of Minnesota Press, Minneapolis, 1993.
16. Ibid., p. 351.
39. Lynne Segal, ʻWhose Left? Socialism, Feminism and
17. Sally Alexander and Barbara Taylor, ʻIn Defence of
the Futureʼ, New Left Review 185, January–February
Patriarchyʼ, in Raphael Samuel, ed., Peopleʼs History
1991.
and Socialist Theory, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London,
40. For imaginative political appropriations of ʻFrench
1981.
feminismʼ, see for example Drucilla Cornell, Beyond
18. Rowbotham, Dreams and Dilemmas, pp. 353, 2.
Accommodation: Ethical Feminism, Deconstruction
19. Rowbotham, Womanʼs Consciousness, Manʼs World,
and the Law, Routledge, London, 1991; Moira Gattens,
Penguin, Harmondsworth, 1973, pp. 66, 34. Imaginary Bodies: Ethics, Power and Corporeality,
20. Rowbotham, Dreams and Dilemmas, p. 83. Routledge, London, 1996.
21. Ibid., pp. 59, 75. 41. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, ʻFrench Feminism in an
22. Ibid., pp. 32–3. International Frameʼ, in In Other Worlds, Routledge,
23. Joan Scott, ʻExperienceʼ, in Butler and Scott, eds., Femi- London, 1988; Barbara Christian, ʻThe Race for Theo-
nists Theorize the Political. ryʼ, in Linda Kaufman, ed., Gender and Theory: Dia-
24. Rowbotham, Womanʼs Consciousness, Manʼs World, logues on Feminist Criticism, Basil Blackwell, New
p. 27. York, 1989; Deborah McDowell, ʻThe “Practice” of
25. Ibid., p. x. Rowbotham prefers, as she writes in 1972, “Theory”ʼ, in Elam and Weigman, eds, Feminism Be-
the idea of ʻconsciousness movingʼ to ʻconsciousness side Itself.
raisingʼ, since ʻyour own perception is continually being 42. See, for example, Alice Jardine, ʻMen in Feminism:
shifted by how other women perceive what has happened Odor di Uomo Or Compagnons de Route?ʼ, in Alice
to them … The main difficulty, still, is that while the Jardine and Paul Smith, eds, Men in Feminism, Methuen,
social composition of womenʼs liberation remains nar- London, 1987, p. 58.
row it isnʼt possible to move naturally beyond certain 43. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, Outside in the Teaching

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 15


Machine, Routledge, London, 1993, p. 4. Recognition? Dilemmas of Justice in a “Post-Socialist”
44. See, for example, Denise Riley, Am I That Name? Femi- Ageʼ, New Left Review 212, July–August 1995.
nism and the Subject of ʻWomenʼ in History, Macmillan, 53. Terry Eagleton, The Illusions of Postmodernism, Black-
London, 1988. well, Oxford, 1996, p. 22.
45. Donna Haraway, ʻA Manifesto for Cyborgs: Science, 54. See Sheila Rowbotham, Women in Movement: Femi-
Technology, and Socialist Feminism in the 1980sʼ, in nism and Social Action, Routledge, London, 1992, pp.
L. Nicholson, ed., Feminism/Postmodernism, Routledge, 8–15.
London, 1990, pp. 197, 215. 55. See Julie Peters and Andrea Wolper, eds, Womenʼs Rights
46. Ibid., p. 215. Human Rights: International Feminist Perspectives,
47. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak, ʻRemembering the Limits: Routledge, London, 1995.
Difference, Identity and Practiceʼ, in Peter Osborne, ed., 56. See Suzanne Gibson, ʻOn Sex, Horror and Human
Socialism and the Limits of Liberalism, Verso, London, Rightsʼ, Women: A Cultural Review, vol. 4, no. 3, Winter
1991, p. 229, emphasis in original. 1993; Laura Flanders, ʻHard Cases and Human Rights:
48. Judith Butler, Gender Trouble: Feminism and the Sub- C. MacKinnon in the City of Freudʼ, The Nation, 9–16
version of Identity, Routledge, London, 1990, p. 33. August 1993, pp. 174–7. For an important and stimu-
49. See Tania Modleski, Feminism Without Women: Culture lating commentary on the challenge of human-rights
and Criticism in a ʻPostfeministʼ Age, Routledge, Lon- internationalism to the recent philosophical embrace of a
don, 1991. ʻpolitics of differenceʼ, see Bruce Robbins, ʻSad Stories
50. Judith Butler, Bodies That Matter: On the Discursive in the International Public Sphere: Richard Rorty on
Limits of ʻSexʼ, London, Routledge, 1993, p. 231; see Culture and Human Rightsʼ, Public Culture, vol. 9, no.
also Peter Osborne and Lynne Segal, ʻGender as Per- 2, Winter 1997.
formance: An Interview with Judith Butlerʼ, Radical 57. Rosemary Pringle and Sophie Watson, ʻ“Womenʼs In-
Philosophy 67, Summer 1994. terests” and the Post-Structuralist Stateʼ, in Barrett and
51. See, for example, Gregor McLennan, ʻFeminism, Phillips, eds, Destabilizing Theory, p. 65.
Epistemology and Postmodernism: Reflections on Cur- 58. Francis Mulhern (quoting Jonathan Rée) in Francis Mul-
rent Abivalenceʼ, Sociology, vol. 29, no. 3, August 1995, hern, Introduction, The Present Lasts a Long Time: Es-
pp. 391–401. says in Cultural Politics, Cork University Press, Cork,
52. See, for example, Nancy Fraser, ʻFrom Redistribution to forthcoming.

16 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Feminism without nostalgia
Diana Coole

The title of the recent Radical Philosophy conference, interventions and successes have recently fallen short
ʻTorn Halves: Theory and Politics in Contemporary here, for reasons broadly connected with the ideo-
Feminismʼ, implied that two things which should be logical climate and an attenuation of the democratic
joined – theory and politics – have come apart; indeed process. Paradoxically, the response by many feminist
have been ripped apart rather violently and now need political theorists – especially in the United States
stitching back together. Is it, then, the case that two – has been to focus on processes of a highly idealized
processes which were, and should be, united, have model of discursive democracy, while paying little
been severed? If this is indeed our situation, then attention to how its preconditions for fair and equal
it suggests that some sort of crisis has befallen us, participation might be realized.
whereby feminist theory and the womenʼs movement At the next level down, feminists identify a series
have moved off in different directions: or even worse, of structures and processes within civil society – such
that one of the pair (and presumably the movement as economy and family – which reproduce sex roles
would be the prime candidate here) has suffered a and gender hierarchies in ways that have formerly been
premature demise. This certainly raises a number of designated oppressive. Intervention is deemed political
pressing questions: what was, or should be, the nature here, since its aim is to eliminate various forms of dis-
of this connection? Why has it been broken? Should crimination and injustice. Arguably this space has seen
we try to repair it, and if so, along what lines? the major staging of second-wave feminism, where the
In trying to respond to these questions, I real- state was more obviously targeted by the first.
ized that the very meanings of politics and theory Now, it is at these two levels, where there is a
have become unclear in feminism. So I will begin massive and resilient institutionalization of more or
by considering each in turn, before addressing their less crude and visible patriarchal power, that women
linkage and suggesting a particular relationship as have been able to situate a politics most unequivocally.
exemplary. It is in these contexts that an earlier discourse was able
to refer to womenʼs oppression and to its opposition
Feminism and the political as the Womenʼs Liberation Movement. Here, then, was
In considering what feminism might mean by the a clear and binary confrontation between the massive
political, I have distinguished between two senses, power of what Habermas calls steering media – state
which I will call the topographical and the dynamic. and economy – on one hand, and a relatively unified
In the topographical sense, politics is located within and militant force on the other. When we lament the
three different domains, each of whose differential demise of our politics, I suspect that it is on these
effects on women have been a source of theory and levels that we situate its loss.
of particular practices. Most explicitly, this spatial But as feminists, we also locate politics in a third
understanding of the political concerns the state as the realm, that of personal life, and although this is both
pinnacle of power, where on the one hand feminists re-enforced by, and in turn re-enforces, the other
demand equal representation and where on the other two levels, the kind of strategies it implies have been
we regard processes of legislation and policy-making quite different from those recognized conventionally as
with a mixture of hope and suspicion. In a rather political. It is surely here that our analyses and prac-
obvious way, anything we do in this context can be tices have been most innovative and specific to gender
regarded as political, and we may well feel that our struggle, although they do not necessarily rely on a

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 17


mass movement since strategies are more individual Feminism and theory
and targets more local. Yet my impression is that poli- I find it helpful to begin here with a distinction between
tics has recently waned here, too, with confrontations empirical studies, theory and abstract philosophy.
over, for example, the division of domestic labour and There are limits to how far this is sustainable, but it
sexual practices either resuming their personal but allows me to associate theory with a specific politi-
apolitical nature, or being displaced by a crisis in the cal task, even if for feminism all three have political
household economy. import. Finding out about womenʼs lives and building
The alternative, dynamic, model of politics con- up empirical data bases has been an essential task in
strues it not spatially but as a process of circulat- overcoming womenʼs social and academic invisibility,
ing and unstable power relations. If one were so and we have succeeded brilliantly here. At the other end
inclined, one could trace it to Machiavelli, Nietzsche of the spectrum, engaging in philosophical questions
and Foucault, but I think it is also encouraged by regarding, for example, epistemology or metaphysics,
feministsʼ own theoretical excavations, which show has given feminism its own grounds for debating the
the powers reproducing sexual inequality and gender foundational nature of gender differentiation. However,
hierarchy moving through all domains of the politi- it is in the middle realms of theorizing, where concept-
cal and indeed overflowing them into the discursive, building and empirical data are brought together, that
linguistic, aesthetic and psychological. This suggests the connection between intellectual work and political
that it is never sufficient to pursue inclusion in gov- intervention is drawn the tightest, and it is here that I
ernment or equal treatment in civil society: instead think we must be concerned if the two part company
politics must involve an ongoing engagement wherever or if theory collapses into either empiricism or abstract
power is present, via deployment of a whole variety of philosophy.
tactics which cannot be formulated in advance. This This does not mean that the only important theory
understanding of politics is most appropriate to the is political theory, but it does suggest that for feminists,
third topographical space of the personal, but it has whose theorizing was from the start directed at chang-
tended to politicize culture as such. ing the world, theory is oriented to political tasks.
There is a certain irony here, since, while many In this sense it is both instrumental in guiding and
feminist philosophers have been intellectually enthusi- inciting practice, and is itself a participant in power
astic about this politics, its significance and efficacy for struggles at a discursive level. Feminism is part of a
a womenʼs movement have been difficult to theorize. tradition that never sees ideas as innocent. Political
The diverse, often aesthetic or performative, strategies, theory, for example, has both legitimized womenʼs
fragmented support and ambiguous goals deployed exclusion from public life and expounded the norms
are not obviously connected to a mass movement and that have constituted and disciplined gendered subjects,
do not self-evidently achieve the sort of outcomes we while it has also been used by feminists as a vehicle
might expect from a successful politics. Indeed I would for framing and legitimizing our own demands.
surmise that it is precisely because this often seems Yet, although theories have often acted as crude
to be the only politics we are currently engaged in ideologies, masking and sustaining patriarchal inter-
that some women might wonder whether we still have ests, they also work more insidiously to represent
a politics at all, or if everything in fact takes place reality in ways that are riddled with gender privileges
within the realm of the theoretical. and exclusions. This means that their demystification
At this stage, however, I only want to question a or deconstruction is a political act. Although it is not
tendency prevalent in this last approach, to collapse easy to point to concrete results, this is an activity that
politics into power relations as such. Power is indeed many feminist theorists and philosophers have been
ubiquitous, but not all power is political. To become engaged in over a long period of time. Presumably
so, it must be structured, conflictual and at least mini- it is an ongoing task we still value, although it may
mally open to change. And, even more importantly, it be helpful to pause every now and then, and to make
must also be articulated in such a way that its presence explicit the strategic aims it bears.
engenders some political mobilization. Where power Where the theory–practice link is more evident,
remains merely habitual and mute, or uncontested, it however, is where theory directs its gaze onto what, for
is at best only latently political and awaits its theor- want of a better phrase, I will call the real world. Now,
etical disclosure and practical resistance to become I have already argued that power becomes political
manifestly so. This, then, brings me to the question only when it is articulated such that conflict becomes
of theory in relation to the political. explicit and a spur to action. But thematizing effects

18 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


of power that were previously only lived is itself a analysis and emphasize fragmentation instead. We
political process. For it is not the case, as we for- are well schooled in antipathy towards Marxian-style
merly tended to believe, that inequalities are hidden totalizations or reductionism. Yet there has also been
truths simply awaiting representation. Power is also a certain retreat from engagement with the real, in
involved in the way – and whether – we problematize light of our epistemological scepticism and its politi-
our situation and the conceptual framework we bring cal intransigence. This needs redressing, whatever its
to bear on the myriad experiences of everyday life. difficulties, if the material and structural bases for
For example, the public/private distinction is not a either equal citizenship, or equal opportunities to be
self-evident opposition simply spread out before us, gender-complex, are to be constructed.
but a wonderfully fecund conceptualization that femi- In this sense I think there is a political problem with
nism has developed to structure the real in ways that the postmodernization of feminism – if I can put it this
explain our exclusions and focus our transgressions. way – in that our pursuit of both diversity and consen-
By representing a complex socio-cultural world from sus has distracted us regarding the nature of political
a particular perspective, we engage in an ideologi- struggle as requiring risky and audacious acts, where
cal/discursive struggle of reality-construction, whereby to theorize politically or to intervene effectively does
lines of conflict, and hence the political itself, are ultimately require acts of conflict and closure, even a
configured. certain militancy. For no matter how much we might
I would not, however, want to claim that this aspire to fulfil the ideals of discursive democracy or
process is reducible to the exercise of naked power to accommodate difference and complexity, we still
or sheer fantasy, since thematizations of oppression or occupy a social field where violence and inequality
discrimination are only resonant to the extent that they require definitive responses which do not fade into
are already materially and existentially suffered prior impotent openness and multiplicity. These latter may
to their discursive representation. The lived world is be, and I believe are, potent strategies on a cultural
sufficiently open to accommodate a variety of interpre- level. But in the socio-economic domain, where there
tations and silencings, and for women the way it is are more or less veiled conflicts of interest, struc-
presented is crucial in giving our politics both a norm- tured inequalities and zero-sum games, more definitive
ative basis and strategic direction. But representation is analyses and mobilizations are necessary.
never just relative, since it is anchored in experience. So far I have been considering what politics and
Moreover, the clarity with which the disadvantages theory mean for feminism, and I would now like to
bestowed by gender at any given time can be articu- be clear about the conclusions I derive from this.
lated must have a bearing on womenʼs politicization A topographical approach to the political locates it
and mobilization, since if theory is to inspire action, in a variety of domains, where the nature of power
it must be felt to be ʻtrueʼ and consequential, not just and of appropriate strategic engagement with it vary.
abstract or ideological posturing. In so far as we both sense an eclipse of womenʼs
Yet this is where I think we do confront a dilemma political practice and feel some urgency regarding
today. Our own studies have increasingly shown sexual its resuscitation, I would situate these specifically in
inequality to be extremely complex and diffuse, as the realms of state and civil society, where I have
well as revealing gender identity as a diverse and suggested that highly organized structures of power
ambiguous phenomenon. In one sense we can use this sustain more or less experiential, explicit and visible
knowledge politically, to deconstruct vulgar notions of forms of discrimination which require collective action
binary sexual difference. But at the same time, our and political mobilization on a significant scale if they
more sophisticated theorizing has tended to dilute a are to be effectively challenged.
formerly more incisive representation of opposition To render the power that operates here political,
and oppression, which makes collective action difficult however, its theorization is required, and this involves
in the political and economic domains – that is, pre- both a direct involvement in discursive struggles and
cisely where the power that sustains sexual inequality a reading of events that takes their density and inertia
regarding rights and resources is most massive and seriously by thematizing a complex field of forces
consolidated. In part it is true that postmodernization where different lines of strategy and defence are, if not
has rendered those realms more difficult to under- determined, at least circumscribed. It follows from this
stand comprehensively, and therefore more immune to that a crucial role for feminist theory is to engage in a
any obvious oppositional strategy. But we have also dialectical reading of the present in order to formulate
been seduced by discourses that distrust structural tactics and opportunities and to mobilize its forces.

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 19


Indeed it is here that I want to locate an exemplary fact crucial, Mitchell argued, in two ways. First, it
theory–practice relationship, and I would suggest that was prefigurative: that is, it might be described as a
it is its demise that has resulted in our current sense form of unmediated political engagement in so far as
of crisis and torn halves. In order to illustrate what small womenʼs groups perform a new mode of inter-
I have in mind, I want to go back twenty-five years subjectivity and a new political style that is consonant
or so, to a brief reconsideration of one of modern with feminist values – ʻcollective workʼ, as she says,
feminismʼs founding texts: Juliet Mitchellʼs Womanʼs ʻis part of the processʼ, although it cannot be an end
Estate (1971). in itself since then it would be a merely moral, rather
than political, solution.
Woman’s Estate Secondly, then, it is important that small groups
In the preface to this work, Mitchell offered a list of should coalesce into revolutionary collectives. This
political actions which provided a legacy for 1960sʼ is strategically necessary, but more importantly, as
feminism. The suffragettes, she recalls, burnt down far as theory is concerned, it is at this level that a
houses, smashed shop windows, destroyed buildings, general theorization of womenʼs oppression, as well
blew up letter boxes and cut telegraph wires. Here as strategies for liberation, are forged. The small
was an unambiguous confrontation negotiated through group allows women to discuss personal experience,
direct action; and although Mitchell never associates and through discussion to recognize that the personal
herself with this type of violence against property, she is political. This does not mean for Mitchell that
does present the movement early in its second wave politics is a micro-matter, reduced to the level of the
as comparable and revolutionary. She also explains individual, but that personal experiences of oppression
its re-emergence and radicalism as a consequence come to be understood as instances of a more general,
of two factors: the contemporary situation (in which structural oppression whose resolution can only be
women were at the forefront of acute contradictions collective. The broader groups then work on analys-
within capitalism) and the simultaneous explosion ing these structures, but it is crucial that they are not
of other radical political movements which forged imposing some pre-existent formula. Theory grows out
important alliances with feminists. She further traces of personal experience and interprets it by eliciting
the womenʼs movementʼs own political influences in generalities which are then related to structural forces.
anarcho-syndicalism, anarchism, the Situationists, the Politics is strategically guided by such theory, and
anti-psychiatry movement and even terrorism, as well theory mobilizes the individuals to whom it speaks
as in Marxist and liberal political thought. In short, to collective acts. In so far as change occurs, then
Mitchell is in no doubt that the womenʼs movement is the new conditions call for new theorization, different
born out of an activist, even revolutionary, past, and strategies, and so on.
that it will continue its trajectory. In this dialectical linkage, there is, then, no question
This does not, however, prevent her from worry- of having to seek the political implications of a theory
ing about its politicization. In contrast to our own subsequently, or of developing an abstract theory whose
anxieties that theory has overtaken practice, she sees connection with lived experience might remain elusive.
the movement in 1971 as tending towards a practice Experience is never taken simply as raw empirical
which is not yet adequately theorized. ʻThe Womenʼs data; nor does theory seek some complete formulation:
Liberation Movementʼ, she writes, ʻis at the stage of they are continuously and mutually refined through
organizing our “instinct” of our oppression as women, their interaction. Women are not presupposed as some
into a consciousness of its meaning.ʼ1 Mitchell insists latent political agency just waiting to be set in motion,
that this cannot be done in abstraction but is a his- but nor do they have to be conjured up subsequently
torical and dialectical process in which theory and out of the complexities of theory.
practice are interwoven at every level. My reason for returning to Mitchell is that her work
The renewed movement had, then, begun as series suggests what I consider to be an exemplary way of
of complaints, derived from experience but at first holding theory and practice together. Much of her work
manifest only in spontaneous protest. This aspect during the 1970s was just such a reading of dominant
must not be lost: ʻWe do have to experience the structures in terms of their contradictions, articulations
implications of our own oppression.ʼ2 But in order and the weak spots at which they were vulnerable to
to render this political, it had to be transformed into change. The details of her analysis, as well as her
a political challenge to social institutions generally. commitment to scientific socialism, may seem dated
The organizational aspect of this challenge was in in the 1990s, but the point is that if we are to act

20 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


strategically; if we are to strike a resonance among the for so-called family values; a popular culture that itself
many and diverse women who suffer various forms of celebrates gender-crossing and which only in its cruder
violence, discrimination, exploitation and oppression forms exhibits the sort of blatant sexism bemoaned
and to incite a further wave of feminist politics; then by Mitchell – these are all structural changes calling
we too need an ongoing analysis of contemporary for new analysis, perhaps new paradigms, regarding
conditions and the political opportunities they allow. their differential effects on women and the feasibility
This surely means turning again to the sort of of response.
political economy and sociology we have largely What is needed, then, is an audit of where women,
abandoned. Of course, for us post-poststructuralists in our commonality and diversity, stand in the context
the cultural and discursive structures that construct of the field of forces which constitutes our situation.
gendered identities remain an important site of analysis This does not mean relying on unmediated accounts
and contestation. But we also need to consider afresh of everyday life, forgetting that our lives are already
the roles and deprivations that are imposed by a system structured by ideology and power, but it does involve
which does identify us as female subjects inhabit- taking account of the specific forms of subordination
ing womenʼs bodies; and granted the anachronism of and power that strike us, since it is impossible to
Mitchellʼs analyses, do we not urgently need a new mobilize people on the basis of theory alone.
theorization of where women (as opposed to genders) Strategically, then, I am suggesting two levels of
stand as the century draws to a close? Should this theorizing. First, we need to look once more at womenʼs
not be the central role for our theory as a guide to an actual experiences in order to elicit generalities. This
engaged practice in public life? was once perceived as intrinsically political, when it
For example, Mitchell wrote of womenʼs exclusion took the form of consciousness-raising and organizing
from the workforce, but today we witness its feminiz- via the proliferation of networks of small groups.
ation. Of course women still occupy worse-paid jobs Should we try to reactivate this process (perhaps
under worse conditions, but the complexities of our via the Internet?), or is it strategic work that might
location in an economy that is both post- and pre- adequately be undertaken from a distance by research-
modern; the growth of a substantial underclass, of ers using interviewing techniques or opinion polls?
which women constitute a significant proportion; the The problem with the latter option is that, although it
effects of information technology on the home/work conveys a sense of objectivity, it ignores a dimension
distinction that has underpinned capitalism thus far, as that was crucial to Mitchellʼs dialectic, where it was
well as our own public/private opposition; the simul- women themselves who collectively articulated the
taneous collapse of the family and a renewed support lacunae they suffered. It is surely not just a matter

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 21


of acquiring knowledge, as if it were already there sometimes collective assaults, are effective. For this
but hidden, but of a process of coming-to-knowledge sort of theorizing must also be resolutely realistic,
which also changes us and our (self-) perceptions on taking into account the status of feminist forces as they
the way. In other words, it is a praxis, not simply an wane or grow; the potential for mass mobilization; the
exercise in data collection. endurance – or not – of a latent feminism that might
Second, we need to locate these findings in a broader be preserved and reactivated; the existence of small
structural context, always remembering that this analy- and piecemeal but nevertheless committed groups of
sis, too, must be resolutely political. Dynamically, the activists and academics. It has some mobilizing capac-
question of the political is one of strategy: of reading ity in its explications of oppressive structures, and it
the present as a shifting field of forces. By this I mean takes an overview of the myriad acts of resistance
that power does not just circulate randomly, passing women still collectively perform, but it is neither naive
through players who are its conduits. It is often exer-
nor unduly pessimistic about the state of womenʼs
cised with hierarchical intent, but in any case it runs
organization at any one time, recognizing that, like
into clots, nodal points, where it undergoes a certain
all movements, it will go through different cycles
ossification and closure whereby some groups are
according to its own inner logic and changing external
consistently more powerful than others. The field of
circumstances. The challenge is to match efficacious
forces may be agonistic, but not all players are equal.
and appropriate strategies to the possibilities of the
A political movement cannot, then, afford to go all
times, while recognizing that womenʼs politics and
the way with a Nietzschean–Foucauldian description of
hardships are themselves constituents of those times,
power flows: it must also focus on the way techniques
of power are captured by institutions; colonized by which do not therefore have to be passively borne. It
privileged groups whose collective acts may indeed is not pragmatism but it is strategic.
result in unintended consequences but whose result
Two waves, no nostalgia!
is nevertheless the reproduction of inequalities and
exclusions. The reason for calling my article ʻFeminism without
A political theorizing must accordingly identify Nostalgiaʼ, despite an appeal to a 1960sʼ praxis, was to
these concentrations of power: not as congealed centres insist that when we express concern over our politics
of domination that would paralyse opposition, but as we must not imagine that we are inhabiting the same
relatively closed (or open) force-fields that must be world. Mitchell was writing during one of those rare
engaged with strategically, in light of their strengths and privileged moments in history when theory and
and gaps. It is in this sense that we continue Mitchellʼs practice do seem able to correspond and reinforce
work, if without the language of contradiction or ambi- one another. Lived experience, as an experience of
tion of liberation. To theorize politically, dialectically, disjunction and discrimination, was relatively homo-
is to ask where resistance might be effective; where geneous and explicit in a context of systemic oppres-
prefigurative alternatives might leave their mark; siveness yet disarray. In other words, there seemed to
where power is experienced as especially intolerable be a certain clarity to the situation which was in step
and whether it thereby incites refusal or complicity. with its articulation by radical groups whom it further
If, for example, we conclude that state and economy served to mobilize and orientate. Today nothing seems
are especially closed and oppressive but that any truly transparent: there are masks, ambiguities, complexities
radical negation is impracticable, then we might invoke and reversals that make the disclosure of oppression
our powers as voters and consumers, both having much more complicated and much less immediately
potentially immense leverage but one dependent on resonant with experience. All this opacity and multi-
effective organization.
plicity makes the dialectical approach, which is what
What this leaves us with is not, at least under
I do want to relearn from Mitchell, so much more
current circumstances, any grand politics. It does not
difficult and mediated, although I am arguing that we
talk of Patriarchy or Capitalism with capital letters,
must attempt it both in terms of immediate strategy,
because it understands that there is no mobilization
currently powerful enough to negate these structures, and in order to make sense of the movementʼs fortunes
even if theory could pin them down. But it does involve in a broader historical context.
a critical engagement by locating all our piecemeal and From this point of view, it seems to me that the
diverse strategies in a larger field of relatively unstable real crisis for feminist politics is that while we are
relations where sometimes small transgressions, and now passing into a historical situation where our

22 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


ʻinstinctsʼ tell us that state and economy – those Although we might pause at Friedanʼs distinction
spaces where the movement has always arisen most between gender issues and social disintegration, or her
dramatically – should again be our target, we no implied relegation of them to smaller issues (especially
longer have the theory or the political organization to since in Britain we may well feel that we have become
respond efficaciously, since our models of theory and insufficiently political even here), I think her emphasis
practice in these domains are now several decades on economic questions is indeed symptomatic of the
old and we do not inhabit a privileged moment in times. It is not a question of adopting her as an
history. We are suddenly lamenting a loss of politics icon, but of noting that, significantly for a liberal
not because women have not been acting politically, feminist, she refers to the limits of an old paradigm
but because what we have been doing is not effective of identity politics and rights, presenting in its place
in the upper topographical regions of power where we a new concern for ʻextreme income inequality, and
now want to engage more dramatically. It would be the concentration of wealth in the top one-half of one
much too complicated to try to work out here why per centʼ. Unsurprisingly, she does not go so far as to
this is, but I would suggest that a worsening economic mention class struggle, but she does look to ʻa new
situation has reached a tipping point, and also that it kind of powerʼ wielded by the combined strength of
has become evident that what many of us believed ʻforces for equalityʼ, which might mobilize support if
would be a temporary phenomenon that could be government and corporations fail to respond to polling
rectified by a change of government is clearly not evidence that the most urgent concerns are those of
after all going to be challenged by parties of the families and jobs. In other words, even Friedan is
so-called Left. arguing for a shift in politics from the personal realm
As an example of some of these developments, I to that of civil society, and she is also anticipating
would like to cite a recent comment in The New Yorker a new mobilization of forces under the banner of
by Betty Friedan.3 The authorʼs identity is significant, economic equality.
since Friedan has long been associated with liberal In the British context, I would like merely to refer to
feminism and the powerful National Organization of an article in The New Statesman and Society,4 which
Women in the United States. She was an icon of reported an extraordinary 81 per cent of respondents
early second-wave feminism alongside Mitchell, since to a recent Gallup poll agreeing that there is a class
she identified ʻthe problem with no nameʼ that was struggle in Britain. Interpreting the responses, the
besetting American housewives. But she was also con- analysts refer to a common-sense view of class derived
sistently criticized by socialist feminists for ignoring from a sense of increasing conflict, predicated upon
the economic obstacles to sexual equality. In 1996, what is happening to people ʻon a day to day basisʼ: an
however, we find her supporting a Stand for Children ʻidea in actionʼ as one calls it, that concerns ʻthe bonds
rally modelled on the Million Man March which had between people that we experience everyday as realʼ.
taken place several months earlier, and writing that The article notes the lack of any political machinery
it ʻis likely to bring out some new thinking that has for reflecting this view, as well as the elusiveness of
been quietly bubbling under the surface of the various the concept of class for theory.
and too often fragmented movements for American These two articles do not, of course, add up to
social renewalʼ. any adequate theorization of the times, but they are
The rallyʼs specific target was draconian cuts in symptomatic, I would argue, of a general feeling that
welfare, which critics saw as disproportionately affect- the political question for the millennium is one of
ing women and children, although its momentum was resource distribution, which calls for more radical
by no means exclusively associated with feminism. responses than the state is willing even to contem-
Nevertheless, Friedan focuses on the womenʼs move- plate. The growth of an underclass, shifts in the job
ment to argue that among many of its supporters market, the decline of welfare support and extensions
there is a of commodification and market relations are all part
growing sense that the time is ripe to go beyond of a resurgence of capitalism which affects all women,
ʻgender issuesʼ that lately have been the move- regardless of our race or class and despite our different
mentʼs prime concerns – abortion, date rape, sexual
situations, and which also affects us more generally as
harassment, pornography, and the like – to such
larger matters as economic distress and social workers and providers. Of course, we have been here
disintegration. before, but in our post-Marxist climate everything

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 23


surely needs to be thought through again, including other words, the question is how to move from tricks
our political responses and interventions which were to tactics; from domination to agonism, where the
clearly inadequate the first time round. ethics Foucault associates with practices of liberty are
Finally, I would also like to situate this problem replaced by collective, political acts.
more historically, and to do so let me take up feminist In a sense this is only repeating what I have already
historiansʼ metaphor of waves. This is quite appro- said, but, since I am broadly trying to synthesis Marx
priate, because the two explosive moments of the and Foucault within a dialectical approach to history,
womenʼs movement – in the latter part of the nine- it is important to realize that Foucault also supports
teenth century and again in the late 1960s – were organized struggle under certain historical conditions.
indeed what I am calling privileged moments, when While it appears to be true that women in the West
women rode the crest of a wave and theory and no longer suffer the degree of oppression evident in
practice were in sync. But between waves there must previous centuries, we might surely claim nevertheless
be troughs – times such as our own, when solidarity that our escape from domination remains hazardous
wanes because lines of oppression are too complex since we have achieved only an incomplete liberation,
and dispersed or invisible to allow experience and where power is neither wholly closed nor open and
theory to gel sufficiently to mobilize mass response. reversible. Accordingly, our dialectical approach to
In this context, the small but multiple transgressions history is also needed to tell us what sort of historical
and resistances, the defences and refusals that diverse cycle we are entering and what kind of strategies are
women have sustained, are appropriate to the con- appropriate. It is not necessarily an approach unique
figuration of forces; and our recent cultural bias is to women (since we are not claiming to be historyʼs
also strategically sensible (although perhaps it is a privileged agents in any teleological sense), but it does
lack of theory we suffer here, in its inability or refusal summon a reading of the present which might locate
to represent these fragments in terms of an overall allies. Moreover, it avoids the false universalizing that
political significance). was a tendency criticized in previous, more overtly
But the movement itself shifts into crisis when the political, feminisms, in so far as it is an approach
situation changes, as the previously cited evidence applicable to diverse groups of women as well as to
suggests it has: when a more organized confronta- women in general, although its focus is on connections
tion with the massive forces of the steering media is and overlappings between them, since it is here that
called for, yet where the kind of organized practices a general theory is constituted out of (and alongside)
that might be efficacious are barely evident in the difference.
current field of forces. To put all this in a different If we are indeed entering a new period where civil
language: we might associate the crests of waves with society is again experienced as the most significant,
a politics of liberation, and the responses appropriate then we need to think about how to mobilize and how
to troughs with what Foucault calls practices of liberty. to act as women. We cannot just assume that new
Or, alternatively, we might align the language of libera- forms of power will incite their own counter-forces,
tion and oppression with the sort of mass politics that but we can read peopleʼs experiences in the context
economy and state require, and the more individualist of our objective situation and begin to theorize and
or grouplet idea of practices of liberty with small mobilize on this basis. We can re-politicize our theory.
resistances and experiments that sustain cultural gains Bringing theory and practice back into a dialectical
during periods of reaction and closure. rapport and inciting an efficacious politics in the real
It is interesting that, although Foucault himself world will be no easy task, but if we do want to repair
saw a weakness of liberation struggles lying in their the tear, then this is where we must begin.
inability to establish the practices of liberty which
would succeed them, he also conceded that liberation Notes
1. Juliet Mitchell, Womanʼs Estate, Penguin, Harmonds-
struggles may well be their precondition – specifically,
worth, 1971, p. 92.
under conditions of domination such as those of nine- 2. Ibid., p. 93.
teenth-century patriarchy5 – because they open up the 3. Betty Friedan, The New Yorker, 3 June 1996. pp. 5–6.
requisite spaces. Under patriarchal domination, women 4. The New Statesman and Society, August 1996, pp.
12–14.
could not reverse the situation. Their limited freedom 5. Michel Foucault, ʻThe Ethic of Care for the Self as a
to resist allowed only ʻtricksʼ: ʻthe problem is in fact Practice of Freedomʼ, Philosophy and Social Criticism,
to find out where resistance is going to organize.ʼ In vol. 12, no. 1, Spring 1987, p. 123.

24 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Feminist activism and
presidential politics
Theorizing the costs of the
‘insider strategy’

Anne-Marie Smith

The 1996 presidential election will be remembered by the very possibility of a truly subversive form of
political analysts in the USA for its ʻgender gapʼ. Polls feminist activism.
show that women backed Clinton over Dole by 59 to
35 per cent, while men split their vote almost evenly, Representational strategies and feminist
43 to 44 per cent. Many assume that this gap emerged discourse
because Dole and the Christian Coalition that shapes Clinton was not, of course, the only presidential candi-
much of Republican policy are viciously opposed to date who deployed complex ideological strategies.
reproductive choice for women, while Clinton is a When the Republican campaign learned during the
staunch defender of womenʼs rights. Prominent fem- summer of 1996 that many voters were offended by
inists such as Gloria Steinem called on women to the extremism of the religious Right, they adopted a
cast their vote for Clinton, declaring that there were fundamentally contradictory strategy. Within the party,
significant differences between his positions and those every effort was made to accommodate the extremist
of Dole, and that it is our job as feminists to move demands of the Christian Coalition into the official
Clinton to the left. party platform. In this moment, the Republican Party
The situation, however, is much more complicated constructed America as an all-out war between two
than this. We will only be able to deal with the chal- great chains of equivalence, the ʻgoodʼ versus the
lenge of pursuing feminist activism in a world that is ʻevilʼ.
profoundly shaped by transnational capital and hybrid While the North American Free Trade Act (NAFTA)
racist sexisms to the extent that we develop much found its most eloquent opponent in Mexico among the
more sophisticated theories about power, identity and Zapatistas, that same role was claimed by right-wing
ideology. Clintonʼs Centre-Right has succeeded in part figures in the USA. Republican presidential primary
because it has effectively deployed strategies of neutral- candidate Pat Buchanan blended his religious funda-
ization, appropriation, co-optation and colonization. mentalist, racist and xenophobic discourse together
Feminist rhetoric was used by the Clinton camp to with explicit attacks on corporate greed. Buchananʼs
sell his Centre-Right agenda, in spite of the fact that it specific version of the ʻgoodʼ versus ʻevilʼ antagonism
includes several major anti-feminist elements. Clinton constructed a chain of equivalence that united right-
himself was skilfully constructed as pro-feminist while wing moral authoritarians with unemployed white
his campaign deliberately pre-empted and censored his working-class males in opposition against not only the
feminist critics. American feminists have almost com- usual enemies of the religious Right – feminists, homo-
pletely lost the power to define their own discourse and sexuals, ʻpermissiveʼ liberal officials, the so-called
to explore what Eisenstein once optimistically called leftist news media, and so on – but blacks, immi-
the ʻradical future of liberal feminismʼ.1 Now, more grants, and the chief executive officers of Americaʼs
than ever, we need to develop feminist theories that largest corporations as well. Buchananʼs bid enjoyed
can analyse the neutralizing articulation of feminist a substantial groundswell of popular support among
discourse, for this operation is threatening to eliminate white workers until the Republican leadership and

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 25


the politically astute Christian Coalition leadership room for the blatant extremism of Newt Gingrich,
ensured his defeat.2 Pat Buchanan, the Christian Coalition and right-wing
When addressing audiences outside the party, how- terrorists; they shut down the government during their
ever, Republican discourse took the form of the logic 1995 budget standoff with Clinton; and they chose a
of difference. Dole attempted to take the moral high stiff and elderly Washington insider as their presiden-
ground as he constructed the Republican Party as a tial candidate.
site in which Americans from all ʻwalks of lifeʼ were Eisenstein argues that Clinton, by positioning him-
welcome and respected. Dole worked for months, with self as the spouse of an empowered woman, and by
limited success, to include in the partyʼs extremist staking out the pro-choice position, won pseudo-femi-
platform language that recognized the legitimacy of nist credentials. She offers a fascinating analysis of
pro-choice Republicans. Explicit extremist language the way in which Hillary Rodham Clinton has been
about abortion and gay rights was almost completely masculinized to symbolize feminist excess precisely to
dropped from Doleʼs public discourse,3 and he waited create a safe space for the construction of Bill Clinton
until his defeat was certain before emphasizing his as her compassionate feminine counterpart.5 Women of
anti-affirmative action and anti-immigration positions. all races are less likely than men to view the budget
Women, people of colour and the handicapped were deficit as an urgent priority, and they are more likely
prominently featured in the partyʼs convention and than men to support education spending, affirmative
campaign materials. action, civil rights, gay rights, health-care reform, and
We should mention in passing that religious-Right welfare programmes.6 Through his symbolic promises,
activists are clearly frustrated with the Republicansʼ and his appropriation of feminist discourse on abor-
dual strategy because it failed to work for Dole. The tion, Clinton won just enough support from women
religious Right, unlike the neo-conservative Republic- voters.
ans, cannot take any solace in the fact that Clinton Clinton also masterfully transformed his small set
has embraced a basically neo-conservative approach of progressive accomplishments into solid evidence of
to social policy. Their priority remains the imposition his principled leadership against the Gingrich–Dole
of a right-wing moral agenda, and they view Clinton Republican Congress. He vetoed the ban on late-
as a dogmatic defender of leftist permissiveness and term abortions, and saw that the act that provides
secular humanism. We should anticipate more ten- for unpaid family leave was passed, along with the
sions within the coalition between the religious Right Violence Against Women Act and the ban on assault
and the neo-conservatives; tensions between the more weapons. Pollitt nevertheless described these accom-
pragmatic leadership of the religious Right and its plishments as a ʻshort, narrowly tailored listʼ.7 Clinton
more dogmatic grassroots membership; an enormous also established an impressive record with respect
surge in grassroots religious-Right activity in school to the appointment of women and minorities to his
boards, local and state government, petition drives, and administration. Underneath his apparent inclusiveness,
ballot initiatives; and the expansion of new extremist however, Clinton actually abandoned many of these
social movements such as the right-wing militias and candidates and appointees – such as Zoë Baird, Lani
the all-male Promise Keepers.4 Guinier and Jocelyn Elders – when they threatened to
Although the Republicans made at least some attempt interrupt his Centre-Right agenda. Throughout his first
to juxtapose their exclusionary logic of discourse with term, and in the early days of his second, Clinton has
an inclusionary logic of difference, the Clinton camp chosen to establish a traditional male-dominated work
deployed much more effective techniques with respect environment and to surround himself with increasingly
to the centring of right-wing extremism. Eisenstein right-wing advisors.8 While Clinton did speak out in
contends that Clintonʼs articulation of feminine and support of affirmative action, he carefully qualified
feminist signifiers played a key role in his campaign. that support to allow himself plenty of room for future
Clinton was constructed as a ʻcaring and sharingʼ capitulations. During the campaign, he and his party
voter-friendly leader for the 1990s: he promised that remained almost completely silent about the anti-
he ʻfelt the painʼ of the voters, and struck a responsible affirmative-action ballot initiative in California until
pose by pledging action on popular symbolic issues he had obtained a safe lead over Dole in the state.9
such as teen smoking, school uniforms, violence on The initiative passed with 54 per cent support.
television and crime. The Republicans themselves As the Republicans gave more and more authority
laid much of the groundwork for this construction of to the Christian Coalition, Clinton and the conservative
Clinton as Doleʼs feminine ʻotherʼ; they created the Democrats knew very well that they offered the only

26 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


credible discourse that could articulate the pro-choice version from within dominant institutions on the one
position. Cockburn points out that this situation gave hand, and vigorous principled opposition on the other,
Clinton enormous leeway in his judicial appointments. where the price of normalization and institutional-
He was assured of feminist support for his appointees ization is too high. They are not, in other words,
simply because they were pro-choice; he knew in calling for a feminist activism that would occupy a
advance that the fact that they were extremely pro- position of pure exteriority; at this point in the strug-
business would be ignored.10 gle, serious feminist activists no longer think politics
Clinton had already made significant efforts to in terms of a simple choice between pure insider and
foreclose feminist criticism before the final days of pure outsider positions. What they are recognizing,
the campaign. Progressive advocates had been lured however, is that the Clinton forces, and much of the
by government appointments and access to the White neo-conservative Centre-Right and Right in general,
House to the extent that they had already abandoned have ʻhegemonizedʼ feminist discourse. They have
the option of expressing oppositional dissent.11 Marian learned how to appropriate key feminist slogans and
Wright Edelman, leader of the Childrenʼs Defence turn them to their advantage, even though they have
Fund, remained silent after Clinton signed the dra- done little to advance concrete feminist struggles,
conian welfare bill; environmentalists praised the and have actually pursued many specific policies that
administration, in spite of its anti-green record; and contradict feminist principles. The Clinton Democrats
gay rights groups endorsed Clinton even after months and other neo-conservatives have also learned how to
of Democratic heterosexist nuclear-family rhetoric and construct their colonized version of feminism as the
Clintonʼs signing of the bill that allows states to ban only legitimate form – such that it seems to exhaust
gay marriages. Feminists and progressives who did the totality of acceptable feminist discourse.
criticize Clinton were marginalized and censored at
the Democratic Convention by Clintonʼs campaign The rightward migration of Clinton’s
machinery.12 ‘Centre’
The effects of these strategies are profound. We The charge that Clinton engaged not only in an attempt
should consider, first, the ways in which Clintonʼs to redefine feminist positions, but in a bid to hegemo-
political tactics have reconstituted feminist activism. nize feminist activism while pursuing a fundamentally
Feminists have been encouraged to seek gains for reactionary agenda, can only be substantiated by exam-
narrowly defined single-issue campaigns, such as abor- ining his concrete policies in detail. While Clinton did
tion, without any consideration of broad-based coali- veto the ban on late-term abortions, his policies left
tion-building. Further, they have been ʻrewardedʼ for the status quo on abortion largely intact. That status
choosing to work within the terms established by the quo is structured according to a class-differentiated
Clinton administration; those who fail to do so have system of access. As many as 84 per cent of American
been excluded. Piven argues that womenʼs groups and counties have no abortion providers. States are free
social-welfare advocacy groups chose to pursue what to impose mandatory counselling, waiting periods
she calls the ʻinsider strategyʼ, even though they knew and parental approval for women under the age of
very well that it entailed the surrender of their right eighteen. In a country in which there is no national
to autonomous critique and oppositional activism.13 health service, the states are also allowed to exclude
Pollitt contends that these developments have seriously coverage for abortions by Medicaid, the health-care
weakened the feminist movement, as more and more plan for the poor.15
feminist leaders succumb to the ʻfantasy of access and Clintonʼs articulation of conservative ʻfamily valuesʼ
influence: to the siphoning off of energies into wishy- rhetoric has also contradicted the broader feminist goal
washy “advocacy,” Beltway schmooze [Washington of securing not just abortion rights for the wealthy, but
lobbying] and fundraising for “moderate” Democrats the right for every women to determine her reproduc-
who happen to be women or minorities.ʼ14 tive choices freely. In contemporary American politics,
Eisenstein, Piven or Pollitt do not ignore the fact the pursuit of this goal must include the defence
that feminists must deploy a complex combination of of poor womenʼs right to have children in the first
struggles both within and against the predominant place. Clintonʼs claim that ʻteen pregnancyʼ consti-
structures of electoral politics in the United States. tutes nothing less than an ʻepidemicʼ that threatens
Feminist activism must continue to take the form of the ʻnational interestʼ corresponds too neatly with
a mobile war of position that shifts back and forth right-wing anxieties about the ʻexcessiveʼ fertility of
between infiltration, constructive engagement and sub- the poor. Poor single mothers on welfare have been

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 27


grossly demonized; they are widely portrayed as hedon- the minimum wage still leaves a family of four under
istic agents of a dysgenic population boom among the poverty line. Through his policies, fundraising
the mostly black and Latino ʻunderclassʼ. Allegations practices and personal conduct he encourages voters to
of this nature by the media and mainstream politi- lower their expectations about what governments can
cal figures alike have remained immune to empirical accomplish.20 He has normalized the right-wing cam-
refutation. The reproduction rate among black teenage paign against illegal immigration with escalated border
women has actually declined, and it only appears patrols and harsh legislation.21 He has abandoned his
to be growing because the reproduction rate among own moderate proposals to reform health care; not
older black women has declined more rapidly. Under only will he not promote a single payer scheme, he
the current law, the states are free to experiment will not even take on the for-profit Health Maintenance
with any number of official welfare measures that Organizations (HMOs) that now dominate the health-
interfere with poor womenʼs right to have children. care industry. He promised to support gay rights,
In some localities, teenage mothers are being charged but capitulated on the issue of gays in the military,
with fornication or coerced by public officials into gave no power to his AIDS ʻczarʼ, distanced himself
marriages. While right-wing commentators such as from his gay supporters, enthusiastically embraced
Murray express – in pseudo-feminist terms – a deep the ideology that children should only be raised by
concern about the availability of abortion, birth control married heterosexual couples, and signed a bill that
and adoption services for ʻunderclassʼ mothers,16 the allows states to ban gay marriages.22
eugenicist spectre of women on welfare being forced Eisenstein, Piven and Pollitt view Clintonʼs approval
to take Norplant lies on the horizon. Clintonʼs own of the welfare law that was passed in August 1996
discourse has only exacerbated these assaults on the as his greatest betrayal of feminist principles. This
reproductive freedoms of all but the most wealthy law changes welfare from a national entitlement pro-
women. gramme to a system of block grants that allows the
Clintonʼs support for free trade is devastating for states to decide how to spend the funds. It eliminates
American workers; his anti-terrorist legislation marks the right of the poor to federal assistance, and gives
a significant setback for civil liberties; his pledges of a free rein to the very level of government that is
support for the inner cities are meaningless without a notorious for its exclusionary policies and closed-door
substantial jobs creation programme; his inaction on deal-making. No state will be able to provide benefits
campaign finance reform perpetuates the corporate after two years, or to provide benefits to a recipient
grip on Washington;17 his record on the environment who has been on welfare for more than five years
is appalling;18 his pandering to conservative Cuban- during her entire lifetime. The bill does not include
Americans has resulted in the strengthening of the any new provisions for job creation, job training or
Cuban blockade;19 and the much-hyped increase in child-care.
The United States
already had the great-
est, as well as the fastest
growing, gap between the
rich and the poor, and
the worst record for aid
to the poor in the entire
ʻWesternʼ world before
this bill was passed. Poor
people will be forced to
seek work in a country in
which the Federal Reserve
is deliberately controlling
interest rates to maintain
a high un-employment
level, which currently
stands at seven million.
In Americaʼs inner
cities, there are fourteen

28 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


applicants for every job in a fast-food restaurant. repeal of welfare rights was justified in terms of bal-
Automation, globalization, specialization according anced-budget rhetoric, private corporations have never
to comparative advantage, and government cutbacks paid such a small share of federal taxes, and they
are rapidly eliminating the jobs in the industrial manu- have never received more public subsidies; corporate
facturing and government service sectors. These are welfare is four times greater than aid to the poor;
precisely the sectors in which Americans with only middle-class home-owners continue to receive non-
a high-school education could find a skilled or semi- means-tested mortgage subsidies; and little is said
skilled unionized job that paid a living wage. Today, about the savings-and-loan bail-outs and the bloated
these same Americans are experiencing a dramatic Pentagon budget.24
decrease in wealth as they become massively grouped Meanwhile wealthy Americans – a class in which
in the low-paying, unskilled and non-unionized service whites are vastly overrepresented – are pursuing an
sector. As the August 1996 welfare law is put into increasingly segregationist agenda which fundamen-
effect, 3.5 million children will be dropped from tally erodes the notion of collective responsibility.
public assistance by 2001, and a million more children Federal taxes for the rich are cut, necessitating not
will be thrown into poverty. This will take place in a only massive cuts in government programmes but
country in which one out of four children already lived also increases in the state and local taxes that are
under the poverty line in 1994; in which over 4,200 less fair for the lower middle class, workers and the
babies below twelve months of age already died every poor. Public transportation cuts reduce the mobility
year as of 1996 because of low birth weight and other of the poor, school zoning boundaries are drawn to
problems related to the poverty of their mothers. isolate the middle class, school voucher programmes
For reasons stemming directly from historical tra- that would use public funds to subsidize wealthy chil-
ditions in which blacks, Latinos and some Asians drenʼs private school tuition are proposed, while gated
were systematically excluded from accumulating the suburban communities cut themselves off from the
resources necessary for upward class mobility, racial inner-city tax base. The Republican Congress approved
minorities remain overrepresented among the popu- an experimental plan that sets up government subsidies
lation that is experiencing the greatest decreases in for individuals who want to opt out of private group
family income. In 1991, the typical white household health insurance to obtain their own personal cover-
was ten times more wealthy than the typical black age. More and more corporations are eliminating the
household. Compared to whites, African-Americans pension plans that used to cover their entire workforce
have a 100 per cent greater infant mortality rate, a
and replacing them with generous tax-subsidized plans
176 per cent greater unemployment rate, and a 300
for the highest-paid managers.25 For the rich, privatiz-
per cent greater poverty rate.23
ation is not enough; they are now demanding explicitly
Clintonʼs repeal of welfare rights coincides with
segregationist forms of privatization.
other public policies that have only exacerbated the
growing inequalities in the distribution of wealth. Passive revolution and expansive
With its strict time limits, the implementation of the hegemony
welfare law will require extensive inter-state record-
Our analysis of the Democratic Partyʼs bid to hege-
keeping, which will in turn open up a huge new
monize feminism can be clarified with reference to
market for the capital-intensive information technology
Gramsciʼs distinction between the ʻpassive revolutionʼ
sector. Keynesianism is not entirely dead, even though
and ʻexpansive hegemonyʼ. A ʻpassive revolutionʼ por-
the Reagan administrations made the maintenance of
trays itself as a popular and democratic movement,
government programmes impossible by deliberately
but it actually engages in profoundly anti-democratic
running up huge deficits. There is a covert boom in
strategies. It neutralizes social movements by satisfy-
the military, policing, penitentiary and public-surveil-
ing some of their demands in a symbolic and reform-
lance sectors within the budgets of the federal, state
ist manner, and shifts authority towards disciplinary
and local governments, while overt campaigns against
apparatuses. Strictly speaking, Gramsci makes a clear
governmental health, education, poverty and housing
distinction between ʻpassiveʼ revolution and hegemony,
expenditures have been launched with full force. In
for a traditional ʻpassiveʼ moment is largely statist and
the first days of his second term, Clinton attempted to
bureaucratic; the ʻmassesʼ do not take an active part,
construct himself as a pro-public-education president,
and brute force, rather than the organization of consent,
but his major initiative in this area was a tax break
becomes predominant. Further, Gramsci insists that
that will mostly benefit the middle class. While the
the ʻpassive revolutionʼ includes substantial economic

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 29


intervention by the state, a dimen-
sion that is almost anachronis-
tic in contemporary globalizing
economies. Gramsciʼs conception
of the ʻpassiveʼ revolution never-
theless contains the provocative
image of a pseudo-popular move-
ment that wins some small degree
of consent by responding to some
of the popular demands from the
grassroots, but uses that appear-
ance of popular consent only
to gain strategic ground for its
fundamentally anti-democratic
project. It seeks to absorb and
to assimilate democratic forces
by appropriating key elements of
alternative popular world-views,
neutralizing their critical poten-
tial by redefining them, and then
articulating these colonized ele- they can also make their contradictions a source of
ments into its world-view.26 strength. As Hall argued with respect to Thatcherism,
Authoritarian forms of hegemony remain funda- an authoritarian hegemonic project does not actu-
mentally contradictory, for they attempt to represent ally need to construct a fully mobilized majority of
themselves as popular democratic movements, even enthusiastic supporters. It only needs to achieve the
though they engage in all sorts of containment strate- disorganization of the potential opposition and the
gies, and pursue initiatives that perpetuate the unequal minimum degree of mobilization necessary for the
distribution of power. While maintaining the façade construction of a ʻpopularʼ façade for the regime.27
of a popular mobilizing force, they do not hesitate to Gramsci contends that where authoritarian ʻpassive
demobilize key sectors of the populace by engaging in revolutionsʼ have become institutionalized, democratic
blatant disenfranchisement tactics, or by dragging the forces will have to wage a protracted ʻwar of positionʼ
political centre so far to the right that more and more and struggle to advance an ʻexpansive hegemonyʼ.
people have no reason to participate in the political Multiple struggles that are plural and contextually
system. We are now witnessing extensive efforts to sensitive in form will have to be deployed at each of
lower political participation in the United States. The the various sites throughout the social in which the
Clinton Democrats have worked together with the ʻpassive revolutionʼ has become entrenched. Where a
other forces on the right to lower popular expectations ʻpassive revolutionʼ seeks to neutralize the democratic
about what governments ought to achieve. Clinton opposition and to construct a simulacrum popular
has also indirectly benefited from the promotion, on movement while perpetuating structural inequality, an
the part of the far Right and the religious Right, of a ʻexpansive hegemonyʼ seeks to promote a genuinely
popular paranoia about the evil forces that lurk within democratic mobilization of progressive social move-
state apparatuses. In spite of their different rhetoric, ments.28 Authoritarian hegemony aims to achieve a
the far Right, the religious Right, the neo-conservative maximum disciplining of difference; even as it pre-
Right, and the neo-conservative Centre-Right have tends to endorse pluralism, it can only promote a fake
constructed a lasting consensus: public programmes multiculturalism. By contrast, the radical democratic
– with the exception of the military, the police, public pluralist approach – expansive hegemony – attempts
surveillance and the penitentiary system – are suspect; to construct the sorts of unifying discourses that
concepts of collective responsibility are obsolete. enhance and promote democratic forms of plurality
There is nothing in the contradictions within authori- and difference. Confronted with a plurality of progres-
tarian hegemonies, however, that will by themselves sive struggles already in motion, it seeks to release
lead to their self-destruction. Not only can contra- the democratic potential within each of them, while
dictory political discourses remain brutally effective; bringing them into mutually constitutive articulatory

30 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


relations. It values the autonomy of each democratic where he has the popular support to do so, and that
struggle as a good in itself, and in a pragmatic sense: it is the task of progressive movements to create that
autonomy facilitates the sort of contextually specific support.33
contestation of oppression and exploitation that is Steinem assumed that the prevailing political struc-
needed in todayʼs complex and hybrid social forma- ture actually does correspond to the pluralist interest
tions. Where authoritarian hegemony strictly regu- group modelʼs predictions; that the system remains
lates the development of political contestation, radical ready to respond to a feminist popular mobilization.
democratic pluralist hegemony multiplies the points of She depicted Clintonʼs capitulation to the neo-con-
contestation and seeks to broaden the terrain of polit- servative Right not as the fruit of his own convictions
icization or reactivation.29 The relatively universalistic but as the product of the Republican-weighted balance
effects of the radical democratic pluralist horizon seeks of power. In this and other similar representations,
to institutionalize deeper and deeper recognition of the Clinton is figured as a vulnerable victim of Republican
plurality and autonomy of the public spaces created power who reluctantly supports right-wing positions
by democratic struggles, while perpetually postponing when he would secretly prefer to take a much more
the final definition of the good.30 To the extent that progressive stance. Considerations about co-optation,
the specific discourses of the relatively autonomous neutralizing articulations and colonization were absent
progressive struggles are successfully articulated with from her argument. Steinem therefore laid most of the
a radical civic sense, the multiplication of these public burden with respect to the advance of the feminist
spaces becomes a source of strength for democratic struggle at the door of feminists. Because the existing
society.31 system ʻworksʼ, we feminists only have to redouble our
efforts. New strategies and radical transformations of
Passive revolution and the entire political structure are not required.
feminist strategy The article reproduced the arguments used by Con-
Clintonʼs political linkages with the Democratic gresswoman Waters, Smeal, Steinem, Abzug, and other
Leadership Council situated him squarely within the leading feminists at the 1996 Democratic Convention.
part of the Democratic Party that has traditionally They called for feminists to vote for Clinton. They
embraced a ʻpassive-revolutionʼ strategy. The direc- also argued that Clinton was forced into signing the
tion and structure of his leadership did nevertheless welfare bill; they contended that because of the elec-
seem to be open to alternative possibilities when he toral strength of the Republicans, his bid for a second
defeated Bush in 1992. Throughout his first term, term would have failed if he had opposed the repeal
however, Clinton distanced himself more and more of welfare rights. From their perspective, feminists had
from progressive positions and prioritized neo-con- to campaign to put Clinton back into office so that he
servative policies. would be able to reverse the welfare bill during his
Feminist leaders, for the most part, failed to adjust second term.34
their strategies accordingly. In a key article that was Clintonʼs feminist supporters, however, ignored the
published in Ms., the flagship feminist magazine, just fact that Clinton had maintained a substantial and
before the 1996 election, Steinem declared that women steady lead over a Republican contender since the
ought to vote for Clinton and then work hard to make Republicans had shut down the government during the
his positions more progressive. She rightly pointed out budget stalemate in 1995.35 Clinton had nevertheless
that right-wing victories depend on a contradictory vetoed two other welfare bills during that period.
populism: the mobilization of right-wing voters and the Some of the Democrats who were up for re-election
demobilization of everyone else. She could have also in the House and the Senate voted against the welfare
pointed out that the rich vote in overwhelmingly larger bill and then easily won their races. There is also
numbers than the poor in the USA.32 But Steinem substantial evidence that Clinton agreed with the basic
also claimed that the Republicans gain whenever we provisions in the bill. Not only had he adopted the
argue that there is little difference between them Republican terms of the welfare debate years before he
and the Democrats, because this argument makes the signed it; he had joined with other neo-conservatives
Republicans appear more moderate and discourages in a consistent campaign to get the attack on welfare
Democratic voters from going to the polls. To her rights onto the mainstream political agenda. On the
credit, she did argue that Clinton failed on welfare, 1996 campaign trail, Clinton explicitly championed the
gays in the military and gay marriage, but she asserted repeal of welfare rights before conservative audiences.
that Clinton will only differ from the Republicans In other campaign venues, he promised to ʻfixʼ some

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 31


of the bill during his second term, especially the of tactical decision-making in the face of Republican
provisions that stop legal immigrants from receiving power. She states that instead of blaming Clintonʼs
benefits. Welfare policy experts predicted, however, neo-conservatism on the Republican Congress, we
that Clinton would fail if he attempted to change the should see the leading politicians of both parties as
fundamental aspect of the bill, namely the basic repeal symptoms of a global phenomenon: ʻthe slashing of
of welfare rights.36 In any event, Clinton reversed his the welfare state, the lowering of the working classʼs
position after his re-election; he now promises merely standard of living and the upward transfer of wealthʼ.
to introduce small changes to the new welfare policy. She asserts that we can ʻplausibly argue that Clinton
Behind the scenes, conservative Democrats are plan- prepared [the] way [for the Republican Congress] by
ning to privatize social security.37 accepting Republican terms of debateʼ. Pollitt concludes
The most damning evidence about Clintonʼs deci- that although a second Bush administration might have
sion-making process on the bill comes from a par- introduced worse measures in some policy areas, only
ticipant in a White House advisorsʼ meeting that took Clinton had the strategic position that allowed him to
place in August 1996. He states that when Morris, neutralize democratic opposition within and outside
Clintonʼs infamous pollster, argued that the president Congress with such a devastating effect.41
needed to sign the welfare bill to win the November Many progressive feminists are rejecting Steinemʼs
1996 election, everyone else completely disagreed with approach, and are advocating a much more sceptical
him. Morrisʼs pro-welfare-repeal side ultimately won approach towards the Democratic Party. They are
the debate in the White House, but its prevailing argu- exploring alternative strategies such as third parties
ment was based on Clintonʼs political values, rather and more autonomous oppositional movements. Burk
than reluctantly deployed electoral tactics. Writing and Hartmann, for example, contend that American
on the eve of the election, Hitchens concluded that, feminist activism has concentrated too exclusively on
ʻThe Clinton Administration does not do what it does the single-issue campaign to defend the status quo on
because it is constrained, by a first term or an impend- abortion; that it must do more to link abortion rights
ing election or anything of the kind, to do so. It does to economic rights; and that it must pay more attention
these things out of conviction.ʼ38 to the issues that concern women the most – namely,
Women voters who chose Clinton over Dole because pay equity, pensions, health care and violence. Burk
they believed that he would be a staunch defender of and Hartmann point out that feminist leaders have
the welfare safety net were therefore misled. Clintonʼs not done enough to construct feminism as one of the
ʻgender gapʼ was built on his neutralizing appro- transnational sites of resistance against the escalation
priation of feminist and feminine symbols, rather than in economic exploitation in the globalizing economy.
his underlying convictions. But Patricia Ireland, the They claim that this shift in strategy would make the
president of the National Organization of Women womenʼs movement more relevant to working-class
(NOW), stood virtually alone as a major feminist women of colour.42
leader when she called for massive opposition against
Clintonʼs support for the welfare bill. To her credit, Popular feminist intellectuals and neo-
she went on a well-publicized hunger strike after conservatism
the bill was passed, and declared that, although she Neo-conservative discourse often successfully seizes
would vote for Clinton, she would not campaign for upon the weaknesses of single-issue reformist feminist
him in any way. NOW directed its campaign support identity politics. Many right-wing forces subversively
exclusively behind the House Democrats and the one borrow identity-politics strategies from the Left and
senator running for re-election, Paul Wellstone, who either promote right-wing elements within existing
voted against it.39 NOW also worked with civil rightsʼ social movements or invent their own versions of
organizations, progressive unions and radical students grassroots activism and ʻdiversityʼ. Anti-feminist
in the ultimately unsuccessful campaign to defeat the women intellectuals, for example, are celebrated as
anti-affirmative action Proposition 209 in California. the spokespersons for the attack on womenʼs studies
When Ireland tried to bring her oppositional campaign that is launched in the name of vague pseudo-feminist
to the Democratic Convention, she was prevented by principles. Blacks and non-Anglo immigrants have
party officials from launching a significant protest.40 emerged as the prominent leaders for anti-affirmative
Pollitt, like Eisenstein, fundamentally questions the action and anti-multiculturalism movements. Identity-
assumption held by Steinem and other pro-Clinton fem- politics discourse legitimated the validity of discourse
inists that Clintonʼs decisions are merely the product that is located with respect to the experience of women

32 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


and minorities. This argument undoubtedly had a pro- ence of Janis Joplin, that turns these women on. But
gressive effect in so far as it promoted a critique of their tattoos and piercings are barely healed before
sexist and racist discourse that passed itself off as uni- they are stolen from them by powerful media interests.
versal. But neo-conservatives have begun to turn the They may find their way into political activism through
logic of identity-politics discourse to their advantage. indirect and unconventional routes; they are more likely
Speaking from what they call their special black and to enter progressive activist discourse via animal rights
ethnic-minority perspectives, these right-wing women and vegetarianism than via feminism, for they can more
and people of colour condemn affirmative action and easily identify with the innocence and helplessness
multiculturalism for promoting racist divisions, thereby of small animals, or the beauty and dignity of an old
identifying the anti-racists as the worst racists. These growth forest, than they can insist on their own rights.
tactics not only contribute to the legitimation of right- Some of my women students are participating in new
wing policies, but also threaten to redefine the entire and exciting multiracial coalitions to fight the attack on
terrain of feminist and anti-racist politics. affirmative action; others are going to the new labour
Further, neo-conservative politicians and corporate organizing summer schools. But these young women are
marketing strategies have successfully normalized an confronted with something that we never had to deal
astonishingly reactionary definition of feminism in the with – namely, the false image that we already inhabit a
United States. Feminist success is now widely equated post-feminist terrain, as feminist demands are appropri-
with any socio-economic gain that is achieved by any ated by right-wing forces and private corporations and
individual woman by any means necessary. Two recent bent to serve their reactionary interests.46
popular films, First Wivesʼ Club and Waiting to Exhale, If feminist leaders have, for the most part, failed
portray womenʼs liberation in crassly consumeristic to grasp the dynamics of contemporary politics in
terms. Nikeʼs sports shoe advertisements embrace which the possibilities for the genuine advance of
womenʼs athletics on explicitly feminist grounds, while feminist struggle have been sharply curtailed, and
their $140 shoes are made by women in Indonesia ʻfeminismʼ has been given a reactionary and anti-femi-
working for $2.20 a day, and by women in China and nist meaning, popular feminist intellectuals have not,
Vietnam working for $30 a month.43 A recent notice on the whole, done much better. The idea that ʻfeminist
on Cornell Universityʼs Womenʼs Studies Programmeʼs successʼ means virtually any socio-economic gain for
list-serve advertised an event that was simply called any individual woman that is achieved by any means
ʻWomenʼs Leadership Seminarʼ. The notice described necessary is explicitly promoted by Wolf. In her ind-
the women speakers only in terms of their affiliations ividualist ʻpower feminismʼ theory, she attacks radical
with the World Bank and private corporations. The feminism for its portrayal of women as ʻvictimsʼ and
term ʻfeministʼ was noticeably absent. contends that ʻweʼ – read wealthy, healthy, white,
Among middle-class girls and young women, there straight, college-educated women – should construct a
are ambiguous signs of backlash and rebellion. In her ʻfeminismʼ that celebrates ʻourʼ power.47 The structural
excellent book, Reviving Ophelia,44 Piper, a therapist analysis of oppression, exploitation and the respon-
who works with young teenage women, reports on sibility of the overempowered to the disempowered is
the extremely hostile environments that they confront entirely foreclosed. This evisceration of feminism will
on a daily basis in their schools, relationships and only encourage more and more white wealthy women
families. I myself am seeing more and more intel- to look out for their own interests – and to invoke the
ligent young middle-class women struggle against the name of ʻfeminismʼ when it suits them in doing so
cultural forces that encourage them to ʻdumb downʼ – and to forget the needs of disadvantaged women.
their public speaking performance; sometimes, their In concrete terms, we should remember that several
brilliance comes through only obliquely or only in of the women elected to the House of Representatives
their writing. with support from feminist political action committees
If we wade carefully through the Disney–ABC/ Time voted for the welfare bill that is going to condemn
Warner–Turner–CNN/General Electric–NBC/Westing- over a million additional children to poverty and throw
house–CBS/Murdoch–Fox/Viacom–Paramount–MTV/ millions of poor mothers with no childcare, no job
Bertellsman swamp of media oligopolies that almost training, and no job prospects off the welfare rolls.48
completely defines American ʻpopular cultureʼ,45 we can This displacement of radical democratic feminism by
find promising moments of young womenʼs rebellion. It non-feminisms or even anti-feminisms that masquerade
is the anger of Courtney Love, Queen Latifah, Alanis as feminism could not be more disastrous, especially
Morissette and Ani di Franco, and not the co-depend- now as automation and globalization ensure economic

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 33


opportunities for a small highly educated elite – which 29 August 1996, p. B13.
includes many college-educated white women – and 7. K. Pollitt, ʻWe Were Wrong: Why Iʼm Not Voting for
Clintonʼ, The Nation, 7 October 1996, p. 9.
increasing exploitation for the rest. 8. T. Purdum, ʻThe Second Clinton Term: Promise, Pitfalls
The anti-feminist feminism of Paglia, Hoff Sommers, and Perilsʼ, New York Times, 6 November 1996, p. B2.
and Roiphe49 has also emerged as a popular intellectual 9. M. Cooper, ʻLetter From California: What Cost, Vic-
tory?ʼ, The Nation, 4 November 1996, pp. 12–14; B.
school. These ʻtheoriesʼ attack virtually every femi-
Ayres, ʻAffirmative Action Measure Nears a High-Profile
nist position but borrow liberal individualist feminist Finishʼ, New York Times, 4 November 1996, p. B6.
rhetoric such that they can represent themselves as 10. A. Cockburn, ʻDonʼt be Fooled Againʼ, The Progressive,
more ʻdemocraticʼ and more ʻfeministʼ than feminism. November 1996, p. 20.
11. Ibid., p. 21.
Many younger women are strongly attracted to them,
12. D. Corn, ʻWhatʼs Left in the Party?ʼ, The Nation, 23
and to Wolfʼs so-called ʻpower feminismʼ, because of September 1996, p. 20.
their apparent irreverence. These discourses have been 13. B. Ehrenreich, ʻFrances Fox Pivenʼ, The Progressive,
masterfully constructed as the rebellious underdog November 1996, p. 34.
14. Pollitt, ʻWe Were Wrongʼ, p. 9.
voices against an omnipotent ʻGoliathʼ – the mythical 15. New York Times, ʻStatesʼ Wrongs on Abortionʼ, editorial,
ʻfeminist establishmentʼ – when they are, of course, 3 September 1996, p. 22.
serving the hegemonic neo-conservative and anti-femi- 16. R. Herrnstein and C. Murray, The Bell Curve: Intel-
nist forces quite nicely. And, because neo-conservative ligence and Class Structure in American Life, The Free
Press, New York, 1994.
values predominate in American academia, students 17. Election experts estimate that a record amount of $1.6
are not being given the critical tools that are needed billion was raised and spent on the 1996 election. Some
to evaluate these texts and are therefore vulnerable to $800 million was spent on the presidential election
their false promises of rebellion. alone, a figure that is three times greater than the 1992
spending level (The Nation, ʻMoney Votesʼ, editorial,
In an instrumentalist sense – and I donʼt think 11 November 1996, p. 5). A recent poll found that the
that our instrumentalist interests should be used to largest political donors were more supportive of free
define the totality of legitimate feminist discourse trade and large corporate interests, and more opposed to
– I have argued that we need to develop much more government spending and government regulation, than
the electorate as a whole (B. Borosage and R. Teixeira,
sophisticated analyses of power and the neutralizing
ʻThe Politics of Moneyʼ, The Nation, 21 October 1996,
effects of ideological appropriations. Since Britainʼs pp. 21–2).
Labour Party leadership has distanced itself from its 18. A. Cockburn, ʻLadies and Gentlemen, I Give You the
progressive grassroots and the trade-union movement Presidentʼ, The Nation, 9–16 September 1996, p. 10; A.
Cockburn, ʻThe Kevorkian in the White Houseʼ, The
at every opportunity, this theoretical and political
Nation, 14 October 1996, p. 9.
problem has now become an urgent priority on both 19. S. Erlanger, ʻTough Talk Aside, Helms Barely Alters
sides of the Atlantic. Foreign Policyʼ, New York Times, 3 November 1996,
p. 18.
Notes 20. J. Nichols, ʻJoel Rogersʼ, The Progressive, October
I would like to thank Zillah Eisenstein for her inspirational 1996, p. 30.
work, Peter Osborne for editorial assistance, and Patty Zim- 21. E. Schmitt, ʻMilestones and Missteps on Immigrationʼ,
mermann for mapping out the monopolistic patterns of owner- New York Times, 26 October 1996, p. 1.
ship that are predominant in American popular culture. 22. D. Kirp, ʻPolitics Out of the Closetʼ, The Nation, 9–16
September 1996, pp. 3–4.
1. Z. Eisenstein, The Radical Future of Liberal Feminism, 23. K. Bradsher, ʻGap in Wealth in U.S. Called Widest in
Longman, New York, 1981. Westʼ, New York Times, 17 April 1995, p. 1; B. Herbert,
2. F. Rich, ʻDoleʼs Unpaid Debtʼ, New York Times, 9 March ʻThe Issue is Jobsʼ, New York Times, 6 May 1996, p.
1996, p. 23; ʻHappy New Year?ʼ, New York Times, 18 23; B. Herbert, ʻSupply Side Seducerʼ, New York Times,
September 1996, p. 23. 12 August 1996, p. 25; M. Marable, How Capitalism
3. A. Nagourney, ʻOn Volatile Social and Cultural Issues, Underdeveloped Black America: Problems in Race, Po-
Silenceʼ, New York Times, 9 October 1996, p. 1. litical Economy and Society, South End Press, Boston
4. F. Rich, ʻThank God Iʼm a Manʼ, New York Times, 25 MA, 1983; R. Takaki, A Different Mirror: A History
September 1996, p. A21; J. Conason, A. Ross and L. of Multicultural America, Little, Brown, Boston MA,
Cokorinos, ʻThe Promise Keepers Are Comingʼ, The 1993; R.M. Williams, ʻAccumulation as Evisceration:
Nation, 7 October 1996, pp. 11–15. Urban Rebellion and the New Growth Dynamicsʼ, in
5. Z. Eisenstein, ʻTheorizing and Politicizing the 1996 R. Gooding-Williams, ed., Reading Rodney King, Read-
Electionʼ, in Clarence Lo, ed., Clinton and the Con- ing Urban Uprising, New York, Routledge, 1993; M.
servative Agenda, Blackwell, Oxford, forthcoming. Harrington, Socialism: Past and Future, Pluto Press,
6. G. Steinem, ʻVoting as Rebellionʼ, Ms., September/Oc- London, 1993; Justice For All, Straight Talk About the
tober 1996, p. 61; C. Goldberg, ʻSoccer Moms Step Real Issues, pamphlet, 1996; B. Herbert, ʻOne in Fourʼ,
onto Political Playing Fieldʼ, New York Times, 6 October New York Times, 16 December 1996, p. 25; Cockburn,
1996, p. 24; A. Nagourney, ʻDemocrats Seek Votes of ʻThe Kevorkian in the White Houseʼ, p. 9; Z. Eisenstein,
Women with a Focus on their Familiesʼ, New York Times, The Color of Gender, University of California Press,

34 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Berkeley, 1994, p. 183; M. Parenti, Democracy for The per cent in 1986, 45 per cent in 1990 and 44.6 per cent in
Few, St Martinʼs Press, New York, 1995, p. 27. 1994. It is only in the distribution of voters according to
24. T. Weiner, ʻClinton as a Military Leader: Tough On-the- income that sharp transitions in turnout are taking place.
job Trainingʼ, New York Times, 28 October 1996, p. 1; According to Gans of the Committee for the Study of
The Nation, editorial, 8 April 1996, p. 7. the American Electorate, the data suggests that upper-
25. New York Times, ʻThe Secret Attack on Have-Notsʼ, income voters ʻsaw an opportunity for the Republicans
editorial, 20 October 1996, p. 24. to get inʼ and responded (ʻLow-Income Votersʼ Turnout
26. C. Buci-Glucksmann, ʻState, Transition and Passive Fell in 1994, Census Reportsʼ, New York Times, 11 June
Revolutionʼ, in C. Mouffe, ed., Gramsci and Marxist 1995, p. 22). Only 27 per cent of eligible voters with
Theory, Routledge & Kegan Paul, London, 1979, pp. incomes less than $15,000 voted in 1994 (A. Keyssar,
216–17, 224; C. Mouffe, ʻHegemony and Ideology in ʻKeep Out the Voteʼ, The Nation, 11 November 1996,
Gramsciʼ, in Mouffe, ed., Gramsci and Marxist Theo- p. 6). In 1992, 54 per cent of participating voters were
ry, p. 182; E. Laclau, Politics and Ideology in Marxist women, as opposed to 51 per cent in 1994 (R. Toner,
Theory: Capitalism, Fascism, Populism, Verso, London, ʻParties Pressing to Raise Turnout as Election Nearsʼ,
1977, p. 161; A.M. Smith, ʻWhy Did Armey Apologize? New York Times, 27 October 1996, p. 28). The voter
Hegemony, Homophobia and the Religious Rightʼ, in A. turnout in 1996, 48.8 per cent, was the lowest since
Ansell, ed., Discourses of Divisiveness: The Agenda of 1924. Analysts are divided as to whether Clintonʼs com-
the Conservative Movement, Westview Press, New York, manding lead over Dole or the nature of the campaign
forthcoming. itself is to blame for voter apathy.
27. S. Hall, The Hard Road to Renewal: Thatcherism and 33. Steinem, ʻVoting as Rebellionʼ, pp. 58–61.
the Crisis of the Left, Verso, London, 1988. 34. R. Coniff, ʻNo More Angry Feministsʼ, The Progressive,
28. Buci-Glucksmann, ʻState, Transition and Passive Revo- October 1996, p. 23.
lutionʼ, pp. 228–9; Mouffe, ʻHegemony and Ideology in 35. New York Times/CBS News, ʻTrial Heats Throughout
Gramsciʼ, pp. 182–3. the Campaignʼ, New York Times, 4 November 1996,
29. E. Laclau, ʻPower and Representationʼ, in E. Laclau, p. B8.
Emancipation(s), Verso, London, 1996, p. 99. 36. D. Corn, ʻThe Fix Ainʼt Inʼ, The Nation, 7 October 1996,
30. Ibid., p. 100; C. Mouffe, The Return of the Political, p. 5.
Verso, London, 1993, pp. 4, 6. 37. ʻGrapes of Wrathʼ, editorial, The Nation, 26 August–2
31. E. Laclau, ʻCommunity and Its Paradoxesʼ, in Laclau, September 1996, p. 3; Cockburn, ʻDonʼt be Fooled
Emancipation(s), pp. 120–21. Againʼ, p. 19.
32. With voting participation rates of about 45 per cent in 38. C. Hitchens, ʻThe Greater Evilʼ, The Nation, 18 Novem-
non-presidential elections, and between 48.8 per cent ber 1996, p. 8.
(1996) and 55.2 per cent (1992) in presidential elec- 39. R. Borosage, ʻToward Democratic Renewalʼ, The Na-
tions, the USA is the least participatory democracy in the tion, 9–16 September 1996, p. 20.
world. Steinem notes that 70–80 per cent of the members 40. Corn, ʻWhatʼs Left in the Party?ʼ p. 20.
of right-wing extremist groups cast ballots in every elec- 41. Pollitt, ʻWe Were Wrongʼ, p. 9.
tion, and that American voters routinely make up their 42. M. Burk and H. Hartmann, ʻBeyond the Gender Gapʼ,
minds based on their vague perceptions of a candidateʼs The Nation, 10 June 1996, p. 20.
image rather than accurate knowledge about his or her 43. Z. Eisenstein, ʻTransnationalismʼs New Politics: Re-
actual positions. Fewer than 10 per cent of the voters in structuring Work, Family and Stateʼ, work in progress.
1994 had even heard of Gingrichʼs extremist Contract 44. M. Piper, Reviving Ophelia: Saving the Selves of Ado-
With America, and fewer than 1 per cent could identify lescent Girls, Putnam, New York, 1993.
one of its goals (Steinem, ʻVoting as Rebellionʼ, p. 56). 45. A. Miller and J. Biden, ʻThe National Entertainment
In the 1994 election, there was a sharp decline in the Stateʼ, The Nation, 3 June 1996, pp. 10–14.
turnout of low-income voters. Sixty per cent of Ameri- 46. Z. Eisenstein, Hatreds, Routledge, New York, 1996.
can voters with incomes of more than $50,000 went to 47. N. Wolf, Fire With Fire, Random House, New York,
the polls, an increase of almost one percentage point 1993.
from the turnout in 1990. For voters with incomes under 48. K. Pollitt, ʻThe Strange Death of Liberal Americaʼ, The
$5,000, the turnout was only 19.9 per cent, down from Nation, 26 August–2 September 1996, p. 9.
32.2 per cent. The decrease in turn-out of voters with 49. C. Paglia, Sexual Personae, Yale University Press, New
incomes between $5,000 and $10,000 was from 30.9 per Haven CT, 1990; C. Paglia, Sex, Art and American Cul-
cent in 1990 to 23.3 per cent in 1994. The proportion of ture, Vintage, New York, 1992; C. Paglia, Vamps and
voters from the highest income groups as compared to Tramps, Vintage, New York, 1994; C. Hoff Sommers,
the total voting population rose from 18 per cent in 1990 Who Stole Feminism? How Women Have Betrayed
to 23.4 per cent in 1994. Turnout rates for the eligible Women, Simon & Schuster, New York, 1994; K. Roiphe,
electorate as a whole in congressional elections that do The Morning After: Sex, Fear and Feminism, Little,
not include a presidential race are relatively stable – 46 Brown, Boston MA, 1993.

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 35


Thinking naturally
John O’Neill

The richness of the debates about the environment realism of postmodernism and accept the significance
has its source not just in the importance of the issue, of the ways in which the concept of ʻnatureʼ has been
and the significance for the future of radical politics used for ideological purpose.
of dialogues between socialists and greens, but also in Soperʼs own position occupies that political space.
the fact that it lies at a point of convergence between Her strategy is to carve out more clearly this posi-
a number of other arguments: between realism and tion between the ʻnature-endorsingʼ perspectives of
constructivism, Enlightenment and its critics, human- naturalists and the ʻnature-scepticalʼ perspectives of
ism and anti-humanism; on the relation of economy, constructivists, by exploiting what are taken to be the
culture and nature; on the future direction of feminist strengths in one position to highlight the weaknesses
thought and action. This richness is represented in Tim in the other. In general, against the postmodernist
Haywardʼs and Kate Soperʼs recent books.* Both are focus on cultural construction of nature, she insists
important contributions. Both are likely to have a wide upon the importance of recognizing the existence
readership and a large influence on current debates in of a discourse-independent natural world on which
environmental politics. Both certainly deserve to do humans have real impacts that have to be addressed,
so. They combine intellectual clarity and rigour with and defends critical realism as the necessary basis for
political commitment and purpose. The arguments a coherent political project of social change. At the
amongst socialists and greens about the political and same time, she criticizes the tendency of the nature-
social implications of our current environmental crisis endorsing positions for their insensitivity to the ways
will be the richer for them. in which the concept of nature has been historically
Kate Soperʼs What is Nature? is engaged in a shaped for ideological effects, some of which have
project of reconciliation between two conflicting per- implications for the environmental cause itself. The
spectives on nature to be found in social theory. On argument is played out over a wide range of topics,
the one side stand broadly ʻnaturalistʼ or ʻrealistʼ from the use of the concept of nature to exclude or
approaches which take the concept of nature to refer downgrade those associated with the natural – the
to a concept-independent reality – a natural world primitive, corporeal, feminine – through to examina-
that has been the object of human exploitation and tion of the ways in which the modern conservation
destruction, and which we have good reason to protect movement appeals to an ideological representation of
from further spoliation. On the other side stand post- the ʻruralʼ. In each case the anti-naturalist tendencies
modernist and post-structuralist approaches that are in constructivism are set against what is defensible in
standardly anti-realist and relativist in orientation, the ecological naturalist and realist positions.
and that focus upon the ways in which different con- The discussion is always rich, and much of the
ceptions of ʻnatureʼ are culturally constructed and argument it will engender will concern the detail. To
employed to legitimate a variety of social and sexual take just one example, Soper makes a useful demarc-
hierarchies and cultural norms. As Soper notes in ation between different levels of nature, pointing out
outlining these conflicting perspectives, they do not that the source of aesthetic pleasure and value is the
map directly onto two theoretically and politically ʻsurfaceʼ lay nature of our everyday encounters and
self-contained oppositional blocs. Green, Marxist and not the ʻdeepʼ level of causal powers and processes to
feminist positions exist which both reject the anti- which the scientific realist refers. The point is an impor-
tant one and is broadly right. However, the two-way
*
Tim Hayward, Ecological Thought, Polity Press, Cambridge, contrast between surface and deep tends to invoke a
1995; Kate Soper, What is Nature? Culture, Politics and the picture of natural science as physics. There are more
Non-Human, Blackwell, Oxford, 1995.
layers to the nature we encounter than the division of

36 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


surface and deep might suggest: it is not clear to me rather than economic, it is the case that those who are
where the work of the biologist, geologist or ecologist realist tend to hold on to materialist explanations of
fits. To the extent that their work generates knowledge social life, which constructivists tend to reject. Now
of the deeper structures, it can transform our ways of while I would be in the same camp both in respect
experiencing the surface order. For example, when I of realism against constructivism, and the emphasis
walk in marshland with one of my botanist friends on the explanatory importance of the material and
I am constantly aware of how much more she sees, economic against the cultural turn in much recent
and am rewarded by the details she can add to my social and political theory, there is a need for more
experience: what is initially aesthetically dull becomes clarity in separating out the different components of
a more interesting place. the argument.
While part of the strength of the book lies in the
detail, its distinctiveness resides in the general project Ecological humanism
of reconciling the different approaches. Judgements In the terms that Soper uses, Tim Haywardʼs Eco-
about its success will tend to be different depending logical Thought belongs in the main within the realist
upon oneʼs starting point. In a footnote to the first camp. However, it also illustrates the complexities in
chapter Soper notes that some on the realist side of the possible positions that can be taken, and the book
the divide in radical theory might find the argument occupies a portion of the intellectual and political
too even-handed: ʻThey will object that postmod- space between nature-endorsing and nature-sceptical
ernist theory is the vehicle of reactionary forms of positions. Whilst realist, and conscious of the very sub-
neo-liberalism which have nothing to offer a green stantial damage done to the environment, normatively
movement committed to radical social changeʼ (p.13). it develops a sophisticated anthropocentric approach
The passage captures my own initial reaction exactly, to the natural world. The book defends an ecological
and my worries were not entirely allayed by the rest of humanism according to which the full development of
the book. To some extent, I think postmodernism gets the human good is bound up with the good of non-
an easy ride. My worry is not what is said but what human nature. Our environmental crisis requires not
is left out – in particular, the degree to which some the rejection of humanism for an ecocentric position,
forms of postmodernism have ended up as celebrations but rather a rejection of the impoverished Promethean
of market capitalism and the modes of consumption it forms that humanism has taken. Haywardʼs ecological
fosters, which are incompatible with ecological impera- humanism attempts to defend the position that humans
tives. This said, Soperʼs openness to what is valuable are at once natural and cultural beings. Haywardʼs
in the specific claims made about the cultural construc- book is also in many ways an exercise in reconcil-
tion of ʻnatureʼ from within postmodern theory is to iation. It aims to show that the defensible core of
be welcomed. the radical ecological critique of modern societies
What is Nature? is a book I would recommend to can be stated without abandoning the emancipatory
constructivist friends and colleagues who would be values of the Enlightenment. The proper response to
less inclined to listen to realists like myself because tensions within the Enlightenment project highlighted
we are less inclined to listen to them. It conveys the by the environmental crisis is not to give up on it,
strong sense of having seriously considered what both but to renew it. In the end the radical ecological
sides have to say. Relatedly, while I think there is critiques of Enlightenment themselves depend upon
nothing in realism that rules out an acknowledgement the emancipatory values of the Enlightenment. The
of the ways in which the concept of nature has been defence of that thesis calls upon and contributes to
historically employed for ideological functions, there recent work within the Frankfurt tradition, especially
has been a fault of omission from within the realist by Benhabib and Habermas. In developing the theme,
framework which Soper rightly identifies. I suspect the book also provides a clear and accessible overview
that part of the reason for this is that the argument of most of the major recent currents in ecological
between realists and constructivists is to some extent ethics, economics and politics. To the student and the
a sublimated version of an old argument about the general reader it will prove an invaluable introduction
relative significance of political economy and culture to recent ecological thought.
in understanding the forms of social oppression and The enterprise in which Hayward is engaged is to
ecological crisis that beset us. While there is no reason be welcomed against recent anti-Enlightenment trends
why one shouldnʼt be an ontological realist, and hold in social theory. One of the virtues of his book is
that the main determinants of social life are cultural that it deals with the Enlightenment in its historic

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 37


complexity, and not as a slogan on which a variety to be particularly acute given the additional claim that
of either banal or implausible-looking claims are set human powers and needs have developed in the course
up for praise or condemnation. Consider, for example, of human history. Soper concurs with Haywardʼs criti-
the question that has long been at the centre of much cism of naturalism. To it she adds an additional point.
radical social theory: whether the language of rights Not only can we not expect a naturalistic theory of
is the appropriate discourse in which to express the the human good to provide a determinate answer to
emancipatory aims of radical politics. Hayward claims the question of what the good life should be. Given
that the language of rights is one part of the Enlight- our ecological constraints, such an answer is not even
enment legacy which we can and ought to retain. We helpful to an ecological politics: ʻ“Flourishing” is what
ought to retain ʻrightsʼ because they secure protec- we ought to be re-thinking in the light of current and
tion of individuals from abuse – protection that will future resources; it is not an a priori given of human
always be necessary, in so far as the circumstances nature whose “true” needs nature can be expected to
of justice cannot be overcome. We can hold on to fulfilʼ (p.168).
the rights discourse since, while their specific liberal
and individualist form may be open to criticism, it
is possible to defend a conception of rights which A flourishing life
recognizes with socialist, feminist and communitarian Both Haywardʼs and Soperʼs criticisms point to a real
critics that we are embodied beings constituted by difficulty with any universalist conception of human
relationships to other persons and ecological condi- flourishing of the kind offered by the naturalist – that
tions. However, I remain unconvinced that these kinds it has to steer a course between vacuity on the one
of move do justice to the traditional radical worries hand, and an implausibly narrow specification of
about the very use of rights language to express basic flourishing on the other. Yet that is a difficulty, not
ethical and political concerns. While the significance an impossibility: a course can be steered. The objec-
of the content of the rights claims can be accepted tions of Hayward and Soper play on an implausibly
– they are used, as Hayward notes, to formulate basic overdeterministic account of what a naturalistic theory
requirements of justice – there remain real issues about of human flourishing has to deliver in order to avoid
the normative adequacy of the language employed to vacuity: they assume that a naturalistic account of
express them. While I think the issue is still open, human flourishing must provide ʻdeterminateʼ answers
there is a thinness and abstractness to rights discourse to the nature of particular social forms and provi-
and an implicit possessive individualism which lend sions. However, no account of our human powers and
weight to the traditional radical scepticism. needs could determine an answer to the details of a
Where, however, I have the greatest problems with flourishing life. As Martha Nussbaum has noted, any
Haywardʼs position is just where it most explicitly defensible theory of the human good should be thick,
and self-consciously converges with Soperʼs – that but ʻvague in a good senseʼ: it will allow that there
is, in their common criticism of naturalism about the are a variety of different specifications of ways in
human good. Both Hayward and Soper reject the kind which humans can lead a flourishing life.1 However,
of naturalism defended, for example, by Ted Benton. an account of the powers, capacities and needs that
This insists upon an account of the specific species make us the kind of being we are does delimit the
powers and needs of humans as natural beings that will target of what a flourishing life can be. As such
allow us both to criticize various social practices and it still has real work to do. For example, to take a
structures as incompatible with a flourishing human standard (and I think true) claim found in naturalistic
life, and to recognize that other animals have their theories of the human good dating back to Aristotle, as
own essential species powers and needs, enabling us humans we are beings that need intimate relations to
to criticize conditions and modes of life imposed upon particular others. That claim does not determine some
them. Hayward argues against such naturalism that its particular form such relations have to take: it allows of
reproach to non-naturalist theories of human nature variability. The relations can take a variety of specific
– namely, that they lack a determinate characterization forms in different social and cultural settings. As such
of human nature which would provide ʻa normative it might provide one part of what Michael Sandel calls
standpoint to criticize late capitalist society and envis- a substantive justification of homosexual relations,
age a preferable futureʼ – could be turned against which appeals not just to the value of autonomy, but
naturalism itself: it fails to provide any clearer guid- to the specific goods and virtues of intimate relations
ance for social critique (p.82). The problem is taken that homosexual unions can realize, in contrast to

38 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


a liberal-voluntarist justification appealing solely to that there are givens of human nature – discovered
free choice.2 empirically and not a priori – that we have room to
At the same time, the existence of a variety of criticize the consequences of current social arrange-
specific cultural forms in which intimate relations can ments. If we could not say now that a flourishing
be realized does not entail that the account has no human life requires clean air and water, topsoil for
negative work to do. If we have a society like our own, sustainable agriculture, conditions for literacy and
in which those who are old and without wealth are human companionship, and so on, we would have
excluded from ties of affiliation with others, then there no place from which to criticize the unsustainable
is room for criticism from within a naturalist account nature of capitalist society. Humans may be able to
of the good. Naturalist accounts of our human powers survive amidst poison and natural squalor – witness
and predicaments have work to do of both a positive life in the worst shanty towns in the Third World.
and negative kind, without providing a ʻdeterminateʼ They cannot flourish in such conditions. We need an
answer to particular questions. Similarly, the indeter- account of flourishing, grounded in our nature, that
minacy of the kinds of historicized naturalismʼ3 that is able to transcend our immediate place and time, if
are to be found in Hegel and Marx can be overplayed, we are to make sense of our specific obligations to
by assuming that a theory of the human good has the future humans and distant strangers. It is the forms a
job of providing ʻdeterminateʼ specification of the flourishing life can take that need rethinking, not the
human good. There is a danger in any historicized concept of human flourishing as such.
naturalism of setting history against biology, and None of this is to claim that there isnʼt a danger in
seeing our powers as completely open, while ignoring naturalist theories. Consider Kant, a major source of
those features of our nature as biological beings that the historicized naturalism of Hegel and Marx: ʻthe
are fixed and which put real limits on what counts history of the human race as a whole can be regarded
as the development of our human powers. This said, as the realisation of the hidden plan of nature to bring
it might be, as Marx and Hegel have it, that specific
about an internally … perfect political constitution as
powers have developed through human history which
the only possible state within which all the natural
entail new needs. For example, the development of
capacities of mankind can be developed completely.ʼ4
certain kinds of power for autonomous choice might
The picture of history as a hidden plan bringing the
be peculiarly modern. Given the beings we are with
full realization of human development can and has
the history we have, these become necessary for our
served as a justification for the colonization of ʻpre-
flourishing; and where the possibility for their exercise
historical peoplesʼ; and the story of inevitable human
is denied, there are needs, and not just wants, that are
progress certainly looks much less plausible today
being denied. This is compatible with the claim that
than it did in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
there are a variety of ways in which the powers of
However, the aims of the Enlightenment as a social
autonomous choice can be realized.
ideal can be divorced from such progressivism and the
It is quite consistent with a naturalist theory to
generalization of local conceptions of the good. As
ask what modes of realizing a flourishing human life
Hayward notes, it is from within its own emancipatory
are compatible with real ecological constraints. In
values that much of the criticism of these features of
particular, one needs to question theories of the human
the Enlightenment can be made.
good that tie it too closely to the high consumption
of material goods. The claim that specific modes Notes
of flourishing might need reconsideration should be 1. M. Nussbaum, ʻAristotelian Social Democracyʼ, in R.
kept distinct, however, from the claim that we can Douglass, G. Mara and H. Richardson, eds, Liberalism
and should redefine the concept of flourishing itself, and the Good, Routledge, London, 1990, p. 217 and
to fit whatever ecological constraints there happen passim.
2. M. Sandel, ʻMoral Argument and Liberal Toleration:
to be. Taken in the second sense, Soperʼs claim that Abortion and Homosexualityʼ, in G. Dworkin, ed., Mo-
ʻ“flourishing” is what we ought to be re-thinking in rality, Harm and the Law, Westview Press, Boulder CO,
the light of current and future resources … not an a 1994.
priori given of human natureʼ, gets things the wrong 3. I borrow the phrase from Allan Wood, Hegelʼs Ethical
Thought, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1990,
way round. If we are considering our relations to
pp. 33–5.
future generations, it would be an ethical mistake to 4. Kant, ʻIdea for a Universal History with a Cosmopoli-
think that the concept of flourishing can be redefined tan Purposeʼ, in Political Writings, edited by H. Reiss,
to fit any constraints: it is because we know now Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, 1977, p. 50.

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 39


40 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)
REVIEWS

A political philosophy that is honest,


decent and true
Michael J. Sandel, Democracyʼs Discontent: America in Search of a Public Philosophy, Harvard University
Press, Cambridge MA and London, 1996. xi + 417 pp., £16.50 hb., 0 674 19744 5.
Avishai Margalit, The Decent Society, translated by Naomi Goldblum, Harvard University Press, Cambridge
MA and London, 1996. xi + 304 pp., £21.95 hb., 0 674 19436 5.

In Liberalism and the Limits of Justice (1982) Michael control over its life and with the erosion of moral
Sandel offered an influential critique of John Rawlsʼs community. He ascribes this discontent to the failure
A Theory of Justice which constitutes one strand in of the liberal political philosophy by which America
the ʻcommunitarianʼ challenge to contemporary Anglo- presently lives. That philosophyʼs defining – and rec-
phone philosophical liberalism. Notoriously, Sandel, ognizably Rawlsian – ideal is that government should
along with other communitarians, was charged with be neutral between the lives that its citizens endorse,
a failure to spell out the political implications of his thereby giving proper (and equal) respect to these
philosophical views, or of doing no more than gestur- citizensʼ free choices, as autonomous ʻunencumberedʼ
ing towards an illiberal politics of the common good selves. ʻUnencumberedʼ here means without communal
which ignored the painfully acquired rights of individ- or moral ties which have not been chosen.
ual citizens. In his new book Sandel recapitulates his This understanding of liberalism is familiar from
critique of Rawlsianism. But he does so by construing Sandelʼs earlier work. But he now seeks to show how
a political philosophy as the public philosophy implicit such a liberalism became Americaʼs public philosophy.
in a set of institutions and practices. His concern is He does so by tracing its increasing influence in
to expose the failure of the liberal public philosophy the judgements of the Supreme Court on religious
which animates contemporary American political life, liberty, freedom of speech, privacy and family. At
and to contrast this inadequate philosophy with that the same time he strives to retrieve an earlier public
earlier, authentically republican public philosophy philosophy, that of the republican tradition, which
which liberalism has supplanted. emphasizes the interdependence of individual liberty
Sandelʼs previous critique was largely an ʻinternalʼ and self-government, the need to cultivate the virtues
one. It sought to show that Rawlsʼs philosophical of citizenship, a concern with the common good, and
project failed on its own assumptions and ideals. Thus, the importance of acknowledging the ties and loyalties
for instance, a Rawlsian self, defined as one which – the ʻencumbrancesʼ – of selves. In the part on ʻThe
could exist prior to its ends, could not choose the Political Economy of Citizenshipʼ, Sandel displays the
terms of its political relations with others in its society. fundamental shift in discussion of wage labour, employ-
Such a self could not, properly speaking, be said to eesʼ rights, manufacturing, and consumersʼ interests,
choose anything. Or, again, Rawlsʼs difference princi- from arguments couched in terms of the civic good
ple required that everyone regard the natural assets of and the dangers of concentrated economic power for
each as communally owned. But the principle operated self-government, to ones that speak only of prosperity
within a context that not only lacked any sense of and the fair distribution of its fruits. The shift is from
community, but precluded its very possibility. civic republicanism to liberal Keynesianism.
The new critique is more of an ʻexternalʼ one. It The discussion is masterful. Sandel yokes his
seeks to expose the gap between theory and reality, defence of the main philosophical claim to a seem-
between that which a given political philosophy prom- ingly effortless command, and clear presentation, of
ises and the reality which its instantiation in a particu- the broad historical developments he thinks significant.
lar society delivers. Sandel starts from the American Moreover, his conclusion could not be clearer or more
publicʼs current discontent – with its lack of political unequivocal. The liberal public philosophy is deeply

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 41


flawed and inadequate to the tasks of contemporary by the liberal public philosophy. It surely cannot be
American political life. The republican tradition must merely an unhappy accidental outcome of the vagar-
be restored. However, as he recognizes towards the ies of Supreme Court jurisprudential reasoning. One
end of his book, the doubts about his claim will be would like to think that the Courtʼs judges have given
both practical and moral. Whilst acknowledging these, expression, in their own way and in their own time, to
Sandelʼs response to them is not entirely convincing. ideas and ideals, however partial and inchoate, forming
The moral concern is that the republican tradition in the American public mind. It is tempting to see
could be revived only at the cost of a loss of individual the republican public philosophy as appropriate to the
freedom and tolerance of difference. Republicanism formation of a young republicʼs social, economic and
sees a place for ʻsoulcraft in statecraftʼ, to use Sandelʼs political institutions, when such a society was striving
suggestive language – that is, according the government to give itself a clear, assured identity robust enough to
the formative role of encouraging certain civic virtues cope with the various interests and competing forces it
and moulding people to the living of certain kinds of recognized as inhabiting its boundaries. Liberalism is
lives. He is certainly right to insist – and the point is the philosophy of a polity that has learned to live with
an important, often neglected one – that such a politics difference, that is confident of its ability to tolerate
inclines to coercion not on account of its formative the varied lifestyles which are the inevitable outcome
ambition alone, but because of an assumption that the of an individual freedom it has also learned to value
common good is single and agreed. But then the clear and encourage. This may be too simple a story. But it
onus is on Sandel to specify the range of virtues and would suggest that there is no going back (and Sandel
kinds of worthwhile lives that a republican government acknowledges the dangerous lure of nostalgic republic-
should play its part in forming. Instead, he merely anism). It might also suggest that the way forward is
repeats that the liberal account of free citizenship is unattractive, as liberalismʼs very success has destroyed
empty and lists the ʻgropings, however partial and the conditions for a revival of a successful democratic
inchoateʼ in recent American political debate which public philosophy.
gesture towards some revival of republican themes. It Whatever is the case, Sandel needs to tell some sort
is all rather insubstantial and unpersuasive. of plausible story as to why (and not just how) America
The practical concern is how to revive a republican has travelled from the civic to the merely ʻproceduralʼ
tradition of confident moral community and robust republic. He needs to do so not least because other-
self-government in the modern world, marked by a wise Americaʼs search for a public philosophy will
hugely increased scale and complexity of interaction at be aimless and fuel the very discontent with politics
all levels. Here Sandelʼs reply seems even more vague his book seeks to address. He also needs to do so
and thin. He cautions against finding the appropri- because otherwise communitarism will continue to be
ate basis for a new democratic politics in either the stigmatized – not unfairly – as a political philosophy
national or global community. He is right to insist that of protest, parasitic on the limits of liberalism, and not
a globalized economy and politics is eroding the role itself a constructive vision of an alternative politics.
of the nation-state at the same time as it is failing Avishai Margalitʼs The Decent Society also starts
to realize a plausible cosmopolitan citizenship. But from a worry with Rawlsianism: is justice enough?
then the game might seem to be up for any kind of At the outset of A Theory Rawls famously described
realistic politics of morally assured, popular self-rule. justice as the first virtue of society and left his readers
Sandel talks of the possibility of a revitalized civic with the impression that it is probably the only virtue.
life in the more particular communities in which we Critics have wondered whether a society that is merely
live, and of the increased importance of the ʻpolitics just need be ideal. Margalit suggests one possible
of neighbourhoodʼ. But this sounds and looks like a alternative measure of evaluation: a societyʼs decency.
retreat from – not a rediscovery of – real politics. Decency is characterized as not humiliating people,
Insisting on community and urban projects, when even and humiliating people is defined as excluding them
the most powerful of the worldʼs states must submit to from the ʻfamily of manʼ. The defence of this claim is
the imperatives of a world economy, does appear to be made by a philosopher who is undoubtedly decent, in
a case of urging the tending of oneʼs own back garden every sense of that word. There are many worthwhile
whilst the new enlarged highway is built out front. discussions of important distinctions – between self-
Notwithstanding these difficulties, there is a further respect and self-esteem, dishonouring and humiliating,
worry about Sandelʼs project. This is that he offers no decent and civilized, and so on. There is much to
account of why the republican tradition was supplanted commend in Margalitʼs treatment of decency in the

42 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


provision of welfare, punishment, employment, protec- kind of level, and unfortunately oneʼs confidence in the
tion of privacy, and multiculturalism. One suspects authorʼs understanding of the real world of politics is
that there are societal virtues, beyond justice, which not helped by finding the ʻBogsideʼ transported from
need to be assured by a societyʼs institutions, and that Derry to Belfast (p. 133).
something very like decency is certainly one of them, Both Sandel and Margalit are writing in the shadow
if not the main one. of Rawls and both are acutely conscious of the need to
Yet if Margalitʼs account is largely unexceptionable, make political philosophy politically adequate – that
this may be due to the fact that there just is little to is, to construct a public philosophy that can, as well
which exception can be taken. It really is hard to disa- as should, animate the institutions of actually exist-
gree with sentiments like, ʻA decent society is … one ing societies. In their own ways each reveals how far
that provides all its members with the opportunity to English-speaking political philosophy has travelled
find at least one reasonably meaningful occupationʼ (p. since the publication of A Theory, and yet how much
254); or, ʻA decent society cares about the dignity of road there still is to cover.
its prisonersʼ (p. 270). Much of the discussion is at this
David Archard

Collective intentions
John R. Searle, The Construction of Social Reality, Allen Lane, London, 1995. xiii + 241 pp., £20.00 hb,
0 713 99112 7.

If, as John Searle remarks, ʻWe live in exactly one intend and do things collectively, and understand what
world, not two or three or seventeenʼ, and if the basic they are doing in that way: it cannot be reduced to a
features of that world are physical in nature, how can mere aggregate of individual actions and intentions.
it also contain, as it seems to do, objective phenom- The basic theory of the creation and structure of
ena that are not obviously physical? Searleʼs previous institutional facts is set out in the initial chapters, and
work attempted to answer this question in respect of largely illustrated by the example of money. Searle
consciousness, intentionality and language. Here he next examines the dependence of institutional facts
turns his attention to the existence of institutional facts on language, and completes his preliminary account
such as money, property, governments and marriage. of institutional ontology. This is then elaborated to
Institutional facts are characterized as those which are describe the logical structure, interdependence, hier-
dependent on human agreement for their existence, in archy and maintenance of a much wider range of
contrast to ʻbrute factsʼ such as Mount Everest having institutional facts, including politics, power, property,
snow and ice near its summit, or hydrogen atoms marriage and war. Searle next deals with the problem
having one electron, which are true independently of of how, if institutions are structured by constitutive
what anyone says or thinks. rules, and if the social agents who participate in
Searleʼs basic theory of institutional facts is sum- institutions are unaware of or mistaken about those
marized in the formula ʻX counts as Y in context Cʼ, rules, the latter can have any causal role to play in the
where X may be some physical object such as a lump behaviour of those agents. He rejects the suggestion
of gold or a piece of printed paper, Y its assigned that agents somehow follow the rules unconsciously,
functional status as money, and C will presumably and argues instead that in learning to operate in social
restrict how it is produced and how and where it can institutions (whether playing baseball or using a bank
be used. In general, the assigned status of such an account) agents acquire dispositions or background
object cannot be explained entirely in terms of its abilities that are sensitive to the rules, enabling them to
physical properties alone. In addition to the assign- operate skilfully within institutions without conscious
ment of status, the creation of institutional facts also (or unconscious) intentions to follow rules.
requires collective intentionality and constitutive rules. Searleʼs analysis of institutional facts is clear and
The latter are the kind of rules that define a particular meticulous throughout and supported by clear argu-
practice, rather than merely regulating it, such as those ments and examples. But the arguments and examples
of chess. Collective intentionality entails that people are very much of his own choosing, and little attempt

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 43


is made to relate them to wider arguments about confronted. In the absence of such realistic alterna-
method and ontology in the social sciences. This is tives, the state is no more dependent on acceptance
odd, since the claim that institutional facts rest on than are the laws of thermodynamics. Likewise with
some form of collective acceptance is hardly new, money: in a trivial sense it is true that for money to
and Searleʼs arguments about background capacities be money people must believe that it is; but if most
are, as he acknowledges, clearly related to well-known people cannot realistically hope to bring it about that
work in the hermeneutic tradition. The overall impres- money is no longer regarded as such, it is nonsense
sion given is that the enterprise is one of tidying up to suggest that the status or value of money rests on
the ontological details of Searleʼs own metaphysical some form of common intention or acceptance on
world-view and assuming that their relevance will be their part. Moreover, even for governments, bankers
apparent to others. The assumption of shared wonder and currency speculators who have some degree of
at metaphysical mystery is no doubt justified in respect control over the value of money, there are objective
of those problems about mind, body and language constraints on their control over it. No one has the
which have been the subjects of Searleʼs previous power to determine for any significant length of time
work. Yet if those problems are set aside, much of that a hard currency has whatever value they see fit to
the metaphysical mystery he perceives in the social give it; and no one, collectively or individually, has the
world will, I think, have been discarded with them. power intentionally to bring about an enduring state
The real mysteries of the social world have to do with of affairs in which money does not exist. The crucial
why we have the kinds of social arrangements we do questions for social scientists and political agents alike
rather than others we can imagine – what possibilities are about how alternatives to existing institutions can
are open to us for change and what possibilities are occur and how they can be recognized or foreseen; and
denied us. Perhaps Searleʼs model of institutional facts it is difficult to see how Searleʼs model provides even
can throw some light on these problems, but he makes the beginnings of answers to such questions.
no attempt to do so. It is a fundamental assumption of Searleʼs analysis
There are, nevertheless, some points at which Searle of institutional facts that there is a real distinction
does touch on substantive disagreements within the between the class of institutional facts, which are
social sciences, and these are indicative of serious dependent on human thought and language, and the
difficulties with his analysis. Searleʼs claim that all unproblematic class of brute facts which are indepen-
institutional facts count as such only if they have a dent of what anyone thinks or says. This distinction is
functional status assigned them by collective intention- threatened, according to Searle, by contemporary rela-
ality – in other words, that money, power, property, tivist arguments which deny the existence of a reality
war and so on only count as such if people con- independent of human representations. In response,
tinuously believe and accept that that is what they are Searle sets out and defends what he describes as ʻexter-
– leads him to argue that the armed
might of the state in democratic
societies ʻdepends on the accept-
ance of constitutive rules much
more than converselyʼ (p. 90). We
cannot assume, Searle thinks, that
a system of acceptance is backed
by a system of force, since the
system of force presupposes other
systems of collectively accepted
status functions. This is chicken-
and-egg stuff. What is required
for people to cease to recognize
or accept a system of status func-
tions such as the state, the army
or the police is that they can see
some alternative to it, and can see
themselves as having the collective
power to resist and overcome the
system of force with which they are

44 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


nal realismʼ (ʻthe world … exists independently of our (not to mention a few other academic disciplines):
representations of itʼ [p. 150]) and a version of the ʻMost people ignore most poetry, because/ Most poetry
correspondence theory of truth. Defending the valid- ignores most people.ʼ
ity of the distinction between institutional and brute So all credit to John Keane for venturing onto this
facts is the only substantive reason given for includ- treacherous terrain. And he is right to see that his own
ing these chapters, and their arguments add nothing cherished project of a ʻcivil societyʼ is imperilled if it
of substance to the real subject of the book. (Searle is continually threatened by a resurgence of violence,
does also say that he has presupposed throughout that or of the plurality of groups within civil society adopt-
in general our statements, when true, correspond to ing violent means to conduct their disputes.
the facts: one shudders at the thought that everyone But his analysis of the problem is far from clear.
who presupposes this should feel obliged to include a He is at great pains to dissociate himself from any-
treatise on the correspondence theory of truth in their thing ʻteleologicalʼ, like the idea of a gradual progress
books.) The anti-realist claims opposed by Searle are towards civility involving a steady decline in levels
familiar enough, but as with the earlier chapters, and of violence and disorder. This he regards as a cosy
beyond the odd fleeting reference to Goodman, Rorty myth, which denies the uneven dialectic of civility
and Derrida, there is little sense of engagement with and aggression that is the real history of humanity.
real opponents, other than Putnam – himself a kind Keane may well be right. But then we have to ask,
of realist – who, in Searleʼs view, makes the mistake why does violence persist? Is it an ineradicable feature
of treating realism as an epistemological thesis, rather of social life or of human nature, as some pessimistic
than an ontological one. commentators suggest? For his part, Keane rejects any
ʻessentialistʼ thesis which proposes, à la Hobbes, that
Kevin Magill
human beings are incorrigibly egoistic and competitive.
Fine. But he doesnʼt get a lot further when it comes
to offering alternative explanations for the alarming
Meandering in a persistence of cruelty, aggression and violence.
There are, I think, reasons for this. The first is
moral maze that, in the best postmodern manner, Keane is all
too anxious to disown any kind of comprehensive or
fundamental explanation as being ʻessentialistʼ and
John Keane, Reflections on Violence, Verso, London
and New York, 1996. 200 pp., £39.95 hb., £9.95 pb., ʻclosedʼ. Otherwise, he would surely have paid some
1 85984 115 5 hb., 1 85984 979 2 pb. attention to Freudʼs argument, in Civilization and its
Discontents, that civilized social life is based upon the
We have lived through what John Keane reasonably repression of basic urges – a repression that may, in
calls ʻa long century of violenceʼ, which, as far as turn, generate tensions which sometimes explode into
killing, cruelty and suffering are concerned, is by violence. Or he might have considered a more limited
no means over. Indeed, Keane cites estimates which version of the same dichotomy which connects, say,
suggest that internal (un)civil wars are currently much the violence associated with football matches with
more widespread than they were, say, thirty years the dreary, routinized, unfulfilling character of daily
ago. The post-Communist disintegration of Yugoslavia working life.
has brought such conflicts into Europe on a scale of Surprisingly, Keane pays little or no attention to
destruction and brutality not seen here for nearly half the mechanization of violence – a development which
a century. allows not only those who instigate it, but even its
Yet political theory, as he points out, has been direct perpetrators, to remain at a distance from the
oddly – indeed, scandalously – reluctant to investi- sufferings they cause. Studies of violent individuals
gate violence, whether the concept or its nature and – murderers, torturers and sadists – cast little light
causes. Academics have generally preferred to analyse on the psychology of men like Adolf Eichmann, as
ʻtheories of justice, communitarianism or the history Hannah Arendt well understood, or on those who, in
of half-dead political languagesʼ (p. 6). If political Stanley Milgramʼs famous experiments, were willing
theory avoids the difficult and disturbing, it merely to obey orders (or even authoritative requests) to inflict
confirms the popular judgement that it is an irrelevant pain on their fellow human beings. No study of what
pursuit. What Adrian Mitchell once said about poetry makes violence possible will get very far unless it
could all too easily be said about political theory takes into account the structural factors which enable

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 45


individuals to evade both the actual consequences of agree with him that there are occasions when recourse
what they do, and any sense of responsibility for doing to violence is justified as having less terrible conse-
it (ʻI was only obeying ordersʼ). quences than passive resistance. But the argument that
If Keaneʼs title – borrowed from Sorel – suggests justifiable violence can breed unjustifiable violence
something a bit meandering, rather than a rigorously is not taken seriously enough. Keane slips too easily
pursued argument, that, regrettably, is not misleading. into calling violence of which he approves ʻcounter-
There are odd hiatuses, and there are too many digres- violenceʼ or ʻcivil violenceʼ. But it is one thing to
sions. We are a third of the way through the book (p. regard violence as a sometimes regrettable necessity
65) before he turns to the definition of violence, and and quite another to claim that the killing or injuring
the ensuing brief discussion is far from satisfactory. of people can be dignified as ʻcivilʼ.
Keane wants to hold on to the traditional concep- Keaneʼs Reflections, though manifestly serious and
tion of violence as ʻthe unwanted physical interfer- enterprising, lack rigour and thoroughness, and the
ence by groups and/or individuals with the bodies book shows many signs of having been hastily com-
of othersʼ (p. 67). But while he dislikes attempts to posed. A diatribe against nationalism, which he claims
extend the meaning of the term, he does not discuss has ʻa fanatical coreʼ (p. 126), is quite inadequate in
the problem raised by his narrow definition. What dealing with such a complex subject, and, significantly,
constitutes ʻphysical interferenceʼ? Are policies which makes no mention of any of the British nationalisms.
result in death by starvation or hypothermia examples Are Scottish nationalists really ʻdriven by the feeling
of such interference? If not, why not? And why are that all nations are caught up in the animal struggle for
ʻbodiesʼ the only object of violence? Modern methods survivalʼ (p. 127)? I think the question answers itself.
of torture, as employed by British forces in Northern There are many unnecessarily long and convoluted
Ireland in the 1970s, may involve no direct physical sentences – the section on the definition of violence
assault on their victims, yet can do terrible damage to (pp. 65–7) is particularly bedevilled by them; and too
the mind and personality, as well as the body. If this is many throw-away asides and unexplained references.
not violence, then the adequacy of Keaneʼs definition What, for instance, is the ʻnear dominant Westphal-
is called into question. Given the huge emotive power ian model of interstate powerʼ which we suddenly
of the word ʻviolenceʼ, these cannot be regarded as encounter on page 45? Or am I the only reader of
merely semantic questions. Radical Philosophy not to know?
Nor, I think, does Keane do sufficient justice to
Anthony Arblaster
the pacifist case against all violence. Personally, I

The first Hegelian Marxist


Kevin Anderson, Lenin, Hegel and Western Marxism: A Critical Study, University of Illinois Press, Urbana
and Chicago, 1995. xviii + 311 pp., $49.95 hb., $15.95 pb., 0 252 02167 3 hb., 0 252 06503 4 pb.

Thanks to its impressive argumentation and wide scholar- dogmatic polemical piece of 1908, Materialism and
ship, this book brings to life a new and unexpected Empirio-Criticism. The Lenin who emerges from the
Lenin, poles apart from both wooden ʻMarxism-Len- Notebooks – a Marxist fascinated with Hegelian logic
inismʼ and dismissive Western scholarship. A fol- – eludes the usual distinction between ʻWesternʼ and
lower of the Hegelian Marxist Raya Dunayevskaya, ʻEasternʼ (or Russian) Marxism.
Kevin Anderson gives us a sympathetic but critical Closely following Leninʼs extracts and comments,
assessment of Leninʼs attempt to assimilate Hegelian Anderson persuasively shows how his attitude changes
dialectics into revolutionary politics. with his reading of Hegel: from an initial ʻmaterial-
The starting point for Andersonʼs argument is istʼ diffidence, to a growing interest in subjectivity
Leninʼs Notebooks on Hegel of 1914–15, a series and self-movement, finally coming to the surprising
of abstracts, summaries and comments, mainly on conclusion that ʻan intelligent (dialectical) idealism is
Hegelʼs Science of Logic. In spite of their fragmen- superior to a stupid (vulgar) materialismʼ. Even if he
tary and unfinished nature, these constitute Leninʼs did not take into account the plenitude of Hegelʼs dia-
philosophical and methodological break with Second lectic, the Lenin of the Notebooks can be considered
International ʻorthodoxʼ Marxism, and, therefore, with the first ʻHegelian Marxistʼ of the twentieth century,
his own earlier views, as codified in his crude and and the first to emphasize the Hegelianism of Marxʼs

46 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Capital: ʻIt is impossible fully to grasp Marxʼs Capital While some Western Marxists, such as Lukács, Bloch,
and especially its first chapter, if you have not studied Goldmann, Lefebvre, Marcuse and, above all, Dunay-
through and understood the whole of Hegelʼs Logic. evskaya, showed interest in them, others (e.g. Colletti
Consequently, none of the Marxists for the past half and Althusser) either ignored or misinterpreted them,
century have understood Marx!ʼ – a famous aphorism from a materialist/positivist standpoint, hoping to drive
with quite obvious ʻself-criticalʼ implications. Hegelʼs shadow ʻback into the nightʼ (Althusser).
Leninʼs public writings on dialectics were much Henri Lefebvre is an interesting example: having
less explicit than the Notebooks: shot through with discovered Hegelʼs Science of Logic thanks to André
philosophical ambivalence (Raya Dunayevskayaʼs Breton – whose place in the history of Hegelian
expression), they refuse to choose between Hegel and
Plekhanov. The call, in 1922, for a ʻsystematic study
of Hegelian dialectics from a materialist standpointʼ is
the nearest Lenin came to a public expression of the
ideas advanced in the Notebooks. On the other hand,
the reissuing of Materialism and Empirio-Criticism
in 1920, without a critical introduction, indicates the
extent of his ʻambivalenceʼ.
However, if one goes beyond Leninʼs strictly philo-
sophical statements, one will discover, according to
Anderson, that some of his most significant post-
1914 theoretical and political writings were variously
grounded in his Hegel Notebooks. His interest in
subjectivity and self-movement, as well as in the dia-
lectical transformation into opposites, contributed to Marxism deserves to be studied one day – he became
his understanding of national liberation movements very much attracted by Leninʼs Notebooks, which
as new revolutionary subjects produced by imperial- he translated into French (1938). However, as long
ism, and of grassroots spontaneous democracy (the as he remained a member of the French Communist
soviets) as the alternative to the centralized bureau- Party, he tried to reconcile Leninʼs Hegelianism with
cratic state. the mechanistic views of Materialism and Empirio-
Curiously enough, Anderson fails to mention a more Criticism. Only in 1959, after his expulsion from the
obvious example of the impact of the Hegel Notebooks Party, did he dare to state that up to 1914 Lenin did
on Leninʼs dialectics of revolution: the ʻApril Thesesʼ not understand dialectics.
of 1917, where, for the first time, he called for the Of all Western Marxists, only Dunayevskaya made
transformation of the bourgeois-democratic revolution the Notebooks central to her overall theoretical project,
into a socialist one. This major turn – a radical break with an extensive – and increasingly critical – series
with the Russian Marxist tradition, common to Men- of writings, from the 1950s to the 1980s. Her Marxism
sheviks and Bolsheviks – was only possible because and Freedom (1958) is the first serious discussion
of Leninʼs emancipation, thanks to Hegel, from the in English of the Notebooks, and the first to try to
strait-jacket of Plekhanovite Marxism, with its rigid, relate them to Leninʼs views on imperialism, national
pre-dialectical notion of ʻstagesʼ prescribed by the liberation, state and revolution. In Philosophy and
Revolution (1973) the issue is taken up again, but
ʻlawsʼ of historical ʻevolutionʼ. The idea at the heart of
this time emphasizing Leninʼs philosophical ambiva-
the ʻApril Thesesʼ of revolution as a dialectical process
lence. Finally, in a new preface for this book (her
owes much to the Notebooks.
last writing), Dunayevskaya insisted on Leninʼs too
The last section of the book deals with Leninʼs
narrowly materialist reading of Hegel.
Notebooks and Western Marxism – a category that
A similar conclusion is drawn by Anderson in
Anderson does not challenge, even though his data
conclusion: while Leninʼs study of dialectics took
show that the opposition between dialectical and
him well beyond the limits of Second International
vulgar-materialist Marxism does not coincide with any
materialism, in spite of occasional critiques of Engels
geographical distinction between ʻEastʼ and ʻWestʼ.
in the Notebooks, he still remained imprisoned within
Leninʼs Notebooks were published in the USSR in
the confines of Engelsian Marxism.
1929, but Soviet Marxism nearly buried them, canon-
izing Materialism and Empirio-Criticism instead. Michael Löwy

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 47


An existentialist Jew
Richard J. Bernstein: Hannah Arendt and the Jewish Question, Polity Press, Cambridge, 1996. xv + 233 pp.,
£45.00 hb., £13.95 pb., 0 7456 1706 9 hb., 0 7456 1707 7 pb.

This is an extremely readable book which advances they feared that its unFrench manners and dress
a straightforward and ungainsayable thesis: Hannah would prompt xenophobia and jeopardize their social
Arendtʼs concern with the Jewish question was central standing. They saw only a combination of beggars,
to the development of her theories. It is thus an interpre- left-wing troublemakers and backward peasants at a
tation of Arendt through the lens of her Jewish experi- time when they needed to build Jewish solidarity and
ence and has the freshness and vitality that Bernstein become ʻconscious pariahsʼ. But that is only part of
claims to have felt when he read her from such a the story: Arendtʼs evaluation of political action is also
perspective. heavily informed by her particular reading of German
That said, there is the question of what precisely existentialism. According to this, human beings can
this reading has to offer. I completely agree that act in the political sphere, initiate new beginnings,
many interpretations of Arendt miss the mark precisely be together in all their plurality and hence be fully
because they fail to take account of her Jewish experi- human, while in the social sphere they merely behave
ence. For example, a way of beginning to understand or conform. Of course, Bernstein knows this, but he
her distinction between the social and the political is not writing a book about Arendtʼs determination to
is to read about her frustration with the Parisian come to terms with being Jewish and the long history
Jewish community in the 1930s, which persisted in of Jewish victimhood in Europe, without abandoning
both renouncing political action and disassociating her fundamental belief in responsibility and freedom
itself from the growing émigré population, because of action as the basic conditions of our humanity. If he
were, it would probably be a more difficult
volume. So is this a fair criticism, espe-
cially given that his study is the outcome
of an invitation to think about Judaism and
Jewishness?
Yes and no. Yes, because Bernstein
goes on to explain Arendtʼs commitment
to freedom as rooted in her reflections on
the concentration camps, which attempted
to eliminate plurality and action and to
destroy not just human bodies, but human
beings. This is undoubtedly one of Arendtʼs
crucial and original insights into the totali-
tarian machine, but I suspect she saw it
not just because she was concerned about
Jews, but because she was a Jew whose
existentialist orientation made her look in
a certain way. No, because again, that is a
different book. Yes, because of one of the
main sub-texts of the book: what does it
mean to be a secular Jew, one who affirms
their Jewishness but rejects Judaism, as
both Arendt and Bernstein do? Existen-
tialist concepts of being-in-the-world and
being-with-others might begin to provide an
answer: perhaps one is a Jew by consciously
affirming certain facts of birth and social
position. The category of ʻconscious pariahʼ
appealed not only to Arendtʼs Jewishness,

48 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


but to her existentialism. Yet Bernstein sidesteps all of particular identity is under attack, however, it tends
this, seeking something that almost looks like essen- to become the most important identity we have. As
tialism. Arendt speaks of her Jewishness as a given for Arendt says: ʻWhen I am attacked as a Jew, I must
which she can only be grateful, and Bernstein finds his respond as a Jew.ʼ
and her Jewishness in this gratitude ʻfor every thing This is not carping. Bernsteinʼs book is a fascinating
that isʼ, in her care for the world and the people in it. read, and I have raised these questions because one of
But this is unpersuasive, for it equally characterizes its pleasures is the way that it opens the discussion. It
many non-Jewish people. Indeed, one can find in this does much else besides – for example, a re-examina-
gratitude and love for the world something very akin tion of Arendtʼs concepts of the banality of evil and
to what I would call a religious or spiritual attitude, radical evil. Whatever you think of the arguments, you
which is certainly not confined to Jews. I am not a Jew, will enjoy the read, whether you are using the book
but, thinking about comparable questions of identity as an introduction to her thought, or are looking for
without belief, I find a far more plausible answer in fresh insights into Arendt. It is a real accomplishment
terms of simply being a member of the family: a given to have written a study that works on both levels.
that you can walk away from or affirm in a variety of
Anne Seller
ways. Membership is not constitutive of identity and
most of us belong to many such ʻfamiliesʼ. When that

Fiction as fiction
Maurice Blanchot, The Most High (Le Très-Haut), translated by Allan Stoekl, University of Nebraska Press,
Lincoln NE and London, 1996. xxxii + 254 pp., £32.95 hb., 0 8032 1240 2.

Blanchot the novelist has suffered at least partial theophanyʼ. In a rather less complex reading, Leon
eclipse by Blanchot the theorist, so it is good to have Roudiez, in French Fiction Revisited (1991), suggests
a new translation of his third novel Le Très-Haut that ʻthe narrator has become the metaphor of God,
(1948). Translator Allan Stoekl makes it clear in his whose creation has become his illness or perhaps
introduction that this is a ʻdifficultʼ novel; the nature of his sin, and whose disappearance is suggested at the
the difficulty is evidently not linguistic, but pertains to end.ʼ
establishing appropriate grounds for interpretation. Such an interpretation is tenable in much the same
The story is easily summarized. Although it lacks way that comparable readings of Kafka are tenable.
specific details of time and place, the book is in effect But Stoekl signals that an overtly political reading
a journal, written in the first person by Henri Sorge, (of the kind Roudiez explicitly rejects) is appropriate;
a minor bureaucrat who aspires to conform to the for him Camusʼ The Plague and Orwellʼs 1984 (both
norms of a totalitarian state. He returns to work after exactly contemporaneous) provide more ready terms
illness, finds his commitment weakened, and leaves of comparison. Roudiez notes a surreal ambience;
the job to recuperate further. The narrative focus Stoekl recognizes the realities of postwar Europe in
broadens to reveal a city hit by plague, the efforts of a landscape of ruins and collapsing buildings, peopled
the authorities to stop the epidemic spreading, and the by the homeless, prostitutes and black marketeers.
attempt by insurgents to seize the opportunity offered Still, beyond this, Sorge the civil servant is simultan-
by this increasingly chaotic situation. The tenement eously, and paradoxically, the embodiment of living
where Sorge resides becomes, in effect, a clinic. The death, and God, the Most High.
revolutionaries engineer their own rise within the state At the end of the novelʼs first chapter, Sorge
apparatus, only to be absorbed by the system they writes:
sought to overthrow. Finally, Sorge meets his death at
the hands of the woman who has nursed him. So, I asked myself, what is this State? Itʼs in me, I
In an essay, ʻSur Maurice Blanchotʼ, published in feel its existence in everything I do, through every
fiber of my body. I was certain then that all I had
Les Temps modernes in 1949, Pierre Klossowski noted
to do was write, hour by hour, a commentary on
the German meaning of Sorgeʼs name, and linked it
my activities, in order to find in them the blossom-
directly to the novelʼs title: ʻGod deprived of his name, ing of a supreme truth, the same one that circulated
or existence deprived of being because it is deprived actively between all of us, a truth that public life
of Godʼs name, would become “anxiety”.ʼ From this constantly relaunched, watched over, reabsorbed,
lexical clue, Klossowski pursued the textʼs ʻnegative and threw back in an obsessive and deliberate game.

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 49


In his 1966 essay ʻThe Thought from Outsideʼ, helpful observation that those opening words are actu-
Foucault manoeuvres deftly through the entanglement ally preceded by the narratorʼs ʻincomplete deathʼ, a
of paradox, noting that ʻwhen Sorge leaves state service structural loop feeding the repetitious and fragmentary
… he does not go outside the law.ʼ Rather, ʻhe forces it journal back into itself:
to manifest itself at the empty place he just abandoned. Sorge the user of language fails to gain possession
The movement by which he effaces his singular exist- of himself through his literary creation. If his book
ence and removes it from the universality of the law in gets away from him, which means in turn that he
fact exalts the law.ʼ Indeed, ʻhe has become one with gets away from himself, it is because their com-
the law.ʼ The real significance of the novelʼs opening mon denominator of language is also a victim of an
incomplete death.
declaration (ʻI wasnʼt alone, I was anybodyʼ) becomes
apparent in this light: the singularity of that ʻIʼ is Gregg aptly names his chapter ʻWriting the Disasterʼ;
converted into ʻthe gray monotony of the universalʼ. Blanchotʼs enduring theoretical concerns clearly inform
John Gregg, in Maurice Blanchot and the Lit- this fiction. Stoekl reminds us of Kojèveʼs legacy to
erature of Transgression (1994), devotes a chapter Blanchot and his contemporaries; this is apt, but the
to analysis of Le Très-Haut. Stoekl cites it as an larger challenge raised by this publication is to read
excellent discussion, while taking issue with some of the philosopherʼs fiction as fiction, with the distinctive
its fundamental claims. Greggʼs account ends with the mode of understanding that entails.
Julian Cowley

More than a charming rhetorical cloud


Régis Debray, Media Manifestos: On the Technical Transmission of Cultural Forms, translated by Eric
Rauth, Verso, London and New York, 1996. viii + 179 pp., £39.95 hb., £12.95 pb., 1 85984 972 5 hb.,
1 85984 087 6 pb.

Régis Debray is arguably one of the most stimulating als persist in describing as ʻAnglo-Saxonʼ readers.
current French thinkers on media analysis and the Thus Debray makes many allusive attempts to explain
problems of French society. Perhaps still best known what mediology is and is not, claiming that it is to
in and outside France as the sometime friend of Castro do with replacing the word ʻcommunicationʼ with
and Che, and as a left-wing intellectual troubled by ʻmediationʼ in the study of the power of signs; that
the usual difficulties that affiliation entailed in Mit- it is the study of the ways and means of symbolic
terrandʼs France, since the late 1970s he has elabor- efficacy, not a version of the history of ideas tweaked
ated a complex approach to the interrelations between to cover ʻcommunicationʼ. Although a short glos-
dominant modes of communication and cultural and sary is provided at the end of the book because ʻa
intellectual activities. The discipline has been created
commitment must be made to being preciseʼ, and ʻa
cumulatively through works such as Teachers, Writers,
rudimentary lexicon will always prove a less grievous
Celebrities (1979), The Scribe (1980), Critique of
flaw than a charming rhetorical cloudʼ, there is no
Political Reason (1983), Courses in General Medi-
entry for ʻmediologyʼ. We learn that mediology draws
ology (1991), A History of the Western Eye (1992), and
selectively from sociology, the history of mentalities,
The Seducer State (1993). To further this approach,
historical psychology, the history of symbolism and
Debray has recently created a new journal, Les Cahiers
de médiologie, which promises to catalyse further cultural history, to become ʻa discipline that treats
mediological research. of the higher social functions in their relations with
Media Manifestos is a translation of part of the technical structures of transmissionʼ – a discipline
Debrayʼs submission to obtain the authority to direct whose ʻmethodʼ determines correlations between the
research in French universities, presented at the ideology, religion, art, literature and other symbolic
Sorbonne in 1994. In reflection of this very French activities of a society and its structures and methods
procedure, it is itself very – perhaps too – French in of using and storing ʻtracesʼ or signs. Charming
style and structure for what Debray and his co-nation- rhetoric with an important message.

50 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Debrayʼs innovation is to have subverted tradi-
tional approaches to the history of ideas, aiming at a Changing the subject
cultural meta-history of the visible (A History of the
Western Eye), and of verbal communication (Courses Simon Critchley and Peter Dews, eds, Deconstructive
in General Mediology), in which attention focuses on Subjectivities, SUNY Press, Albany NY, 1996. vii +
257 pp., $64.50 hb., $21.95 pb., 0 7914 2723 4 hb.,
ʻthe “becoming-material” forces of symbolic formsʼ.
0 7914 2724 2 pb.
This is, of course, where the importance of ʻtechnical
transmissionʼ arises, in the analysis of interactions One way of looking at the modern history of the idea
between culture and the technologies which trans- of subjectivity reduces it to a simple opposition. Either
mit and structure it. Technical transmission is the you are for ʻthe subjectʼ – the fixed, stable, rational
ʻmediumʼ (procedure of symbolizing, code, supporting self that was just the place from which to build the
material system or recording device) in an expanded edifice of metaphysics for Descartes and Kant – or you
sense, building on McLuhanʼs construction of ʻthe are against it. Continental thinking since structural-
ground floorʼ of an understanding of historically and ism has come up with more and more reasons for
geographically defined ʻmediaspheresʼ. This analysis being against it. Hence the widespread urge to kick
draws inspiration from Benjamin, Barthes, Eco, Peirce, over the last traces of the unifying Cartesian subject
Foucault and Althusser, identifying the three primary and celebrate the unpindownability of difference and
mediaspheres of ʻlogosphereʼ (diffusion by writing and the very impossibility of subjectivity as conceived in
orality), ʻgraphosphereʼ (diffusion by printed text), and Enlightenment humanist discourse.
ʻvideosphereʼ (diffusion by audiovisual media). Media It is this sort of easy dichotomy (subject bad, no
Manifestos and mediology in general are more than subject good) that Deconstructive Subjectivities sets
another contribution to ʻmedia studiesʼ, since Debrayʼs out to undermine. Though broadly sympathetic to the
new discipline implies a historical and philosophical critique of the subject in Heidegger and in so much
perspective on communication/mediation necessary recent continental philosophy, its various contributors
to trace developments in dominant forms of techni- reject the conclusion that the topic is thereby somehow
exhausted, or deconstructed out of meaningful exist-
cal transmission. This is more than a postmodern
ence. This rejection need not mean, as Critchley and
celebration of the endless possibilities of technology,
Dews put it in their useful introduction, ʻa naive
offering fruitful insights into current developments in
attempt to return to a pre-deconstructive, pre-Heideg-
virtuality and multi-media.
gerian, or, indeed, pre-Kantian positionʼ. But it does
Hugh Dauncey demand that subjectivity be taken with the sort of
seriousness befitting an issue which, far from being
outmoded, arises with new urgency just as the
traditional, foundational philosophical quest
comes up against its limits.
As a collection the essays have, I think,
two main points to make. One is that recent
thinking in (for example) post-structuralism,
psychoanalysis and Frankfurt Critical Theory
has been just as fixated as the ʻmainstreamʼ
philosophical tradition with a certain view of
the subject: as autonomous, rational, world-
objectifying, and thus as the universal ground
for epistemic certainty, the very starting point
of all philosophy. So it is this Cartesian heritage
– sustained by Kant and, ironically enough, by
its supposed gravediggers in twentieth-century
continental thought – that has been thrown into
question, rather than the notion of subjectivity
itself.
What has largely been ignored is another,
less familiar current, to be found in early
responses to the Enlightenment (in Friedrich

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 51


Heinrich Jacobi, for example, and in Schelling) which have deconstructed themselves. And on this score the
subverted the Cartesian model and disrupted the sure book provides a rich resource, with many of the essays
path of metaphysics long before Heidegger wrote Being finding illuminating links between otherwise incongru-
and Time. According to the pieces by Andrew Bowie ous thinkers, most of them providing valuable insight
and Manfred Frank, Schelling in particular invoked in mapping the resultant new terrain, and almost all of
a subjectivity quite divorced from that which pro- them displaying a refreshingly reconstructive approach
vides the simplistic target of postmodernist critiques, to the topic. All of this adds up to a valuable diagnosis,
one ranging beyond the Kantian model of thought as well as a useful prognosis.
as representation and the ideal of the self-grounding Gideon Calder
philosophical system.
The other main theme, already suggested, is that
there is a real imperative, existential and ethical,
to avoid simply dropping all talk of the subject as
Quirky
necessarily wrongheaded, reactionary or oppressive.
Philip Goodchild, Gilles Deleuze and the Question of
This registers itself in various ways. In his own piece
Philosophy, Associated University Presses, Cranbury
Simon Critchley presents Levinasʼs work as a response NJ and London, 1996. 194 pp., £25.00 hb., 08 386
to the post-structuralist and anti-humanist critique, 3634 9.
rooting subjectivity in material lived experience (and
in the relation to alterity), rather than in abstract, Interpretation is translation. For it to work, the distance
deconstructable models of consciousness or rationality. between the source language and the target must be
Peter Dews argues that Lacanian psychoanalysis can maximal. An interpretation of Heidegger in Heidegger-
be seen as a return to the good old philosophical ques- ese is about as much use as A.L. Rowseʼs transla-
tions of who we are and what we ultimately desire, and tion of Shakespeareʼs sonnets into English prose, for
involves a model of intersubjectivity which defies the the American market. In the case of Gilles Deleuze,
fashionable tendency to presume that ʻcontext is allʼ the main interpretive danger is stylistic mimicry, for
when it comes to questions of truth. Meanwhile, half the result is not clarification, but obfuscation. One
the essays explore the legacy of Heideggerʼs critique dreams of an interpretation that would wrongfoot the
of the subject, concentrating for the most part on the master and proceed more geometrico, in the manner
general question of whether Heidegger is (as he called of Spinoza or the early Wittgenstein.
Nietzsche) the ʻlast metaphysicianʼ, or whether Being At first it seems that Philip Goodchildʼs account
and Time should rather be treated as the very start- provides just that. The first three chapters expound the
ing point for any post-metaphysical subjectivity. The early Deleuzeʼs basic concepts with admirable vigour
pieces by Dominique Janicaud and Rudolf Bernet are and clarity. I have long wished for a short and methodi-
especially helpful, the former demonstrating the failure cal introduction to Deleuze for my non-specialist stu-
of Heideggerʼs attempt to destroy the subject, and the dents, and I thought I had found it. Unfortunately, the
latter incorporating insights from psychoanalysis and book gets bogged down in the fourth chapter, where
Derrida into a fresh account of self-experience. In mimicry takes over and the exposition becomes convo-
common, they seek to show that ʻthinking the subjectʼ luted and unconvincing. By contrast, the final chapter
after Heidegger, though fraught with ambiguities, is by is a translation of Deleuze into another language, but
no means a simple contradiction in terms. since that language is the language of theology, one
This collection is for specialists, and for those who cannot help thinking the translation misguided: there
already have some sympathy with its purpose. Anyone is a vast difference between pointing out Deleuzeʼs
approaching it with reservations about the force of vitalism, in the line of Bergson, and crowning oneʼs
the anti-humanist critique of the subject in the first exposition of Deleuzeʼs conception of philosophy with
place is not likely to be persuaded of the need to the category of ʻspiritʼ, whatever the contents one
ʻrethink the subjectʼ in its wake. But that is probably seeks to impose upon it. The book turns out to be a
beside the point: the agenda here seems set precisely highly interesting, but quirky and idiosyncratic version
for those who are by and large convinced by the of Deleuze, in which, to speak like the French, the
post-structuralist angle, but wonder what is left once Deleuzian cat will fail to recognize her offspring.
traditional views of the subject have been overcome, or
Jean-Jacques Lecercle

52 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


NEWS

A funny thing happened…


The Forum for European Philosophy

T
he last few years have seen some signs of a significant historical shift in the intel-
lectual posture and self-understanding of analytical philosophy in Britain. One such
indication has been the recent spate of publications and conferences concerned with
the origins of analytical philosophy as a distinctive theoretical tradition – a belated, albeit
implicit, recognition of cultural relativity. Another is the increasing openness among less
parochially minded analytical philosophers towards other traditions of European philosophy.
Institutionally (or proto-institutionally) this second development has recently been reflected in
the announcement of the creation of a ʻForum for European Philosophyʼ. The proclaimed aim
of the Forum, which as yet has no formal organization or constitution, is to ʻpromote dialogue
between philosophers in Britain and the rest of Europeʼ. Its inaugural meeting was held on
the premises of the Royal Institute of Philosophy in London on 20 February this year.
Alan Montefiore of Balliol College, Oxford, one of the founders of the Forum, opened
the proceedings by announcing that the Collège Internationale de Philosophie in Paris
had generously donated the sum of £1,500 to assist the formation of an organization in
Britain devoted to aims similar to its own. He introduced François Jullien, President of
the Collège Internationale, who spoke about the origins of his own institution, its aims and
modus operandi, as a locus of philosophical discussion outside the established framework
of the university. Jullien then spoke interestingly about his own philosophical work, which
involves in-depth comparisons of the Chinese and Western philosophical traditions, with
the aim of elucidating what is distinctive about our own European modes of thought. Brief
responses by Alison Denham (Oxford) and Garbis Kortian (Paris and Vienna) were fol-
lowed by François Jullienʼs replies and some questions from the audience. Monsieur Jullien
spoke in French – as was of course his privilege – but unfortunately, as the evening wore
on, the arrangements for periodic translation began to break down. This must have left a
considerable proportion of the audience without much clue as to what was happening in the
discussion, which was unfortunate for an inaugural meeting intended to draw people in.
The evening concluded, as intended, with a general debate on the future format and role
of the European Forum. Alan Montefiore and the other organizers present (Nick Bunnin,
Marion Hobson and Jonathan Rée) welcomed the written submission of suggestions and
proposals from all interested parties.
During the concluding debate high passions were aroused. Some of those hoping that the
Forum might function as a gathering place for the dispersed and often beleaguered com-
mmunity of non-analytical philosophers in Britain were disappointed as it became apparent
that the crucial interface of the Forum would be between British analytical and European
non-analytical philosophy. As a result, by the end of the evening, two organizations were
being proposed: an organization of ʻcontinentalʼ philosophers in Britain, part of whose
aim would be to combat the institutional hegemony of analytical philosophy in Britain
and its intellectual consequences (see the advertisment on p.5, above), plus the European
Forum, whose membership and goals would be more inclusive. As one member of the
audience remarked, the notion of two organizations in Britain devoted to European phil-

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 53


osophy seemed rather lavish, given that only half an hour previously there had been
none. It remains to be seen how these projects will develop, and how they will inter-
relate.
It seems clear that there is now a need for some kind of association in Britain for
teachers and research students working in the various non-analytical traditions of
European philosophy. It is time for some assertion of collective self-confidence – a
confidence which must surely be boosted by the increasing pressure from students for
courses on these philosophical traditions, which even staunchly analytical departments
are now finding it difficult to ignore. At the same time, an organization – such as the
Forum – with the financial resources to stage significant encounters between British
philosophers and their European counterparts may also be able to play a role in the
pluralization of philosophical voices. However, the fact that the Forum is being estab-
lished under the aegis of the Royal Institute of Philosophy will debar it from being a
single-member organization with a democratic structure.
Clearly, some potentially positive developments are on the horizon. But how long
will it be before the power-brokers of the analytical establishment feel ashamed to
announce – as Ted Honderich did when introducing Donald Davidson to an audience in
London a couple of years ago – that analytical philosophy is the ʻonly philosophy that
mattersʼ?

Peter Dews

Honouring Levinas
‘Visage et Sinaï ’, Collège International de
Philosophie, 8–9 December 1996

Since Emmanuel Levinasʼs death in December 1995, the philosophical community has
mourned one of its most fecund thinkers. A memorial symposium in Paris, organized
by the Collège International de Philosophie on 8–9 December 1996, brought together a
number of speakers to reflect on Levinasʼs most important contributions to contempo-
rary philosophy. It was organized around the theme of ʻVisage et Sinaïʼ.
In his opening remarks, Jacques Derrida revisited his readings of Levinas, reorgan-
izing them around an ʻethics of hospitalityʼ or the ʻwelcome of the otherʼ (lʼacceuil de
lʼautre). He followed the thread of Levinasʼs reflections on subjectivity, from the image
of the subject as host/guest in Totality and Infinity to that of the hostage in Otherwise
than Being. The figure par excellence of receptivity and hospitality – he suggested – is
the figure of the feminine, a theme that will be familiar to Derridaʼs readers. Finally,
in turning to Levinasʼs ʻTalmudicʼ texts, Derrida linked the question of hospitality to
the question of peace and considered the possibility of an ʻethical politicsʼ, a politics
that would be founded on the irreducible and unthematizable welcome of the other
in hospitality – a politics of mourning, then, because the other welcomed has always
already been thematized (cannibalized, said Derrida, recalling his seminar title,
ʻManger lʼautreʼ, of a few years ago).
In contrast to Derridaʼs emphasis on the feminine, Jean-Luc Marionʼs presentation,
ʻLa voix sans nomʼ, focused on the question of God the Father. Arguing that the face-
to-face relation between Father and son is the philosophical nucleus of Levinasʼs work,
Marion examined the questions of fecundity, transcendence, infinity and the ethical
relation developed in Totality and Infinity, and their reinscription in Otherwise than

54 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)


Being, and attempted to link them to his own project outlined in his study Réduction
et donation. For Marion, the paternal relation of Father to son is structurally the same
as that of infinity to the finite; the voice of the Father remains as a trace, an echo, of
the originary donation. The Father, however, remains inexorably withdrawn from that
which is given by Him, and hence cannot be said.
Paul Ricoeur traced the path of Levinasʼs hermeneutics of language in his presen-
tation ʻDire et Dedireʼ. Following the path opened in Totality and Infinity, Ricoeur
concentrated on the important transitional essays ʻMeaning and Senseʼ and ʻLanguage
and Proximityʼ, where Levinas first articulates the notion of ʻsubstitutionʼ. This notion
is taken up again in an important chapter of the same title in Otherwise than Being,
which Ricoeur considered at length, especially in relation to Levinasʼs thought of
ʻilleityʼ. The infinite substitution of oneself for an other is the ethical itself, and as
such is the condition of possibility of all ʻcommunicationʼ
and hermeneutics, precisely because in substitution ʻthe
destitution and desituation of the subject do not remain
without significationʼ. Signification – language – continues to
modulate and moderate the relation of the subject to alterity,
and my relation to the other, a relationship of responsibility,
is always a hermeneutical one.
Developing a theme implicit in Derridaʼs presentation,
Simon Critchley sought to situate ʻLevinas avec la psy-
chanalyseʼ in his contribution. The welcome of the other, the
impingement of the other upon me – what Derrida names
ʻhostipitalityʼ – was analysed by Critchley in terms of the
ʻoriginal traumaʼ. As with psychoanalysis, where the ego is
a secondary process of the id suffering the traumatic experi-
ence of civilization, so too is the subject in Levinas the
result of a trauma, and hence epiphenomenal to something
more fundamental.
Italian philosopher Giorgio Agamben devoted his lecture
to a reading of Levinasʼs first published essay – not ʻDe
Lʼévasionʼ, as one might suspect, but rather a little-known
piece on the sense and meaning of Nazism in Europe. His
own ongoing project concerning the question of concentra-
tion camps and political refugees was already sketched out,
albeit differently, by Levinasʼs short meditation, in which he argues that the polit-
icization of life is the hidden agenda of the modern state, here the Nazi state. For
Agamben, this agenda – the technologization of bio-power by the oppressive state
– was already clearly foreseen by Levinas, and remains a paradigm that crosses all
modern sovereign spaces, be they totalitarian or democratic.
Thus Levinasʼs oeuvre was appropriately honoured in its richness and diversity.
Memorials were also offered by Catherine Chalier, Pierre Bouretz, Miguel Abensour,
Jacques Colleony, Jacques Rolland, Shmuel Trigano and Stephane Moses. The papers
of the colloquium will appear in a volume published by the Collège International,
though no publication date has yet been set. They should be read in conjunction with
Derridaʼs recently published essay ʻÁ-dieuʼ, the text of the oration he pronounced at
Levinasʼs funeral.
Another conference devoted to Levinas is scheduled to take place on 20–22 May
1997 in Namur, Belgium. Organized by the Faculté Universitaire Notre-Dame-de-la-
Paix in Namur, the colloquium is devoted to ʻLevinas et lʼhistoireʼ, and will welcome
Jacques Taminiaux and Catherine Chalier, among other scholars of note.

Robert Vallier

Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997) 55


Cogito humana: dynamics of knowledge
and values
XVIIth German Conference for Philosophy, University of Leipzig,
23–27 September 1996

With this conference the Society for Philosophy in Germany honoured the historical contribution of Leib-
nizʼs Rationalism to modern philosophy and science – his birth in Leipzig 350 years ago, the time he spent
there at the university – as well as the birth of his French Rationalist counterpart Descartes. However, the
conference was not primarily of a historical nature and did not focus exclusively on these two important
figures. Where they did feature, it was not in the context of unchanging, or even past, constructs. Thus, for
example, workshops devoted to Descartesʼ morale provisoire emphasized the provisional nature of ethics
under the pressure of rapid changes in knowledge and technology, foregrounding the contemporary orienta-
tion and subtitle of the conference – the dynamics of knowledge and values.
Problems of legitimation were considered in the context of the pressures exerted by globalization and
intercultural encounters. In his treatment of Hannah Arendt, Albrecht Wellmer praised the importance of
freedom and the possibility of starting afresh, which are inherent in action as a central concept in her politi-
cal philosophy, but was sceptical of the applicability of her version of republicanism in the modern world,
Changes in the international activity of multinational companies, NGOs and communications networks led
Onora OʼNeill to argue in favour of legitimation processes which are not restricted to a Hobbesian fixation
on the state.
Friedrich Kambartel held that it is the hermeneutic problem of understanding in the face of polysemy
which is of prime importance in ever-expanding and intensifying intercultural encounters. Bernard Williams
argued against Kambartel on the grounds that the latterʼs reliance on Wittgenstein resulted in him buying
into a problematic hermetic relativism. Williamsʼs own position was that modernity has produced a legiti-
mation demand on states, which means that they have to ʻhave a story to tellʼ as to why their actions are
legitimate; and that this story has to be acceptable to each and every person whose welfare is influenced by
these actions. Williams expressed serious doubt as to whether the booming efficiency economies can meet
this demand. Jürgen Habermas also dealt with the ʻefficiency economiesʼ in Asia, and the encounter between
religious fundamentalism and the postmetaphysical state. He asked whether the modern Occidental form of
legitimation and its accompanying entrenchment of human rights are a European idiosyncrasy, and whether
a demand that these be internationally respected is consequently masked imperialism. According to him,
they are one possible solution to the problems typical of modernity which non-European cultures also have
to deal with in the face of their increasing involvement with modern technologies and economy.
The choice of Leipzig University as the first place in the former GDR to host this conference is signifi-
cant. It was one of the centres of popular uprising leading to the German Wende, or turnabout, in 1989. The
university takes pride in its fully refurbished philosophy department. At the same time it was from within
this department that the still-raging debate about the winding up (Abwicklung) of former GDR philosophy
departments arose. These growing pains are reminiscent of the period after the war when Hans-Georg
Gadamer was briefly rector of the university. In this context, his award of an honorary doctorate could not
avoid the ambivalent tension of a troubled relation to a fractured past.
Stephan Meyer

56 Radical Philosophy 83 (May/June 1997)

You might also like