You are on page 1of 14

Political Philosophy and Sophistry: An Introduction to Plato's Protagoras

Author(s): Robert C. Bartlett


Reviewed work(s):
Source: American Journal of Political Science, Vol. 47, No. 4 (Oct., 2003), pp. 612-624
Published by: Midwest Political Science Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/3186122 .
Accessed: 10/08/2012 12:24

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

Midwest Political Science Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to
American Journal of Political Science.

http://www.jstor.org
Political Philosophy and Sophistry: An Introduction
to Plato's Protagoras
RobertC.Bartlett EmoryUniversity

Thisstudyof Plato'sProtagorasseeksnotonlyto advancetheunderstanding of ancientsophistry,


a taskbothimportantin
itsownrightandessentialtothestudyof thehistoryofpoliticalthought,butalsoto layafoundationforsubsequent inquiries
intotheconnectionbetweenancientsophistryand therelativismcharacteristic of ourage.According to theProtagoras,the
chiefdifferencebetweenphilosopherandsophistis thatthelatterwronglybelieveshimselfto bebeyondorabovetheconcern
forjusticeas a the
virtue; examination moralteaching,then,provesto be thekeyto understanding
of Protagoras' himand
therewiththeintellectual he
position represents.

his study of Plato'sProtagorasseeksnot only to tus trilogy, which treats (among other things) Protago-
advance the understanding of ancient sophistry, ras' understanding of knowledge and is thus of fun-
a task both important in its own right and essen- damental importance, for that very reason takes place
tial to the study of the history of political thought, but after and presupposes familiarity with the Protagoras.
also to lay a foundation for subsequent inquiries into the The Protagorasis thus the proper point from which to
connection between ancient sophistry and the relativism begin to study the origins of "sophistry" according to
characteristicof our age. That there is some such connec- Plato.
tion, and that Protagoras is of crucial importance to it, A fresh return to these origins is essential in part be-
is suggested by the greatest observer of modern times, cause the available evidence has generally been treated
Friedrich Nietzsche: "our contemporary way of think- condescendingly or naively.It is not enough to saythat so-
ing is to a great extent Heraclitean, Democritean, and phistic teaching aimed, "[b]y its very principle," at "prac-
Protagorean:it suffices to say it is Protagorean, because tical success" or at opening "careersin public speaking"
Protagorasrepresenteda synthesis of Heraclitusand Dem- to all; we are not yet at the heart of things if we under-
ocritus" (Nietzsche Willto Power#428 = Nietzsche 1968). stand the "intellectual content" of ancient sophistry to
But because we are not yet in a position to grasp this kin- have consisted in "a wisdom and experience born of the
ship fully, the present essay is devoted to analyzing the art of properlyconducting one's thoughts," i.e., of "know-
most important evidence concerning Protagoras, "[b]y ing how, by means of arguments, to analyze a situation"
far the most famous" sophist of antiquity (Kerferd 1981, (Romilly 1988, 23-4). Here too Nietzsche is a sharp ob-
42);1 and because none of Protagoras'books survives, the server and helpful guide: "the sophists verge upon the
evidence in question consists solely of quotations or re- first critiqueof morality,the first insight into morality:-
ports supplied by other authors, Plato chief among them they juxtapose the multiplicity (the geographical relativ-
(Diels and Kranz 1952, 2:253-71 [DK 80B1-12]). And ity) of the moral value judgments;-they let it be known
Plato too affirms the importance of Protagoras in un- that every morality can be dialecticallyjustified; i.e., they
derstanding the phenomenon "sophistry,"for of the six divine that all attempts to give reasons for morality are
Platonic writings that most obviously investigatesophists necessarily sophistical... " (Will to Power#428, emphasis
or sophistry (Hippias Major, Hippias Minor, Protagoras, original). In the introduction that follows, we will pay par-
the Theaetetus-Sophist-Statesmantrilogy), the Protago- ticular attention to Protagoras'view of justice or morality
ras deserves our attention first: Hippias proves to be a because it is his challenge to morality that proves crucial
less serious thinker than Protagoras, and the Theaete- to understanding him.

RobertC. Bartlettis AssociateProfessorof PoliticalScience,EmoryUniversity,Atlanta,GA 30322 (rcbartl@emory.edu).


'For helpfulbiographicalstatements,see Kerferd(1981, 42-44) and Morrison(1941).
AmericanJournal of Political Science,Vol. 47, No. 4, October2003, Pp. 612-624
?2003 by the MidwestPoliticalScienceAssociation ISSN 0092-5853

612
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS 613

The Opening Scenes or more of Socrates' own thoughts, as only conversa-


tion with or "testing" of another can do (347c5-349a6;
consider also, e.g., 328d8-el, as well as 357e2-8: Socrates
The bulk of the Protagorasconsists of Socrates'report to an
is not consistently concerned with harming the business
unnamed comrade of a conversation he has just had with
the famous sophist at the behest of the young and impetu- prospects of the sophists, Protagoras included). The first
ous Hippocrates.2 Hippocrates has heard (because "all" impression we receivefrom the dialogue of Socrates'con-
cern for the moral education of Hippocrates, a concern
say it: 310e6) that Protagorasis "wisest at speaking";and
remarkable not least for its patient forbearance, is due
he wishes to become the student of Protagoras evidently
in part to the fact that Socrates is addressing or adapt-
because he believes that acquiring such wisdom or skill
himself is essential to fulfilling his political ambition-to ing himself throughout to his unnamed comrade (to-
his becoming "held in high regard in the city" (310e6- gether with certain anonymous others: 310a2, 5-7)-to
a man who, however well-disposed to Socrateshe may be,
7; 316b10-cl). For his part, Socrates warns Hippocrates
is more interested in gossip than philosophy (309b2-3,
that he is about to entrust the education of his soul to a
cl-3), is thoroughly conventional in his deference to
sophist even though he is ignorant of what wise matter
Homer and his preference for the homegrown over the
the sophist teaches and hence of its worth. And despite his
foreign (309al-b2, c9-10), and is even less privy to the
eagerness to study with Protagoras, Hippocrates blushes
intellectual happenings in Athens than is Hippocrates:
at the suggestion that he wishes to do so in order to be-
if Hippocrates knew of the arrival of Protagoras a day
come a sophist himself (312a2; compare 315a4-5); even
later than did Socrates, the comrade remains unaware
Hippocrates doubts the respectability of sophistry, how-
of it on the third day after the fact (compare 310b7-8
ever useful it may be. In these ways the argument and
with 309d3-4). The comrade assumes the relationship
the action of the dialogue indicate its most obvious task:
between Socrates and Alcibiades, of which he playfully
Socrates attempts to uncover, for the sake of Hippocrates,
the characterand worth of Protagoras'instruction-and disapproves, to be a sexual one (309al-5), and Socrates
does not stoop to correct this assumption (consider Sym-
indeed to warn him away from it. But as Socrates himself
insists, to evaluate the worth of the education Protagoras posium 219c6-d2 and context). But the account he gives of
his attempt to shield Hippocrates from an education at the
offers, one must be a knower of the things that benefit
and harm the soul or a "physicianexpert in what pertains hands of a sophist would go some way toward protecting
him from suspicion that he in any way corruptsthe young:
to the soul" (313el-5). If Socrates' critique of Protago-
he prevents their corruption. It is true that, after Socrates
ras is to be convincing, then, it must not merely stymie
has succeeded in embarrassing Protagoras by pursuing
or embarrass the sophist but demonstrate to us, its audi-
ence, the soundness of the standard or goal to which it questions that Protagoras finds annoying-that is, after
he has dulled the luster of Protagoras' reputation in the
looks in doing so. Does the education Protagoras offers
meet the Socratic requirements of a good education- eyes of his potential students-Socrates indicates his in-
tention to leave the get-together (335c3-7). Yet Socrates
whateverthese maybe? The sophist as educator,especially
in his difference from the philosopher, is the theme of the stays in fact, and he must have suspected that the mere
statement of his intention to leave would elicit the pleas
Protagoras.
and negotiations it did elicit and so permit the conver-
We may nonetheless wonder whether Socrates' con-
sation to continue on terms more agreeable to him. It is
cern for Hippocrates fully explains the conversation be-
certain that Socrates did not have any pressing matter to
fore us. After all, it is Socrates who suggests that he and
attend to elsewhere, as he claims to have, for upon finally
Hippocrates make their way to Protagoras and the other
leaving Callias'home he happens upon his unnamed com-
sophists (314b6-c2), just after he has issued a stinging
rade and repeatsthe just-completed conversationin allbut
rebuke to Hippocrates for his uninformed desire to do
its entirety (compare 335c5-6 and 362a2-4 with 310a2-5;
so, and at an important juncture in the dialogue Socrates
for the omissions, see 314c3-7, 316a6-7, and 348b1). And
assures Protagoras that his cross-examinations have as
Socratesnever indicates what effect any of this had on Hip-
their goal the discovery of the truth about virtue, about
a question that perplexes Socrates himself; his conver- pocrates (or for that matter on his comrade). Could it be
that Socrates'deepest concerns, the question or questions
sation with Protagoras is intended to make certain one
he wishes to examine together with Protagoras, are pre-
sented in the guise of his concern for the moral education
21haveusedthe textof Croiset1923,althoughI havefrequentlycon- of Hippocrates, or at any rate that the latter is strictly sub-
sulted the following editions or commentaries:Adam and Adam
(1921), Burnet (1903), Manuwald (1999), Sauppe (1892), and ordinate to the former?If this is so, then Socratesdemon-
Verdenius (1974). Translations throughout are my own. strates before our eyes his "good counsel concerning his
614 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

own affairs,"which issues in a manifest or ostentatious toms (nomoi) is loosened considerably (consider again
concern for the affairs of others. 309c9-10). Here apparently one can enjoy the freedom
As Socratesand Hippocrates arriveoutside the home necessary to discuss openly the gravest matters, includ-
of Callias, the two complete a conversation the substance ing "the things aloft" and their fixed "nature":here the
of which Socratesrefrainsfrom reporting to the comrade things aloft are assumed to be not divine but natural-
but which leads the feisty eunuch who does hear it to perhaps stones and earth, for example (Apologyof Socrates
conclude that they too are sophists: to the mostly (but not 26dl-5 and context). And here one can venture the view,
entirely) uninformed, Socratesand the sophists areas one. as Hippias does later on, that those present are governed
With the begrudging compliance of the eunuch, Socrates and united by nature and not at all by the "tyrant"nomos
gains entry and immediately surveys the scene inside: he (337c6-e2).
first sees Protagoras,who enjoys the greatest number of
followers, including very prominent Athenians (Callias,
the two sons of Pericles, Charmides) as well as a good
many foreigners;then Hippias with a smaller retinue that Protagoras' Teaching
includes two sometime members of the Socratic circle
(Eryximachus and Phaedrus); and finally Prodicus, who The "sophisticated"atmosphere we are thus introduced
is also with a mix of Athenians (the young Agathon) and to makes all the more striking both the extreme caution
foreigners.Quoting from Odysseus'remarksin the course with which Protagoras speaks throughout and the deli-
of his famous passage through the House of Hades, the cacy, marked by forethought, with which Socrates first
Greek underworld, Socrates implies that Hippias is akin approaches him (316c5; 318d5-7). Even here, in what is
to Heracles, Prodicus to Tantalusand, more generally,the at most a semi-public gathering, Protagoras' first con-
House of Calliasto the House of Hades-and not without cern is with the nature of the audience he is to address
reason. For Callias and Hades enjoy the dubious distinc- (316b3-4; compare 317c6-dl), and he is prompted by
tion of having kept company with their respective wives that concern to offer to the restrictedaudience of Socrates
and the mothers of their wives.3 Perhapsbecause he is dis- and Hippocrates some important reflections on the great
tractedby Protagoras'delightfully comic chorus, Socrates danger to which his practice of sophistry subjects him
neither describes Protagorashimself (beyond his capacity and, in particular,on the difference between him and his
to bewitch people with his voice) nor indicates the sub- predecessors in grappling with that danger. For whereas
ject matter of his discourse to which all are so attentive; all previous sophists endeavored to conceal, by means of
Protagoras' voice fails to bewitch Socrates. Only in the one sort of "cloak" or another, the very fact that they
case of Prodicus-a man "altogetherwise and divine"- were sophists, the aptly named Protagoras ("firstto speak
does Socratesmake known his (unfulfilled) desire to hear out") is perfectly open about his being a sophist. But for
what is being said (consider also 340e8-341a4), and only all his distance from the earlier sophists with their ap-
in the second and central case does Socratesstate the sub- parently clumsy and even counterproductive efforts at
ject matter of the discussions: Hippias is giving detailed concealment-effective only with the many, who "per-
responses to certain astronomical questions pertaining to ceive as it were nothing" (317a4-5), as distinguished from
"natureand the things aloft" (315c5-6; note also the men- the powerful few-Protagoras nowhere claims to have re-
tion of astronomy at 318d9-e4). Coming in just behind moved the necessity dictating the use of such conceal-
Socrates are Critias and Alcibiades, the latter being the ment. On the contrary, Protagoras' openness is itself a
supposed object of Socrates'affection (316a6-b2; 390a5). precaution (317b5) meant to protect him, and he men-
In this closely guarded and rather exotic underworld, tions but fails to specify certain other means of conceal-
filled to capacity with sophists and their devotees, for- ment that keep him from suffering harm as a result of
eigners with their foreign ways mix easily with the best of agreeing that he is a sophist (317b6).4 Put another way,
Athenian society or its youth-including a budding poet Protagoras'openness is only a partial openness and it too
(Agathon), two future tyrants (Critias,Charmides), and a is motivated by the need for self-protection. As the re-
philosopher. In the unconventional and even decadent at- sults of Socrates' cross-examination of Hippocrates al-
mosphere created by the profligacy of Callias (Apologyof ready suggest, Protagoras is frank about the fact that he
Socrates20a4-6 and Xenophon Symposium1.5), it would teaches but not about what he teaches (consider also
seem that the hold of the merely homegrown ways or cus- 352a8-bl).

3See Andocides On the Mysteries 124-27 (= Macdowell 1962) and 4Thebest discussionof Protagoras'self-presentationis Coby (1987,
Strauss (1970, 157-8). 37-44).
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS 615

Only under pressure from Socrates does Protago- incapable?) of offering it; no special expertise in politics
ras state more or less candidly the nature of his instruc- is attainable through instruction and hence it cannot be
tion: "The subject in question is good counsel concerning demanded. If the evidence Socratesoffers is uncontrover-
one's own affairs-how he might best manage his own sial, his interpretation of it surely is. For would not the
household-and, concerning the affairs of the city, how Athenians claim rather that all citizens are equally capa-
he might be the most powerful in carrying out and speak- ble of giving political advice because all-all gentlemen, at
ing about the city's affairs"(318e5-319a2). The successful least-not only possess the relevant expertise but can and
student of Protagoras, then, will of course benefit him- do teach it to their fellow citizens (see, e.g., Meno 92e3-6
self by managing his private affairs well, but Protagoras and context)? Socrates would appear to be on more solid
leaves unclear the end with a view to which his student will ground when he notes, in the second place, that even "our
exercise preeminent power in the city: will he be guided wisest and best citizens" cannot bestow on their own kin
by the desire to benefit the city or himself? It is certainly the expertise they possess, an expertise he now, and for the
true that Socratesimmediately imposes on Protagorasthe first time, calls "virtue" (319e2; also 320a3, b5). Pericles,
most respectableinterpretation of his remarkspossible- for example, has as yet been unable to educate his young
to the effect that Protagoras teaches the political art and ward Cleinias, let alone turn him into another Pericles. It
good citizenship, words that had never passed Protagoras' is clear on reflection that Socrates has in mind two quite
lips-just as it is true that Protagorashappily concedes this different conceptions of political excellence, the one char-
to be what he publicly pronounces or "professes"(319a6- acteristic of the good or dutiful citizen, the other of the
7). But since we have just been alerted to the dangerous greatest statesmen: "good citizenship" differs from "the
character of Protagoras' activity, to the "ill will and hos- political art"at its peak, and if the latter cannot be taught,
tile plots" to which it can give rise (316d3), as well as to does not every city claim, at least, to teach the former?
his necessary recourse to arts of concealment, we must be Or-since the teachability of virtue proves to rest on its
especially wary of becoming, like "the many," his dupes. being knowledge in the strict sense (episteme:361a6-c2;
Could it be that Protagoras promises to teach his stu- Meno 87bl-c7)--does Socrates here mean to cast doubt
dents how to benefit themselves in matters public as well on the rationality of what is conveyed in and through
as private, or that he teaches them how to gain preem- the "education"to citizenship?Socrates'challenge to Pro-
inent power in order to use the common good for the tagoras concerning the teachabilityof virtue certainlyun-
sake of their own good? Is not Protagoras' claim to be- dermines the sophist's business prospects, but it also in-
stow the greatest political power on his students-that troduces the question of what properly constitutes virtue
is, on anyone who can pay the tuition (consider 316b8- and whether in all its various forms or guises it is rational
9), however unpromising his nature5-at least a little and hence teachable.
troubling? All this suggests that when Socrates turns to Protagoras'lengthy response to Socrates includes the
raise the question of whether such good citizenship is in complex myth of Prometheus and Epimetheus for which
fact teachable, we must keep on the table the prior and the dialogue is probablybest known. We limit ourselvesto
more fundamental question of precisely what Protagoras some preliminary observations.6 To begin with, the myth
teaches. indicated is but one part of a long speech that also contains
To support his view that the political art or good cit- an argument, a logos,properly speaking (320c6-7; 324d6-
izenship (319a4-5, 8-9) cannot be taught, Socrates offers 7; 328c3), and the ostensible purpose of the long speech
two pieces of evidence. First, when some technical matter as a whole is of course to prove that virtue is teachable
requiring expert advice arises, the democratic assembly of and that Protagoras himself can teach it. But Protago-
Athens refuses to hear from any but the acknowledged ex- ras also achieves two different (if related) ends by means
perts. Whenever deliberation is required concerning the of it: he intimates to his potential students in the room,
city's management more generally,however, any and ev- Alcibiades, Critias,and Charmides among them, the truth
ery citizen is permitted to speak because-according to of what he (truly) teaches, even as he shores up the conven-
Socrates-all believe such political expertise to be un- tional opinions he and his successful students will exploit
teachable and thus all citizens to be equally capable (or in their quest to become "most powerful." For it seems
that Protagoras believes of Zeus not only that he exists
5Compare316b9-10 with 10-11: Socratesvouches only for Hip- but that he is a divinely beneficent lawgiver-a Zeus who
pocrates' wealth and his political ambition, not for the opinion cares for the whole human race, who in his care for us
pertainingto the boy's nature. And Protagorasshows no interest
in discerningthe suitabilityof that naturefor instruction(consider
327b7-cl, as well as 351a3 and b2: Protagorasis of courseawareof 6Forhelpful extendedtreatments,see Goldberg(1983, 13-66) and
the importanceof one's naturein makingtrue progress). Coby (1987, 53-70).
616 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

gave justice and shame to all, and who made political life of injustice. He teaches, that is, that the unjust way of life
possible by setting it down as a law that anyone who does is superior to the just life, that the happy few exploit the
not share in these will be killed on the grounds that he is ignorant many, and that the only true virtues are wisdom
an illness in the city (322dl-5). But in truth-even if one and courage:7according to Protagoras'account of it, "po-
ignores the fact that all this is conveyed in what is explic- litical virtue" (323a6-7, b2, 324al) is limited to modera-
itly a myth largely of Protagoras'creation-the details of tion, justice, and piety, or to what might be called ordinary
it suggest a rather dark picture of the human condition. decency, and the so-called education necessary to instill
Zeus cares for the human race, i.e., he is indifferent to it consists of exhortations, forced memorization, threats,
the fate of individuals; his concern for the race extends and even beatings: "'Do these things!' 'Don't do those!"'
only so far that it not perish entirely (321a2, b6, and es- (325d5 and context; the beliefs of the Athenians and in-
pecially 322cl); and such care as he exercised took the deed of all human beings pertaining to virtue properly
form of intrusting our well-being to two bunglers, for belong to Protagoras' myth rather than to his logos:see
even the prudence of Prometheus ("Forethought") did 322d5-324dl and the transition at 324d6-7). This is not
not prevent him from allowing the erring Epimetheus the education Protagoras offers, of course, but is rather
("Afterthought")to distribute the various capacities or what everyone receives initially at the hands of the law,
powers to all creatures (320d4-8). The world is funda- of nomos broadly understood (consider 326c7-d8, which
mentally "Epimethean":thought follows ratherthan pre- is the climax of this section; by thus instilling justice, the
cedes creation. The only comforts we have were invented altogether human law accomplishes the task initially as-
by us through arts of our own devising; and we attained signed to Zeus). Such an "education"never mentions, be-
fire, the prerequisite of their development, only through cause it has absolutely nothing to do with, wisdom, "the
an act of rebellion against the gods for which, "it is said," greatest of the virtues" according to Protagoras (330a2;
Prometheus was later made to pay (322al-2). Our true 352dl-3). In fact it is this mere habituation to unthink-
condition is one of utter abandonment. There is only the ing obedience, to preferring the city's good to one's own,
naturalorder that (at most) favorsthe continuation of the that Protagoras' instruction must undo-carefully but
human species. Even the brute animals are better off by surely.
nature than we are, for in addition to possessing natural In accord with this, when Socrates asks Protagoras
defenses, they easily come together to form communities whether the individual virtues are parts of a whole, either
of a kind, whereas we fell to slaughtering one another as bits of gold are part of gold or as mouth, nose, eyes,
almost as soon as we drew together. And to restrain our- and ears are parts of the whole that is the face, Protagoras
selves, to make political life possible, it was necessary not replies without hesitation that the latter is the case. He
that Zeus actuallybecome a lawgiverbut that "all"believe does so because "the virtues"-justice, moderation, and
him to have done so. Protagoras'myth thus puts before piety on the one hand, wisdom and courageon the other-
our eyes the kind of conviction that human beings must prove to be distinct from one another in a way that the
have if they will restrain themselves sufficiently to form former image does not permit: as Protagoras admits, in
lasting political communities. But this is not quite cor- an (almost) unguarded moment, "thereare many who are
rect: Protagorasnotes as if in passing that not all are just courageous but unjust, and there arethose who arejust, in
in fact and that it would be madness to admit to one's turn, but not wise" (329e5-6). Courage and injustice can
injustice or to fail to pretendto possess justice (323a5-c2). go together-successful bank robbers, for example-and
He does not say that it would be madness to be unjust, justice can go together with a lack of wisdom or indeed
and he omits mention of the fatal wrath of Zeus extend- foolishness (consider 332a4-6). The crucial question is
ing to such unjust dissemblers. Political societies require, thus alluded to: is the combination "wise,""courageous,"
not the universal agreement as to the goodness of jus- and "unjust"a possible one? More sharply stated, might
tice and the divine sanctions attending its violation, but the wise as such be unjust? Socrates tries, mostly unsuc-
the near-universalagreement;political society will endure cessfully,to force Protagorasto concede that all the virtues
perfectly well if only a few understand the truth about are one inasmuch as justice is, or is most akin to, piety,
justice, especially if these few also happen to be clever
enough to conceal their true thoughts (consider 310e5-7; 7Note the transition at 329e5-330a2 and the absence to that point of
317b5-cl) by "speakingwith god" (compare 317b7), for wisdom and courage from Protagoras' account of "political virtue";
example, or by using such devices as myth and poetry see also Strauss (1968, 57). (The references to "technical wisdom,"
"the wisdom pertaining to one's livelihood [bios]," and "political
(339a3-6). wisdom" in this context [321dl-5] do not constitute exceptions to
The subsequent exchangesbetween Socratesand Pro- this; as for the mention of cowardice at 326cl, consider pp. 619-620
tagoras confirm the suspicion that Protagorasis a teacher above.
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS

wisdom to moderation, and, finally, justice (= piety) to The Unity of Virtue: Pittacus
moderation (= wisdom). Such begrudging agreement as and Simonides
Socrates is able to wrest from Protagorasresults less from
the cogency of his arguments here8 than from their ex-
With considerable reluctance, Protagoras takes up
tremely sensitive subject matter: as Socrates orchestrates Socrates' invitation or challenge, and he does so by initi-
things, Protagoras would have to agree that piety is un-
ating the discussion of poetry that appears to be a rather
just and justice impious (331a6-bl), for example, were
he openly to oppose him. Yet Socrates' failure to secure baffling, and lengthy, digression (338e6-347a5). Yet Pro-
tagoras himself indicates what is at stake: "the question
unambiguous agreement to the proposition that all the will concern the same thing that you and I are now con-
virtues are one means in the context that indeed the wise
versing about, namely virtue." The question of the unity
may not be just, and Protagorasfinally asserts,under pres- of virtue, of virtue in its relation to wisdom, will somehow
sure from Socrates and not of course in his own name,
remain in play.9
that it is a mark of moderation-hence of thinking well,
of deliberatingwell, of faring well, hence of possessing for Protagoras begins by quoting from the poetry of
Simonides, whom he had earlier identified as a crypto-
oneself the good or advantageous things-to commit in-
sophist (316d7), to the effect that it is difficult to become
justice. No wonder, then, that this line of argument imme- a good man. But Protagoras'immediate interest in the ode
diately precedes the first breakdown of the conversation
and strikes Protagoras as "annoying" (333d2; compare provesto be less with the substanceofthe line than with the
author'sblatant self-contradiction: Simonides states in his
also 332a2).
own name that it is difficult to become good and then
Socrates' initial question as to what a student will
learn from Protagoras culminates in, because it is most promptly criticizes Pittacus, "a wise man" (339c4; also
343a2), for maintaining essentially the same view. Thus,
honestly answered by, this exchange. It also prompts Pro- "wheneverhe criticizes one who says the same things as he
tagoras to make a rather angry outburst concerning his himself does, it is clear that he criticizes himself as well"
understanding of the good that is preceded by his first
oath or curse in the dialogue (333dl0-334c7). Protagoras (339d7-8). Protagoras'immediate reason for speaking of
stresses not only that "the good" must be judged in refer- poetry, then, is to air the complaint that one very clever
man is criticizing another for holding exactly the same
ence to the nature or needs of a given thing, but also, and
view he does. Now, Protagorashas already indicated that
for that very reason, that what is good or bad, advanta-
poetry is one means of sophistic concealment (316d6 and
geous or harmful, is extraordinarily complex-manure,
for example, being highly advantageous to mature plants context), and we must put two and two together: does
but harmful to young ones. For his part, Socrates notes Protagoras mean to indicate to Socrates that he knows
that Socrates too holds the same view about justice that
only that lengthy speeches make him forget the question he himself does, that it is improper of Socrates to criti-
at issue (334c8-dl). Shortly thereafter,Socrates stands up
cize him in this way, and that he had better cease his ag-
as though to leave. The threat of his departure prompts
the future tyrant Critias to strike a moderate compro- gressive cross-examination? Socrates, for his part, lets us
know that Protagoras'blow has hit home, for he is "dizzy
mise between Callias' proposal and Alcibiades' counter-
and woozy" as a result of Protagoras'statement (and the
proposal, although it is Socrates' own amendment-that crowd's reaction to it). Socrates lets us know too that in
Protagorasshould pose questions to him, who will answer his opinion a poet who contradicts himself might speak
briefly and then pose questions again to Protagoras-that
carries the day. For all the applause that Protagoras wins correctly,if not nobly (339b7-10, with the reading of mss.
T and W): intentional self-contradiction might well be ex-
from his audience (334c7-8), Socratesproves to be a mas-
cusable. Accordingly, the first two of his attempts to free
ter at getting the whole of the crowd on his side (338e2-3):
Simonides from the charge of self-contradiction are dis-
Socrates too is a clever speaker,one not above using such
mal failures. That is, when Socrates notes that Simonides
devices as flattery, for example (compare 338b4-c6 with
had said it is difficult to becomegood, whereasPittacushad
d6-e2).
said it is difficult to be noble, Protagorassimply dismisses
the resulting view (of Hesiod, but apparently compatible

8Theargumentthat wisdomand moderationmustbe the same


thing,for example,dependson the unprovedassertionthateach 9I follow Coby (1987), Goldberg(1983), and Weingartner(1973)
thinghas one and onlyone contrary(332c8-9and context);that and in maintainingthatthe discussionof poetry"advancesthe main
Socrateselsewhereholdsmoderationto havetwocontraries(fool- theme of the dialogue"(Weingartner1973, 95), in contrastto Paul
ishnessandlicentiousness)
appearsfromGorgias507a5-7;notealso Shorey,for example,who suggeststhat "Itcontainslittle or nothing
the otherwisepeculiarpluralat Protagoras332d4. that bearson the main argument"(Shorey 1933, 128).
618 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

with Simonides') that it is easy to possess virtue: it is the all, that they do not protect forever those whom they do
opinion of all human beings that virtue is the most dif- love, and that the goodness of the good does not owe
ficult thing of all. Abandoning his first response without its origin to the gods or their love. Simonides' poem, as
even attempting to defend it, Socrates next suggests that interpreted by Socrates, insists on the frailty of human
what Simonides meant by "difficult"was in fact "bad": goodness and the necessarily exposed character of our
"so for these reasons... he also criticizes Pittacus for say- happiness: knowledge or virtue is no guarantee against
ing that 'it's difficult to be noble,' just as if he heard him decline or misfortune. There is no "providential"care of
say, 'it's bad to be noble"' (341c3-5). But the difficulty human beings sufficient always to protect us.
remains: if we suppose that Simonides understood "dif- Going together with this harsh view is an explicit
ficult" to mean "bad"in both his own lines and those of statement of Socrates' own thought, the only one in a
Pittacus, the self-contradiction stands! And far from de- passage that otherwise presents itself as his explication of
fending this suggestion, Socratesdismisses it, though not Simonides' intention: "I pretty much think this: none of
before he has made explicit its impious character(341d6- the wise men holds that any human being willingly [vol-
9). It is striking that Socrates does not avail himself of the untarily] errs or willingly [voluntarily] does any shameful
obvious difference between Simonides' saying and that and bad deed. Rather they know well that all who do the
of Pittacus: whereas Simonides speaks of becoming good shameful and bad things do them unwillingly [involun-
(agathos), Pittacus speaks of being noble (esthlos). Since tarily]" (345d9-e3). This view of the wise is but a variation
Protagoras takes each man to be saying the same thing, on Socrates' dictum that virtue is knowledge and vice ig-
does he thus assume that the good and the noble are iden- norance or (as he puts it in the Protagoras)that "thisalone
tical? Socrates leaves this assumption unchallenged here. constitutes bad action-being deprived of knowledge"
The relation of what is noble to what is good proves to (345b5): all shameful and bad action is the product of a
be a "touchy" subject, one to which Socrates will force regrettablebut strictlyspeakinginvoluntary ignorance (of
Protagorasto return. the good), involuntary because no one would willingly or
Socrates' third and final response (342a6-347a5) be- knowingly retain such ignorance; it is indeed contrary to
gins lightheartedly, with a portrait of the exceedingly "human nature"to seek out bad things when it is possible
philosophic Spartans. Yet the official view of virtue now to secure the good (358dl-2). Thus the wise, who under-
on the table, according to which virtue is one because stand these things and their consequences, do not blame
it is knowledge (wisdom), permits or requires Socrates those who do any shameful or bad deed. In the immediate
to describe the Spartans as he does: the Spartans are ex- context, this means that Simonides is not finally among
ceedingly virtuous; therefore the Spartansare exceedingly the class of wise men, for he agrees with their defining
wise. The premise that virtue is knowledge can thus lead to opinion only partially or inconsistently: Simonides' last
ridiculous results, for "virtue"is an ambiguous term, just word here is "I blame" (347a3), and he blames Pittacus
as Protagorashas intimated: such courage as the Spartans for the errorshe makes because those errors concern "the
possess (342b5) is not based on or identical to wisdom greatest things" (347a2; compare 358c3-5 and context).
(compare 329e5-330a2, where Protagorasplaces wisdom (Simonides contends that he will not blame the middle or
and courage together). The long speech that follows will middling view, but Pittacus'is just that: Hesiod maintains
state some of the serious consequences of the view that that virtue is easy,Pittacusthat it is difficult but possible to
"virtue is knowledge," i.e., something of what it would possess, Simonides that it is impossible to do so.) Could it
mean to possess such virtue as is properly identified with be that Simonides' self-contradiction here, on this point,
knowledge. is not a prudent adaptation to political or familial author-
In his laconic way, Simonides contends that while it is ity but is ratherthe product of a certain confusion or that
in truth difficult to become good, it is impossible to be (to his attachment to justice goes well beyond the recognition
remain) good over time; and because it is impossible to of its utility to the city, of its necessity as (mere) conven-
remain such, Pittacus was wrong to assert that becoming tion (346c3-5)? We suggest that, as Protagorasbegan the
noble is merely difficult. All human excellence is doomed section on poetry with an implicit message to Socrates,so
to decline as a result of time, toil, and illness, for exam- Socrates concludes it with one to Protagoras:the sophist
ple (345b2-4), and it is precisely those who have gained who is concerned with wisdom for the sake of honor or
the most knowledge and so act or fare best who have ambition (343b7-c3) and who seeksto gain a victory over a
the most to lose-and will lose it eventually.Perhapsthere wise man (343a2), is not himself wise because he is incon-
is some consolation in the conviction that "best for the sistent on a matter of fundamental importance. It is the
longest time are those whom the gods love" (345c3), but burden of the remaining section of the dialogue to deter-
even this formulation suggests that the gods do not love mine whether Protagorasshares some such inconsistency
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS 619

and, if he does, what its specific characteris. In doing so, those of expert divers, cavalrymen, and light-shieldsmen
moreover, the final part of the dialogue also clarifies what (peltasts)-knowledge has the effect of diminishing the
the health of the soul would have to include according to risk to the courageous themselves or of thus benefiting
Socrates and therewith a part of what the "physician of them, and in this respect Protagoras' understanding of
the soul" would look to in applying his treatments. courage is consistent with his implicit account of justice:
justice is service to the good of others and hence foolish
or "shameful,"courage is the strength of soul needed to
accomplish good things with a minimum of riskto oneself
The Unity of Virtue: Courage and hence is sensible or "noble."This amounts to saying
that Protagorasdoes not here recognize any class of noble
After a brief interlude in which Protagoras appears to be
things that transcend the good or advantageous for one-
shamed into continuing the conversation (348c1 and con- self, that are choiceworthy on account of their intrinsic
text), Socrates turns to examine the one virtue that Pro- worth or beauty regardlessof whether they are advanta-
tagoras himself had introduced (329e5-6) but that they geous to those who possess them or act in accord with
have yet to examine, courage.10Protagorasis now willing them. Far from objecting to Socrates' account of courage
to amend his earlier position by conceding that the four that links its noble characterto advantageous knowledge,
other virtues-wisdom, moderation, justice, and piety-
Protagorashere accepts it.
are "reasonablycomparable to one another" (349d2-4). Socratesattempts to take advantageof Protagoras'in-
On the one hand, this concession gives to Socratesa much sistence that courage is marked by (a certain) knowledge,
clearervictory over Protagorasthan did their original ar- in contrast to his previous claim that courage can be com-
gument. On the other hand, by thus dropping the delicate bined with the greatest ignorance (compare 350a2-3 and
question of the relation of wisdom to justice, Protagoras a6-bl with 349d4-8; 360el-2), for this final step would al-
spares himself the threat of further embarrassment (or low Socratesto conclude, by means fair or foul, that virtue
worse). Yet Protagoras does not concede everything to is knowledge. In response, Protagorasfocuses on a logical
Socrates: courage, he insists, differs very much from the blunder he attributes to Socrates, and because Socrates
other virtues, for in the case of "many among the human does not even attempt to defend himself,11 it could well
beings," at least-surely not Protagoras himself! (com- appearthat this first section (349a8-35 lb2) of the last part
pare 349d6 with 333c1-3 and context)-courage can go of the dialogue constitutes a victory for Protagoras. His
together with the greatest injustice, impiety, licentious- selfish account of nobility is permitted to stand.
ness, and lack of learning (ignorance). Courage, then, is
Protagoras' presentation of courage is not without
not (necessarily) a "moral" virtue. It would seem to be
complication. To repeat, Protagoras begins by insisting
rather a certain steadiness or toughness of soul, whether that great courage can go together with great ignorance,
for the sake of heroic combat or illegal thievery. but he subsequently traces the noble characterof courage,
Given this "amoral"view of courage, Socrates won- understood as a virtue, to precisely its being guided
ders what the relation of courage to mere boldness or con-
by knowledge; and then again, in response to Socrates'
fidence is. In his response, Protagoras now has recourse
suggestion that "wisdom would be courage," Protago-
not to the many but to their opposite: the courageous ras appears to separate courage from boldness entirely
are indeed bold; they are even eager in the face of things and to trace the source of boldness to (among other
"the many" fear to advance toward. The crucial premise
things) knowledge,12whereas courage he traces, not now
in the ensuing exchange is Protagoras' contention, per- to knowledge, but to nature and the proper rearingof souls
haps made with a view to what he must claim publicly as (Weiss 1985, 19). Protagoras,it seems, uses "courage"am-
a teacher of virtue, lest he be held to be "mad" (349e3-
biguously, in both a political and a private sense: courage
8; compare 323b2-7), that the whole of virtue and hence is that habituation, achieved through the training of the
courage in particular is altogether noble: the courageous body, meant to ensure that citizens never act as cowards
are indeed bold, but not all the bold are courageous; only in war and hence in service to the city, as Protagoras
those who are bold in a noble way can be said to be had noted in his description of the political "education"
courageous, and what distinguishes the noble virtue of
courage from its shameful counterpart is knowledge. But
why is knowledge so important? In the examples given- 1Fora thoughtfulattemptto vindicateSocrates'logic,see Weiss
(1985).
l?This complex section has occasioned much commentary: see, e.g., 351a7in thelightof a2;on thekinshipbetweentechne
12Consider
Coby(1987,131-41),Weiss(1985). and episteme, see 357b4.
620 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

(326b6-c3);13 and it is that steadiness or toughness, the pleasures are good or that pleasure itself is the good; he
product of both nature and the proper training of the contends, rather,that there are some bad or harmful plea-
soul (351a5-b2), needed to benefit oneself in certain sit- sures and some good or beneficial pains, a view charac-
uations. It is true that neither conception of courage can teristic of the many according to Socrates:Protagorasand
be said to be knowledge strictly speaking, but the latter the many are united in their rejection of hedonism or in
is at least in service of knowledge: those who know the their sharedconviction that only noble pleasuresare good
truth about justice and the gods, for example, must also (consider also 352b2, where Socrates again attributes to
be courageous enough to act on that knowledge or to live him the view of the many on this score). Still, Protagoras,
their lives in accordwith it. Protagorassurelyunderstands in contrast to the many, need not mean by "noble"here
himself to possess some such courage as this, for he enters anything other than the (truly) advantageous.
large foreign cities to teach the young there, an act at once The disagreement between Socrates and Protagoras
very risky, as he stresses, and very much to his advantage concerning hedonism is momentarily abandoned when
if successful (316c5-d3; Meno 91d2-4). the two join forces to criticize the many for their view
that it is not so much knowledge that rules us and de-
termines our actions as it is the passions-spirited anger,
Hedonism and the Power pleasure, pain, erotic love, fear. Yet as Socrates explicitly
of Knowledge indicates (351e3-352al and following), the purpose of in-
vestigatingthis latter question concerning knowledge is to
For a reason that becomes clear only gradually,Socrates make clear that pleasure is the good, i.e., to overturn the
shifts direction by taking up the question of whether plea- view that Protagoras appears to hold in common with
sure is the good. He prompts Protagorasto agree that to the many. We will be able to determine the connection
live with distress and pain would not be to live well, but between the two arguments, that knowledge determines
Protagorasdoes not agree that to live pleasantly is to live our actions and that pleasure is the good, only by first
well: that is so, he suggests, only if one "should live his setting forth Socrates' arguments meant to establish that
life by taking pleasures in the noble things" (tois kaloisg': it is knowledge alone that determines our actions or that
351c1-2). Protagoras, then, is no hedonist. At any rate one who knows the good will of necessity pursue it.
he is unwilling to admit publicly that he is one (note Socrates first argues to the many that, whatever they
the mention of what is "safer"in his response: 351d3). may claim, they are hedonists in fact because they are
Whether sincere or calculated, his stated position com- unable to state any end of their actions other than the at-
pels him to recognize a distinction between noble and tainment of long-term pleasure or the avoidance of long-
base pleasures, which is to say that he here recognizes term pain (352e5-354e2). Indeed, Socratesasksrepeatedly
nobility as a standard higher than pleasure. Now, if Pro- whether the many could state any other end that gov-
tagoras is to be consistent with his just-stated view of the erns them (353c9-353el; 354a3-c3; 354c3-e2; 355al-5),
nobility of courage, he should mean by "noble things" no on each occasion insisting that they could not. Second,
more than the good or advantageous:just as the nobility according to Socrates, to be "overcome by oneself'-to
of courage stems from its knowledgeable use in order to give in to temptation, as we might say-is nothing other
benefit oneself under certain circumstances, so the nobil- than to make a mistake in one's calculations concern-
ity of the noble pleasures should stem from their being ing pleasure and pain; Socrates insists, in other words,
conducive to one's own good. Evidently assuming such that this failing is a purely intellectual one (354e3-356c3).
consistency on the part of Protagoras, Socrates imme- Finally, Socrates proposes, as a remedy sufficient to cor-
diately equates the noble things with the good and the rect this failing, a scientific "artof measuring"that would
shameful things with the bad, for he does not ask whether precisely determine the means to maximize pleasure and
Protagoras calls some pleasant things ignoble and some minimize pain throughout life and so "save"or "preserve"
painful things noble, as one might expect given Protago- it (356c4-357e8).14
ras' statement, but ratherwhether he calls "some pleasant
O40nthe "hedonistic calculus," see Dyson (1976), Richardson
things bad and some distressing things good" (351c2-3,
(1990), Weiss(1989). Nussbaum(1986), while acknowledgingthat
emphasis added). Protagorasrefuses to state flatly that all Socratescannothold pleasureto be the properend of life and hence
of the scientificartof measuringhe adumbrates,nonethelessmain-
13This meaning of courage may shed light on why Protagoras iden- tains that Socratesis serious in holding out the possibilityof a life
tifies justice, moderation, and piety as being, in sum, "the virtue lived altogetherscientifically,which she takesto mean beyond the
of a man [aner]" (325al-2): the aner is distinguishedby his spir- reachof all chance or misfortune. In fact such a doctrine, and the
ited devotion to the common good and its supports.For a playful hope informingit, proceedsfrom what one might callthe unphilo-
exampleof courageemployedin the name of justice,see 310d3-4. sophic view par excellence.
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS 621

Two difficulties with Socrates' argument deserve Socratesalso sketchesin the same context a world without
mention. First, Socrates' purely intellectual account of "providence":the good necessarilydecline at the hands of
weakness does not seem to fit the facts in every respect. Is illness, toil, and time, and neither gods nor knowledge
it not the case that some human beings are by nature un- protects them from these in the end. Such convictions
able to withstand the pull of certain immediate pleasures, of the wise, whatever their ultimate basis, would require
or the repulsiveforce of certain pains, whatevertheir intel- of those who come to hold them considerable fortitude
lect may tell them? Do not some know that it is better (or or toughness, a kind of courage (among of course other
more productive of pleasure in the long run) to visit the qualities). For if knowledge is indeed the good we seek, as
doctor regularlythan to fail to do so, for example, but are the wise contend, there can be no guaranteethat the world
nonetheless unable to bring themselves to do it? Socrates revealedby our seeking will support our every hope con-
here dismisses out of hand the possibility of such under- cerning it. If knowledge about the most important things
lying weakness. Second, is it true that the many could not comes at the price of our initial and perhapsdearestexpec-
state an end of their actions, or at least of some of them, tations of the world, it would to that extent be profoundly
other than pleasure?Forthe experience of being overcome unpleasant or painful and hence would require some ca-
("giving in to temptation") amounts to pursuing, for the pacity in addition to a great intellect not only to grasp it
sake of the advantage or pleasure involved, an action that but to live in accord with it. Those who cannot endure
appearsboth advantageous or pleasant and shameful, just such pain would then cling with greatertenacity to opin-
as resisting temptation is to refuse to pursue such an ac- ions that act as a salve for it or prophylactic against it,
tion in order to be noble or to avoid shame. It is then opinions of the kind that Socrates obscures or abstracts
the nobility of an action that is (also) of concern to us, from in his presentation of the many. And so-to return
that is the end of (some of) our actions-as both Pro- now to the question of hedonism in its relation to the
tagoras and Socrates have alreadyindicated (351c1-3). In power of knowledge-the toughness indicated would be
persistently arguing that the many make mistakes merely unnecessary only if pleasure is the good and knowledge
in calculating their own long-term pleasure, rather than or wisdom is a pleasure untainted by pain: no particular
in weighing the pleasant or advantageous against what is toughness would be required to seek out, attain, and act
noble, Socrates seems intent on stripping their view of its in accord with knowledge so understood because it would
concern for nobility, of its "moral"character.15 be by definition pleasing to us.
We may now make a tentative suggestion as to a possi- The purpose of these complex passagesis not to estab-
ble connection between hedonism, which Protagoras re- lish the truth of hedonism, a doctrine Socrates elsewhere
jects, and the view that those who know the good neces- criticizes. Indeed, Socrates proves at most that the opin-
sarily seek it out, which he accepts. It is helpful to begin ions of the many are confused: on the one hand they deny
by returning to the view, stated by Socrates in his explica- that pleasureis the good (35 1c3), deferringinstead to what
tion of the thought of Simonides in particular and "all" is noble; on the other hand they assert that pleasure is the
the wise in general, according to which being deprived of good.16 The purpose of these passages is rather to make
knowledge alone constitutes bad action or faring badly clear that, his manifest contempt for them notwithstand-
and hence (one may infer) acquiring or retaining knowl- ing (317a4-5; 352e3-4; 353a7-8), Protagorasis as confused
edge alone constitutes good action or faring well (345b5 as the many; we understand now why Socrates had indi-
and context). The possession of knowledge, i.e., wisdom, cated in this context that he was about to reveal a further
is thus the proper end of human life, and this end makes aspect of Protagoras'thought (352a8-bl). For the reason
possible a clear calculus, an art of measuring, by which to indicated, Protagoras should maintain that the good is
live: all that contributes to wisdom is virtue, all that de- pleasure, if he wishes to maintain also that knowledge
tracts from it vice. But as we have alreadynoted, the wise alone is sufficient to guide us aright. That he resists he-
also refuse to blame anyone for any shameful or bad deed; donism may mean in the context that he is insufficiently
evidently they cannot discern in the world the necessary awareof the cost we may incur in pursuing the good that
supports of what might be called moral desert. Moreover, is wisdom or understanding, for he in effect assumes that
the good has the characterof the pleasant, which requires
'5CompareSocrates'initial statement of the many'sview with his
second:in the former,the difficultyis thatthey givein to thingsthey O60nemaywonderwhetherhe does even that much:although
know to be "base"or "low"or even "wicked"(ponera),whereasin Socratesbeginsfromthe premisethatall pleasuresaregood-a
the latterit is thatone givesin to thingshe knowsto be "bad"(kakos), premisecompatiblewith the view that the good includesother
ultimatelyin the sense of unpleasantfor oneself (compare353c6- thingsin additionto pleasure-headoptsthepremise,in hiscross-
8 with 355a5-8): the first statementdescribesmore accuratelythe examination of themany,thatthegoodis pleasure(andonlyplea-
phenomenon at issue. sure):compare351c4-d2 and 358a5-6 with 355al-5.
622 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

no special fortitude to pursue, even as he refuses to pro- what is good and hence pleasant. Courage is now noth-
fess to being a hedonist. Put another way, Protagorasun- ing other than knowledge of what is truly frightening or
derestimates the importance of, and himself may lack, terrible, cowardice the ignorance of it, and this means
the steadiness or toughness needed in every case to fol- either that the courageous will enter battle because they
low the dictates of knowledge. And because he does not know there to be nothing truly frightening in doing so-
abandon his lofty view of knowledge (352c8-d3), he is and hence there to be nothing truly heroic in so acting,
compelled in the sequel to accept or at least relent to a as with the highly skilled divers, cavalrymen, and light-
version of hedonism. This proves to be an element of his shieldsmen earlier;or that the courageous will know that
undoing. it is indeed frightening to enter battle and so will do the
only sensible thing in the face of such harmful terrors:
flee them. It is these consequences of the proposition that
virtue is knowledge, or more precisely of the reduction
The Refutation of Protagoras: of courage to knowledge, that Protagoras cannot finally
Courage as Knowledge stomach, for he too is moved by the willingness of the
courageous to enter battle, come what may for themselves
Socratespreparesto examine Protagorasby first opening (359el-4).
up the conversation to include the others present (358al- What Protagoras seeks to exploit in the case of jus-
359al; compare 314b7-8), and he establishes the follow- tice, then, he admires in the case of courage, namely the
ing theses, with the aid of all or most of those present willingness to sacrifice oneself for the sake of a good other
(compare sunedokei at 358b6 with the more inclusive and greater than one's own. Protagorastoo, it turns out,
agreements at 358b2-3, c6, d4, and 359al; Socratesmakes admires a nobility not reducible to one's own good, to
explicit his own agreement only at 358d4): all actions con- say nothing of one's own pleasure. This admiration is
ducive to living pleasantlyand free of pain arenoble, and a in harmony with the sensitivity to shame he has exhib-
noble deed is as such both good and advantageous.More- ited in the dialogue, especially such sensitivity as prompts
over, only ignorance, or having a false opinion about the him to continue a conversation the progress of which
most important things, is responsible for our errors in he surely, and rightly, suspects will harm him (348cl;
choosing better from worse, since no one willingly ad- consider also 333cl). And earlier in the conversation
vances toward or does things he supposes to be bad. No (332c3-6), Socrates had unobtrusively brought out Pro-
one, that is, who either knows or supposes that other tagoras' conviction, as further evidence of a general con-
things are better than those that he does, then does the clusion that had already been established clearly enough
inferior things. And since being afraid of something is to (332c1-3), that there is only one contrary of the noble
expect something bad or harmful from it, no one willingly (namely the shameful) and only one of the good (namely
advances toward that which he is afraid of, if it is possible the bad). But to agree to this is to hold that the noble
not to do so. and the good are distinct from one another, not that the
Socrates now trains his sights on Protagoras (359a2 noble is reducible to the good as Protagoras had main-
and following). Since it has just been shown to be im- tained in his first discussion of courage. And although the
possible, given human nature, for human beings to ad- separation of the noble from the good may have a nasty
vance willingly toward things they are frightened of, the implication, to the effect that nobility is bad ("it is bad to
courageous as much as the cowards must advance toward be noble"), it may also mean that nobility is higher than
things they are confident (bold) about, that is, toward any merely personal good and hence amounts to one vital
things from which they expect to gain some benefit: the aspect of what might be called the moral view: morality
courageous man enters battle because he believes doing seems to demand that we sometimes choose to do what
so to be noble, hence good-hence pleasant (360al-3)! is noble whether or not we benefit ourselves thereby. To
In this way Socrates does everything in his power to link summarize, Protagorashad recourse in his initial discus-
courage with knowledge or wisdom-the knowledge of sion of courage to a nobility reducible to the good for
what is advantageousfor oneself-and so to strip courage oneself, and he subsequently reaffirms his view that "all
of that which most elicits our admiration of it, its noble noble actions" are as such "good" (359e5-8); but Pro-
(self-sacrificing) character. That the good is here iden- tagoras has shown himself to be unable to stick to this
tified with the pleasant only furthers this goal, for the view of nobility because he has shown himself to be-
pleasure-seeking courageous differ from the pleasure- lieve that some things are noble and hence choicewor-
seeking cowards merely in their divergent opinions as to thy despite the fact that-or precisely if-they are bad or
PLATO'SPROTAGORAS 623

disadvantageous for oneself. Protagoras has thus shown of the teachability of virtue pertains only to "the polit-
himself to be confused. ical art" and to political virtue strictly construed, not
to virtue understood as knowledge (of the good). The
chief difference between the two comes to sight when one
considers Socrates' failed attempt to persuade Protago-
Conclusion ras of the unity of the virtues as aspects of knowledge, a
proposition to which Protagorasrelents ratherthan agrees
Toward the end of the Protagoras,Socrates notes that a (360d8-e5). The subordination of the virtues, or most of
strange inversion has taken place. For whereas Socrates them,17 to knowledge seems to bring with it the conse-
had begun his examination of Protagoras by stating that quence to which Protagoras objects so strongly (see also
he himself did not hold virtue to be teachable, he notes Meno 87e5-89a5 for a comparable reaction). In order to
now that he has been arguing that virtue is knowledge and agree to it, then, one would have to be free of the con-
therefore teachable; and just as Protagoras had begun by fusion characteristicof even Protagoras,who (to repeat)
contending that virtue is indeed teachable, so now at the understands himself to seek only his own advantage but
end of the conversation he resists Socrates'attempt to link in fact also admires those who sacrifice theirs. Socrates
courage with knowledge and hence to imply, at least, its is surely free of this confusion. But because a full ac-
teachable character(361a3-d6). To account for this pecu- count of the consequences of this freedom goes beyond
liarity, one must track the different meanings of "virtue" the present reading of the Protagoras,it must suffice to
in the dialogue: "virtue" first comes to sight as justice, note that, in reporting his conversation with Protagoras,
piety, and moderation-all virtues conducive to politi- Socrates permits us to put ourselves to the same tests to
cal life and instilled in us by nursemaid, mother, father, which he subjects Protagoras and so to begin to under-
teachers, and, as their ultimate guide, the laws themselves. stand our own concern for virtue-a service that, be-
What Protagoras offers his students instead is indicated ing carried out without expectation of payment, makes
by his unexpected expansion of virtue to include courage clear both Socrates' relative indifference to lucre and the
and wisdom, wisdom being the greatest of the virtues. generosity that is compatible with the pursuit of true
According to Protagoras, moral or political virtue can be virtue.
beaten into one but it cannot be taught strictly speak-
ing, whereas courage and wisdom can be taught because
they are rational or consist in knowledge, in the knowl-
References
edge of the priority of the good for oneself (or the foolish
characterof justice) together with the necessary strength Adam, J., and A. M. Adam. 1921. PlatonisProtagoras.Cam-
bridge:CambridgeUniversityPress.
of soul both to see through the conventional virtues and
Burnet,John. 1903. OperaOmnia PlatonisVol.III. Oxford:
to act accordingly. Protagoras thus admires those who, OxfordUniversityPress.
through the right combination of toughness and under- Coby,Patrick.1987. Socratesand the SophisticEnlightenment:
standing, seek and attain their own good in the face of A Commentary on Plato'sProtagoras.Londonand Toronto:
what family, friends, city, and gods say. But, as we have BucknellUniversityPress.
seen, he himself lacks such a combination of qualities; Croiset,Alfred,ed. 1923.PlatonOeuvrescompletestomeIII 1re
his knowledge of what is good does not consistently de- partie:Protagoras.Paris:LesBellesLettres.
termine his actions because he lacks the "courage of his Diels, Hermann,and WaltherKranz.1952.Die Fragmenteder
Vorsokratier.6th ed. Berlin:Weidmann.
convictions." In particular, he cannot consistently stick
Dyson,M. 1976."Knowledge andHedonismin Plato'sProtago-
to the reduction of the noble to the good that the admi- ras."Journalof HellenicStudies96:32-45.
ration indicated implies; or, he admires also those who
Goldberg,Larry.1983. A Commentaryon Plato'sProtagoras.
are willing to sacrifice themselves, if not in the name of New York:PeterLang.
justice then in the name of courage. And being confused Kerferd,G. B. 1981. The SophisticMovement.Cambridge:
on this point, he could hardly bring his students to clarity CambridgeUniversityPress.
concerning it. Macdowell,Douglas, ed. 1962. Andocides:On the Mysteries.
One might say that the Protagorasboth diminishes Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.
the differences between philosopher and sophist (314d3)
and sharpens those that remain: like Protagoras,Socrates
holds the initial education we receive not to be an ed- '7Consider361bl-3,notingespeciallypantaat 361bl andthe in-
ucation properly speaking (p. 615 above) for his denial completelistthatfollows.
624 ROBERTC. BARTLETT

Manuwald, Bernd. 1999. Protagoras.Gottingen: Vandenhoeck Shorey, Paul. 1933. What Plato Said. Chicago: University of
& Ruprecht. Chicago Press.
Morrison, J.S. 1941. "ThePlace of Protagorasin Athenian Public Strauss,Leo. 1968. "The Liberalismof ClassicalPolitical Philos-
Life (460-415 B.C.)." ClassicalQuarterly35(January-April): ophy." In LiberalismAncient and Modern. New York:Basic
1-16. Books, pp. 26-64.
Nietzsche, Friedrich. 1968. The Will to Power. Trans. Walter Strauss, Leo. 1970. Xenophon's Socratic Discourse. Ithaca:
Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale. New York:Vintage. Cornell University Press.
Nussbaum, Martha. 1986. "The Protagoras: A Science Verdenius, W. J. 1974. "Bemerkungen zur Einleitung des
of Practical Reasoning." In The Fragility of Good- Protagoras."In Studia Platonica, ed. K. Doring and W.
ness. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, pp. 89- Kullmann. Amsterdam: Gruener, pp. 41-8.
121.
Weingartner,Rudolph. 1973. The Unity of the PlatonicDialogue:
Richardson, H. S. 1990. "Measurement, Pleasure, and Practi- The Cratylus, the Protagoras, the Parmenides. Indianapolis:
cal Science in Plato's Protagoras."Journal of the History of Bobbs-Merrill.
Philosophy28(1):7-32. Weiss, Roslyn. 1985. "Courage,Confidence, and Wisdom in the
Romilly, Jacqueline de. 1988. Les Grandes Sophistes dans Protagoras."Ancient Philosophy5(1):11-24.
l'Athenesde Pericles.Paris:tditions de Fallois. Weiss, Roslyn. 1989. "The Hedonic Calculus in the Protagoras
Sauppe, Hermann. 1892. Protagoras.Trans. James A. Towle. and the Phaedo."Journal of the History of Philosophy27(4):
Boston: Ginn & Co. 511-29.

You might also like