You are on page 1of 18

Stanford Encyclopedia of

Philosophy
Alfred Schutz
First published Tue Oct 29, 2002; substantive revision Tue
Feb 27, 2018

Alfred Schutz, more than any other phenomenologist,


attempted to relate the thought of Edmund Husserl to the
social world and the social sciences. His Phenomenology of
the Social World supplied philosophical foundations for
Max Weber’s sociology and for economics, with which he
was familiar through contacts with colleagues of the
Austrian school. When Schutz fled Hitler’s Anschluss of
Austria and immigrated to the United States in 1939, he
developed his thought further in relationship to the social sciences, American pragmatism, logical
empiricism, and to various other fields of endeavor such as music and literature. His work has
been influential on new movements in sociological thought such as ethnomethodology and
conversation analysis.

1. Life and Influence


2. The Phenomenology of the Social World
3. Extensions
3.1 The Bergson Writings
3.2 The Social Sciences
3.3 Other Philosophies
3.4 Applications
3.5 Phenomenology
Bibliography
Works by Schutz
Secondary Literature
Academic Tools
Other Internet Resources
Related Entries

1. Life and Influence


Vienna-born Alfred Schutz (1899–1959) joined the artillery division of the Austrian army during
World War I and served on the Italian front before returning to pursue studies at the University of
Vienna. There Schutz studied law, social science, and business with renowned figures such as
Hans Kelsen and Ludwig von Mises, but his most significant educational experience occurred
while he was a member of the Mises Circle, one of many Viennese circles, of which the “Schlick
Circle” was the most famous. In the interdisciplinary Mises Circle, Schutz formed friendships that
would continue throughout the cataclysmic decades of the 1930s and 1940s and that included,
among others, economists Gottfried von Haberler, Friedrich A. von Hayek, Fritz Machlup, Oskar
Morgenstern, philosopher Felix Kaufmann, and political scientist Eric Voegelin. While continuing
to pursue his academic interests, in 1927 Schutz was named executive officer of Reitler and
Company, a leading Viennese banking firm with international business relations, and thus he
commenced a life-long pattern that led Edmund Husserl to describe him as “a banker by day and
a philosopher by night.”

From the beginning, Schutz had been taken with the methodological writings of Max Weber, who
had lectured in Vienna in the summer of 1918 and whose work was immensely popular among
Viennese intellectuals. However, Schutz felt that Weber’s work rested on tacit, unexamined
presuppositions resulting from his lack of interest in fundamental epistemological problems that
had no direct bearing on his special sociological problems. In 1925–1927, Schutz turned to Henri
Bergson’s philosophy of consciousness and inner time in order to clarify notions such as meaning,
action, and intersubjectivity, and his results have been collected in manuscripts published as Life
Forms and Meaning Structure. Dissatisfied, though, with his analyses of temporality to the extent
that he never published them and prompted by comments of Felix Kaufmann, he discovered the
relevance of the phenomenology of the consciousness of inner time of Edmund Husserl (1859–
1938). He then went on to produce his major life’s work, The Phenomenology of the Social World
(1932), a work for which Husserl praised him as “an earnest and profound phenomenologist.” He
spent the rest of the 1930s authoring brief essays showing how his phenomenology of the social
world could come to terms with the economic thought of Mises and Hayek. Also, before any
direct encounter with American pragmatism, he developed a manuscript on personality in the
social world that stressed the pragmatic elements of the everyday social world.

Schutz’s career, academic and business, was thoroughly convulsed when Adolf Hitler
implemented the annexation (Anschluss) of Austria by Germany on March 13, 1938, especially
since he, on a business trip in Paris, was separated for three months from his own family, whose
emigration to Paris he finally arranged. As an international lawyer and businessperson, he was
able to assist numerous intellectuals to escape Austria, but the westward movement of the Nazi
juggernaut eventually compelled him to immigrate with his family to the United States on July
14, 1939.

In the United States, he continued assisting immigrants and working with Reitler and Company in
reestablishing its business, and he supported the United States war effort by reporting on German
and Austrian economic matters for the Board of Economic Warfare. He also cooperated with
Marvin Farber in founding the International Phenomenological Society, whose initial turf-battles
he often mediated, and in instituting and editing Philosophy and Phenomenological Research. In
1943, Schutz began teaching sociology and philosophy courses on The Graduate Faculty of The
New School for Social Research, and his reponsibilities included presenting papers in the school-
wide General Seminar, supervising dissertations, and serving as chair of the Philosophy
Department from 1952–1956. In spite of his many activities, he managed to carry on an extensive
philosophical correspondence with Farber, Aron Gurwitsch, Fritz Machlup, Eric Voegelin, and
Maurice Natanson, his graduate student from 1951 to 1953. However, to date, only the
correspondence with Gurwitsch has been published as Philosophers in Exile: The
Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and Aron Gurwitsch, 1939–1959. While in the United States,
Schutz published a collection of articles on a wide variety of topics, explaining and criticizing
Husserl’s thought; examining the works of American philosophers such as William James or
George Santanyana; engaging continental philosophers such as Max Scheler or Jean-Paul Sartre;
developing his own philosophical positions on the social sciences, temporality, language, multiple
realities, responsibility, and symbolism; addressing socio-political questions dealing with
strangers, homecomers, well-informed citizens, and equality; and treating themes in literature and
music.

Several thinkers have continued Schutz’s tradition in philosophy and sociology, such as Maurice
Natanson who emphasized the tension between individual, existential and social, anonymizing
dimensions of everyday life experience. Thomas Luckmann, who served as co-author for the
posthumous publication of Schutz’s The Structures of the Life-World, developed the sociology of
knowledge implications of Schutz’s thought and stressed the differences between science and the
life-world as well as the importance of language, symbolism, and the moral order of society.
While John O’Neill has fused Schutz’s thought with that of Merleau-Ponty by focusing on the
lived, communicative body, Richard Grathoff has investigated the experience of normality within
the bounded and situated context of a milieu. Ilja Srubar developed the pragmatic dimensions of
Schutz’s thought and several of its economic and political implications, Lester Embree clarified
his typology of the sciences, and Fred Kersten has expanded his aesthetic insights. Drawing on
Schutz’s thought, Harold Garfinkel launched ethnomethodology, and George Psathas, a
commentator on ethnomethodology, played a key role initiating the new discipline of
conversation analysis. Several other scholars worldwide have dedicated themselves to Schutz’s
work and to the development of his insights, and Germany, Japan, and the United States are home
to archives containing Schutz’s work and correspondence.

2. The Phenomenology of the Social World


In his principal work, Schutz placed three chapters of philosophical discussion between
introductory and concluding chapters that discussed the social scientific positions his philosophy
attempted to engage. In the initial chapter Schutz praised Max Weber’s views on value-freedom in
social science and the autonomy of science vis-à-vis other activities (e.g. politics), and he
commended Weber’s methodological individualism and ideal-type methodology. In addition, he
applauded Weber’s refusal to reduce the social sciences to the natural sciences, while allowing
their ideal-typical results to be testable for adequacy. However, Schutz also supplemented Weber,
pointing out how interpretation was involved even in selecting an experience out of one’s stream
of experience and highlighting how the meaning of an action to an actor depended upon the
project guiding the extended temporal process of the sub-acts leading to its realization.

These initial criticisms of Weber required Schutz to develop his own theory of meaning and
action, beginning with Husserl’s study of the consciousness of internal time, in particular
consciousness’s capacity to capture reflectively and distinguish lived experiences, which at first
appear as undefined phases melting into each other. Schutz had appropriated this notion of
flowing consciousness, or duration, from Bergson, on whom he had relied in the manuscripts later
published as Life Forms and Meaning Structure. Those manuscripts, for analytic purposes, split
the ego, indivisible in its lived experience, into ideal-typical constructs of various life forms, that
included the “I” living in duration, remembering, acting, thinking, and relating to a “Thou.”
Though Schutz never made explicit his reasons for not publishing those earlier manuscripts,
Helmut Wagner rightly speculated that he was ill at ease since one could only have access to
duration through acts of memory, which, of course, constituted a life-form entirely separate from
duration itself. As a result of this methodology relying on distinct ideal-types, duration began to
appear as an inaccessible Ding-an-sich. Husserl’s account of the consciousness of inner time
remedied just this problem by carefully describing how the stream of duration was changed at
every moment into a remembered having-just-been-thus, as the primal impression passed into into
primary remembrance, or retention. The continuum extending backward from the now of the
primal impression through its retentions formed a “specious” present, to which the reflective acts
of secondary remembrance, that is, recollection or reproduction, turned, differentiating one
experience from another. In sum, Husserl’s phenomenological description of experience
uncovered the process of retention that bridged the duration/(reflective) memory gap that had
bedeviled Schutz’s earlier efforts insofar as he had relied on an ideal-typical methodology, which
prevented insight into what goes on within conscious processes themselves.

Schutz, though, turned the Husserlian account of temporality in the direction of an action theory,
demarcating levels of passive experience (e.g. bodily reflexes), spontaneous activity without a
guiding project (e.g., acts of noticing environmental stimuli), and deliberately planned and
projected activity, known technically as “action” (e.g., writing a book). In planning an action to be
realized in the future, one relies on reflective acts of “projection,” like those found in reflective
memory, only now oriented in a future as opposed to past direction. Through such reflectivity, one
imagines a project as completed in future perfect tense, that is, what will have been realized after
one’s acting, and this project, also of central importance for Martin Heidegger and the pragmatist
tradition, establishes the “in-order-to motive” of one’s action. By contrast, one’s “because
motives” consist in the environmental, historical factors that influenced the (now past) decision to
embark upon the project and that can only be discovered by investigating in the “pluperfect
tense,” that is, exploring those past factors that preceded that past decision.

Schutz’s distinctions here are relevant to contemporary debates about whether freedom is
compatible with determinism since from the perspective of the lived in-order-to motive, one
experiences oneself as free and morally responsible, but from the perspective of examining one’s
because motives after completing one’s action, one correlates, as an observer of oneself, the
choice of the project with its historical determinants. Of course, Schutz, working within the
parameters of Husserl’s non-naturalistic account of consciousness, would have conceived such
determinants not so much as empirico-mechanical causes but rather as influences discoverable
through an interpretive process, associating earlier events with the later ones they seem to have
influenced. Schutz’s position comes closest to the roughly compatibilist outlooks of P.F. Strawson
and Thomas Nagel, who distinguish between the participant and observer attitudes prior to
theoretical discussions and who align the participant attitude with freedom and the observer
attitude with determinism. Schutz, however, contributes the unique insight that these attitudes
take place within distinctive temporal frameworks, oriented toward the future or the past.

Schutz’s account of the temporal framework of motivation permitted criticism of Weber’s view
that one could orient one’s action to the past behavior of others, since, while such behavior might
have served as the because motive of an action, one could not aim at affecting another’s already
completed action. Similarly, failure to appreciate temporality often leads to misinterpretations of
action, as when one assumes that the outcome of an act may have been its motive without
considering the actor’s in-order-to motive, which due to unforeseen events may have been
adjusted or may have led to results contrary to those intended. Likewise, one can interpret an
economic action after the fact as less than rational without taking sufficient account of the limited
information that was available to the actor at the time of deciding to act and that might make her
action seem perfectly rational. Moreover, the fact that one’s own temporal stream of
consciousness never completely coincides with that of another, whose sequence of events and
intensity of experience inevitably differs from one’s own, places limits on one’s understanding of
another. As a consequence, the objective meanings of language, defined in dictionaries as
invariant regardless of users, also bear subjective connotations for language users due to their
unique histories of linguistic experience, even though for practical purposes of communication
they are able to set aside such differences. For instance, one would have to consider in depth
Goethe’s works as a whole to understand what he meant by “demonic.” Schutz’s basic point in all
these examples involves getting behind constituted meanings to the temporal processes by which
actors build up the meaning of their own actions—a meaningful build-up accentuated by the
German title of his Phenomenology of the Social World (Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt).

In addition to this account of consciousness, motivation, and action, he examined the structure of
the social world, including Consociates who share the same time and spatial access to each
other’s bodies, Contemporaries with whom one shares only the same time, and Predecessors and
Successors with whom one does not share the same time and to whose lived bodies one lacks
access. Consociates, present to each other physically, partake of each other’s inner time, that is,
the on-rolling life of the other, grasp the building up of the other’s experience, and live in a We-
relationship that entails “growing older together.” While Consociates revise their types of each
other immediately, one must proceed more inferentially with Contemporaries, Predecessors, and
Successors, constructing ideal types based on letters or reports and running greater risks of
misunderstanding, depending on the degree of anonymity of the person to be understood. One
could say, then, that Weber’s method of ideal type construction, illustrated in his sociological
account of the Protestant at the origins of capitalism, is not really that foreign to the everyday life-
world in which actors beyond the Consociate level continually relate to each other via such type
construction. Human actors in everyday life already adopt toward each other the attitudes of
social scientists.
Schutz conceived his work as developing a “phenomenological psychology” of “inner
experience” and focusing on the invariant features of the life-world toward which theoreticians,
including social scientists, turn reflectively. Although Jürgen Habermas criticizes Schutz’s
account of the life-world for being “abridged in a culturalistic fashion” and not addressing
institutional orders and personality structures (Habermas 1987, 2:126–132), it would seem that
Schutz himself delimits his own work in just this fashion. According to him, social scientists
develop constructs, ideal types, of the meaning-contexts of life-world actors, and they test these
types to determine if they are causally adequate, that is conforming to past experience, and
meaning adequate, that is, consistent with whatever else is known about the actor. Responding to
Mises’s critique that Weber’s ideal-types are too historically specific, Schutz suggested that the
later Weber’s ideal types in Economy and Society attain a generality comparable to that of Mises’
own economic theory, which itself could be interpreted as presenting ideal-typical descriptions of
the behavior of economic agents. The later Weber’s types depict the invariant subjective
experiences of anyone who acts within the economic framework as defined by the principle of
marginal utility, that is, choosing to maximize satisfaction.

3. Extensions
3.1 The Bergson Writings

Schutz’s manuscripts on Bergson, produced from 1925 to 1927 and finally published in English in
1982, illuminate his subsequent works, with which they share the general purpose of “the
grounding of the social sciences in the Thou experience.” (Schutz 1982, 34) In reaction to
positivistic approaches of the Schlick Circle (in which Felix Kaufmann participated) that reduced
experience to what the method of natural scientific observation found tolerable, Schutz sought to
give an account of the life-form of pre-scientific experience preceding conceptual-categorical
comprehension, the “highest and most powerful life-form” (Schutz 1982, 53). Of course, by
moving in this direction, he encountered the problem, faced by Georg Wilhelm Friedrich Hegel,
Wilfrid Sellars, John McDowell, Robert Brandom, and others, namely, how it is possible to access
the pre-conceptual without conceptualizing it. Hence, he acknowledged that his work is “in
conflict with its material” since it “is forced to resort to conceptual formulations” (Schutz 1982,
70). This problem parallels the problem of reaching the life-form of the present unfolding of
experience (duration) since one can only speak of it by arresting its flow, distinguishing its
moments, and thus remembering what has lapsed—but then one is in the new life-form of
memory. Although this gap between present duration and memory prompted his turn to
Husserlian phenomenology, the problematic itself highlighted for him the pervasiveness and
hiddenness of interpretive activity as one moves between interpretive frameworks—a principal
theme of all his later work. He took notice of this theme when he frequently pointed out how
one’s reconstitution of a past experience in memory varied according to the interests of the
present from which one remembered the past. Indeed a favorite example from Bergson’s work
involved an actor reflecting upon a prior process of choosing and interpreting it as if it had been a
choice between two clearly defined possibilities, whereas in fact the process often oscillated
between several options, retaining, reproducing, comparing, and modifying them in succession. In
general, Schutz concurred with Bergson on such notions such as attention to life, planes of
consciousness, the body as the intersection of outer and inner temporality, music as the model of
duration, and multiple types of ordering, but rejected his bio-evolutionary theory, vitalism, and
the idea of a supra-personal elán.

3.2 The Social Sciences

Although Schutz defended Weber against Mises, he agreed with many basic premises of Mises
and the Austrian tradition that focused on the subjective preferences of the purchaser conferring
value on objects instead of explaining value as the result of objective processes such as
production costs or labor time invested. He also shared Mises’s suppositions about value-freedom
in economic science, the need to describe rather than evaluate preferences, and the instrumental
task of science, namely, of showing how to achieve ends rather than assessing their value. Since
Mises considered all acting economic insofar as any consumer choice involved maximizing
satisfaction in the widest sense, he opposed the narrow type of the homo economicus, modeled on
the businessperson driven solely by economic motives at the expense of all others. Schutz,
however, posited the life-world with its wide diversity of motivations at the base of economic
theory. He conceived such theory as adopting a reflective perspective governed by the principle of
marginal utility, namely, that ideal types ought to be constructed as if all actors “had oriented their
life-plans to realize the greatest utility with minimal cost.” (Schutz 1964, 87) Besides thus
resuscitating a version of homo economicus, Schutz insisted that economists study purposive-
rational actions, which, in Weber’s sense, involved a reflective comparison of alternative projects
before adopting one as an in-order-to motive. In addition, he classified the sense of uneasiness
that Mises described as prompting the search for satisfaction under the category of because
motives; one first adopts an rationally determined economic project and in retrospect discovers
the preceding dissatisfaction. To understand the difference between conceiving all action as
economic and conceiving economic action as one type of action within an more encompassing
life-world, one might compare Mises with Schutz with reference to a problem raised within
contemporary discussions of collective action, namely, how traditional non-economic values (e.g.,
those of politics or ethics) ought to intersect the market. Mises would countenance economic
agents registering their values economically, that is, by deciding to purchase or not (e.g. as a
protest against polluting companies), thereby converting all values into economic ones, whereas
Schutz would call for a process negotiating the boundaries between different life-world value
domains.

In “Concept and Theory Formation in the Social Sciences,” Schutz addressed the broader issue of
the relationship between philosophy and the social sciences in general. In that essay, Schutz
responded to Ernest Nagel’s positivistic view that the social sciences should make use of natural
scientific methods, identifying evidence with sensory observable data and criticizing the Weberian
method of “understanding” as appealing to uncontrollable and unverifiable introspection. Schutz
agreed with Nagel on several counts, namely that social scientists needed to validate theoretical
beliefs, that lack of predictability in the social sciences did not disqualify their scientific character,
and that Weber would have been wrong if his method of “subjective interpretation” implied
empathy with unobservable, introspective states. The problem was, though, that the natural
scientific approach to the social sciences, insofar as it separated verifiable observable behavior
from unverifiable inner states (purposes, emotions), seemed to play on the map drawn by
Descartes who divorced body from mind and allowed only statements about the former to be
scientifically verifiable. Further, the natural scientific approach depended on a basic
presupposition since without first examining the object of social science—social reality, in
Schutz’s terms—one would be simply presupposing that the methods of the natural sciences were
appropriate to its study. Therefore, Schutz attempted first to clarify social reality, described in
depth by his own phenomenology of the social world, and to indicate how actors sustain that
reality by understanding each other’s in-order-to motives in typical terms (e.g., going to school,
making a purchase, marrying). Such mutual understanding takes place without either somehow or
other penetrating into the other’s private, inner sanctum, or reducing the other to the status of
animal organism responding to stimuli. Given this account of social reality, in which actors give
meaning to their world, as opposed to physical reality whose objects (e.g., electrons, quarks) do
not interpret their world, Schutz argued that the appropriate social scientific method involved
developing constructs of everyday actor’s constructs. Social scientific constructs, ideal types in
Weber’s sense, aimed at capturing the subjective meaning of the actor, that is, according to
Weber’s intentions, the meaning of the actor as opposed to the social scientist and not some
introspective inner process. Schutz conceived statistical and other formulations of social scientific
laws as a legitimate kind of intellectual shorthand, always presupposing the meaningful activity
of the individual social actor, the “forgotten man” of the social sciences (Schutz 1964, 6–7). To
ensure the kind of validation that Nagel sought, mistakenly though, by restricting himself to
sensory observable data, Schutz proposed that social scientists displace their everyday practical
interests in favor of a guiding interest in accurate scientific description and observe postulates of
logical consistency and adequacy to the experiences described.

In order to elucidate the meaning of rational action, Schutz hypothesized what a rational actor
would have to know, even though such completely rational actions might never be realized in
everyday life. Such an actor would have to know: an end’s relationship with other ends, the
consequences and by-products of realizing an end, the means suitable for the end, the interaction
of such means with other ends and means, and the accessibility of those means. In addition, the
rational actor would need to understand: her interactors’ understanding of all the previous factors,
the interpretation of her act by others, the reactions of other people and their motivation, and the
useful categories she had already discovered in the social world. Although social scientists might
use such models of completely rational action to assess the rationality of everyday actors, Schutz
cautioned social scientists that if their task were to describe life-world actors, they also needed to
be wary of replacing the viewpoint of everyday actors with a fictional, non-existing world
constructed by scientific observers. In fact, a central point of discussion in the published
correspondence between Schutz and Talcott Parsons concerned the subjective viewpoint of the
actor, whose sub-acts, for example, could not be adequately understood without comprehending
the actor’s overarching project, whose temporal span is at first accessible only to that actor.
Finally, it should be noted that Schutz himself produced two pieces of applied research in which
he constructed ideal types of the Stranger and the Homecomer, taking account of what their
experiences meant to them instead of what social scientists or others might think they meant.

3.3 Other Philosophies


Although references to philosophers in the pragmatist tradition, such as John Dewey and George
Herbert Mead are scattered through Schutz’s writings, it was to William James that he devoted his
first full-length essay after arriving in the United States. Briefly alluding to the methodological
differences between Husserl and James, he emphasized two points where the “great masters”
converged: the stream of thought and the theory of fringes. Both thinkers stressed that personal
consciousness involves no multiplicity of elements needing to be reunited, but rather a unity from
which one separates out components, and they each examined the modifications that reflection
introduces into the lived stream, converting an “I” into a “Me” or uncovering the workings of
intentionality. Further, Husserl’s idea that the kernel of meaning distinguishing an object stood out
against the unthematized network of relationships that makes up its horizon parallelled James’s
belief that topics have their “fringes.” Such fringes connect a topic with other experiences, such
that, for instance, one does not hear merely “thunder,” but “thunder-breaking-in-upon-silence-
and-contrasting-with-it.” Similarly, the Jamesian idea about grasping as a unity what must be
learned through a many-stepped processes, such as the Pythagorean theorem, could be translated
into the Husserlian terminology regarding the monothetical grasping of polythetic processes.
Likewise, James’s discussion of focusing on an object within a broader topic resembled Husserl’s
view that one could discern a noema, that is, a perspectival aspect through which a thing
constituted of many such aspects presented itself.

Another American philosopher to whom Schutz dedicated an entire essay was George Santayana,
whose Dominations and Powers he reviewed. While most of the essay was expository, Schutz
praised Santayana’s effort to base politics on a philosophical anthropology and his insights into
the enslaving potential of technology. However, Schutz, no doubt convinced by Mises’s positive
assessment of economic activity, resisted Santayana’s reduction of it to domination. Likewise, as
a phenomenologist opposed to a Santayana’s naturalistic founding of spirit on the physical order
of nature, Schutz dissented from a conviction derived from this naturalism, namely, that
democracy could solve it problems only by returning to the “generative order” of agriculture.

Besides these interchanges with American philosophers, Schutz (later in his career) interpreted
the work of Max Scheler and (earlier) engaged thoroughly his treatment of intersubjectivity, a
topic that Schutz insisted was to be treated within the natural attitude, in which one never doubted
the existence of others. Schutz agreed with Scheler’s belief that the “We” is given prior to the
“I”—a position that the latter defended on the basis of the psychology of children and cultures
less accustomed to self-reflection. Schutz supported this priority, however he did so on the
grounds that while living in one’s acts in the natural attitude and living also in the other’s present
experience as it unfolds, one at first does not clearly distinguish one’s own thoughts from others’.
Nevertheless, as soon as one reflects on his own stream of consciousness—and children and
cultures may develop this capacity for self-reflection later—he becomes aware that his
experiences are his own. Schutz found plausible Scheler’s belief in the inner (indubitable)
perception of the other, if “inner perception” refers to anything connected with mental life or if
one locates the experience of living in the vivid simultaneity of the “We” within his own
conscious stream, as Schutz believed possible. However much in that vivid simultaneity one
might be unable to doubt the other’s existence, one could still be mistaken about specific thoughts
of the others, since by belonging to the other’s stream of consciousness these thoughts share the
dubitability characterizing outer perceptions, likewise transcendent to one’s stream of experience.

Another figure, more or less within the phenomenological tradition, whose views on
intersubjectivity Schutz examined and criticized, was Jean-Paul Sartre, particularly the Sartre of
Being and Nothingness. In “Sartre’s Theory of the Alter Ego,” Schutz elucidated Sartre’s attempt
to develop an extra-empirical, real communication with the other that avoids the extremes of an
empiricist intersubjectivity beginning with the other’s body and an idealist reduction of the other
to a series of presentations. After explaining Sartre’s differences regarding intersubjectivity with
Husserl, Hegel, and Heidegger, Schutz laid out Sartre’s existential account of how the other is
given as a subject through the Look and how one can in turn objectify the other by returning the
gaze. Although Sartre had intended to describe how one’s body is given to the other, he instead
portrayed how the other’s body is given to oneself, assuming that such descriptions were
reversible. Schutz, who did not believe that the problem of intersubjectivity could be addressed
adequately within the transcendental sphere, applauded Sartre’s rejection of Husserl’s
transcendental approach to intersubjectivity; however, Sartre’s emphasis on the other as a center
of activity reflected a continuing Husserlian influence. The main problem, though, with Sartre’s
doctrine was that its starting point in a mutual looking, by which each subject reduces the other to
an object, precluded any possibility of a relationship between the I-subject and other-subject.
Further, Schutz wondered how Sartre would know that the other’s body was given to him in the
same way that his body was to the other if the other’s subjectivity escaped his “I.” Moreover,
Schutz acknowledged that the other’s interests might not coincide with his own, but he failed to
see how this fact entailed that either the other or he reduce each other to a utensil. Instead, he
pointed to the “mutual tuning-in” to be found in making music together and in language as proof
that subjects interact as “co-performing subjectivities” and that mutual interaction in freedom
better describes intersubjectivity than Sartre’s practical solipsism.

3.4 Applications
In 1945, Schutz published an essay, “On Multiple Realities,” that extended the theory of The
Phenomenology of the Social World and anticipated later essays applying that theory. While he
reiterated earlier views about levels of activity, Bergsonian tensions of consciousness, and the
structure of the social world, his work took a decidedly pragmatic twist, emphasizing “working”
(Wirken) as involving bodily movements as opposed to the covert performances of mere thinking.
In manuscripts in the 1930s and after The Phenomenology of the Social World, Schutz had already
turned in this pragmatic direction. In “On Multiple Realities,” he enlarged upon the “world of
working” by demonstrating how reflection dissolves the self unified in lived action into partial,
role-taking selves and by expanding Mead’s idea of the “manipulatory sphere” to include worlds
within “potential reach,” either restorable (from the past) or attainable (in the future). This “world
of working” constitutes the paramount reality, organized in its interests in the face of the
fundamental anxiety that derives, as it did for Heidegger, from the inescapability of one’s own
death. Following Husserl’s views on how consciousness can modify its stances toward reality and
de-ontologizing James’s sub-universes of reality, Schutz developed the notion of various finite
provinces of meaning. One enters any of these provinces, such as those of phantasms, dreams, the
theater, religious experience, or theoretical contemplation, by undergoing different types of
epoché, analogous to the phenomenological protoype, as when one slips into a daydream, falls
asleep, watches theater curtains open, commences a ritual, or assumes the scientist’s role. Each
province contains its distinctive logical, temporal, corporal, and social dimensions, and movement
between the provinces only becomes paradoxical (e.g., asking how phenomenologists are able to
communicate their private findings publicly) if one conceives the provinces as ontological static
realms to which one transmigrates as a soul to another world. Rather the provinces are permeable,
and one adopts the attitudes of scientist or religious believer within the world of working as if it
were seen through by another viewpoint, all the while that its communicative activities subtend
these other provinces. There is something paradoxical, though, about describing one’s dreams or
theorizing about religious experience since to give an account one must absent oneself from the
province for which one accounts, and Kierkegaard’s notion of indirect communication and
various postmodern critiques of theory address themselves to just such paradoxes.

The essay on multiple realities underpins Schutz’s theory of signs and symbols in “Symbol,
Reality, and Society,” published almost ten years later. Synthesizing the notion of potential reach
from the earlier essay with Husserl’s concept of appresensation, namely that one element of a pair
refers to another not directly given in experience, Schutz describes how agents overcome
whatever transcends them. Hence they leave marks to bring within reach what they leave behind
(e.g., breaking a twig to remind oneself to turn when one returns) or follow indications, that is,
regular connections not of their making (e.g. smoke indicating a not yet visible fire), to bring
within their knowledge what lies beyond it. Signs, however, appresent in an intersubjective setting
the meanings of one person to another, but an insuperable transcendence still remains insofar as
the each one’s stream of consciousness and therefore meanings are never identical with another’s.
Finally, through symbols, developed within groups, something given within everyday reality
appresents a reality belonging to a entirely different province of meaning, an ultimate
transcendence (e.g., the stone where Jacob dreamed of a ladder to heaven memorializes God,
accessible within the religious province of meaning).

Schutz dealt with this theme of language in other contexts, comparing Husserl’s distinction
between prepredicative (prepropositional) and predicative levels with Kurt Goldstein’s separation,
based on studies of brain lesions, of a concrete attitude relying on automatic speech associations
from an abstract attitude forming propositions and utilizing rational language. Husserl’s
prepredicative/predicative differentiation plays a key role in Schutz’s essay “Type and Eidos in
Husserl’s Late Philosophy,” in which he shows a gradual development from empirical types
passively constituted within the prepredicative sphere to presumptive universals spontaneously
formed in the predicative sphere. At the predicative level, scientific reflection further transforms
nonessential types (e.g., that whales are fish) into essential ones (whales are mammals), and
philosophy seeks eidetic universals. At the end of this essay, Schutz speculates whether the
Husserlian method of freely varying examples to determine the essential features that survive
through such variations is not constrained by both ontological structure (e.g., sounds are not
colors) and the socially shaped, natural-attitude experience of types. In his essay “Tiresias, or our
Knowledge of Future Events,” produced contemporaneously with the type essay, Schutz explains
how knowledge based on natural attitude types functions in contrast to the mythical Tiresias’
knowledge of the future, which is private and detached from his present or past experience. These
types, based on past experiences or socially transmitted, aim at future occurrences not in their
uniqueness but with an emptiness that future events will fill in, such that only in retrospect, after
an event occurs, is one able to determine how much that event was expected or unexpected.
Finally, there are future events lying beyond one’s influence that one expects only to conform
with past experience and there are indeterminate projects that provide direction—not too tightly,
though—as one gives shape to what is within one’s power.

Schutz, himself a trained pianist and widely read musicologist, integrated his phenomenology
with his understanding of music. Music, differing from language in being non-representative,
lends itself to phenomenological analysis in the meaning it carries beyond its mere physical
nature as sound waves and in its character as an ideal object that must be constituted through its
unfolding stages, i.e., polythetically. Further music is bound to inner temporality, and its themes,
even though their note sequences are the same, vary according to context, require reflection for
their recognition, and emerge through an interplay between musical elements and the listener’s
attention and interest. Schutz found music instructive in regard to social relationships insofar as,
prior to any communication, parties to musical performances establish a non-linguistic, non-
conceptual “mutual tuning in relationship.” This “tuning-in,” this sharing of another’s flux of
experience in inner time already described in his Phenomenology, is very clearly exhibited
whenever a listener to a musical performance participates in quasi-simultaneity in the composer’s
stream of consciousness or when co-performers orient themselves to each other, the composer,
and the audience. Hence, Schutz disagreed with Maurice Halbwachs who posited musical
notation as the basis of social relationships between performers, when in fact it is merely a
technical device accidental to their relationship. In another essay, Schutz depicted Mozart as a
social scientist, presenting a succession of situations that different characters interpret, and Schutz
showed how orchestral representations of characters and their moods in melody made possible a
simultaneity of fluxes of inner time that the non-operatic, nonmusical dramatist could only unfold
successively. Without self-consciously philosophizing, Mozart conveyed in music and better than
most philosophers in their own medium, how human beings meet each other as a “We.”

Fred Kersten discovers in Schutz’s musical writings important philosophical insights. For
instance, music and inner time unfold polythetically and cannot be grasped monothetically; that
is, one must live through the unfolding of a symphony or inner experience, and any conceptual
summary of their contents inevitably fails to do justice to their meaning. However, since all
conceptualization consists in a monothetical grasping of polythetic stages, Schutz is actually
realizing that certain dimensions of consciousness elude conceptualization and thus demarcating
the limits of rationalization, just as he had pointed out how certain provinces of meaning (e.g.
dreams) evade theoretic comprehension or duration eludes memory. According to Kersten, Schutz
has seen clearly that the passive associations of listening (e.g. recognizing the appearance of
symphonic theme) differ from those of sight (e.g., apprehending an object like a house) and that
listening does not identify numerically distinct items but produces an illusion of identification.
Schutz’s conclusion that sameness in music involves not numerical unity but recurrent likeness
challenges the fundamental Husserlian thesis that the synthesis of passive identification is
universal, at the basis of the constitution of the world.

Schutz was also a master of literature, a careful student of the works of Goethe, and author of an
article that analyzed Miguel de Cervantes’s Don Quixote through the prism of the theory of
multiple realities. Cervantes repeatedly brings Quixote’s “world of chivalry”—an order of reality
with its arguments for its own reality, its stock of knowledge, modes of social reinforcement, and
views about space, time, and causality—into conflict with the worlds of drama, common sense,
and science. Although Quixote is capable of constructing a defense of his own chivalrous world
from within that world, the fact that this phantasied world contains an enclave of dreams (at the
cave of Montesinos) ends up undermining it by raising the possibility that it itself is but a dream.
Quixote’s withdrawal of the accent of reality from his private province of meaning reveals for
Schutz the importance of the paramount reality of everyday life and the value of Sancho Panza
who “remains deeply rooted in the heritage of common sense.” (Schutz 1964, 158)

Schutz also brought his phenomenology to bear on political issues such as citizenship or racial
equality. His essay “The Well-Informed Citizen,” dealing not only with citizenship but also the
sociology of knowledge under the rubric of the social distribution of knowledge, constructs ideal
types of the expert, the man on the street, and the well-informed citizen (to whom it falls to
determine which experts are competent). Schutz delineates various zones of interests, or
relevances, extending from those within reach to those absolutely irrelevant, comments on the
constant changeability of relevance configurations, and differentiates between relevances intrinsic
to a theme, which one chooses, and those imposed. Paradoxically, as modernity’s rationalization
processes heighten anonymity, modern technology also brings everyone within reach, as the
nuclear arms race demonstrates, and Schutz suggests as a solution that citizens become broadly
informed rather than succumb to the narrow dogmatism of the man on the street or the short-
sighted specialization of experts. In becoming well-informed, one depends on knowledge socially
derived through the consultation of eyewitnesses, insiders, analysts, and commentators,
depending on their access to facts and governing relevances, much as Alvin Goldman’s social
epistemology involves appraising the veritistic value of assorted agents’ claims and practices.
Schutz, usually the value-free describer of social reality, in his conclusion endorses a normative
notion of democracy in which it is a duty and a privilege, frequently not available in non-
democratic societies, for well-informed citizens to express and defend opinions that often conflict
with the uninformed opinions of the man in the street.

Schutz composed “Equality and the Meaning Structure of the Social World” at the time of the
legal decision of Brown v. Board of Education that ended racially segregated education in the
United States. With typical dispassion, Schutz explains how the meaning of the term “equality”
depends on the domain of relevances to which it pertains (e.g., economic equality, equality of
civil rights, etc.) and on the in-group or out-group utilizing it—and here he conceives
interpretation in terms of groups rather than individuals. He spends most of the essay contrasting
subjective and objective interpretations of group membership, equality, and equality of
opportunity, construing “subjective” and “objective” in terms of in-group and out-group
interpretations. As regards group membership, he illustrates that the mere categorization of
another as a member of a group need not be discriminatory, but depends upon an appropriate
evaluation of the category from the viewpoint of the categorized individual. In-groups and out-
groups differ in whether they understand equality merely as “formal,” i.e., as nondiscrimination,
or “real,” calling for special rights and services. Similarly groups think of equality of opportunity
from an out-group perspective as “the career open to all” without appreciating how in-group
members might subjectively experience insuperable obstacles in trying to avail themselves of
opportunities supposedly objectively equal. In this essay, Schutz is concerned not to present a
final definition of equality, but to highlight the differences between in-group and out-group
understandings that serve as the preconditions of any discussion about it.

Some recently published texts that Schutz authored during an ethics institute in 1956 make
possible an even richer awareness of his views on politics. In these documents, he recognizes the
complex, unforeseen consequences resulting from social change, urges active engagement with
others as crucial for developing social and civil judgment, and examines the barriers to sound
civil judgment created by government, political parties, pressure organizations, mass media, and
educational, familial, religious, and professional institutions. At one point, he even criticizes
views that limit democracy to mere majoritarian rule insofar as they neglect the importance of the
single individual’s ability “to make his personal opinion be heard and appreciated,” preferably in
smaller publics, such as families, schools, local communities (cited in L. Embree 1999, 271). One
could take Schutz’s thoughts here to converge with political theories favoring what is today
known as deliberative democracy. Moroever, his normative judgment against implementations of
democracy that increase the anonymity of citizens suggests that a parallel normative, even ethical,
dimension informs his many theoretic endeavors to retrieve from anonymity the neglected
subjective viewpoint of actors, whether strangers, homecomers, victims of discrimination, or the
“forgotten man” of social sciences.

3.5 Phenomenology
Schutz’s philosophical targeting of the social world had its repercussions upon phenomenology,
particularly in his critique near the end of his career of Husserl’s account (also referred to as a
“transcendental constitution”) of how the other person comes to appearance in consciousness. In
“The Problem of Transcendental Intersubjectivity in Husserl,” Schutz first objected when Husserl
in his Fifth Cartesian Mediation prepared the ground for the other’s appearance in consciousness
by the methodology of screening off everything that referred to other minds. Husserl had begun
the Cartesian Meditations by reflectively abstaining from believing in the existence of what
appeared in experience in order to refrain from any dogmatic suppositions, but since this first
epoché, or phenomenological reduction, still left meanings with intersubjective references, the
screening off methodology, or second epoché, became necessary. For Husserl, one’s actual or
potential experiences of correlates that were not properly of the ego still would belong to one’s
sphere of ownness, but one had to seek to exclude any reference those correlates, as products of
the sense-determining of other subjectivities, might have to those other subjectivities. For Schutz,
however, insofar as those experiences of what was not properly of the ego, supposedly confined
within the sphere of ownness, had their origin in the intersubjective world of everyday life that
higher level phenomenological reflection presupposed, it seemed difficult to see how one could
exclude from such correlates any reference to the sense-determinining of other subjectivities. It
was as though Husserl was striving for a theoretical detachment that the ontological origins of
theory would not allow. In addition, for Schutz the very consciousness of another inevitably
instituted a relationship with her. Husserl’s argument in the Fifth Meditation continued by
affirming that a non-ratiocinative “pairing” occurred through which one transferred the sense
“another living body” to another. One could then verify that the other’s living body was like one’s
own if it continued manifesting behavior congruent with what one would expect of a living body.
Schutz challenged this sense-transfer, however, since one experienced the other’s body from the
outside, unlike one’s own, which was given interiorily (but might the similarities suffice for the
transfer?), and he suggested that verification through what was “congruent” behavior drew on
social-world presuppositions of how bodies ought to behave. Finally, he questioned whether the
philosopher, refraining from belief in the existence of the world or others and entering into a
certain reflective solitude, could ever experience the transcendental community of which Husserl
spoke, since she only constituted the world for herself and not for all other transcendental egos.
Intersubjectivity, Schutz concluded, was a matter of everyday life to be simply described and not
to be constituted within the transcendental sphere of a self-reflective consciousness giving an
account of how the other comes to appearance. Just as Schutz had argued that the social world
dictated the methods for its own social scientific investigation, so here it seemed to prescribe to
phenomenology the approach appropriate to its description.

In the last thirteen years of his life, Schutz was preparing a comprehensive phenomenology of the
natural attitude, and one manuscript, edited by Richard Zaner, was posthumously published as
Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, and another, co-authored by Thomas Luckmann,
appeared as The Structures of the Life World. The former book distinguishes different sets of
interests, or relevances: topical (which focus attention on themes), interpretive (which confer
meanings on experiences or objects), and motivational. Such relevances often involve a subject,
with more or less systematic interests, or relevances, interacting with the world, and from this
interaction between subject and world, it becomes evident what is “of relevance” to an actor.
These relevances, interdependent on each other and conjoined with one’s system of types or
categories, constitute a stock of knowledge, which Schutz examines in terms of its genesis and
structure. He further explores the meaning of one’s biographical situation, including types and
relevances, one’s body, and the ontological constraints of space and time that, for instance,
prevent one from being at certain places at certain times or compel one to wait (for salt to
dissolve in water).

The Structures of the Life-World represents a most complex and thorough restatement of many of
the themes Schutz addressed throughout his life. After a more general account of the life-world
and its relation to the sciences, the book takes up its various stratifications, such as provinces of
meaning, temporal and spatial zones of reach, and social structure. Schutz and Luckmann then
comment on the components of one’s stock of knowledge, including learned and non-learned
elements, relevances and types, and trace the build-up of such a stock. The authors study the
social conditioning of one’s subjective stock of knowledge and inquire about the social stock of
knowledge of a group and different possible combinations of knowledge distribution (generalized
and specialized). They consider how subjective knowledge becomes embodied in a social stock of
knowledge and how the latter influences the former. In addition, the authors pursue such issues as
the structures of consciousness and action, the choosing of projects, rational action, and forms of
social action, whether such action be unilateral or reciprocal, immediate or mediate. A final
section analyzes the boundaries of experience, different degrees of transcendencies (from simply
bringing an object within reach to the experience of death), and the mechanisms for crossing
boundaries (e.g. symbols).

In the years after Schutz’s death in 1959, his works have been posthumously published and his
thought expanded in several directions. Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann wrote The Social
Construction of Reality, which focused on how subjective human processes construct objective
structures that human subjectivity in turn interprets and reacts to and which was among the most
widely read books of social science in the twentieth century. Ilja Srubar emphasized the
importance of the pragmatic dimensions of Schutz’s corpus, just as Hans-Georg Soeffner, along
with Jochen Dreher, has developed its symbolic aspects. On Schutzian grounds, Lester Embree
produced a theory of science in the model of a Wissenschaftslehre, and George Psathas extended
Schutz’s thought in the direction of ethnomethodology and conversation analysis. Recently,
sociologists Hubert Knoblauch and Carlos Belvedere have shown the relevance of Schutz’s
framework to communication theory and questions of social ontology, respectively. The Austrian
Economic School has continued to make use of Schutz’s works, as Daniela Griselda López has
shown. López and Dreher have further argued that Schutzian theory can adequately account for
the exercise of institutional power through the interplay between objective structures and
subjective meaning-interpretation and the idea of relevances that are imposed upon agents.
Michael Staudigl and George Berguno have edited a collection of essays on the connection
between the Schutzian approach and various hermeneutic traditions. And Staudigl and Michael
Barber have highlighted the connections between Schutz’s philosophy of multiple realities and
religion and humor. Furthermore, collections of essays have addressed the value of Schutz’s
paradigm for music, literature, and the arts. The work of Alfred Schutz opens a wide field that is
fruitful for addressing multiple themes and underpinning and supporting multiple disciplines.

Bibliography
Works by Schutz

1932, Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt: Eine Einleitung in die verstehenden Soziologie,
Vienna: Springer (also in 1960) and Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1974; English translation: The
Phenomenology of the Social World, G. Walsh and F. Lehnert (trans.), Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1967.
1962, Collected Papers I: The Problem of Social Reality, Maurice Natanson (ed.), The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
1964, Collected Papers II: Studies in Social Theory, Arvid Brodersen (ed.), The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff.
1966, Collected Papers III: Studies in Phenomenological Philosophy, I. Schutz (ed.), The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
1970, On Phenomenology and Social Relations: Selected Writings, H. Wagner (ed.), Chicago:
University of Chicago Press.
1971, Reflections on the Problem of Relevance, R.M. Zaner (ed.), New Haven: Yale University
Press.
1972, “Choice and the Social Sciences,” in Lester Embree (ed.), Life-World and Consciousness,
Evanston: Northwestern University Press, 565–596.
1973, (with T. Luckmann), The Structures of the Life-World, R.M. Zaner and T. Engelhardt
(trans.), Evanston: Northwestern University Press, and London: Heinemann; German
edition: Strukturen der Lebenswelt, vol. 1, Neuwied: Luchterhand, 1975; vol. 2: The
Structures of the Life-World, R.M. Zaner and David J. Parent (trans.), Evanston:
Northwestern University Press, 1983; German edition: Strukturen der Lebenswelt, vol. 2,
Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1984.
1976, “Fragments on the Phenomenology of Music” in In Search of Musical Method, F.J. Smith
(ed.), London, New York, and Paris: Gordon and Breach Science Publishers, 23–71.
1978, (with T. Parsons), The Theory of Social Action: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and
Talcott Parsons, R. Grathoff (ed.), Bloomington and London: Indiana University Press;
German edition: Zur Theorie sozialen Handelns: Briefwechsel/Alfred Schutz, Talcott
Parsons, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1977.
1982, Life Forms and Meaning Structure, H. Wagner (trans., ed.), London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul; German edition: Theorie der Lebensformen, I. Srubar (ed.), Frankfurt: Suhrkamp,
1981.
1989, (with A. Gurwitsch), Philosophers in Exile: The Correspondence of Alfred Schutz and
Aron Gurwitsch, 1939–1959, R. Grathoff (ed.), J.C. Evans (trans.), Bloomington and
Indianapolis: Indiana University Press.
1996, Collected Papers IV, H. Wagner and G. Psathas (eds.), in collaboration with F. Kersten,
Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
1997, “Positivistic Philosophy and the Actual Approach of Interpretative Social Science: An
Ineditum of Alfred Schutz from Spring 1953,” L. Embree (ed.), Husserl Studies, 14: 123–
149.
1999, “Some Considerations concerning Thinking in Terms of Barriers,” “Memorandum (to
Doctor Harold Lasswell),” “Report on the Discussions of Barrier to Equality of Opportunity
for the Development of Power of Social and Civil Judgment,” “Letter of Alfred Schutz to
Clarence H. Faust, The Fund for the Advancement of Education,” all in L. Embree, “The
Ethical Political Side of Schutz: His Contributions at the 1956 Institute on Ethics concerned
with Barriers to Equality of Opportunity,” in Schutzian Social Science, L. Embree (ed.),
Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishing, 235–318.
2003, Theorie der Lebenswelt 1: Die pragmatische Schichtung der Lebenswelt, M. Endress and I.
Srubar (eds.), vol. 5,1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar
(eds.), Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2003, Theorie der Lebenswelt 2: Die kommunikative Ordnung der Lebenswelt, H. Knoblauch, R.
Kurt, and H-G. Soeffner (eds.), vol. 5,2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G.
Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2004, (with Eric Voegelin), Eine Freundschaft, die ein Leben ausgehalten hat: Briefwechsel
1938–1959, G. Wagner and G. Weiss (eds.), Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
Translated as A Friendship that Lasted a Lifetime: The Correspondence Between Alfred
Schutz and Eric Voegelin, 2011, G. Wagner and G. Weiss (eds.), trans. W. Petropulos,
Columbia: University of Missouri Press.
2004, Der sinnhafte Aufbau der sozialen Welt: Eine Einleitung in die verstehende Soziologie, M.
Endress and J. Renn (eds.), vol 2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner,
and I. Srubar; Redaction, M. Endress (eds.), Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2004, Relevanz und Handeln 1: Zur Phänomenologie des Alltagswissens, E. List (ed.), vol. 6,1:
Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M.
Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2005, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 2: Studien zu Scheler, James, und Sartre, H.
Kellner und J. Renn (eds.), vol. 3,2: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner,
and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2006, Sinn und Zeit: Frühe Wiener Arbeiten und Entwürfe, M. Michailow (ed.), vol. 1: Alfred
Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M.
Endress/G. Sebald, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2009, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 1: Zur Kritik der Phänomenologie Edmund
Husserls, G. Sebald (ed.) in collaboration with R. Grathoff and T. Michael; Redaction, G.
Sebald, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2009, “Private Family Journal of First Trip to the United States of America,” Evelyn S. Lang
(trans.), Schutzian Research, 1: 245–271.
2009, “Understanding, Self-reflection, and Equality: Alfred Schutz’s Participation in the 1955
Conference on Science, Philosophy, and Religion,” ed. Michael Barber, Schutzian Research,
1: 273–291.
2009, Philosophisch-phänomenologische Schriften 1: Zur Kritik der Phänomenologie Edmund
Husserls, Gerd Sebald (ed.) based on preliminary work by Richard Grathoff and Michael
Thomas, vol. 3,1: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar
(eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2010, Zur Methodologie der Sozialwissenschaften, Thomas S. Eberle, Jochen Dreher and Gerd
Sebald (eds.), Vol 4: Alfred Schütz Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar
(eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2010, “The Problem of Transcendental Intersubjectivity in Husserl(with Comments of Dorion
Cairns and Eugen Fink),” Fred Kersten (trans.), Schutzian Research, 2: 9–51.
2010, “Problems of a Sociology of Language”(Fall Semester, 1958), Fred Kersten (ed.), Schutzian
Research, 2: 53–105.
2011, Relevanz und Handeln 2: Fremdheit, Gesellschaftliches Wissen und politisches Handeln,
Andreas Göttlich, Gerd Sebald and Jan Weyand (eds.), Vol. 6(2): Alfred Schütz
Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress,
Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2011, Collected Papers V. Phenomenology and the Social Sciences, Lester E. Embree (ed.),
Dordrecht: Springer.
2011, “Interview with Dr. Alfred Schutz,” (November 20, 1958 New York City), Interviewed
Bettina Bien Greaves, Schutzian Research, 3: 23–30.
2012, Collected Papers VI. Literary Reality and Relationships, Michael D. Barber (ed.),
Dordrecht: Springer.
2013, Schriften zur Literatur, Michael D. Barber and Jochen Dreher (eds.), Vol. 8: Alfred Schütz
Werkausgabe, R. Grathoff, H-G. Soeffner, and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress,
Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
2013, “Fragment of a Phenomenology of Rhythm,” Gerd Sebald and Jasmin Schreyer
(transcription, ed., & trans.), Schutzian Research, 5: 11–22.
2016, Schriften zur Musik, ed. Gerd Sebald and Andreas Georg Stascheit, Vol. 7, Alfred Schütz
Werkausgabe, H-G. Soeffner and I. Srubar (eds.); Redaction, M. Endress, Cologne: Herbert
von Halem Verlag.

Secondary Literature
Barber, M., 1989, Social Typifications and the Elusive Other: The Place of Sociology of
Knowledge in Alfred Schutz’s Phenomenology, Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press and
London and Toronto: Associated University Presses.
–––, 2004, The Participating Citizen: A Biography of Alfred Schutz, Albany: State University of
New York Press.
–––, 2017, Religion and Humor as Emancipating Provinces of Meaning, Dordrecht: Springer.
Barber, M. and Dreher, J. (eds.), 2014, The Interrelation of Phenomenology, Social Sciences and
the Arts, Dordrecht: Springer.
Belvedere, C., 2016, “Lester Embree on Collective Subjects,” Schutzian Research, 9: 79–84.
Berger, P.L. and Luckmann, T., 1967, The Social Construction of Reality, Garden City, New York:
Doubleday Anchor.
Bergson, H. 1889, Essai sur les données de la conscience, Paris: Félix Alcan; English translation:
Time and Free Will: An Essay on the Immediate Data of Consciousness, trans. by F.L.
Pogson, London: George Allen and Unwin, 1921.
Bernstein, R.J., 1976, The Restructuring of Social and Political Theory, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Brandom, R., 1994, Making It Explicit, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Cox, R.R., 1978, Schutz’s Theory of Relevance: A Phenomenological Critique, The Hague:
Martinus Nijhoff.
Dreher, J., 2011, “Alfred Schutz,” The Wiley-Blackwell Companion to Major Social Theorists,
Volume 1: Classical Social Theorists, ed. G. Ritzer and J. Stepnisky, West Sussex: Wiley-
Blackwell, 489–510.
Dreher, J. and López, D. G, 2015, “Subjectivity and Power,” Human Studies, 38: 197–222.
Eberle,T.S., 1984, Sinnkonstitution in Alltag und Wissenschaft: Der Beitrag der Phänomenologie
und die Methodologie der Sozialwissenschaften, Bern and Stuttgart: Paul Haupt.
Embree, L., ed., 1988, Worldly Phenomenology: The Continuing Influence of Alfred Schutz On
North American Human Science, Washington, D.C.: Center for Advanced Research in
Phenomenology and University Press of America.
–––, 1999, “The Ethical-Political Side of Schutz: His Contributions at the 1956 Institute on Ethics
concerned with Barriers to Equality of Opportunity,” in Schutzian Social Science, ed. L.
Embree, Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 235–318.
–––, 2013, Alfred Schutz’s “Sociological Aspect of Literature”, Dordrecht: Springer.
–––, 2015, The Schutzian Theory of the Cultural Sciences, Dordrecht: Springer.
Embree, L., and Barber M. (eds.), 2017, The Golden Age of Phenomenology at the New School
for Social Research, 1954–1973, Athens, Ohio: Ohio University Press.
Endress, M., 2006, Alfred Schütz, Konstanz: UVK.
Endress, M; Psathas, G.; and Nasu, H. (eds.), 2004, Explorations of the Life-World: Continuing
Dialogues with Alfred Schutz, Dordrecht: Springer.
Grathoff, R., 1989, Milieu und Lebenswelt, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
–––, and B. Waldenfels, 1983, Sozialität und Intersubjektivität: Phänomenologische Perspektiven
der Sozialwissenschaften im Umkreis von Aron Gurwitsch und Alfred Schütz, Munich:
Wilhelm Fink.
Gurwitsch, A., 1979, Human Encounters in the Social World, ed. A.Métraux and trans. F.
Kersten, Pittsburgh: Duquesne University Press, 1979.
Habermas, J., 1987, The Theory of Communicative Action, 2 vols., trans. T. McCarthy, Boston:
Beacon Press.
–––, 1988, On the Logic of the Social Sciences, trans. S.W. Nicholsen and J. A. Stark, Cambridge,
Mass.: MIT Press.
Husserl, E., 1969, Formal and Transcendental Logic, trans. D.Cairns, The Hague: Martinus
Nijhoff.
–––, 1973, Cartesian Meditations, trans. D. Cairns, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
–––, 1973, Experience and Judgment: Investigations in a Genealogy of Logic, ed. L. Landgrebe,
trans. J. S. Churchill and K. Ameriks, Evanston: Northwestern University Press.
–––, 1990, On the Phenomenology of the Consciousness of Internal Time (1893–1917); trans. J.B.
Brough, Dordrecht, Boston, London: Kluwer Academic Publishers.
James, W., 1893, The Principles of Psychology, 2 vols., New York: Henry Holt.
Kersten, F., 1976, “Preface” to “Fragments on the Phenomenology of Music” in In Search of
Musical Method, ed. F.J. Smith, London, New York, and Paris: Gordon and Breach Science
Publishers, 6–22.
Knoblauch, H., 2013, “Alfred Schutz’s Theory of Communicative Action,” Human Studies, 36:
323–327.
List, E. and Srubar, I. (eds.), 1988, Alfred Schuütz : Neue Beiträge zur Rezeption seines Werkes,
Amsterdam : Rodopi.
López, D. G., 2016, “The Epistemic Claim to the Life-world: Alfred Schutz and the Debates of
the Austrian School of Economics,” The Review of Austrian Economics, 29: 177–203.
Luckmann, T., 1983, Life-World and Social Realities, London: Heinemann.
–––, 2007, Lebenswelt, Identität, und Gesellschaft, Konstanz: UVK.
McDowell, J., 1994, Mind and World, Cambridge, Mass: Harvard University Press.
Mises, L. 1960, Epistemological Problems of Economics, trans. G. Reisman, Princeton, N. J: Van
Nostrand.
–––, 1966, Human Action: A Treatise on Economics, Chicago: H. Regnery Co..
Nasu, H.; Embree, L.; Psathas, G.; and Srubar, I. (eds.), 2009, Alfred Schutz and His Intellectual
Partners, Konstanz: UVK Vergesellschaft, mbH.
Natanson, M., 1986, Anonymity: A Study in the Philosophy of Alfred Schutz, Bloomington,
Indiana: Indiana University Press.
O’Neill, J., 1974, Making Sense Together: An Introduction to Wild Sociology, New York: Harper
and Row.
Parsons, Talcott, 1968, The Structure of Social Action, 2 vols., New York: The Free Press.
Salice, A. and Schmid, H.B. (eds.), 2016, The Phenomenological Approach to Social Reality:
History, Concepts, Problems, Dordrecht: Springer.
Sanna, G.L., 2007, Realizzazione etica del sé in Alfred Schütz: Tra pragmatismo e fenomenologia,
Rome: Armando.
Santayana, G., 1951, Dominations and Powers : Reflections on Liberty, Society, and Government,
New York : C. Scribner’s Sons.
Sartre, J-P., 1956, Being and Nothingness: An Essay on Phenomenological Ontology, trans. H.
Barnes, New York: Philosophical Library.
Scheler, M., 1954, The Nature of Sympathy, trans. P. Heath, New Haven: Yale University Press.
Sellars, W., 1956, “Does Empirical Knowledge Have a Foundation?” in H. Feigl and M. Scriben
(eds.), The Foundations of Science and the Concepts of Psychology and Psychoanalysis,
Minnesota Studies in the Philosophy of Science, vol. 1, Minneapolis: University of
Minnesota Press, 293–300.
Soeffner, H.G., 1997, The World of Rituals: The Interpretation of Everyday Life, New Brunswick:
Transaction Press.
Sprondel, W. M. and R. Grathoff (eds.), 1979, Alfred Schutz und die Idee des Alltags in den
Sozialwissenschaften, Stuttgart: Ferdinand Enke.
Srubar, I., 1988, Kosmion, Die Genese der pragmatischen Lebenswelttheorie von Alfred Schütz
und ihr anthropologischer Hintergrund, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp.
–––, 2007, Phänomenologie und soziologische Theorie: Aufsätze zur pragmatischen
Lebenswelttheorie, Wiesbaden: VS, Verlag für Socialwissenschaften/GWV Fachverlage
GmbH.
Staudigl, M., 2017, “Alfred Schutz and Phenomenology of Religion: Explorations into
Ambiguous Territory,” Human Studies, 40: 491–499.
Staudigl, M. and Berguno, G. (eds.), 2014, Schutzian Phenomenology and Hermeneutic
Traditions, Dordrecht: Springer.
Strassheim, J., 2016, “Type and Spontaneity: Beyond Alfred Schutz’s Theory of the Social
World,” Human Studies, 39: 493–512.
Ten Have, P. and G. Psathas (eds.), 1995, Situated Order: Studies in the Social Organization of
Talk and Embodied Activities, Studies in Ethnomethodology and Conversational Analysis,
no. 3, Washington, D.C.: International Institute for Ethnometholodology and Conversation
Analysis and University Press of America.
Thomason, B.C., 1983, Making Sense of Reification: Alfred Schutz and Constructionist Theory,
London: Macmillan.
Vaitkus, S., 1983, How is Society Possible?, Dordrecht, Boston, and London: Kluwer Academic
Publishers.
Voegelin, E., 1952, The New Science of Politics: An Introduction, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
Wagner, H. R., 1983, Alfred Schutz: An IntellectualBiography, Chicago: University of Chicago
Press.
–––, with I. Srubar, 1983, A Bergsonian Bridge to Phenomenological Psychology, Edmonton:
University of Alberta Press.
Waldenfels, B., 1971, Das Zwischenreich des Dialogs: Sozialphilosophische Untersuchungen in
Anschluss an Edmund Husserl, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Webb, R.B., 1976, The Presence of the Past: John Dewey and Alfred Schutz on the Genesis and
Organization of Experience, Gainesville: University Presses of Florida.
Weber, M., 1978, Economy and Society: An Outline of Interpretive Sociology, trans., E. Fischoff
et al, ed., G.Roth and C. Wittich, 2 vols., Berkeley: University of California Press.
–––, 1958, The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, trans. T. Parsons, New York:
Scribners.
Williame, R., 1973, Les Fondements Phénoménologiques de la Sociologie Comprehénsive: Alfred
Schutz et Max Weber, The Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Wolff, Kurt, ed., 1984, Alfred Schutz: Appraisals and Developments, Dordrecht: Martinus
Nijhoff.
Academic Tools
How to cite this entry.
Preview the PDF version of this entry at the Friends of the SEP Society.
Look up this entry topic at the Indiana Philosophy Ontology Project (InPhO).
Enhanced bibliography for this entry at PhilPapers, with links to its database.

Other Internet Resources


Bibliography of Secondary Sources on Alfred Schutz, Center for Advanced Research in
Phenomenology.
The Alfred Schutz Archive (Department of Sociology/Waseda University)
Schutzian Research

Related Entries
atheism and agnosticism | existentialism | Habermas, Jürgen | Husserl, Edmund | Mead, George
Herbert | phenomenology | Sartre, Jean-Paul | Scheler, Max | Weber, Max

Copyright © 2018 by
Michael Barber <michael.barber@slu.edu>

Open access to the SEP is made possible by a world-wide funding initiative.


Please Read How You Can Help Keep the Encyclopedia Free

The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy is copyright © 2016 by The Metaphysics Research


Lab, Center for the Study of Language and Information (CSLI), Stanford University

Library of Congress Catalog Data: ISSN 1095-5054

You might also like