You are on page 1of 10

Topoi

DOI 10.1007/s11245-016-9422-z

Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication,


Affirmation, and Denial
Christian Barth1

 Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2016

Abstract The aim of the paper is to illuminate some core Judgement is a neglected topic in the Leibniz scholarship.
aspects of Leibniz’s conception of judgement and its place At least, this is true with respect to the metaphysics and
in his conception of the mind. In particular, the paper epistemology of judgement.1 The monographs on Leibniz’s
argues for three claims: First, the act of judgement is at the conception of the mind and his general epistemology touch
centre of Leibniz’s conception of the mind in that minds the topic only peripherally.2 Scholars working on Leibniz’s
strive at actualising innate knowledge concerning deriva- logic are mostly interested in his conceptions of predication
tive truths, where the actualising involves an act of and of proposition, but not in his metaphysics and episte-
judgement. Second, Leibniz does not hold a judgement mology of judgements.3 The concept of judgement is also
account of predication, but a two-component account that central to Leibniz’s legal writings. But scholars investi-
distinguishes between predication and alethic evaluation. gating Leibniz’s legal works focus on his application of
Third, Leibniz understands the act of affirmative judgement logic to law and his conception of natural law, but not on
in terms of establishing active dispositions, i.e. strivings, to Leibniz’s general conception of judgement.4
make reasons available for future reasoning that aims at The aim of the paper is to illuminate some core aspects
answering whether-questions (whether a proposition p is of Leibniz’s conception of judgement and its place in his
true or not). Correspondingly, he understands the act of conception of the mind. In particular, I will argue for three
negative judgement in terms of establishing dispositions to claims:
ban propositions from future reasoning that aims at
1. The act of judgement is at the centre of Leibniz’s
answering whether-questions. In the final analysis, the acts
conception of the mind in that minds strive at
of affirmative as well as of negative judgement turn out to
actualising innate knowledge concerning derivative
be acts of changing memory dispositions.
truths, where the actualising involves an act of
judgement (Sect. 1).
Keywords Leibniz  Mind  Judgement  Predication 
2. Leibniz does not hold a judgement account of pred-
Innatism
ication, but a two-component account that distin-
guishes between predication and alethic evaluation
(Sect. 2.1).
3. Leibniz understands the act of affirmative judgement
in terms of establishing active dispositions, i.e. striv-
ings, to make reasons available for future reasoning
that aims at answering whether-questions (whether a
1
An exception is Losonsky (2001, ch. 7).
& Christian Barth 2
See Kulstad (1991) and McRae (1976).
christian.barth@philosophie.hu-berlin.de 3
See Burkhardt (1980), Couturat (1901), Kauppi (1960), Lenzen
1
Institute of Philosophy, Humboldt University Berlin, Unter (1990, 2004), and Parkinson (1965, esp. ch. 1).
4
den Linden 6, 10099 Berlin, Germany See Armgardt (2001) and Berkowitz (2005).

123
C. Barth

proposition p is true or not). Correspondingly, he souls.8 From the Platonist9 tradition he takes up the idea that
understands the act of negative judgement in terms of souls are thoroughly self-moving, i.e. spontaneous, entities.
establishing dispositions to ban propositions from This goes hand in hand with the idea that—if we neglect the
future reasoning that aims at answering whether- dependence on divine conservation and concurrence—all
questions. In the final analysis, the acts of affirmative souls are causally autonomous. This conception of souls as
as well as of negative judgement turn out to be acts of spontaneous and causally autonomous entities implies that—
changing memory dispositions (Sect. 2.2).5 speaking with metaphysical rigor—all inner acts and their
contents come from the soul’s own ground.10
Simple souls and animal souls are only capable of non-
conceptual representations,11 whereas rational souls do not
1 The Place of Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception
only possess non-conceptual, but also conceptual repre-
of the Mind
sentations. I will call the non-conceptual representations
‘perceptions’ and the conceptual ones ‘thoughts’.12
1.1 Aristotelian and Platonist Elements in Leibniz’s
Conception of the Mind
8
In his monadological metaphysics he calls them ‘simple monads’,
According to Leibniz, the history of philosophy is a trea- ‘animal monads’, and ‘rational monads’ (see Leibniz’s Principles of
Nature and Grace (henceforth referred to by ‘PNG’), sections 4–5
sure chest. He believes that philosophical traditions contain and his Monadology (henceforth referred to by ‘M’), sections 18–30).
important insights that philosophers are expected to iden- It needs to be pointed out, however, that Leibniz’s understanding of
tify and to integrate into one view—a view that should also souls in general and of the three types of souls in particular very much
cohere with theological doctrines and reflect the empirical differs from the Aristotelian scheme. For one, Leibniz understands all
souls to be engaged in cognitive activity. More precisely, all souls—
and theoretical insights of the new physics. Thus, proper including simple monads—exhibit states (so-called ‘perceptions’) that
philosophy is necessarily historical and integrative. Far represent outer things (in fact, they represent their own bodies
from being a matter of mere cherry picking, the task of perfectly and by virtue of representing their own bodies they represent
integration is a constructive task in that it requires the the whole universe); and the inner activities of all souls are propelled
by inner strivings (so-called ‘appetites’) that are sensitive to the
development of new ideas and innovative lines of thought contents of these representational states (the appetites strive at
in order to overcome obstacles of integration. In addition, increasing the represented goods and at diminishing the represented
philosophy proper also includes the tasks of broadening the evils). Furthermore, Leibniz rejects Aristotelian hylomorphism and
view that results from integration and of applying it to new accounts for the unity of soul and body in terms of the infamous
doctrine of pre-established harmony.
problems.6 9
Following Stephen Menn, I distinguish between Platonic and
Leibniz’s account of souls in general and of the rational Platonist views. The former can be found in Plato’s writings, the latter
soul or mind7 in particular takes up aspects from the Aris- in Platonist writers, i.e. writers who do philosophy on the basis of
totelian as well as from the Platonist tradition. In a broadly mainly Platonic doctrines (see Menn 1998, xii).
10
Aristotelian fashion, Leibniz distinguishes between three At an early stage of Book I of the New Essays on Human
types of souls: simple souls, animal souls, and rational Understanding, Leibniz points out that ‘all the thoughts and actions of
our soul come from its own depths and could not be given to it by the
senses’. Having put his metaphysical cards on the table, Leibniz
hastens to add that he will engage with Lockean views from the
perspective of ‘accepted ways of speaking’ according to which ‘the
outer senses can be said to be, in a certain sense, partial causes of our
thoughts’; Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe (henceforth referred to by
‘A’) 6.6.74; see also A 6.6.6 and A 6.6.392. Leibniz applies here his
methodological doctrine according to which, for reasons of persua-
siveness, one should discuss positions from the opponent’s
standpoint.
11
Leibniz believes that souls essentially are engaged in representa-
tional activity. The inner states of all souls—not only of animal and
5
rational souls—are representational states.
Note that this paper is concerned with Leibniz’s general conception 12
Leibniz’s usage of the Latin ‘perceptio’ and the French ‘percep-
of judgement. Hence, I will abstract from the differences Leibniz
tion’ on the one hand and of ‘cogitatio’ and ‘pensée’ on the other is an
might recognise between theoretical, practical, aesthetic etc. judge-
intricate matter. He uses the former terms in three different ways: In a
ments and merely be concerned with features that are, for Leibniz,
generic sense, they denote all inner representational states of all souls
characteristic of the activity of judging in general.
6
(see, for instance, PNG 2 and M 17). But apart from their generic
This view of Leibniz’s method comes close to the ‘conciliatory sense, Leibniz also uses them in two slightly different contrastive
eclecticism’ Christia Mercer attributes to the early Leibniz (see ways. In the first contrastive use, he contrasts perceptions with
Mercer 2001, 49–59). apperceptions (see A 6.6.134, PNG 4, and M 14). In the second
7
I use the terms ‘rational soul’ and ‘mind’ interchangeably in this contrastive sense, perceptions are contrasted with thoughts (see
paper. Leibniz’s Discourse of Metaphysics (henceforth referred to by ‘DM’),

123
Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication, Affirmation, and Denial

Thoughts convey propositional contents and are made omniscient. But whereas the perceptual omniscience regards
possible by ideas. Referring again to the Platonist tradition, the representation of what was, is, and will be actual, the
Leibniz understands ideas as innate.13 He conceives them conceptual omniscience also concerns what is possible and
as active dispositions, i.e. as strivings,14 that aim at pro- necessary. However, our conceptual omniscience is largely
ducing true acts of thought.15 Concepts are parts of acts of merely virtual omniscience. Since most active dispositions
thinking that take subject or predicate position in them.16 remain impeded and never get fully actualized, only few innate
truths ever come to our awareness.20
1.2 Rational Souls: Striving at Actual Knowledge In the New Essays on Human Understanding and related
writings, Leibniz distinguishes between different conceptions
In line with the Aristotelian tradition, Leibniz sees rational of innateness with respect to truths. According to what he
souls in top position of a tripartite hierarchy of souls. Fur- regards as a customary understanding, truths are innate if and
thermore, in line with both the Aristotelian and the Platonist only if we affirm them immediately when they come to our
tradition he considers rational souls to be marked out by pos- awareness.21 Leibniz, however, prefers a different notion of
session of an intellect. But Leibniz understands the intellect in a innateness. First, he restricts the term to truths that we can
Platonist fashion as containing innate ideas and thoughts in come to actually22 know to be true a priori, i.e. independently
virtue of which rational souls come much closer to divine of the senses.23 These truths consist in all and only necessary
omniscience than non-rational souls. According to the Dis- truths.24 Accordingly, in contrast to the earlier Discourse on
course on Metaphysics, created souls are omniscient in the Metaphysics, Leibniz here excludes contingent truths from the
sense that they non-conceptually represent the created universe innate truths. The reason for this is that in the New Essays,
completely with respect to all past, present, and future events.17 Leibniz is willing to discuss Locke’s empiricism on the basis of
We might call this the ‘perceptual omniscience’ of created the vulgar assumption that not all thoughts stem from our own
substances. But due to possession of an intellect, rational soul, but are caused by external impact on the senses. Second,
substances also conceptually represent divine thoughts, i.e. the he distinguishes between a narrow and a wide understanding of
true propositions of divine thinking. In fact, rational substances this notion of innateness. The difference between the narrow
conceptually represent all divine truths. They do so in virtue of and the wide understanding is related to Leibniz’s distinction
the fact that all ideas, i.e. the ideas of all possible entities, are between primitive and derivative truths. Leibniz’s draws this
innate to them.18 Since Leibniz understands the idea of an distinction as follows: Primitive necessary truths comprise the
entity X as the set of active dispositions to think all truths principle of identity and its instances.25 Primitive contingent
about X,19 we are not only perceptually, but also conceptually
Footnote 19 continued
Footnote 12 continued case of substances). Hence, ideas as strivings must be understood as
section 14). Similarly, Leibniz uses ‘cogitatio’ and ‘pensée’ in a including active dispositions to actualise all true thoughts about the
broad and in a narrow sense. In the broad sense, the terms denote all thing in question.
inner representational states of all souls, i.e. they are used equiva- 20
See Die philosophischen Schriften von Leibniz (henceforth referred
lently to ‘perceptio’ and ‘perception’ in the generic sense (A 6.6.161
to by ‘GP’) IV 469–470 and IV 395. The notion of impediment is
and A 6.6171). In the narrow sense, the terms denote only proposi-
central to Leibniz’s metaphysics of substances as forces. I will not go
tional acts in rational souls (see A 6.6.173, A 6.6.210, and A 6.1.286
into Leibniz’s conception of impediment in this paper, but restrict my
revision note 16). In this paper, I use ‘perception’ in the second
focus on logical and epistemological questions.
contrastive sense and ‘thought’ in Leibniz’s narrow sense. 21
13 See A 6.6.12 and 6.6.84.
Leibniz is famous for his innatism of ideas and truths. Primarily, 22
ideas are innate to us. But since truths are merely relations of Actual knowledge contrasts with virtual knowledge. A subject
containment between ideas, with innate ideas come innate truths. possesses the latter just in virtue of the possession of innate ideas;
14 possession of the former requires actualisation of the virtual
When I talk of dispositions in the following, I will mean active
knowledge (see A 6.6.52, A 6.6.77, and A 6.6.86).
dispositions in the Leibnizean sense of strivings, not in the 23
contemporary sense of passive dispositions that require a stimulus See GP III 291, A 6.6.12, A 6.6.76, A 6.6.84, and A 6.6.392.
24
in order to get actualised. See A 6.6.77.
15 25
See A 6.6.52 (innate ideas are dispositions) in combination with A The principle of identity comes in two different forms: affirmative
6.6.110 (there are no passive dispositions). From A 6.4.1370 we learn A = A, and negative A = non-A and A = B, where B is an object of
that ideas are faculties to think and since ideas are given to us by God an idea that is different from the idea of A (A 6.4.1644 and A
(see DM 28), they must be faculties to think truths rather than 6.6.361–362). As Leibniz explains, in order to become aware of
falsehoods. False thoughts result from defective actualisations of primitive necessary truths in contexts of knowledge-seeking activity
ideas. they only need to be ‘distinguished’ rather than ‘formed by the intellect
16
See DM 27. and by the reason’ (A 6.6.12). This refers to Leibniz’s view that (true or
17 supposed) instances of the principle of identity are involved in all our
See DM 9.
18
thinking in that thoughts express containment relations between ideas
See DM 26, DM 28, and A 6.6.300. (see DM 8). Becoming aware of them only requires distinguishing
19
Ideas represent natures (see DM 26) and the nature of a thing them from the other elements involved (see A 6.6.84 for distinguishing
contains all predicates truly predicable of the thing (see DM 8 for the ‘general principles [that] enter into our thoughts’).

123
C. Barth

truths are contents of acts of inner sense, i.e. acts of registering ideas must contain active dispositions to such infallible
the occurrence of thoughts in us.26 They consist in propositions intuitive acts. In the case of innate derivative truths,
of the form ‘I think’ and ‘Various things are thought by me’.27 coming to know them to be true requires reasoning. For
Both types of primitive truths share the feature that minds do instance, innate derivative necessary truths are capable of
not recognise their truth in light of further reasons.28 They do demonstration, i.e. we can come to know them to be true
not recognise their truth through reasoning, but immediately by through a finite sequence of deductive steps. This requires
infallible acts of intuition.29 Derivative necessary and contin- not only proper attention, but also proper order of reason-
gent truths, in contrast, are propositions whose truth is recog- ing. But if we reason properly, we will finally come to
nised through further reasons. With the exception of those affirm the truths justifiably and, thus, come to know them
derivative truths that we affirm by innate natural instinct,30 the to be true. Thus, innate ideas are active dispositions not
recognition of their truth results from reasoning.31 Now, merely to bring truths to awareness, but to cognitive
according to the narrow sense of Leibniz’s conception of activities that aim at coming to actually know the innate
innateness only primitive necessary truths count as innate. truths to be true.
Leibniz favours, however, the wider conception according to In sum, the intellect comes with innate ideas that enable
which also the derivative necessary truths are innate. Hence, rational souls to actualise innate knowledge, i.e. to come to
the truths that we can come to actually know to be true a priori actually know the innate truths to be true. Since this
comprises primitive as well as derivative necessary truths.32 actualisation essentially involves justified affirmation,
Leibniz’s conception of innatism is epistemically loaded innate ideas include active dispositions to cognitive activity
since, for him, it is essential to innate truths that, in prin- that aims at justified affirmation of innate truths. The jus-
ciple, we can come to know them to be true. This applies to tification rests either on infallible intuition or on reasoning.
the metaphysically rigorous notion of innateness from the
Discourse on Metaphysics as well as to the vulgar notion of 1.3 Judgement as Affirmation or Denial
innateness from the New Essays on Human Understanding. of Derivative Truths
It means that innate ideas do not merely consist in active
dispositions to bring truths to awareness. Instead, they must Surveying Leibniz’s uses of the Latin term ‘iudicium’ and
also include dispositions to acts through which we come to the French ‘jugement’ as well as their cognates reveals that
know them to be true. Since coming to know them to be Leibniz regularly uses these terms in characterizing the
true requires taking a stance on their truth-value, innate method of analysis. Analysis starts from questionable
ideas must include dispositions to affirm the innate truths. propositions and attempts to answer questions concerning
Furthermore, the affirmation must be justified since only them. Leibniz distinguishes between two types of ques-
justified affirmation can lead to the acquisition of actual tions35: Whether-questions ask for whether a given
knowledge. Furthermore, as Leibniz points out, we have to proposition is true or false. In this case, analysis aims at
conduct our epistemic endeavours with proper attention proving a proposition’s truth or falsehood. This happens by
and in proper order in order to succeed in finding innate means of tracing the proposition back to known principles.
truths and in coming to know them to be true.33 For What- and how-questions ask for explanations. In the New
instance, innate primitive truths are immediate truths in the Essays on Human Understanding, where Leibniz sets out
sense that we affirm them immediately when they come to his account as opposed to Locke’s account of judgement,
awareness.34 Since immediate affirmation rests on infalli- Leibniz claims that judgement as a capacity aims at
ble intuitive recognition of the proposition’s truth, innate answering whether-questions rather than what- and how-
questions.36 Indeed, it is the capacity to answer whether-
26
Leibniz variously characterises the acts of inner sense as acts of questions in the light of reasons: ‘[…] judgement consists
conscientia (GP IV 357 and A 6.6.238), of reflection (A 6.6.14 and A in the examination of propositions in accordance with
6.6.238), and inner sentiment (A 6.4.1830 and A 6.6.236). reason’.37 In fact, judgements result from the recognition of
27
See A 6.4.1500 and GP IV 357. a connection of the questionable proposition to ‘known
28
See A 6.4.1655. truths’ or reasons.38 We might thus say that judgement
29
See A 6.6.361–367 and A 6.6.434. results from an examination of reasons in favour of and
30
See A 6.6.89–94 and 101. against the truth of a proposition p in response to the
31
See A 6.4.1655 and A 6.6.361–368.
32
See A 6.6.12 and A 6.6.78. 35
33 See A 6.6.368.
See A 6.6.86. 36
34 See A 6.6.368 and Opuscules et Fragments inédits de Leibniz
See A 6.4.1655, A 6.6.361, and A 6.6.434. Hence, Leibniz
(henceforth referred to by ‘C’), 495.
includes the customary understanding of innateness in terms of 37
immediate affirmation in his characterisation of innate primitive A 6.6.141.
38
truths as immediate truths. See the quote from A 6.6.475 to be discussed in Sect. 2.1.

123
Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication, Affirmation, and Denial

question as to whether p is true or not. This characteriza- usually understood along the lines of the Platonic-Aris-
tion reveals that, for Leibniz, not all acts of affirming totelian tradition as an act of predication, i.e. as an act of
propositions are judgements. As we have seen above, (affirmatively or negatively) saying something (predicate)
affirmation of primitive truths does not result from an of something (subject).42 The result is a content that is
examination of reasons with respect to a given proposition truth-evaluable and, thus, propositional in virtue of its inner
whose truth-value is in question. Instead, if we are atten- predicative structure.
tive, we immediately affirm primitive truths when we Especially the Port-Royal logicians and John Locke are
become aware of them. Judgements are then the termini of commonly believed to hold the view that predication and
strivings at justified affirmation only of derivative and not alethic evaluation are one and the same act.43 According to
of primitive truths. In judgements we affirm or deny this position, content formation happens by way of alethic
derivative rather than primitive propositions. In contrast, evaluation. The idea is that the act of affirmatively saying
the termini of strivings concerning knowledge of primitive predicate B of subject A just is the act of taking B to be true
truths are non-judgemental affirmations.39 of A which, in turn, is nothing else than taking to be true
that A is B; and the act of negatively saying B of A just is
the act of taking B not to be true of A which is nothing else
2 Leibniz on the Act of Judgement than taking to be false that A is B. But this judgement
account of predication faces notorious problems.44 One
In the previous section we have seen that judgements play a bunch of problems derives from the fact that according to
central role in Leibniz’s conception of the mind. They are the judgement account all propositionally contentful acts
essential for coming to actually know derivative truths to are judgements. But it seems obvious that there are
be true. But what does the act of judgement itself consist propositional acts that are neither affirmative nor negative
in? judgements. Typical examples are ‘optative’ acts such as
wishing that p. And even if we restrict attention to truth-
2.1 Judging is not predicating evaluable acts, problems arise: assuming that p and imag-
ining that p are not acts of judgement since they do not
Gottlob Frege famously claimed that acts of judgement include taking a stance on whether p is true or not.
consist of two components: an act of grasping a thought What is Leibniz’s view of predication? Does he distin-
(content aspect) and an act of recognising the thought’s guish between predication and alethic evaluation? There
truth (evaluative aspect).40 Frege understands thoughts as are passages in Leibniz’s texts that seem to provide evi-
abstract entities. They do not need to be formed by the dence for the claim that he does not draw the distinction at
judging subject, but exist independently of individual issue. In the text Metaphysical Definitions and Thoughts
minds and are up for grasp.41 from the period 1678–80/1, for instance, Leibniz writes:
With the notable exception of Malebranche (and argu-
Judgement is affirmation or negation, and this is true
ably also Descartes and Spinoza), early modern thinkers
or false. (A 6.4.1394)
commonly claim that the contents judged need to be
formed by composition and, thus, depend for their exis- Furthermore, in revision notes Leibniz added in the
tence on the judging mind. The act of content formation is period 1697-1700 to his early work A New Method for
Learning and Teaching Law we read:
39
However, in some places Leibniz seems to apply a wider notion of
judgement that also denotes affirmation of primitive truths. This Every act of thinking [cogitatio] is conveyed [fertur]
seems to be the case in the piece On the Method of Distinguishing by an enunciation, i.e. a proposition, i.e. an affirma-
Real from Imaginary Phenomena (1683–1685/1686?) in which tion or negation […]. (A 6.1.284)
Leibniz explains: ‘I judge without proof, from a simple perception
or experience, that those things exist of which I am conscious within
me. There are, first, myself who am thinking of a variety of things and
then, the varied phenomena or appearances which exist in my mind’
42
(A 6.4.1500/Philosophical Papers and Letters (henceforth referred to This goes back to Plato’s Sophist and Aristotle’s De Interpreta-
by ‘L’), 363). Here, Leibniz characterises affirmation of primary tione (see Soph. 262c–d and 263e; De Int. 16b26–17a26).
contingent truths as judgement. According to the wider notion, 43
See Owen (2007, 412–418) and Buroker (1996, 8). Jennifer
judgements are co-extensive with acts of affirmation and denial. Marusic agrees that Locke does not distinguish between proposition
However, the epistemically more significant notion of judgement is formation and evaluation, but argues extensively that this does not
the narrow notion because it picks out those cases in which have the devastating consequences generally thought it would have
affirmation is given in light of reasons and in response to a (see Marusic 2014). Gabriel Nuchelmans and Walter Ott, in contrast,
whether-question. claim that Locke in fact distinguishes between proposition formation
40
See Frege (1956, 294). and evaluation (see Nuchelmans 1983, 139–147; Ott 2002).
41 44
See Frege (1956, 302). The locus classicus of this critique is Geach (1962, 24).

123
C. Barth

The revision note suggests that every act of thinking—at to innatism in his New Essays on Human Understanding
least every act that gets expressed linguistically by an (the translation by Remnant and Bennett is henceforth
enunciation45—is conveyed by an affirmative or negative referred to by ‘RB’). At one point of the dispute, Leibniz’s
enunciation. But if acts of thinking get expressed by either spokesman Theophilus says:
an affirmative or negative enunciation, then it seems that
I have already replied (§5) to the objection (§22)
acts of thinking must be acts of mental affirmation or
which maintains that when it is said that innate
denial. And if one understands the first quotation as
notions are ‘‘implicitly’’ in the mind, that should
expressing an identification of judgement with affirmation
signify only that the mind has a faculty for knowing
and denial, this seems to imply that Leibniz holds a
them; for I have pointed out that it has in addition a
judgement account of predication.
faculty for finding them in itself, and the disposition,
But passages such as these do not decide the issue
if it thinks of them as one should, to approve of them.
because Leibniz uses the terms ‘affirmatio’ and ‘negatio’
(A 6.6.84/RB 84; translation modified)
ambiguously. Both terms can refer to affirmative and
negative judgings in the mental realm and assertions in the Subjects can ‘find’ innate notions in themselves, i.e.
linguistic realm. However, they can also refer to acts of under proper circumstances they can bring innate truths to
merely conceiving or merely saying that p rather than acts their awareness. But, for Leibniz, finding the proposition
of judging or asserting that p. For example, in a piece from must consist in an act of merely conceiving or entertaining
1678/1679 Leibniz characterises affirmatio in the mental the proposition rather than in an act of alethic evaluation.
sense as follows: Otherwise, we would not only approve the proposition ‘if
[one] thinks of [it] as one should’, but we would already do
Affirmation is a thought of two [concepts], insofar as
so in forming the proposition and independently of how we
the one concept is contained by the other concept. (A
think of the proposition formed. Hence, Leibniz separates
6.4.141)
the predicative act of proposition formation from the
Here, Leibniz describes an affirmative thought as one of evaluation of the proposition’s truth-value.
two concepts that are related by containment. He does not A second passage from the New Essays on Human
mention any act of evaluating the thought’s truth-value. Understanding presents further evidence for the view that
This indicates that he uses ‘affirmatio’ here in the sense of Leibniz distinguishes between predication and alethic
‘merely conceiving’ and that the term ‘affirmation’ merely evaluation. Here is what his spokesman Theophilus says:
indicates that a concept is thought of as containing rather
A reason is a known truth whose connection with
than as not containing another concept. In other words,
some less well-known truth leads us to give our
Leibniz uses the term ‘affirmatio’ merely in order to indi-
assent to the latter. (A 6.6.475/RB 475)
cate the logical form of the thought, namely that it is of the
form ‘A is B’ rather than ‘A is not B’.46 But it does not We affirm a found derivative truth (‘a less well-known
indicate the occurrence of an affirmative evaluation. In truth’) in light of known truths or reasons. Hence, to think
general, due to the mentioned ambiguity, passages that of a found derivative proposition ‘as one should’ so as to
suggest that Leibniz identifies thinking with affirming or come to justifiably affirm it is to think of it in the light of
denying do not show that he holds a judgement account of reasons that speak in favour of its truth. Leibniz indicates
predication. He might merely express the view that all acts here that finding a derivative truth is different from
of thinking either have an affirmative or a negative logical approving it, i.e. different from evaluating it as true.
form. Finding the derivative truth that p consists in merely con-
Furthermore, there is ample evidence that Leibniz does ceiving that p, not in judging that p. Again, Leibniz sepa-
not hold a judgement account of predication. We find a rates the act of predication from the act of alethic
telling passage in Leibniz’s response to Locke’s objections evaluation.
In sum, while the considered textual evidence for a
45
conflation of predication and evaluation in Leibniz does not
I understand the terms ‘enuntiatio’ and ‘propositio’ in the
turn out to be decisive, at least in the New Essays on
quotation as referring to linguistic acts. However, this is not self-
evident. While ‘enuntiatio’ usually stands for a linguistic entity, this is Human Understanding there is considerable textual evi-
not true of the term ‘propositio’. Leibniz uses ‘propositio’ in order to dence in favour of the view that Leibniz keeps predication
refer to linguistic as well as mental items. However, in the passage at separate from evaluation and that he thus does not hold a
hand, Leibniz’s use of the verb ‘ferre’ indicates that the reference is to
judgement account of predication.47 Instead, Leibniz holds
linguistic items. It would not make much sense to think of acts of
thinking as being conveyed by other mental acts. But it makes good
sense to think of acts of thinking as being conveyed by linguistic acts. 47
Leibniz also talks about judging what one represents, indicating
46
Cf. Nuchelmans (1983, 220). that these are distinct acts, see Opera Philosophica Omnia I, 419–420.

123
Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication, Affirmation, and Denial

a two-component account of judgement that does not fall that p is true. And one might think that the same must then
prey to conflating predicating and evaluating. hold true on the mental level of judging as well. But a few
lines later Leibniz implicitly rejects this view. He writes:
2.2 The Acts of Affirmation and Denial
Enunciation and affirmation of the enunciation are
equivalent, i.e., the enunciation itself commands
Having seen that Leibniz holds a two-component account
[jubet] by itself that its truth is to be affirmed. (A
of judgment, let us deepen our analysis and take a closer
6.4.737)
look at his account of the acts of alethic evaluation. In
Sect. 1.3 we have learned that, for Leibniz, judgement Leibniz states here that an enunciation of p and the
results from an examination of reasons in favour of and affirmation that the enunciation that p is true are equiva-
against the truth of a proposition p in response to the lent; they are substitutable salve veritate. More important
question as to whether p is true or not. Hence our question for our concern is the second part of the sentence, in which
is: what are the evaluative acts like that result from an Leibniz says that the enunciation of p commands (‘jubet’)
activity of examining reasons in favour of or against the the affirmation of its truth. As so often, it is not fully clear
truth or falsehood of a proposition p in response to a whether Leibniz is referring to an act of merely saying or
whether-question concerning p? Although in one list of an act of asserting that p. But his talk of ‘commanding’ the
definitions Leibniz acknowledges that it is difficult to affirmation of the enunciation’s truth suggests that he has
explain what it is to affirm and to deny,48 other texts at an assertion in mind and that he wants to claim that
least suggest a particular view on these two acts. assertive force does not consist in predicating truth or
One conception of affirmation and denial understands falsehood. In any case, the latter passage shows that the
them as a special form of predicating. According to it, the former passage is not an expression of a predicative
acts of affirming and denying consist in the acts of predi- account of affirmation and denial. Assuming that he is
cating truth and falsehood. Affirming that p would then concerned with acts of asserting in this document, then
come down to thinking that p is true; and denying that assertive force does not require predication of truth or
p would come down to thinking that p is false. The pred- falsehood. Nor would ‘judgemental force’ require mental
icative account of affirmation and denial faces a problem, predication of truth or falsehood. The act of affirmation
though. Once predication is distinguished from alethic that Leibniz defines here as an enunciation of an enuncia-
evaluation so as to make room for acts of merely con- tion does not provide assertive force, but only makes lin-
ceiving, the acts of affirmation and denial no longer allow guistically explicit a feature that is already incorporated in
for explanation in terms of specific types of predicating, the original enunciation.
not even in terms of predication of truth and falsehood. But what do acts of alethic evaluation then consist in for
Predicating just is not evaluating truth, no matter what is Leibniz? To my knowledge, passages in which Leibniz
predicated of what. Predicating as such only leads to an act elaborates on this question are scarce. Yet, even if some-
of merely conceiving; and merely conceiving that a what speculatively, I would like to propose a suggestion as
proposition is true or false is not affirming it or denying, to what Leibniz’s position could be like in view of the way
i.e. evaluating it as true or evaluating it as false. in which he characterizes judgements as a result of an
But Leibniz might be unaware of this problem and examination of reasons. We have seen above that Leibniz
nevertheless understand the act of judgement as an act of considers substances to be immaterial forces. They are
predicating truth. Does he? In a short logical text from permanently active in that they exhibit at each moment of
1686 entitled De Vero et Falso, Affirmatione et Negatione, their existence an infinite manifold of strivings. These
et de Contradictoriis he characterises affirmation as strivings aim at bringing about accurate non-conceptual
follows: perceptions and in the case of minds also true conceptual
thoughts.
Affirmation is enunciation of an enunciation, saying
How do acts of affirmation and denial fit into Leibniz’s
that the latter is true. (A 6.4.737)
metaphysical picture of minds as forces? As we have seen,
Here, an affirmation is meant to be a linguistic act of the acts of affirmation and denial do not consist in predications
form ‘p is true’ or ‘It is true that p’. If we understand of truth and falsehood; nor can they be explained in terms
Leibniz in this passage as not referring to an act of merely of other kinds of predication. Against the backdrop of his
saying, but to an act of asserting, the passage suggests that metaphysics of minds, according to which minds only
he holds a predicative account of affirmative assertion exhibit strivings and representational states (perceptions
according to which to assert affirmatively that p is to say and thoughts), Leibniz thus seems to be committed to
accounting for these acts in terms of strivings. How might
48
See C 497. this work? To begin with, we have seen that acts of

123
C. Barth

judgement have their home in the context of an examina- affirmative judgements are acts that establish dispositional
tion of reasons in response to whether-questions. Now, beliefs concerning derivative truths and, in doing so, make
posing a whether-question—asking oneself internally derivative truths available as reasons for future reasoning
whether p is true or not—and addressing this question are in response to whether-questions. The upshot is that the act
manifestations of cognitive attention. This cognitive of affirming a proposition as a result of an examination of
attention is constituted by strivings eventually aiming at reasons comes down to an act of establishing a disposi-
answering the whether-question. I will call these strivings tional belief stored in memory; and in virtue of this belief, a
‘judgement strivings’. By means of sub-ordinated epis- further reason—the content of the belief—has become
temic strivings they effect that the cognitive activity of the available for future reasoning. Acts of affirmation then are
mind is focused on answering the whether-question and acts of changing the structure of memory dispositions. Acts
engages in the examination of reasons. of merely thinking that p, in contrast, do not establish
Consider the case of a subject who has heard of beliefs in memory and, thus, do not make new reasons
Pythagoras’ theorem for the first time. For Leibniz, this available for future reasoning.
proposition would count as an innate truth. This means that And what about denying? Again, negative judgement
there is an innate disposition—a judgement striving—to is the consequence of an examination of reasons in
find and to justifiably affirm the theorem. However, cog- response to the question whether p is true or not. But
nitive effort (reasoning) is required in order to enter the what does the act of denial consist in? We said that
frame of mind in which these active dispositions become affirmation consists in an act of establishing a belief in
unimpeded and a justified act of affirmative judgement memory to the effect that a further reason is available for
occurs. At the beginning, the subject neither affirms nor future reasoning. This belief consists in a striving that
denies the theorem she has heard of or found in herself. aims at bringing the proposition to consciousness in order
Next, if the subject wills to find out whether the theorem is to be employed as a premise. This striving will mostly be
true or not and poses a whether-question to herself, the impeded, but might be realised in some future reasoning.
judgement striving that aims at answering the question in And, importantly, once the affirmed proposition is ren-
the affirmative turns effective. As a result, the cognitive dered conscious in the context of an examination of
activity that examines reasons concerning the theorem gets reasons, it has the potency—usually in cooperation with
started. If the resulting reasoning is successful, a justified other reasons—to bring new conclusions to conscious-
affirmative judgement concerning the theorem occurs and ness, i.e. to ‘un-impede’ judgement strivings that have
the subject comes to actually know the theorem’s truth. been impeded so far. In this sense, affirmed propositional
The examination of reasons begins with a search for contents contribute to the augmentation of the subject’s
relevant reasons from memory and acts in which these actual knowledge. Denied propositions, by contrast, are
reasons come to consciousness. Now, the reasons searched contents that do not possess this potency of contributing
for are propositional contents the subject believes to be to reasoning and of broadening the subject’s knowledge.
true. These beliefs are active dispositions in memory; they In Leibniz’s framework, this need not mean that denied
are active dispositions to bring the believed proposition to propositional contents might not come to consciousness
awareness under appropriate conditions. But where do in an examination of reasons at all. However, if they do
these dispositions come from? How are they established? so they do not play the role of a premise in reasoning
The answer put forward here is, of course: through acts of that aims at answering a whether-question. Denied
affirmation. By affirming a proposition, the subject propositional contents are expelled from this epistemic
acquires the belief that the proposition is true, i.e. a new role. Hence, acts of denial also lead to an establishing of
memory disposition gets established. Or more precisely: active dispositions in memory. They establish active
The memory disposition the actualisation of which brings dispositions to bring to consciousness propositional con-
the proposition p to consciousness in an act of merely tents, but—in contrast to acts of affirmation—they do not
conceiving that p changes into a belief. This implies that function as fodder for inferences in contexts of answering
the actualisations of the disposition are allowed to play the whether-questions. They establish ‘disbeliefs’ rather than
role of premises in reasonings that respond to whether- beliefs. This is the major mark that distinguishes acts of
questions. And since Leibniz understands dispositions as denial from acts of affirmation in Leibniz’s framework.
strivings, affirmation establishes strivings that aim at The characteristic role Leibniz attributes to acts of
bringing premises to consciousness for further knowledge- judgement can then be described as follows:
expanding reasoning. Now, we have seen that affirmation
(a) Affirmative judgements make propositions available
can rest on intuition (primitive truths) or on reasoning
as premises for future reasoning in response to a
(derivative truths). Affirmations that rest on reasoning and
whether-question. This means that reasoning that
concern derivative truths are judgements. Hence,

123
Judgement in Leibniz’s Conception of the Mind: Predication, Affirmation, and Denial

aims at answering a whether-question now provides does he understand the evaluative acts of affirmation and
a context in which the proposition can come to denial as predications of truth and falsehood. Leibniz nei-
consciousness in order to be employed as a premise. ther holds a judgement account of predication nor a pred-
In this context, the striving to bring this proposition icative account of (the evaluative aspect of) judgement.
to consciousness can now get unimpeded. Instead, he holds a two-component account that distin-
(b) The act of denial in negative judgements bans guishes between predication and alethic evaluation. Fur-
propositions from playing the role of premises in thermore, according to this account the evaluative acts of
reasoning that aims at answering a whether-question. affirmation and denial are understood as acts of changing
It might still be that negatively judged propositions the structure of memory dispositions, i.e. of the strivings
occur as premises in hypothetical reasonings that that compose memory. They group propositions into those
start with counterfactual or even counterpossible that are licensed to play a role as a premise in reasoning in
premises. But reasoning in response to a whether- response to whether-questions and those that are not
question starts with premises that are believed to be licensed to play this role. Affirmation and denial are acts of
true, and negatively judged propositions do not fall disposition change.
into this category. Hence, the disposition to bring a
proposition, which is negatively judged, to con- Acknowledgments I would like to thank the participants of the
conference ‘Perception and Negative Beliefs—from Plato to Kant’
sciousness in order to employ it as a premise, will be
(Hamburg, August 28–29, 2014) for helpful discussions on the
impeded in the context of reasoning with the aim of paper’s topics. I would also like to thank the editors and the reviewers
answering a whether-question. for their comments on the text.

Apart from judging affirmatively or negatively, a subject


can also withhold judgement. Withholding judgement References
should not be understood as an act in its own right, but
rather as absence of judgement. A subject withholds Ackrill JL (ed) (1963) Aristotle: categories and de interpretatione.
judgement as long as the examination of reasons in Clarendon Press, Oxford
response to a whether-question has not been successful or Armgardt M (2001) Das rechtslogische System der ,,Doctrine
Conditionum‘‘ von Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz. Elwert Verlag,
has not yet started. Such propositions are also not available Marburg
for playing the role of premises in reasoning that is sup- Berkowitz R (2005) The gift of science, Leibniz and the modern legal
posed to answer a whether-question. However, in contrast tradition. Harvard University Press, Cambridge
to negatively judged propositions, they are potential objects Burkhardt H (1980) Logik und Semiotik in der Philosophie von
Leibniz. Philosophia, München
of whether-questions.49 Buroker J (1996) Arnauld on judging and the will. In: Kremer E (ed)
Interpreting Arnauld. University of Toronto Press, Toronto,
pp 3–12
3 Conclusion Couturat L (1901) La Logique de Leibniz. Alcan, Paris
Couturat L (ed) (1903) Opuscules et Fragments inédits de Leibniz.
Alcan, Paris (=C)
In this paper I have argued that acts of judgement are Deutsche Akademie der Wissenschaften (ed) (1923) Gottfried
central to Leibniz’s conception of the mind. For Leibniz, Wilhelm Leibniz: Sämtliche Schriften und Briefe. Akademie
minds permanently strive for actualising innate knowledge. Verlag, Darmstadt Berlin. Cited by volume and page (=A)
Duerlinger J (ed) (2005) Plato: the Sophist. Peter Lang, New York
The actualisation of virtual knowledge concerning deriva- Erdmann JE (ed) (1840) God. Guil. Leibnitii: Opera Philosophica
tive truths happens by means of judgements. Acts of Omnia I. G. Eichler, Berlin
judgement result from reasoning in response to a whether- Frege G (1956) The thought: a logical inquiry. Mind
question concerning a derivative proposition p, i.e. a 65(259):289–311
Geach P (1962) Reference and generality. Cornell University Press,
question that asks whether p is true or not. Furthermore, I Ithaca
have argued that Leibniz neither understands predication in Gerhardt CI (ed) (1875–1890) G. W. Leibniz: Die philosophischen
terms of the evaluative acts of affirmation and denial nor Schriften von Leibniz, 7 vol. Weidmann, Berlin. Reprint
Hildesheim 1978. Cited by volume and page (=GP)
49
Kauppi R (1960) Über die Leibnizsche Logik. Helsinki, n.p.
Once propositions have become the object of a whether-question Kulstad M (1991) Leibniz on apperception, consciousness, and
they are allowed to play the role of a premise in indirect proofs reflection. Philosophia, München
(reductio ad absurdum) in which their falsehood is revealed by Leibniz GW (1686) Discourse of metaphysics. Cited by section as in
deducing a contradiction. One reviewer raised the point that A 6.4.1531–1588 (=DM)
negatively judged propositions can be reconsidered. For instance, Leibniz GW (1714) Monadology. Cited by section as in GP VI
one can check the reasons for the previous negative judgement or 607–623 (=M)
search for new reasons that might speak in favour of the proposition’s Leibniz GW (1714) Principles of nature and grace, based on reason.
truth. However, in such cases the question is not whether p, but Cited by section as in GP VI 598–606 (=PNG)
whether the denial that p is well-founded.

123
C. Barth

Lenzen W (1990) Das System der Leibnizschen Logik. De Gruyter, Mercer C (2001) Leibniz’s metaphysics. Its origins and development.
Berlin Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Lenzen W (2004) Calculus Universalis. Studien zur Logik von G. Nuchelmans G (1983) Judgment and proposition. From Descartes to
W. Leibniz. Mentis, Paderborn Kant. North-Holland Publishing Company, Amsterdam
Loemker L (ed) (1969) Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz: philosophical Ott W (2002) Propositional attitudes in modern philosophy. Dialogue
papers and letters. Kluwer, Dordrecht (=L) 41:1–18
Losonsky M (2001) Enlightenment and action from Descartes to Owen D (2007) Locke on judgment. In: Newman L (ed) The Cambridge
Kant. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge companion to Locke’s ‘‘Essay concerning Human Understanding’’.
Marusic J (2014) Proposition and judgment in Locke and Arnauld: A Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp 406–435
monstrous and unholy union? J Hist Philos 52(2):255–280 Parkinson GHR (1965) Logic and reality in Leibniz’s metaphysics.
McRae R (1976) Leibniz: perception, apperception, and thought. Clarendon, Oxford
University of Toronto Press, Toronto Remnant P, Bennett J (eds) (1996) G.W. Leibniz: New Essay on
Menn S (1998) Descartes and Augustine. Cambridge University Human Understanding. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Press, Cambridge (=RB)

123

You might also like