You are on page 1of 2

Philosophy of space

Leibniz and Newton

Gottfried Leibniz
In the seventeenth century, the philosophy of space and time emerged as a central
issue in epistemology and metaphysics. At its heart, Gottfried Leibniz, the German
philosopher-mathematician, and Isaac Newton, the English physicist-mathematician,
set out two opposing theories of what space is. Rather than being an entity that
independently exists over and above other matter, Leibniz held that space is no
more than the collection of spatial relations between objects in the world: "space
is that which results from places taken together".[5] Unoccupied regions are those
that could have objects in them, and thus spatial relations with other places. For
Leibniz, then, space was an idealised abstraction from the relations between
individual entities or their possible locations and therefore could not be
continuous but must be discrete.[6] Space could be thought of in a similar way to
the relations between family members. Although people in the family are related to
one another, the relations do not exist independently of the people.[7] Although
there was a prevailing Kantian consensus at the time, once non-Euclidean geometries
had been formalised, some began to wonder whether or not physical space is curved.
Carl Friedrich Gauss, a German mathematician, was the first to consider an
empirical investigation of the geometrical structure of space. He thought of making
a test of the sum of the angles of an enormous stellar triangle, and there are
reports that he actually carried out a test, on a small scale, by triangulating
mountain tops in Germany.[14]

Henri Poincar�, a French mathematician and physicist of the late 19th century,
introduced an important insight in which he attempted to demonstrate the futility
of any attempt to discover which geometry applies to space by experiment.[15] He
considered the predicament that would face scientists if they were confined to the
surface of an imaginary large sphere with particular properties, known as a sphere-
world. In this world, the temperature is taken to vary in such a way that all
objects expand and contract in similar proportions in different places on the
sphere. With a suitable falloff in temperature, if the scientists try to use
measuring rods to determine the sum of the angles in a triangle, they can be
deceived into thinking that they inhabit a plane, rather than a spherical surface.
[16] In fact, the scientists cannot in principle determine whether they inhabit a
plane or sphere and, Poincar� argued, the same is true for the debate over whether
real space is Euclidean or not. For him, which geometry was used to describe space
was a matter of convention.[17] Since Euclidean geometry is simpler than non-
Euclidean geometry, he assumed the former would always be used to describe the
'true' geometry of the world.[18]Leibniz argued that space could not exist
independently of objects in the world because that implies a difference between two
universes exactly alike except for the location of the material world in each
universe. But since there would be no observational way of telling these universes
apart then, according to the identity of indiscernibles, there would be no real
difference between them. According to the principle of sufficient reason, any
theory of space that implied that there could be these two possible universes must
therefore be wrong.[8]

Isaac Newton
Newton took space to be more than relations between material objects and based his
position on observation and experimentation. For a relationist there can be no real
difference between inertial motion, in which the object travels with constant
velocity, and non-inertial motion, in which the velocity changes with time, since
all spatial measurements are relative to other objects and their motions. But
Newton argued that since non-inertial motion generates forces, it must be absolute.
[9] He used the example of water in a spinning bucket to demonstrate his argument.
Water in a bucket is hung from a rope and set to spin, starts with a flat surface.
After a while, as the bucket continues to spin, the surface of the water becomes
concave. If the bucket's spinning is stopped then the surface of the water remains
concave as it continues to spin. The concave surface is therefore apparently not
the result of relative motion between the bucket and the water.[10] Instead, Newton
argued, it must be a result of non-inertial motion relative to space itself. For
several centuries the bucket argument was considered decisive in showing that space
must exist independently of matter.

Kant

Immanuel Kant
In the eighteenth century the German philosopher Immanuel Kant developed a theory
of knowledge in which knowledge about space can be both a priori and synthetic.[11]
According to Kant, knowledge about space is synthetic, in that statements about
space are not simply true by virtue of the meaning of the words in the statement.
In his work, Kant rejected the view that space must be either a substance or
relation. Instead he came to the conclusion that space and time are not discovered
by humans to be objective features of the world, but imposed by us as part of a
framework for organizing experience.[12]

You might also like