You are on page 1of 16

The Moral Permissibility of Punishment nevertheless, we can identify a number of features that are commonly

cited as elements of punishment.


The legal institution of punishment presents a distinctive moral
challenge because it involves a state’s infliction of intentionally harsh,
or burdensome, treatment on some of its members—treatment that First, it is generally accepted that punishment involves the infliction of
typically would be considered morally impermissible. Most of us a burden. The state confines people in jails and prisons, where
would agree, for instance, that it is typically impermissible to imprison liberties such as their freedom of movement and association, and their
people, to force them to pay monetary sanctions or engage in privacy, are heavily restricted. It imposes often heavy monetary
community service, or to execute them. The moral challenge of sanctions or forces people to take part in community service work. It
punishment, then, is to establish what (if anything) makes it subjects people to periods of probation during which their movements
permissible to subject those who have been convicted of crimes to and activities are closely supervised. In the most extreme cases, it
such treatment. executes people. Theorists disagree on precisely how to characterize
Traditionally, justifications of punishment have been either this feature of punishment. Some describe punishment as essentially
consequentialist or retributivist. Consequentialist accounts contend painful, or as involving the infliction of suffering, harsh treatment, or
that punishment is justified as a means to securing some valuable harm. Others instead write of punishment as involving the restriction
end—typically crime reduction, by deterring, incapacitating, or of liberties. However we characterize the specific nature of the burden,
reforming offenders. Retributivism, by contrast, holds that it is relatively uncontroversial that punishment in its various forms is
punishment is an intrinsically appropriate (because deserved) burdensome.
response to criminal wrongdoing. Each type of account has been
roundly criticized, on a variety of grounds, by theorists in the other One might object that some prisoners could become accustomed to
camp. In an effort to break this impasse, scholars have attempted to incarceration and so not see it as a burden, or that the masochist
find alternative strategies that incorporate certain consequentialist or might even enjoy his corporal punishment. In response to supposed
retributivist elements but avoid the standard objections directed at counterexamples such as these, a defender of the “burdensomeness”
each. Each of these accounts has, in turn, met with criticism. Finally, feature of punishment might argue that the comfortable prisoner and
abolitionists argue that none of these defenses of punishment is the masochist are still punished insofar as they are treated in ways
satisfactory, and that the practice is morally impermissible; the salient that are typically regarded as burdensome by those on whom they are
question for abolitionists, then, is how else (if at all) society should inflicted. Alternatively, one might argue that a particular case of
respond to those forms of wrongdoing that we now punish. incarceration, corporal punishment, and so forth, indeed does not
count as punishment if the prisoner does not find it burdensome
This article first looks more closely at what punishment is; in (Boonin, 2008: 8-10). Whatever one makes of these attempted
particular, it examines the distinctive features of punishment in virtue counterexamples, it remains the case that punishment theorists by
of which it stands in need of justification. It then highlights various and large agree that burdensomeness is an essential feature of
questions that a full justification of punishment would need to answer. punishment.
With these questions in mind, the article considers the most
prominent consequentialist, retributivist, and hybrid attempts at But punishment is not merely burdensome. A second widely accepted
establishing punishment’s moral permissibility. Finally, it considers feature of punishment is that it is intended to be burdensome. This
the abolitionist alternative. feature distinguishes punishment from other forms of treatment that
may be burdensome but are not intentionally so. Many people
1. What is Punishment? undoubtedly regard it as burdensome to pay their taxes, for instance,
When we consider whether punishment is morally permissible, it is but presumably most do not regard this as a form of punishment. This
important first to be clear about what it is that we are evaluating. is because although taxes may be foreseeably burdensome, they are
Theorists disagree about a precise definition of punishment; not intentionally so. That is, the state does not levy taxes intending for
them to be burdensome; rather, the intention is to pay for roads, an role in the justification of the practice, this expressive function is
education system, and other public goods. That paying for these goods typically accepted as a distinctive feature of punishment.
is burdensome to many taxpayers is incidental, and if there were a way
to collect sufficient revenue to pay for needed public goods without Finally, it is worth highlighting that this article focuses on the legal
this being a burden to taxpayers, then so much the better. institution of punishment—rather than, say, parents’ punishment of
their children or other interpersonal cases of punishment (but see
Punishment, however, is different. Punishment is intended to be Zaibert, 2006). Legal theorists often assert as one of punishment’s
burdensome. If it were not burdensome, then it would not be doing its features that it must be imposed by a properly constituted legal
job. For instance, as we will see below, some theorists contend that the authority (typically, the state). They thereby aim to differentiate legal
aim of punishment is to reduce crime by deterring potential criminals. punishment from private vengeance or vigilantism. This does not
But for the threat of punishment to be the sort of thing likely to deter mean we must accept uncritically that the state is the proper authority
criminals, the punishment itself must be burdensome. Other theorists to impose punishment. Ideally, a full account of punishment should
(retributivists) contend that wrongdoers deserve to suffer, and that provide a plausible answer to why (or if) the state has an exclusive
punishment is justified as the infliction of this deserved suffering. right to impose punishment.
Here again, the burdensomeness of punishment is not merely
incidental, it is intended. These, then, are the most commonly cited features of punishment:
punishment involves the state’s imposition of intended burdens—
Of course, not all impositions of intended burdens count as burdens that express social condemnation—on people (believed to be)
punishment. A third commonly accepted feature of punishment is that guilty of crimes, in response to those crimes. This is not intended as a
it is imposed on someone guilty of an offense, as a response to that precise definition or a set of necessary and sufficient conditions for
offense. Actually, there is some disagreement about this point. To punishment. Theorists may disagree about particular elements, or
count as punishment, must it be imposed on someone who is actually especially about how exactly to flesh out the various elements. But this
guilty of a crime? Or would it make sense to talk of punishing an description is sufficient to give us a sense of why punishment stands in
innocent person (either mistakenly or intentionally)? Some scholars need of justification: It involves the state’s treating some of its
contend that punishment must be of a guilty person. Susan Dimock members (imposing intentionally burdensome, censuring sanctions)
writes, “The innocent may be ‘victimized’ by the penal system, but in ways that typically would be morally impermissible.
they cannot be ‘punished’” (Dimock, 1997: 42). By contrast, H. L. A.
Hart contends that we should acknowledge not only punishment of 2. Various Questions
actual offenders, but also cases (which he calls “sub-standard or When theorists ask whether punishment is justified, they typically
secondary”) of punishment “of persons…who neither are in fact nor assume a backdrop in which the legal system administering
supposed to be offenders” (see Hart, 1968: 5).
punishment is legitimate, and the criminal laws themselves are
reasonably just. This is not to say that they assume that all legal
A fourth feature of punishment, widely acknowledged at least since systems are legitimate and all criminal laws are reasonably just in the
the publication of Joel Feinberg’s seminal 1970 article “The Expressive actual world. Indeed, questions of political legitimacy and
Function of Punishment” is that it serves to express condemnation, or criminalization are important topics that have received a great deal of
censure, of the offender for her offense. As Feinberg discusses, it is attention in their own right. But even in societies in which the legal
this condemning element that distinguishes punishment from what he system is legitimate and the laws are reasonably just, a general
calls “nonpunitive penalties” such as parking tickets, demotions, question arises of whether (and if so, why) it is permissible for the
flunkings, and so forth. (Feinberg, 1965: 398-401). As we will see state to impose intended, censuring burdens on those who violate the
below, some scholars have taken this expression of censure to be laws.
central to the justification of punishment. But whether or not it plays a
This general question of punishment’s moral permissibility actually about the proper mode of punishment. We may critique certain
comprises a number of particular questions. A full normative account sentences not in virtue of their severity but because we believe the
of punishment should provide answers to each of these questions. form of punishment (incarceration, capital punishment, and so forth)
is in some sense inappropriate (Reiman, 1985; Moskos, 2011). What
First, there is the question of punishment’s function, or purpose. Put considerations, then, should guide assessments of whether
simply, what reason is there to want an institution of punishment? H. imprisonment, fines, community service, probation, capital
L. A. Hart referred to this as punishment’s “general justifying aim,” punishment, or some other form of punishment is the appropriate
although this term may be misleading in two ways: on one hand, to response to instances of criminal wrongdoing?
say that the aim is justifying implies that it is sufficient, by itself, to
establish punishment’s permissibility. As we will see, some scholars Finally, as mentioned, it is important to ask about the state’s role as
point out that more is needed to justify punishment than merely citing the agent of punishment. Why is it the state’s right to impose
its function, no matter how valuable. On the other hand, talk of a punishment (if indeed it is)? Furthermore, what gives the state
justifying aim seems to privilege consequentialist accounts, according the exclusive right to punish (Wellman, 2009)? Why may victims not
to which punishment is justified as a means to some socially valuable inflict punishment on their assailants (or hire someone to inflict the
goal. But even for retributivist accounts, according to which punishment)? Another question related to the proper agent of
punishment is justified not as a means to some end but rather as an punishment—a question that has become increasingly salient in the
intrinsically appropriate response to wrongdoing, we still need an decades following the Nuremberg trials—is when (if ever) the
explanation of why such a response is important enough to warrant international community, rather than a particular state, can be the
the state’s institution of punishment. A first question, then, is what proper agent of punishment. What sorts of crime, and which
sufficiently important function punishment serves. criminals, are properly accountable to the institutions of international
criminal law rather than (or perhaps in addition) to the domestic legal
Even if we establish some sufficiently valuable function of systems of particular states?
punishment, this may not be enough to justify the practice. Some
scholars contend that a crucial question is whether punishment As we will see, various accounts of punishment focus on different
violates the moral rights of those punished. If punishing offenders questions. Also, some accounts seek to answer each of these questions
violates their rights, then it may be morally impermissible even if it by appealing to the same moral principles or considerations, whereas
serves some important function (Simmons, 1991; Wellman, 2009). others appeal to different considerations in answering the different
What we need, according to this view, is an account of why, in questions.
principle, the practice of imposing intended burdens on people in the
ways characteristic of punishment does not violate their moral rights. 3. Consequentialist Accounts
Consequentialism holds that the rightness or wrongness of actions—or
In addition to justifying the practice of punishment in general, a rules for action, or (relevant to our context) institutions—is
complete account of punishment should also provide guidance in determined solely by their consequences. Thus consequentialist
determining how to punish in particular cases. Even if the institution accounts of punishment defend the practice as instrumentally
of punishment is morally permissible, a particular sentence may be valuable: the consequences of maintaining an institution of legal
impermissible if it is excessively harsh (or on some accounts, if it is punishment, according to this view, are better than the consequences
too lenient). What principles and considerations should guide of not having such an institution. For many consequentialists, the
assessments of how severely to punish? burden of punishment itself is seen as a negative consequence—an
“evil,” as Jeremy Bentham called it (Bentham, 1789: 158). Thus for
Relatedly, although this point has received less attention, we should punishment to be justified, it must be the case that it brings about
other, sufficiently valuable consequences to outweigh its onerousness
ask not only about the appropriate severity of punishment but also
for the person on whom it is inflicted. Typically, punishment is on an offender in hopes that her aversion to undergoing such
defended as a necessary means to the socially valuable end of crime treatment again will convince her not to reoffend. Punishment with
reduction, through deterrence, incapacitation, or offender reform. the aim of offender reform, by contrast, aims to reshape offenders’
moral motives and dispositions.
a. Deterrence
Deterrence accounts contend that the threat of punishment serves as a d. Sentencing
disincentive for potential criminals. On such accounts, for the threat Each of these aims—deterrence, incapacitation, and reform—will have
of punishment to be effective as a deterrent, it must be credible—it distinct implications with respect to sentencing. Punishment aimed at
must have teeth, so to speak—and thus the legal system must follow reducing crime through deterrence would in general need to be severe
through on the threat and impose punishment on those who violate enough to provide members of the public with a significant incentive
laws. Theorists have distinguished two potential audiences for the not to offend, or to provide offenders with an incentive not to
deterrent threat: first, the threat of punishment might serve to reoffend. Also, as Bentham explained, the severity of sentences should
dissuade members of the public generally from committing crimes reflect the relative seriousness of the crimes punished (Bentham,
that they might otherwise have committed. This is 1789: 168). More serious crimes should receive more severe
called general deterrence. Second, for those who do commit crimes punishments than do less serious crimes, so that prospective
and are subjected to punishment, the threat of future punishment offenders, if they are going to commit one crime or the other, will have
(namely, the prospect of having to experience prison again, or pay an incentive to choose the less serious crime.
further fines, and so forth) might provide a disincentive to
reoffending. This is typically referred to as specific (or special) For punishment aimed at reducing crime through incapacitation,
deterrence. sentences should be restrictive enough that dangerous offenders will
be unable to victimize others (so, for instance, prison appears
b. Incapacitation generally preferable to fines as a form of incapacitative punishment).
Punishment might also help to reduce crime by incapacitating In terms of duration, incapacitative sentences should last as long as
criminals. Unlike deterrence, incapacitation does not operate by the offender poses a genuine threat. Similarly, sentences aimed at
dissuading potential offenders. Incapacitation instead aims to remove reducing crime through offender reform should be tailored, in terms
dangerous people from situations in which they could commit crimes. of the form, severity, and duration of punishment, in whatever ways
Imprisoning someone in a solitary confinement unit, for instance, may are determined to be most conducive to this aim.
or may not convince her not to commit crimes in the future; but while
she is locked up, she will be unable to commit (most) crimes. Finally, insofar as punishment itself is considered to be, in Bentham’s
words, an “evil,” the consequentialist is committed to the view that
c. Offender Reform sentences should be no more severe than is necessary to accomplish
A third way in which punishment might help to reduce crime is by their aim. Thus whether she endorses deterrence, incapacitation,
encouraging or facilitating offender reform. The aim of reform is like reform, or some other aim (or a combination of these), the
that of specific deterrence in one respect: both seek to induce a change consequentialist should also endorse a parsimony constraint on
in the offender’s behavior. That is, the aim for both is that she should sentence severity (Tonry, 2011). After all, to impose sentences that are
choose not to reoffend. In this respect, both reform and specific more severe than is necessary to accomplish punishment’s aim(s)
deterrence differ from incapacitation, which is concerned with would appear to be an infliction of gratuitous suffering—and so, from
restricting rather than influencing offenders’ choices. But reform a consequentialist perspective, unjustified.
differs from specific deterrence in terms of the ways in which each
seeks to induce different choices. Punishment aimed at specific e. Objections and Responses
deterrence provides prudential reasons: we impose onerous treatment
Typical consequentialist accounts of punishment contend that the Even if we accept, for argument’s sake, that punishment contributes to
practice is justified because it produces, on balance, positive crime reduction, it still may not be justified on consequentialist
consequences by helping to reduce crime, either through deterrence, grounds if it also generates costs that outweigh its benefits. The costs
incapacitation, or offender reform. Critics have objected to such of punishment are not limited to the suffering or other burdens
consequentialist accounts on a number of grounds. inflicted on offenders, although these burdens do matter from a
consequentialist perspective. Scholars have also highlighted burdens
First, some have objected to deterrence accounts on grounds that associated with certain forms of punishment—in particular,
punishment does not actually deter potential offenders. A key worry is incarceration—for offenders’ families and communities (Mauer and
Chesney-Lind, 2002). These costs matter in consequentialist
that often (perhaps typically) those who commit crimes act
impulsively or irrationally, rather than as efficient calculators of calculations. In addition, we must consider the financial costs of
expected utility, and so they are not responsive to the threat of maintaining an institution of criminal punishment. In 2012, the Vera
punishment. The question of whether punishment deters is an Institute of Justice released a study of 40 U.S. states that found that
empirical one, and criminological studies on this question have come the total taxpayer cost of prisons in these states was $39 billion. Thus
to different conclusions. In general, evidence seems to indicate that defenders of punishment on consequentialist grounds must show not
punishment does have some deterrent effect, but that the certainty of only that punishment is beneficial, but also that its benefits are
apprehension plays a greater deterrent role than does the severity of significant enough to outweigh its costs to offenders and to society
generally.
punishment (Nagin, 2013).

A similar line of objection has been raised against reform-based Furthermore, even if punishment’s benefits outweigh its costs,
accounts of punishment. Criminological research in the 1970s led consequentialists must make the case that these benefits cannot be
many scholars and practitioners to conclude that punishment did not, achieved through some other, less burdensome response to crime. If
indeed could not, promote offender reform (the mantra “nothing there are alternatives to punishment that are equally effective in
works” was for many years ubiquitous in these discussions). More reducing crime but are less costly overall, then from a consequentialist
recent criminological work, however, has generated somewhat more perspective, these alternatives would be preferable (Boonin, 2008: 53,
optimism about the prospects for offender reform (Cullen, 2013). 264-67).

Whereas critics have questioned whether punishment deters or Suppose, however, that the benefits of punishment outweigh its harms
facilitates offender reform, there is little doubt that punishment— and also that there are no alternatives to punishment that generate, on
especially incarceration—incapacitates (prisoners may still have balance, better overall consequences. In this case, punishment would
opportunities to commit crimes, but their opportunities are at least be justified from a consequentialist perspective. Many theorists,
however, do not endorse consequentialism. Indeed, the most
significantly limited.) Critics have raised questions, however, about
prominent philosophical objections to consequentialist accounts of
the link between incapacitation and crime reduction. For punishment
to be justified on incapacitative grounds, after all, it would need to be punishment take aim specifically at supposed deficiencies of
the case not only that punishment in fact incapacitates, but that in so consequentialism itself.
doing it helps to reduce crime. At least in some cases, there is reason
to doubt whether the link between incapacitation and crime reduction Perhaps the most common objection to consequentialist accounts is
holds. Most notably, locking up drug dealers or gang members does that they are unable to provide principled grounds for ruling out
not appear to decrease drug- or gang-related crimes, because the punishment of the innocent. If there were ever a situation in which
incapacitated person is quickly and easily replaced by someone else punishing an innocent person would promote the best consequences,
(Tonry, 2006: 31-32). then consequentialism appears committed to doing so. H. J.
McCloskey imagines a case in which, in the wake of a heinous crime, a
small-town sheriff must decide whether to frame and punish a person prohibition on punishing the innocent. Some consequentialists have
whom the townspeople believe to be guilty but the sheriff knows is accepted this implication, albeit reluctantly (see Smart, 1973: 69-73).
innocent if doing so is the only way to prevent rioting by the
townspeople (McCloskey, 1957: 468-69). If punishing the innocent A similar objection to consequentialist accounts is that they cannot
person defuses the residents’ hostilities and prevents the riots—and provide a principled basis for the widely held intuition that
thereby produces better overall consequences than continuing to punishment should be no more severe than an offender deserves
search for the actual criminal—then it appears that the (where desert is the product of the seriousness of the offense and the
consequentialist is committed to punishing the innocent person. But offender’s culpability). On this view, it is morally wrong to subject
knowingly punishing an innocent person strikes most of us as deeply
those guilty of relatively minor crimes to harsh punishment; such
unjust. punishment would be excessive. For consequentialist accounts,
though, it appears that excessively harsh sentences would be
Consequentialists have responded to this objection in various ways. permitted (indeed, required) if they produced the best overall
Some contend that what McCloskey describes is not actually consequences.
punishment, because punishment, by definition, is a response to those
guilty of crimes (or at least believed to be guilty, whereas in Jeremy Bentham contended that consequentialism does have the
McCloskey’s example, the sheriff knows the person to be innocent). H. resources to ground relative proportionality in sentencing—that is,
L. A. Hart refers to this response as the “definitional stop” and he lesser offenses should receive less severe sentences than more serious
suggests it is unhelpful because it seeks to define away the interesting
offenses receive. His reasoning was that if sentences for minor
normative questions. Setting terminology aside, the relevant questions offenses were as harsh as for more serious offenses, potential
are whether and why it is permissible to impose intended, offenders would have no incentive to commit the lesser offense rather
condemnatory burdens on those (believed to be) guilty of crimes. The than the more serious one (Bentham, 1789: 168). If Bentham is right,
consequentialist’s response is that doing so produces the best then there is a consequentialist basis for punishing shoplifters, for
consequences, but then it seems that the consequentialist should be instance, less harshly than armed robbers. But this does not rule out
committed to imposing such burdens on those not (believed to be) punishing shoplifters harshly (more harshly than most of us would
guilty of crimes when doing so produces the best consequences. Such think justified) and punishing armed robbers even more harshly;
a practice would strike many as morally wrong, however. Thus the again, a consequentialist would seem committed to such a sentencing
objection arises for consequentialists regardless of definitions. scheme if it promoted the best overall consequences.

Others have responded to the objection that consequentialism would Defenders of consequentialist sentencing have another response
allow for punishing the innocent by suggesting that scenarios such as available, namely that excessively harsh sentences do not, in practice,
McCloskey suggests are so far-fetched that they are unlikely to occur
produce the best consequences. For instance, criminological research
in the real world. In actual cases, punishing the innocent will rarely, if
suggests a) that stiffer sentences do not produce significant deterrent
ever, produce the best consequences. For instance, some contend that effects (it is primarily the certainty of punishment rather than its
the sheriff in the example would likely be found out, and as a result severity that deters); b) that extremely long prison terms are not
the public would lose its trust in law enforcement officials; the long- justified on incapacitative grounds (for one reason, most offenders
term consequences, therefore, would be worse than if the sheriff had “age out” of criminal behavior anyway by their 30s or 40s); and c) that
not punished the innocent person. As critics have pointed out, extremely harsh sentences may, on balance, have criminogenic effects
however, this response only shows that punishing the innocent will (that is, they may make people more likely to reoffend). This sort of
usually be ruled out by consequentialism. There might still be cases, response, of course, makes the prohibition of disproportionate
albeit rare, in which punishing the innocent would generate the best
punishment a contingent matter; in other words, if extremely harsh
consequences (maybe the sheriff is adept at covering up his act). At sentences did help to reduce crime and this produced, on balance, the
best, then, consequentialism seems only able to ground a contingent
best overall consequences, then consequentialism would appear to them as potential offenders and aims to provide an incentive not to
endorse such sentences. Critics thus charge that consequentialist offend (that is, general deterrence). For those who have committed
accounts are unappealing insofar as they are unable to ground more crimes, deterrent punishment similarly regards them as potential
than a contingent prohibition on disproportionately harsh (re)offenders and aims to provide an incentive not to (re)offend (that
punishment. is, specific deterrence). In this way, punishment with a deterrent aim
might be said to speak to all community members in the same terms,
Even if we prohibit punishment of the innocent or disproportionate and thus not to be objectionably exclusionary.
punishment of the guilty, a third, Kantian objection holds that
consequentialist punishment is not properly responsive to the person 4. Retributivist Accounts
being punished. According to this objection, to punish offenders as a As we have seen, consequentialist accounts of punishment are
means to securing some valuable social end (namely, crime reduction) essentially forward-looking—punishment is said to be justified in
is to use them as mere means, rather than respecting them as ends in virtue of the consequences it helps to produce. A different sort of
themselves (Kant, 1797: 473; Murphy, 1973). account regards punishment as justified not because of what it brings
about, but instead because it is an intrinsically appropriate response
In response to this objection, some scholars have contended that to crime. Accounts of the second sort have traditionally been
although consequentialists regard punishment as a means to an end, described as retributivist. In general, we can say that retributivism
punishment does not treat offenders as mere means to this end. If we views punishment as justified because it is deserved, although
particular accounts differ about what exactly this means.
limit punishment to those who have been found guilty of crimes, then
this treatment is arguably responsive to their choices and does not use
them as mere means. Kant himself suggested that as long as we Theorists have distinguished two varieties of retributivism: positive
reserve punishment only for those found guilty of crimes, then it is retributivism and negative retributivism. Positive retributivism is
permissible to punish with an eye toward potential benefits (Kant, typically characterized as the view that an offender’s desert provides a
1797: 473). positive justifying reason for punishment; in other words, the state
should punish those who are found guilty of criminal wrongdoing
because they deserve it. Negative retributivism, by contrast, provides a
A more recent objection to consequentialist systems of punishment,
developed by R. A. Duff (1986, 2001), charges that consequentialist constraint on punishment: punishment is justified only of those who
systems of punishment, with their focus on crime reduction, treat deserve it. Because negative retributivism provides only a constraint
offenders as dangerous “outsiders”—as the “they” whom “we,” the law- on punishment, not a positive reason to punish, the negative
abiding members of society, must threaten, incapacitate, or remold to retributive constraint has featured prominently in attempts at mixed
ensure our safety. Such a conception of the criminal law is accounts of punishment; such accounts allow punishment for
consequentialist aims as long as the punishment is only of those who
inappropriately exclusionary, Duff claims. The criminal law, and the
deserve it. On the other hand, because negative retributivism does not
institution of punishment, in a liberal polity should treat offenders
inclusively, as (still) members of the community who despite having provide a positive justifying reason to punish, some scholars argue
violated its values could, and should, nevertheless (re)commit to these that it does not properly count as retributivism at all.
values.
The distinction between retributivism and consequentialism is not
In response, one might object that systems of punishment aimed at always a neat one. Notice that one might endorse the claim that
crime reduction need not be exclusionary in the way Duff suggests. In punishment is a deserved response to wrongdoing and then further
particular, punishment that aims to deter crime might be said to treat assert that it is a valuable state of affairs when wrongdoers get the
all community members equally, namely as potential offenders. For punishment they deserve—a state of affairs that therefore should be
promoted. On this type of account, retribution itself essentially
those who have not committed crimes, deterrent punishment regards
becomes the consequentialist aim of punishment (Moore, 1903; becomes a free rider, because she counts on others to play by the rules
Zaibert, 2006). Nevertheless, in keeping with general practice, this that she violates. By failing to restrain herself appropriately, she gains
article will treat retributivism as distinct from, and in competition an unfair advantage over others in society. The justification of
with, consequentialist accounts. punishment is that it corrects this unfair advantage by inflicting
burdens on the offender proportionate to the benefit she gained by
a. Deserved Suffering committing her crime (Morris, 1968).
One common version of retributivism contends simply that
wrongdoers deserve to suffer in proportion to their wrongdoing. Often On the fair play view, then, punishment is justified as a deserved
this claim is made by way of appeal to intuitions about particular, response to an unfair advantage taken against members of society
usually heinous crimes: surely the unrepentant war criminal, for generally. Such an account offers a relatively straightforward answer
example, who has tortured and murdered many innocent people, to the question of why punishment is the state’s business. The state
deserves to suffer for what he has done. Proponents argue that has an interest in assuring those who accept the burdens of
retributivism is justified because it best accounts for our intuitions compliance with the law that they will not be at a disadvantage to
about particular cases such as these (Moore, 1987; Kleinig, 1973). those who would free-ride on the system.

Justifying retributivism requires more, of course, than merely Critics of the fair play view have argued that it provides a
appealing to common intuitions about such cases. After all, even if counterintuitive conception of the crime to which punishment
many (even most) people do feel, in hearing reports of terrible crimes, responds. It seems strange, for instance, to think of the wrong
that the perpetrators deserve to suffer, not everyone feels this way. perpetrated by, say, a rapist as a sort of free-riding wrong against
And even those who do have such intuitions may not feel entirely society in general, rather than an egregious wrong perpetrated against
comfortable with them. What we would like to know is whether the the victim in particular. In response to this charge, Dagger (1993)
intuitions themselves are justified, or whether, for instance, they argues that crimes may be wrong in both senses: they may wrong
amount to an unhealthy desire for vengeance. Critics contend that particular victims in various ways, but they are also in every case
those who rely on our intuitions about particular cases as evidence wrongs in the sense of free riding on society generally.
that retributivism is justified fail to provide the needed explanation of
why the intuitions are justified. c. Censure
Another influential version of retributivism begins with the claim,
There are other questions for such a view: does any sort of moral discussed earlier, that one of punishment’s distinctive features is that
wrongdoing deserve to be met with suffering, or only some cases of it communicates censure, or condemnation, of the offender for her
wrongdoing? Which ones? And why is meting out deserved suffering offense. This retributivist account, developed most notably by R. A.
for wrongdoing properly the concern of the state? Duff (1986, 2001), takes the censuring feature as the key to
establishing punishment’s moral permissibility. Offenders deserve to
be censured for what they have done, and punishment is justified
b. Fair Play
Another prominent type of retributivist account begins with a because it delivers this censuring message.
conception of society as a cooperative venture in which each member
benefits when there is general compliance with the rules governing the Duff understands crimes as public wrongs, as violations of important
venture. Because each of us benefits when everyone else plays by the public values. It follows on this account that the state is the
rules, fairness dictates that we each have an obligation to reciprocate appropriate agent of punishment; the state properly calls offenders to
by playing by the rules, too. A criminal, like other members of society, account for their violations of the political community’s shared values.
benefits from general compliance with laws, but she fails to
reciprocate by complying with the laws herself. She essentially
Censuring involves, in part, urging an offender to think about the an account, however, is whether the prudential threat will tend to
wrong she has done, to repent and (re)commit herself to the values drown out the moral message.
that she has violated. Thus it follows from censure accounts such as
Duff’s that offender self-reform is an aim of punishment. But notice d. Other Versions
the crucial distinction between this sort of account and the variety of Alternative versions of retributivism have been offered. Some
consequentialist account that aims at offender reform. Although scholars, for instance, argue that those who commit crimes violate the
offender reform is an aim of punishment on the censure account, it is trust of their fellow community members. Trust, on this account, is an
not a justifying aim. In other words, on the censure view, punishment essential feature of a healthy community. Offenders undermine this
is not justified insofar as it tends to promote offender reform. Rather,
trust when they victimize others. In such cases, punishment is a
punishment is justified because it communicates deserved censure. deserved response to such violations and an appropriate way to help
Part of what it means to censure, however, is to urge wrongdoers to maintain (or restore) the conditions of trust among community
repent and reform. members (see Dimock, 1997). Advocates of this trust-based variety of
retributivism must explain which violations of trust rise to the level
A common critique of the censure view asks why punishment—that is, that warrants criminalization, so that violators should be subject to
the imposition of intended burdens—is the proper way to censure punishment. Also, we might question whether such accounts are
wrongdoers. It seems that the polity could communicate messages of purely retributivist after all: if punishment is justified at least in part
censure to offenders without imposing intended burdens; for example, as a means of helping to maintain conditions of trust in a community,
it could issue a public proclamation condemning the crime and then this appears to be a consequentialist rationale. On the other
blaming the offender. Why, then, is the hard treatment characteristic hand, if punishment is justified not for what it helps to bring about
of punishment an appropriate vehicle for conveying such messages? but rather as an intrinsically appropriate (because deserved) response
One type of response, offered by Duff and others (see also Falls, 1987), to violations of trust, then we need an explanation of why such
holds that hard treatment is needed to convey adequately the polity’s violations deserve punishment, perhaps as opposed to some other
condemnation of crimes. Nonpunitive censure—blaming without form of response.
imposing intended hard treatment—would fail to communicate the
seriousness of the wrongdoing. Another form of retributivism holds that offenders incur a moral debt
to their victims, and so they deserve punishment as a way to repay this
Also, on Duff’s account, hard treatment can function to induce in debt (McDermott, 2001). This moral debt is distinct from the material
offenders the sort of moral reflection that may lead to repentance, debt that an offender may incur. In other words, a person who robs
reform, and reconciliation (with their victims and the community from another person incurs a material debt equal to the value of
more generally). Some have objected, however, that such an account whatever was stolen, but she also incurs a moral debt for violating the
implies too intrusive a role for the state. It is not a proper function of victim’s rights. The offender takes not only a material good from the
the state, critics charge, to seek to induce repentance and moral victim but also a moral good. Repayment of material goods does not
reform in offenders. Thus even some scholars who agree that settle this moral debt, and so punishment is needed to fill this role. As
punishment is justified as a form of censure nevertheless disagree Daniel McDermott characterizes it, punishment serves to deny the ill-
about the role of the hard treatment element. For Andrew von Hirsch gotten moral good to the perpetrator (McDermott, 2001: 424).
(1993), for instance, the intended burdens characteristic of
punishment act as a sort of prudential supplement: punishment, as Such an account raises a host of questions: what precisely is the nature of the
censure, serves to remind offenders (and community members) of the
moral good that has been taken from the victim? How can a moral good be
moral reasons to comply with the law. Punishment, as hard treatment,
taken away from someone? In what sense (if at all) has the perpetrator gained
also provides a prudential threat as a sort of supplement for those of
this good? How does punishment deny this good to the offender, and how
us for whom the moral message is not sufficient. One worry with such
does this thereby make things right for the victim?
e. Sentencing children to serve the sentence. Considerations such as these do not in
Because retributivism claims that punishment is justified as a themselves demonstrate that the tenets of ordinal proportionality are
deserved response to wrongdoing, retributivist accounts should false (that like cases should not be treated alike, for instance, or that
provide some guidance about what sentences are deserved in more serious violations should not receive harsher sentences). Rather,
particular cases. Typically, retributivists hold that sentences should be these considerations raise challenges to our ability in practice to
no more severe than is deserved. This negative retributivist constraint implement a just sentencing scheme that reflects ordinal
on sentencing corresponds with the negative retributivist constraint proportionality.
on punishment itself (namely, that punishment is justified only of
those who deserve it). By contrast, positive retributivism holds that
Even if sentences can be devised that satisfy ordinal proportionality,
offenders’ sentences should be no less severe than they deserve. Some however—in other words, even if a sentencing scheme itself is
scholars find this positive retributivism unappealing because it seems internally proportionate—particular sentences may fail to be
to preclude the state from taking into account mercy or other proportionate if the entire sentencing scheme is too severe (or
considerations that might count in favor of lenient sentences. In other lenient). For instance, a sentencing scheme in which even the least
words, some are more comfortable with retributivism’s setting a offenses were punished with prison terms would appear
ceiling but not a floor on sentence severity. One question, though, is disproportionate even if sentences in the scheme were proportionate
whether (and if so, why) retributivists are justified in endorsing the relative to each other. Thus theorists note a second sense of
negative retributivist constraint on sentencing without also endorsing
proportionality: cardinal, or nonrelative, proportionality. Cardinal
the positive retributivist constraint. proportionality considers whether sentences are commensurate with
the crimes they punish. A prison term for jaywalking would appear to
Retributivists often discuss sentencing in terms of proportionality, violate cardinal proportionality, because such a sentence strikes us as
where a proportionate sentence is understood as one that is deserved too severe given the offense, even if this sentence were proportionate
(or at least, on some accounts, not clearly undeserved). Sentences may with other sentences in a sentencing scheme—that is, even if it
be proportionate in two senses: first, they may be proportionate (or satisfied ordinal proportionality. Thus cardinal proportionality
disproportionate) relative to each other. This sense of proportionality, concerns not the relation of sentences to one another, but instead the
called ordinal proportionality, holds that similarly serious offenses relation of a sentence to the crime to which it is a response. Put
should receive similarly severe punishments (like cases should be another way, even if an entire sentencing scheme is internally
treated alike); that more serious offenses should be punished more (ordinally) proportionate, we need guidance in how to anchor the
harshly than less serious offenses (murder should be punished more sentencing scheme to the crimes themselves so that offenders in
harshly than shoplifting, for instance); and that differences in particular cases receive the sentences they deserve.
sentence severity should reflect differences in relative seriousness of
offenses (because murder is much more serious than shoplifting,
In addition to addressing questions of deserved sentence severity, we
murder should carry a much more severe sentence). would like retributivism to provide some guidance about how to
determine what mode, or form, of punishment is appropriate in
Some scholars have challenged the notion of ordinal proportionality response to a given crime. Is prison time, community service, capital
constraints in sentencing, both because offenders cannot neatly be punishment, probation, or something else the deserved form of
distinguished into a manageable number of desert-based groups— response, and why?
Michael Tonry calls this the “illusion of ‘like-situated offenders’”
(Tonry, 2011)—and because individual offenders’ subjective The implications of retributivism for sentencing will depend on the
experiences of the same sentence may vary greatly. For example, specific account’s explanation of why punishment is said to be the
someone who is young, physically imposing, or has no children may
deserved response to offending.
have a much different experience of a 10-year prison term from
someone who is much older, physically frail, or must leave behind her
Those who appeal to intuitions that the guilty deserve to suffer, for relatively more severe punishments. This is a violation of ordinal
instance, can similarly appeal to intuitions that those who are guilty of proportionality.
more serious offenses deserve to suffer more than those who are guilty
of less serious offenses. As discussed, however, we would like to know Similar problems arise for other versions of the fair play view.
how much punishment is deserved in particular cases in nonrelative Suppose, for instance, that the unfair advantage a criminal gains is not
terms, and also what form the suffering should take. One well-known freedom from the burden of complying with the particular law she
account of sentencing is provided by lex talionis (that is, an eye for an violates, but rather freedom from complying with the rule of law in
eye, a tooth for a tooth). Immanuel Kant famously endorsed this general. This general compliance, Richard Dagger writes, is a genuine
principle: “Accordingly, whatever undeserved evil you inflict upon
burden: “there are times for almost all of us when we would like to
another within the people, that you inflict upon yourself” (Kant, 1797: have the best of both worlds—that is, the freedom we enjoy under the
473). As critics have noted, though, not every crime appears to have an rule of law plus freedom from the burden of obeying laws” (Dagger,
obvious like-for-like response—what would lex talionis demand for 1993: 483). Critics have objected, however, that on this conception of
the childless kidnapper, for instance (Shafer-Landau, 2000: 193)? And the unfair advantage all offenses become, for the purposes of
even when a like-for-like response is clearly indicated, it will not punishment, the same offense. Both the murderer’s and the tax cheat’s
always be palatable (torturing the torturer, for example). unfair advantage is freedom from compliance with the rule of law
generally. If the unfair advantage is the same, however, then removing
We might assert instead that the sentence and the offense need not be the advantage would seem to require equal sentences. Again, such
alike in kind, but that the sentence should impose an amount of sentencing appears to violate ordinal proportionality.
suffering equal to the harm done by the offender. Still, questions arise
of how to make interpersonal comparisons of suffering. And again, for For the censure view, questions arise about what form of punishment
the most heinous crimes, a principle of inflicting equal amounts of and what severity will communicate the deserved message of
suffering may recommend sentences that we would find troubling. condemnation in particular cases. On such a view, the principles of
ordinal proportionality appear to follow straightforwardly: censure
The fair play view holds that punishment functions to remove an should reflect the seriousness of the wrongdoing, and so if
unfair advantage gained by an offender relative to members of society punishment is the vehicle of communicating censure, then sentences
generally. Critics of this view often object, however, that it provides should reflect the appropriate relative degree of censure for each case.
insufficient or counterintuitive guidance about sentencing. Put simply,
there does not seem to be any advantage that an offender gains, in The censure view should provide guidance not only about how
proportion with the seriousness of her crime, relative to community severely to punish crimes relative to each other, but also how severely
members generally. On one version of the view, the offender gains to punish in absolute terms, and also the appropriate mode of
freedom from the burden of self-constraint that others accept in
punishment. To say that manslaughter should be censured more
complying with the particular law that the offender violates. If so, then
severely than theft, for instance, does not actually tell us how severely
the sentence severity should be proportionate to the burden others to censure manslaughter or theft, or with what form of punishment.
feel in complying with that law. But compliance with laws is often not Again, the challenge is in determining how to anchor the sentencing
a burden for most citizens. Indeed, it is often less burdensome to scale to actual offenses. Should the least serious offenses receive
comply with prohibitions on serious offenses (murder, assault, and so censure in the form of a small fine, a day in jail, or a year in jail?
forth) than it is to comply with prohibitions on lesser crimes (tax Should the most serious offenses receive capital punishment, life
evasion, jaywalking, and so forth), given that we are more often imprisonment, or some less severe sentence?
tempted to commit the lesser crimes. But if the unfair advantage that
punishment aims to remove is freedom from the burden of self-
constraint, and if self-constraint is often more burdensome with lesser Similar questions arise for accounts that characterize punishment as a
crimes, then these less serious crimes will often appear to merit deserved response to violations of trust, or as a deserved response to
the incurrence of a moral debt. What form and severity of punishment Notice that the forfeiture view itself does not imply any particular
is appropriate to maintain conditions of community trust in response positive justification of punishment; it merely purports to explain why
to attempted kidnapping, or the theft of a valuable piece of art? How punishing offenders does not violate their rights. This is consistent
severe must a sentence be to resolve the moral debt that is incurred with maintaining that the positive justification of punishment is that it
when one impersonates a police officer, or cheats on her taxes? helps reduce crime, or conversely, that wrongdoers deserve to be
punished. Thus the forfeiture view does not provide a complete
Indeed, questions about fixing deserved sentences in response to account of the justification of punishment. Proponents, however, take
particular offenses arise for retributivist accounts generally. Critics this feature to be a virtue rather than a weakness of the view.
have charged that retributivism is unable to provide adequate,
nonarbitrary guidance about either the deserved severity or deserved The forfeiture claim raises a number of key questions: first, why does
form of punishment in particular cases (see Shafer-Landau, 2000). someone who violates the law thereby forfeit the right not to be
punished? For those who are gripped by the dilemma of why
punishing offenders does not violate their rights, the mere answer that
Retributivists are, of course, aware of such objections and have sought
to meet them in various ways. Nonetheless, questions about offenders forfeit their rights, without some deeper account of what
proportionate sentencing continue to be a central challenge for this forfeiture amounts to, may seem inadequate. Thus some theorists
retributivist accounts. attempt to ground their forfeiture claim in a more comprehensive
moral or political theory (see, for instance, Morris, 1991).

5. Alternative Accounts
Second, what is the nature of the rights forfeited? Do offenders forfeit
In part as a response to objections commonly raised against
consequentialist or retributivist views, a number of theorists have the same rights they violate? If so, then this raises some of the same
sought to develop alternative accounts of punishment. challenges as we saw with certain forms of retributivism: what right is
forfeited by a childless kidnapper, for example? Alternatively, is the
forfeited right simply the right not to be punished? If every offender
a. Rights Forfeiture forfeits this same, general right, then on what basis can we distinguish
At the outset, we said that the central question of punishment’s what sentence is permissible for different offenders? For example, if
permissibility is why (if at all) it is permissible to treat those who have the burglar forfeits the same right as the murderer, then what
committed criminal offenses in ways that typically would be prevents us from imposing the same punishment in each case (could
impermissible. For some theorists, this question is best cast in terms two offenders forfeit the same right to different degrees, as some have
of rights: why are the sorts of intended burdens characteristic of suggested)?
punishment, which would constitute rights violations if imposed on
those who have not been convicted of criminal wrongdoing, not
violations of the rights of those punished? Third, how should we determine the duration of the forfeiture?
Fourth, if an offender forfeits her right against punishment, then why
does the state maintain an exclusive right to punish? Why are other
One way in which punishment would not violate the rights of individuals not permitted to punish?
offenders is if, in committing the crime for which they are convicted,
they forfeit the relevant right(s). Because offenders forfeit their right
b. Consent
not to be punished, the state has no corresponding duty not to punish
them. As W. D. Ross writes, “the offender, by violating the life or Rights forfeiture theorists argue that punishment does not violate
liberty or property of another, has lost his own right to have his life, offenders’ rights because offenders forfeit the relevant rights. Another
liberty, or property respected, so that the state has no prima way that punishment might be said not to violate offenders’ rights is if
facie duty to spare him, as it has a prima facie duty to spare the offenders waive their rights. This is the central claim of the consent
innocent” (1930: 60-61). view. Defended most notably by C. S. Nino (1983), the consent view
holds that when a person voluntarily commits a crime while knowing c. Self-Defense
the consequences of doing so, she effectively consents to these Another proposed justification of punishment conceives of
consequences. In doing so, she waives her right not to be subject to punishment as a form of societal self-defense. First consider self-
punishment. This is not to say that she explicitly consents to being defense in the interpersonal context: When an assailant attacks me, he
punished, but rather that by her voluntary action she tacitly consents culpably creates a situation in which harm will occur: either harm to
to be subject to what she knows are the consequences. me if I do not effectively defend myself or harm to him if I do. In such
a circumstance, I am justified in acting so that the harm falls on my
Like the forfeiture view, the consent view does not supply a positive attacker rather than on me. Similarly, when an offender creates a
situation in which either she or her victim will be harmed, the state is
justification for punishment. To say that a person consents to some
treatment does not by itself provide us with a reason to treat her that permitted to use force to ensure that the harm falls on the perpetrator
way. So the consent view, like the forfeiture view, is compatible with rather than on the victim (Montague, 1995).
consequentialist aims or with the claim that punishment is a deserved
response to offending. So far, this view appears to justify state intervention only to stop
ongoing crimes or ward off impending crimes. How does this view
One challenge for the consent view is that it does not seem to justify justify punishment as a response to past crimes? Advocates of the view
punishment of offenders who do not know that their acts are subject claim that the state is not only justified in intervening to stop actual
to punishment. For someone to have consented to be subject to offenses; it is also permitted to threaten the use of force to deter such
crimes. For the threat to be credible and thus effective as a deterrent,
certain consequences of an act, she must know of these consequences.
What’s more, even if an offender knows she is committing a however, the state will need to follow through on the threat in cases in
punishable act, she might not know the extent of the punishment to which offenders are not deterred. Thus punishment of offenders is
which she is subject. If so, then it is not clear how she can be said to permissible.
consent to her punishment. It is not clear, for example, that a robber
who knows that robbery is a punishable offense but does not realize Notice that although the self-defense account views punishment as a
the severity of the punishment to which she will be subject thereby deterrent threat, it is not a pure consequentialist account. Crucial to
consents to her sentence. punishment’s permissibility on the self-defense view is the claim that
an offender has culpably created the circumstance in which harm will
By contrast, other critics have charged that the consent view cannot fall either on the perpetrator or the victim. This backward-looking
rule out sentences that most of us would find excessive. This is element is missing from pure consequentialist accounts that cite
because a person who voluntarily commits an action with knowledge punishment’s deterrent effects in defending the practice.
of the legal consequences, whatever these consequences happen to be,
has consented to be subject to the consequences. As Larry Alexander Critics object that the analogy between self-defense and punishment
has put it: “If the law imposes capital punishment for overparking, breaks down in a number of respects. First, many self-defense
then one who voluntarily overparks ‘consents’ to be executed” theorists argue that the logic of defensive force permits the use of such
(Alexander, 1986). force even against “innocent” threats. But we do not typically believe
that, by analogy, punishment of innocent people is permitted, even if
Another difficulty for the consent view is that tacit consent typically such punishment helped to maintain the credibility of a deterrent
can be overridden by explicit denials of consent. Thus it would seem to threat. Second, the degree of force that is permitted to stop an actual
follow that one who tacitly consents to be subject to punishment could attack may far exceed what we intuitively believe would be permitted
override this tacit consent by explicitly denying that she consents. But as punishment of an offense that has already been committed.
of course, we do not think that an offender should be able to avoid
punishment by explicitly refusing to consent to it (Boonin, 2008).
Third, it is one thing to follow through on a threat in order to deter the education view, however, holds that only certain means are
person who has just offended from offending again. It is another appropriate for pursuing this goal: namely, punishment aims to
thing—and one might argue, more difficult to justify—to punish one engage with the offender as a moral agent, to teach her that (and why)
person in order to maintain a credible deterrent threat against the her behavior was morally wrong, so that she will reform herself. Thus
public generally. If we believe the primary deterrent effect of we can even distinguish the education view from consequentialist
punishment is as a general deterrent (rather than as a specific accounts that aim at crime reduction through offender reform. For
deterrent), then the analogy with typical accounts of self-defense such consequentialist accounts, punishment’s justification is solely a
seems strained. It would be as if, to deter the oncoming assailant from matter of whether, on balance, it promotes these ends. The education
following through with his attack, I grab someone nearby (who has view sets offender reform as an end, but it also grounds certain
previously attacked me) and inflict the same degree of harm that I constraints on how we may appropriately pursue this end.
would aim to inflict on the assailant to defend myself. This might, of
course, be permissible if my previous attacker had thereby acquired a The education view, like the retributive censure view discussed earlier,
duty to protect me from future harm by allowing himself to be views punishment as a communicative enterprise. Punishment
punished as a means of maintaining a credible deterrent threat communicates to offenders (indeed, to the community more
(Tadros, 2011). generally) that what they have done is wrong. Thus on both accounts,
punishment aims to encourage offenders to reform themselves. But
d. Moral Education whereas the retributive censure theorists view the message conveyed
The moral education view shares certain features of consequentialist by punishment as justified insofar as it is deserved, education
accounts as well as retributivist accounts. On this view, punishment is theorists contend that punishment is justified in virtue of what it aims
justified as a means of teaching a moral lesson to those who commit to accomplish. In this respect, the education view sits more
crimes (and perhaps to community members more generally, as well). comfortably with standard consequentialist accounts than with
retributivist views.
Like standard consequentialist accounts, the education view
acknowledges that part of the story of punishment’s justification The education view conceives of punishment as aiming to confer a
involves its importance in reducing crime. But the education theorist benefit on the offender, the benefit of moral education. This is not to
also takes seriously the worry expressed by many retributivists that say that punishment is not burdensome; as we have seen, its
aiming to shape people’s behavior merely by issuing threats is, in G. burdensomeness is an essential feature of punishment. But the
W. F. Hegel’s words, “much the same as when one raises a cane burdens of punishment are intended to be ultimately beneficial. Thus
against a dog; a man is not treated in accordance with his dignity and education theorists roundly reject accounts according to which it is
honour, but as a dog” (Hegel, 1821: 36). By contrast, a central feature permissible (or even required) to inflict harm on those guilty of
of the moral education view is that those who commit crimes are wrongdoing. Instead, education theorists hold, following Plato, that
moral agents, capable of reflecting on and responding to moral we should never do harm to anyone, even those who have wronged us.
reasons. Thus moral education theorists view punishment not as a
means of conditioning people to behave in certain ways, but rather of Critics have raised various objections to the moral education view.
“teaching the wrongdoer that the action she did (or wants to do) is Some are skeptical about whether punishment is the most effective
forbidden because it is morally wrong and should not be done for that means of moral education. Others point out that many (perhaps most)
reason” (Hampton, 1984). offenders are not apparently in need of moral education: many
offenders realize they are doing something wrong but do so anyway.
Another way to express this difference between the education view Even those who do not realize this as they are acting may recognize it
and standard consequentialist views is that consequentialist views soon afterward. Thus they do not seem to need moral education.
focus entirely on whether punishment promotes some goal. The Finally, some object that the education view is inappropriately
paternalistic. According to the education view, after all, the state is retributivist constraints, there is no reason in principle why we should
justified in coercively restricting offenders’ liberties as a means to distinguish only two questions. As we saw earlier, punishment actually
conferring a benefit (moral education) on them. Many liberal theorists raises a host of specific normative questions, and so if we accept the
are uncomfortable, however, with the idea that the state may coerce a general strategy of distinguishing questions and answering them by
person for her own benefit. appeal to different considerations, then there is no reason in principle
to stop with only a two-level hybrid theory. A hybrid view might offer
e. Hybrid Approaches distinct considerations in answer to a variety of questions: what is the
Finally, some theorists have responded to seemingly intractable positive aim of punishment? Does punishment violate offenders’
rights? How severely may we punish in particular cases? What mode
disputes between consequentialists and retributivists by contending
that the question of punishment’s permissibility is not actually a single of punishment is permissible in particular cases? And so on.
question at all. Instead, establishing punishment’s permissibility
involves answering a number of questions: questions about the aim of Also, although hybrid theories typically follow the pattern of aims and
the practice, about its limits, and so on. Once we distinguish different constraints, so that consequentialism provides the reason to have an
questions that bear on punishment’s permissibility, we can then institution of punishment and retributivism provides constraints on
recognize that these questions may be answered by appeal to different how we punish, there is no reason in principle why this could not be
moral considerations. What emerges is a hybrid account of reversed. A hybrid theory might hold that suffering is an intrinsically
punishment’s permissibility. appropriate (deserved) response to wrongdoing, but then endorse as a
constraint, for example, that such retributive punishment should
The most famous articulation of a hybrid view comes from H. L. A. never tend to undermine offender reform.
Hart (1968), although there have been numerous attempts to develop
such accounts both before and after Hart. The specifics of these Critics have charged hybrid accounts with being ad hoc and unstable.
accounts vary somewhat, but in general the point has been to Although we can distinguish different questions related to
distinguish the question of punishment’s aim (Hart called this the punishment’s permissibility, it is a mistake to think that the answers
“general justifying aim”) from the question of how we must constrain to these questions are entirely independent of each other, so that we
our pursuit of that aim. The first question, about punishment’s aim, is can answer each by appeal to entirely distinct considerations. For
usually answered according to consequentialist considerations, example, if we accept the consequentialist view that punishment’s
whereas the second question, about appropriate constraints, is general justifying aim is that it helps to deter crime, then why would
typically answered by appeal to retributivist principles. In other considerations of deterrence not also play a role (even a decisive role)
words, if we are asking what reason could justify society in in how severely we punish in particular cases? Why should
maintaining a system of punishment, the answer will appeal to retributivist proportionality considerations govern in sentencing if
punishment’s role in reducing crime, and thereby protecting the safety these conflict with the pursuit of crime reduction through deterrence?
and security of community members. But if we ask how we may
punish in particular cases, the answer will appeal to retributivist Retributivists, for their part, often argue that hybrid theories such as
principles about proportionality and desert. Some have distinguished Hart’s, on which consequentialism supplies the justifying aim of
these questions in terms of the proper (consequentialist) rationale of punishment, relegate retributivism to a peripheral role. Retributivists,
legislators in criminalizing certain types of behaviors and the proper after all, tend to regard consequentialism as providing inappropriate
(retributivist) rationale of judges in imposing sentences on those who reasons to punish. Characterizing retributivism’s role as providing
violate the criminal laws. constraints on the pursuit of consequentialist aims is thus unsatisfying
to many retributivists.
Although such views are sometimes described as “two-question” or
“two-level” views, with the focus on consequentialist aims and
6. Abolitionism
Some scholars are unpersuaded by any of the standardly articulated rather than as moral agents who are responsible, and should be held
justifications of punishment. In fact, they conclude that punishment is responsible, for their actions (Morris, 1968).
morally unjustified, and thus that the practice should be abolished. An
obvious question for abolitionists, of course, is what (if anything) Critics of the restitutive and restorative models may point out that
should take the place of punishment. That is, how should society some crimes do not clearly lend themselves to restitution or
respond to those who behave in ways (committing tax fraud, burglary, restoration: some crimes may seem so heinous that no victim
assault, and so on) that currently are subject to punishment? restitution or restoration of relationships is possible. Other crimes do
not have clearly specifiable victims. In addition, consequentialists may
One option would be to endorse a model of treatment rather than worry that practices of restitution or restoration may be inadequate as
punishment. On this model, an offender is viewed as manifesting means of crime reduction if, for example, they are less effective than
some form of disease or pathology, and the appropriate response is punishment at deterring potential offenders. Retributivists also may
thus to try to treat and cure the person rather than to punish her. argue that something important is lost when we respond to
Treatment differs from punishment, first, because it need not be wrongdoing solely with restitutive or restorative practices. Particularly
burdensome. At least in principle, treatment could be pleasant. In for those who hold that an important function of punishment is to
practice, of course, treatment may often be burdensome—indeed, it convey societal censure, restitution or restoration may seem
may involve many of the same sorts of restrictions and burdens as we inadequate as responses to crime insofar as they are not essentially
find with punishment. But even though courses of treatment may be concerned with censuring offenders. Alternatively, some retributivists
burdensome, treatment does not typically convey the condemnation argue that the restorative ideals can best be served by a system of
that is characteristic of punishment. After all, we generally think of retributive punishment (Duff, 2001; Bennett, 2008).
those who are sick as warranting sympathy or concern, not
condemnation.

Other options for abolitionists would be to endorse some model of


restitutive or restorative, rather than criminal, justice. We might
require that offenders make restitution to their victims, as defendants
in civil lawsuits are often required to make restitution to plaintiffs
(Boonin, 2008: 213-75). Or offenders might engage with victims in a
process of restorative justice, one in which both offenders and victims
play an active role, with aims of repairing the harms done and
restoring the relationships that have been damaged (Braithwaite,
1999). Neither the restitutive nor the restorative models are centrally
concerned with imposing intended, censuring burdens on offenders.

Not surprisingly, these alternative accounts are themselves subject to


various objections. Critics of the treatment model, for instance, charge
that it provides insufficient limits on what sort of treatment of
offenders is permissible. The aim of “curing” diseased individuals
might warrant quite severe treatment, both in scope and duration.
Similarly, scholars have argued that the treatment model fails
properly to respect offenders, as it treats them merely as patients

You might also like