You are on page 1of 14

Sour Grapes, Sweet Lemons, and the Anticipatory

Rationalization of the Status Quo

Aaron C. Kay
Maria C. Jimenez
Joim T. Jost

Reprinted from Personality and Social Psychology Bulletin


Volume 28, No. 9, September 2002, pp. 1300-13 12
© 2002 by the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc.
Reprinted by permission of Sage Publications, Inc.
Sour Grapes, Sweet Lemons, and
the Anticipatory Rationalization of the Status Quo

Aaron C. Kay
Maria C. Jimenez
John T. Jost
Stanford University

Integrating theories of cognitive dissonance, system justifica- comes in the future (e.g., Lind & Tyler, 1988; Rasinski,
tion, and dynamic thought systems, the authors hypothesized that Tyler, & Fridkin, 1985).
people would engage in anticipatory rationalization of An additional underestimated factor is that people
sociopolitical outcomes for which they were not responsible. In imbue institutions and organizations with legitimacy and
two studies, the authorsfound that people adjusted theirjudg- stability not only because of external cues that explicitly
ments ofthe desirability ofafuture event to makethem congruent communicate procedural fairness but also because of
with its perceived likelihood, but only when the event triggered the human capacity for rationalization (e.g., Elster, 1983;
motivational involvement. In Study• 1, a political survey Jost, 1995; Lane, 1962). It has been argued that people
administered to288 Democrats, Republicans, and nonparti- possess a “psychological immune system” that allows
sans prior to the Bush-Gore presidential election manipulated them to adjust to suboptimal outcomesby enhancing the
theperceived likelihoodthat each candidatewould win and mea- subjective value of the status quo while devaluing alterna-
sured thesubjective desirability ofeach outcome. In Study2, 203 tives to it (Gilbert, Pinel, Wilson, Blumberg, & Wheatley,
undergraduate students rated the desirability of a large orsmall 1998). This notion also is consistent with research on
tuition increase or decrease that was low, medium, or high in individual adaptation and coping, which suggests that
likelihood. Underconditions evoking high motivational involve- normal, healthy people make cognitive adjustments to
ment, unfavorable as well asfavorableoutcomes werejudged to be minimize the emotional impact of threatening circum-
more desirable as theirperceived likelihood increased. stances and to maximize the hedonic value of things that
happen to them (e.g., Aspinwall & Taylor, 1992;
Lyubomisky & Ross, 1999; Taylor & Brown, 1988). Thus,
A famished fox saw some clusters of ripe black grapes the motivated tendency to bring preferences into line
hanging from a trellised vine. She resorted to all her with expectations—as in the case of “sour grapes” and
tricks to get at them, but wearied herself in vain, for she related forms of rationalization—may play an essential
could not reach them. At lastshe turned away, hiding her
disappointment and saying: “The Grapes are sour, and Authors’ Note: This article is based in part on a 1st-year graduate the-
not ripe as I thought.” sis submitted to the Stanford University Department ofPsychology,
—Aesop, traditional fable, The Fox and the Grapes by the first author under the guidance of the third author. We thank
Susan Kay for her assistance with data collection and Agnieszka
Flizik, Dale Griffin, Curtis Hardin, andJennifer Overbeck for help-
For social systems to survive in stable, legitimate ful discussions concerning this research. Finally, we are particularly
forms, their constituents must be willing to adapt to out- grateful to Grainne Fitzsimons, Orsolya Hunyady, Alan Lambert, Tom
comes that are initially defined as undesirable (e.g., Pyszczynski, Lee Ross, and several anonymous reviewers for extremely
Ginsberg & Weissberg, 1978; Nadeau & Blais, 1993). For helpful comments on an earlier version of this article. Please address
example, democratic institutions are associated with rel- correspondence to Aaron C. Kay, Department ofPsycholog~Building
420,Jordan Hall, Stanford Universit~Stanford, CA 94305, orJohn T.
atively high levels of consent in part because of explicit Jost, Graduate School of Business, Stanford University, Stanford, CA
procedural features that cue fairness, neutrality, and 94305; e-mail: aaronk©psych.stanford.edu orjost_john@gsb.stanford.
voice. As a result of these cues, people may be willing to edu.
trust that even though they might lose some decisions, PSPB, Vol. 28 No. 9, September 2002 1300-1312
they will be able to exert some control over their out- © 2002 by the Society for Personality and Social Psychology, Inc.

1300
Kay et al. / ANTICIPATORYRATIONALIZATION 1301

role in maintaining the mental stability of individuals concept of rationalization. Contemporary social psy-
and the social stability ofsystems. As Marcel Proust (1993) chologists have largely abandoned the field’s
wrote, “We do not succeed in changing things according psychodynamic origins, but the notion that cognitive
to our desires, but gradually our desires change” (p. 609). and motivational factors are intertwined—often at an
The U.S. presidential election of 2000 provides as implicit or nonconscious level—has remained strong
good an example of coping and rationalization as any (e.g., Kruglanski, 1996; Kunda, 1990; Sherman, 1991).
political outcome in recent memory Although pundits With respect to processes of rationalization, the theory
and citizens alike anticipated that the election between of cognitive dissonance has inspired most of the empiri-
Al Gore and George W. Bush would be one of the closest cal research in social psychology (e.g., Festinger, 1957).
in American history, no one could have predicted that it It also has been enormously influential among social sci-
would be decided by only a handful of votes. Under such entists seeking to understand individual and collective
conditions—when outcomes are highly consequential responses to procedures, outcomes, and institutions
and at the same time highly uncertain—people face an (e.g., Beasley &Joslyn, 2001; Elster, 1983; Frenkel &
interesting psychological dilemma: They hope for the Doob, 1976; Granberg & Nanneman, 1986; Kuran, 1998;
best but they must also prepare themselves for the worst. Regan & Kilduff, 1988).
Indeed, in the aftermath of the inconclusive election
results, the very stability of the U.S. political system Cognitive dissonance theory. According to cognitive dis-
depended on the willingness of the “losers” to accept the sonance theory, people are “rationalizing animals”
unwelcome result and support the candidate whom they (Aronson, 1973/1989). This conclusion follows from
had formerly opposed (see also Nadeau & Blais, 1993). three main bodies ofresearch. First, studies indicate that
Electoral politics is not the only social institution that people change their attitudes and generate post hoc3us-
benefits from people’s èapacities to adapt to unwanted tifications following hypocritical (i.e., counteratti-
outcomes (Elster, 1983; Jost, 1995; Kuran, 1998). For tudinal) behavior (e.g., Aronson, 1973/1989; Festinger
instance, businesses and otherwork organizations could & Carlsmith, 1959). Second, dissonance researchers
notfunction effectively if employees and customers were have argued that people invent new reasons (rationaliza-
unwilling to accommodate unpleasant changes such as tions) for choices that they have made, especially when
budget cuts and price increases. Similarly, university stu- those choices are associated with aversive consequences
dents are often forced to adapt to administrative deci- (e.g., Cooper & Fazio, 1984; Staw, 1976). Third, people
sions to implement policies affecting them in areas such subjectively enhance the value of chosen alternatives
as tuition and cu~riculumrequirements. Like employees, and derogate rejected alternatives (e.g., Brehm, 1956;
customers, citizens, and voters, students must also psy- Lyubomirsky & Ross, 1999). These operational defini-
chologically prepare themselves forwhatever outcome is tions of dissonance reduction differ in the extent to
most likely to occur, regardless ofpersonal preferences. which rationalization is assumed to be a purely evaluative
response versus a more cognitively elaborated set of rea-
How, then, do people align internal standards of
desirability with external evidence concerning likeli- sons. Our investigation focuses more on evaluative
responses than on elaboratejustifications, but the pro-
hood? How do they constrain their hopes in the face of
uncertainty and, perhaps more interestingly, how do cesses of evaluation and justification are by no means
they cope defensively with the threatening possibility of opposed. On the contrary, it seems most likely that they
are mutually reinforcing.
unwanted outcomes.? One possibility, we argue, is that
the relevant actors engage in a rationalization of antici- Systemjust ~fi
cation theory. The theory ofsystemjustifica-
pated outcomes so that events that are perceived as more tion builds in many ways on dissonance theory, but it
likely come to be seen as more desirable and events that addresses a broader set of rationalizations, including ste-
are perceived as less likely come to be seen as less desir reotypes and ideologies, that are used to rationalize the
able (Elster, 1983; McGuire, 1960; McGuire & McGuire, status quo as well asjudgments and evaluations that are
1991; Pyszczynski, 1982). In advancing this argument, we used to rationalize specific behaviors and events (Jost &
draw on three social psychological theories of rational- Banaji, 1994;Jost, Pelham, Sheldon, & Sullivan, in press).
ization: cognitive dissonance theory, systemjustification As a general rule, dissonance researchers have confined
theory, and the dynamic theory of thought systems. themselves to cases of rationalization in which (a) peo-
ple are personally responsible for the outcomes theyjus-
Theories of Rationalization
tify and (b) the rationalization occurs post hoc. But what
Since Freud argued that rationalization is a “defense about nonvolitional outcomes? How do people respond
mechanism” that allows people to excuse themselves to anticipated socialand political events, including those
from painful realizations about themselves and their cir- that are not of their own choosing? According to system
cumstances, psychologists have been interested in the justification theory, people engage (to varying degrees)
1302 PERSONALITYAND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

in a rationalization of the existing state of affairs whether ical outcomes. First, a number of survey studies address
they are personally responsible and whether they stand postdecisional dissonance reductiOn following voting
to gain or lose. Furthermore, the legitimation needs of behavior. Second, a set of studies indicates that expecta-
the system are best served by people anticipating likely tions and evaluations are intercorrelated. We briefly
outéomes and rationalizing them in advance; to the review the contributions and limitations of each of these
extent that people are highly motivated tojustify the sys- lines of research before providing an overview of our
tem, they should engage in anticipatory rationalization own hypotheses and research designs.
of probable outcomes in addition to the more typical Dissonance reduction and the voting booth. Social scien-
rationalization of past action. tists often have drawn on dissonance theory in seeking to
The dynamic theory ofthought systems. Probably the most understand responses to electoral outcomes (e.g.,
comprehensive theoretical treatment of the specific Beasley &Joslyn, 2001; Frenkel & Doob, 1976; Granberg
relation between expectations and evaluations comes & Brent, 1983; Granberg & Nanneman, 1986; Regan &
from McGuire and McGuire’s (1991) dynamic theory of Kilduff, 1988). This link makes a great deal of sense
“thought systems.” Their general assumption is that atti- given that the element (or illusion) of choice is pre-
tudes and beliefs are linked probabilistically in the men- sumed to be central to the operation of cognitive disso-
tal system so that a change in one beliefproduces ripple nance and to the effectiveness of democratic institu-
effects on other remote areas of the mental system (see tions. Research demonstrates that people evaluate their
also McGuire, 1960; Wyer, 1970). According to the preferred candidates more favorably after having voted
“rationalization postulate,” people cope with future than before (Frenkel & Doob, 1976; Regan & Kilduff,
events by bringing their judgments of desirability into 1988). In addition, people provide more diffuse support
congruence with judgments of likelihood. The authors for the political system after having voted, even if their
specify a symmetrical relation, such that preferred candidate lost the election (Ginsberg &
Weissberg, 1978; Nadeau & Blais, 1993). Thus, voting
This adjustment includes both (a) a “sweet lemon” ratio- appears to increase commitment to the system as a
nalization such that an increase in [likelihood] should whole.
raise [desirability] and so raise the number of desirable Most previous applications of rationalization and dis-
consequencesthat the core eventis perceived as promot-
sonance theory to political contexts have emphasized
ing and the number of undesirable consequences it is
the role of self-justification and the post hoc rationaliza-
perceived as preventing; and also (b) a “sour grapes”
rationalization such that a decrease in [likelihood] tion of one’s own voting preferences or behaviors. By
should decrease [desirability] and so raise the number drawing on system justification theory (Jost & Banaji,
of undesirable consequences that the core event is per- 1994), we propose that people rationalize not only their
ceived as promoting and the number of desirable conse- own attitudinal or behavioral commitments but also
quences it is perceived as preventing. (McGuire & anticipated outcomes forwhich they are not responsible.
McGuire, 1991, p. 7) This approach is consistent with research on “outcome
biases,” according to which people attribute favorable
Putting the “sweetlemon” and “sour grapes” rationaliza- characteristics to winning candidates and unfavorable
tions together, one derives the prediction of a positive, characteristics to losing candidates once the outcome is
linear relation betweenjudgments of likelihood and de- known (Allison, Mackie, & Messick, 1996).
sirability. By changing the subjective probability ofa core Ourtheoretical perspective also is consistent with sur-
event, it should be possible to observe changes in its per- vey results reported by Granberg and Nanneman (1986)
ceived desirability. The idea here is not simply that peo- that voters’ overall liking for Ronald Reagan increased
pIe hope that their wishes will be fulfilled. The rational- immediately following his 1980 electoral victory, and
ization postulate holds that people will even embrace their liking for Jimmy Carter decreased following his
and adapt to unwanted outcomes by enhancing the sub- defeat. Similarly, Beasley and Joslyn (2001) found that
jective value of an event as it becomes more likely to oc- people whose preferred candidate lost the election sub-
cur. Somewhat counterintuitively, people should even sequently elevated their evaluations of the winning
subjectively enhance the value of impending outcomes (nonpreferred) candidate and derogated the losing
that are contrary to their own consciously held interests (initially preferred) candidate. These results suggest
(Elster, 1983;Jost, 1995; Lane, 1962). that people do adjust their own wishes to come to terms
with irreversible outcomes (see also Gilbert & Ebert,
Limitations ofPast Research on
2001; Gilbertetal., 1998), buttheydo notprovide defini-
the Rationalization ofSocial and Political Outcomes
tive support for the notion that people bring their evalu-
There are two separate bodies of research that are ations into line with expectations or that they engage in a
directly relevant to the rationalization ofsocial and polit- “sour grapes” rationalization ofpolitical candidates. The
Kay et al. / ANTICIPATORYRATIONALIZATION 1303

chief limitation of previous studies is that rationalization events”) were not motivationally charged enough to
is inferred from the difference between pre-election and prompt rationalization by undergraduate respondents.
post-election attitudes, but there is no methodological A study conducted by Pyszczynski (1982) lends sup-
control over what happens in the interim. Thus, changes port to the notion that people rationalize anticipated
in desirability are confounded with a number of other outcomes only when they are relatively consequential.
factors, including media coverage of the elections and Research participants who believed that their chances of
the candidates’ actual responses to winning or losing the winning a lottery were relatively high were more likely to
election. perceive the reward as attractive than were people who
believed that their chancesof winning were low, but only
The preference-expectation link and the role ofmotivational when the potential reward was large (and therefore
involvement. A number of studies conducted over several highly motivating) and notwhen itwas small. Pyszczynski
decades indicate that, in general, ratings of probability (1982) concluded that people derogate unlikely positive
and desirability are positively intercorrelated (e.g., Eiser
outcomes as a way of avoiding disappointment, and it is
& Eiser, 1975; Granberg & Brent, ~983; McGuire, 1960;
true that his results seem to provide more support for the
Rothbart, 1970). For instance, McGuire (1960) com- “sour grapes” derogation of the highly attractive prize
pared ratings of the truth and the desirability of48 differ-
than for the “sweet lemon” appreciation of the less
ent propositions and found that the mean correlation
attractive prize. However, it may be that the motivational
was .40. Eiser and Eiser (1975) obtained a mean correla-
properties of the large reward in his study—and not nec-
tion of .54 between estimates of the probability and
essarily its level of attractiveness per se—produced the
desirability of 39 possible future events. In the domain of
rationalization effect. In other words, people may not
politics, Granberg and Brent (1983) reported an average
have cared enough about the small reward to rationalize
correlation of .51 between the expectation that Reagan
it, but they might have rationalized a highly motivating
(or Carter) would win the 1980 U.S. presidential elec-
negative possibility such as a large punishment. Thus,
tion and the comparative evaluation of that candidate.
previous failures to support both “halves” of the rational-
The fairly obvious limitation of such correlational evi-
dence, however, is that it does not allow one to distin- ization postulate might be attributable to researchers’
relative neglect of the importance of motivational
guish between wish fulfillment (the tendency to rate
desirable events as more likely to occur) and rationaliza- involvement in the process of rationalization.
The notion that motivational involvement is critical to
tion (the tendency to rate likely events as more
desirable). rationalization tendencies is present not only in Freud-
ian theory but also in contemporary theorizing in the
To overcome this ambiguity, McGuire (1960) experi- area of motivated social cognition (e.g., Festinger, 1957;
mentally induced a change in the belief that an event Kruglanski, 1996; Kunda, 1990). If outcomes are
would occur to observe changes in desirability. Findings motivationally insignificant, then it follows that people
supported the general notion that people engaged in would have no need to rationalize them. If the fox truly
rationalization by increasing the judged desirability of a did not care whether she reached the grapes, then she
proposition and, to a lesser extent, a logically related would have no psychological need to derogate them. To
proposition following a change in their estimates of the clarify the difference between our position and tradi-
likelihood of that proposition being true (McGuire, tional dissonance theorizing, we point out that motiva-
1960, p. 85). This demonstration was provocative but tional involvement is not the same as personal responsi-
failed to provide a strong test of both “halves” of the bility. Thus, people may be highly affected by (and
rationalization postulate, which would include both (a) therefore rationalize) social and political outcomes that
a “sour grapes” derogation of an initially attractive out- are not of their own choosing (e.g., Elster, 1983; Jost,
come and (b) a “sweet lemon” elevation of an initially 1995; Lane, 1962).
unattractive outcome. An increased focus on motivation is consistent with
McGuire and McGuire (1991) sought to provide McGuire and McGuire’s (1991) hypothesis that some
more concrete support for the rationalization postulate links in a thought system are “tighter” than others. They
by examining the number of desirable and undesirable argue that structural links among beliefs are more tightly
consequences freely generated by research participants articulated to the extent that they involve events or out-
in response to a range of attractive and unattractive comes that are highly self-relevant. Furthermore,
events. Unfortunately, their results failed to provide any according to the theory of thought systems, the tighter
evidence of rationalization, regardless of the type of the link, the more likely it is that a disturbance in one
event. One reason for the lack of evidence may be that area will affect another. This means that changes in the
the events studied by the McGuires (e.g., “Admission perceived likelihood of an event are more likely to pro-
prices will increase substantially for major sports duce (rationalization) effects on judged desirability to
1304 PERSONALITYAND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

the extent that the domain is highly motivating. Thus, as hood of a wanted outcome—people would express
Sherman (1991) has pointed Out, the theory of thought greater commitment toward their preferred choice. A
systems is like other theories that stress the interplay of similar prediction follows from theories of scarcity and
cognitive and motivational factors in arriving at desired reactance, which would predict that as a desired out-
conclusions (e.g., Kunda, 1990). come becomes less available (i.e., less likely), it also
would become more desirable (e.g., Cialdini, 2001). By
Summary ofHypotheses contrast, our rationalization hypothesis indicates that
people should engage in a stibjective.elevation of all out-
Our integration of theories of cognitive dissonance,
comes to the extent that their likelihood increases.
systemjustification, and dynamic thought systems led us
In writing about the subjective utility of anticipated
to predict that people would engage in anticipatory
outcomes, Elster and Loewenstein (1992) proposed that
rationalization of probable nonvolitional outcomes as
people “savor” desirable events that are likely and
long as they were motivationally involving. We sought to
“dread” undesirable events that are likely. The hypothe-
investigate both the “sour grapes” and “sweet lemon”
sis that follows from their analysis is that the initial
forms of rationalization. Specifically, we hypothesized
valence of an event will be experienced in more intense
that for both initially attractive and unattractive out-
terms as its likelihood increases. The savoring of desir-
comes people would bring their judgments of desirabil-
able events as they become more likely is consistent with
ity into line with their perceptions of likelihood, but only
the rationalization hypothesis, but the dreading of unde-
when motivational involvement was high. For outcomes
sirable events as they become more likely is at odds with
that were low in motivational involvement (whether
the “sweet lemon” form of rationalization.
attractive or unattractive), judgments of desirability
Finally, the rationalization hypothesis also differs
should be unaffected by perceptions of likelihood. We
from what would be expected on the basis of theories of
examined these hypotheses in one quasi-experimental
intergroup conflict (e.g., Tajfel & Turner, 1986), namely,
field study involving the rationalization of anticipated that partisans under threat would derogate outgroup
electoral outcomes (Study 1) and one experimental
members in the presence of intense competition, as in a
study involving the rationalization of tuition increases
tightly contested political election. By contrast, our pre-
and decreases (Study 2). diction, which hinges on the notion that motivated par-
Ourmain rationalization hypothesis differs from sev-
ticipants will come to rationalize whichever outcome
eral other predictions that one could make concerning
they deem to be likely, is that highly involved partisans
people’s reactions to changes in perceived likelihood. In will derogate their own candidate when faced with the
the realm of politics, for instance, researchers have
likelihood of his or her defeat (a “sour grapes” rational-
argued for the existence of an “underdog effect” ization) and enhance or elevate ratings of the opposing.
whereby people shift their preferences in the direction candidate when faced with the likelihood that he or she
of the less popular (and thus less likely) candidate (e.g., will be elected (a “sweet lemon” rationalization).
Ceci & Kain, 1982). This is a tendency that would pre-
sumably lead people to shift their evaluations of a less
STUDY 1
likely outcome in a positive direction. Conversely,
Mehrabian (1998) has provided evidence for a “band- In the first study, we hypothesized that political parti-
wagon effect” such that people show increased support sans (who are highly self-involved), but not nonparti-
for the candidat&’whom they believe to be more popular sans, would enhance the perceived desirability of either
(see also Simon, 1954). Our rationalization hypothesis candidate’s election in response to evidence indicating
differs from the bandwagon hypothesis largely in terms that he is• likely to win. To investigate this possibility, we
of the two hypotheses’ implications for the behavior of examined beliefs and attitudes concerning the 2000 U.S.
nonpartisans and undecided voters. Whereas our presidential election. In the context of a briefsurvey, we
hypothesis suggests that nonpartisans would be less manipulated the perceived likelihood that Gore or Bush
likely than partisans to enhance the subjective desirabil- would win the election and then measured attitudes
ity of the leading candidate, the bandwagon hypothesis toward each of the candidates. We also obtained infor-
implies that people who are not as invested in the out- mation about respondents’ political affiliations so that
come would be more likely to be influenced by consen- we could compare the responses of Democratic and
sual influence. Republican partisans (who one might expect to be
Our rationalization hypothesis also differs from some highly involved in the outcome of a Gore-Bush election)
formulations of cognitive dissonance theory, such as with those of Independent and undecided nonpartisans
those of Festinger, Riecken, and Schachter (1956) and (who one would expect to be less personally involved in
Batson (1975), which would suggest that in the face of the outcome of this election). We hypothesized that for
disconfirming evidence—such as a decrease in the likeli- partisans only there would be a positive, linear relation-
Kay et a!. / ANTICIPATORYRATIONALIZATION 1305

ship between the perceived likelihood of a given candi- research participants were asked to indicate their politi-
date’s being elected and the assessed desirability of that cal affiliation (Republican, Democrat, Independent,
outcome. Other), age, and gender.
Method Results

PARTICIPANTS Effects of demographic variables. We conducted a


During the week immediately preceding the election multivariate analysis to examine the effects of gender
and age on desirability ratings of the two candidates. In
of November 7, 2000, we approached a total of 288 indi-
addition to variables of partisanship and outcome likeli-
viduals and asked them to complete a short written sur-
hood, the analysis included dummy variables for demo-
vey at one of three locations: (a) the San Francisco air-
graphic variables ofrespondent sex and age, the latter of
port, (b) a shopping mall in Palo Alto, California, and
which was coded as 1 of 6 discrete categories according
(c) the campus ofStanford University. Ofthe 286 partici-
to the following age ranges: 18-30, 31-40, 41-50, 51-60,
pants who disclosed information about political affilia-
61-70, 71 and older. The analysis yielded only a main
tion, 115 indicated that they were Democrats, 83 indi-
effect of gender on desirability ratings, F(2, 157) 3.09,
cated that they were Republicans, and 88 indicated they
p < .05. Univariate analyses revealed that a Gore presi-
were Independents, nonpartisans, or undecided. The
dencywas rated as more desirable by female respondents
respondents were diverse with respect to race and eth-
(M= 5.78) than by male respondents (M= 5.26), F(1,
nicity, age (ranging from 18-81, M= 41.0), and gender
158) = 4.40, p< .05, whereas a Bush presidency was rated
(154 men, 130 women, and 4 who declined to indicate
as more desirable by men (M = 4.45) than by women
their sex).
(M= 4.16), F~1,158) = 5.93,p< .05. This pattern is consis-
PROCEDURE tent with past research on the “gender gap” in politics
Research participants received one of five different (see Miller, Taylor, & Buck, 1991). There were no signifi-
versions of an election survey designed first to manipu- cant main effects of age and there were no interaction
late beliefs concerning likelihood and second to mea- effects between demographic and experimental vari-
sure attitudes concerning desirability. All versions of the ables. Thus, gender and age were dropped from all fur-
questionnaire began with the same introduction: ther analyses.
MULTIVA JATEANALYSIS
There is an exp~ertgroup of political analysts (working
together at Stanford, Harvard, Gallup Poll services, and Effects of partisanship and outcome likelihood. We con-
the Brookings Institute) who specialize in predicting ducted a multivariate analysisofvariance to examine the
“last minute shifts” in public opinion. This group has effects of independent variables of partisanship (three
successfully predicted the outcomes ofthe last four pres- levels: Republicans, Democrats, and nonpartisans) and
idential elections within a 1% margin of error. Accord- outcome likelihood (five levels rangingfrom strong likeli-
ing to theircalculations, the mostlikely outcome ofvotes hood ofa Gorevictory to strong likelihood ofaBush victory) on
that will be cast on election day this year will be as fol- the two dependent measures ofBush and Gore desirabil-
lows... ity ratings. The analysis yielded main effects of outcome
likelihood, F(4, 272) = 4.23, p < .05, and partisanship,
Following this introduction, the questionnaire indicated F(2, 271) = 106.41, p< .001, on the combined desirability
that the expert grotip predicted either a 51% to 43% scores. The predicted interaction between outcome like-
Gore victory (condition 1), a 49% to 45% Gore victory lihood and partisanship also was significant, F(8, 271) =
(condition 2), a 47% to 47% tie (condition 3), a 49% to 2.14, p < .05. Mean desirability ratings for Bush are
45% Bush victory (condition 4), or a 51% to 43% Bush graphed in Figure 1 and for Gore in Figure 2 as a func-
victory (condition 5). Thus, we adapted McGuire’s tion of perceived likelihood and motivational involve-
(1960) method of introducing a change in perceived ment (i.e., partisanship). Follow-up univariate analyses
likelihood and observing remote changes injudged de- of variance were conducted to examine the specific
sirability. effects of study variables on each of the Bush and Gore
Following the manipulation of beliefs concerning desirability ratings separately.
likely electoral outcomes, research participants were
UNIVARIATE ANALYSES
then asked, (a) “How desirable or undesirable would it
be for you ifGore were elected president?” and (b) “How Bush desirability ratings. To determine whether the per-
desirable or undesirable would it be foryou if Bush were ceived likelihood of Bush winning the election affected
elected president?” Participants responded to both ques- ratings of the desirability of a Bush presidency, a
tions on 9-point scales ranging from 1 (strongly undesir- between-subjects univariate ANOVA was conducted.
able) to 9 (strongly desirable). At the end of the survey, The analysis yielded a significant main effect of outcome
1306 PERSQNALITYAND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

~9

6
8

~+- ~
— —

—• Republicsns
t~__
6 ~ -.... ...•. —— Republicans
—0—Democrats
—el---Democrats
~ 45 •. ~ . .. .1.. ... 4 ~.•_ •.. Nonpsrtissns
- -• Nonpartissns

n2 3 ~-~--~-
~
~l
43/51 45/49 47/47 49/45 53/41 43/51 45/49 47/47 49/45 53/41

Perceived Likelihood ofa Bush victory Perceived Likelihood of aGore victory

Figure 1 Desirability ratings of a Bush presidency. Figure 2 Desirability ratings of a Gore presidency.

likelihood, F(4, 271) = 2.96, p< .02, indicating that Bush Once again, to test for linearity between perceived
was indeed perceived as more desirable as the likelihood likelihood andjudged desirability, separate weighted lin-
of his winning the election increased. Not surprisingly, ear contrast tests were performed on the ratings pro-
there was a huge main effect of partisanship, F(2, 271) = vided by the three respondent groups of Republicans,
97.18, p < .001, such that Bush was rated as much more Democrats, and nonpartisans. Evidence of rationaliza-
desirable by Republicans than by Democrats or nonpar- tion was obtained for both of the highly involved parti-
tisans. As hypothesized, a statistically reliable interaction san groups (see Figure 2). Republicans showed a “sweet
between outcome likelihood and partisanship also was lemon” tendency to rate Gore as more desirable as the
obtained, F(8, 271) = 2M4, p < .05. perceived likelihood of a Gore victory increased, F( 1,
To clarify the nature of this two-way interaction and to 78) = 16.82, p < .001. The same linear contrast effect also
investigate hypothesized linear relationships between was obtained for Democratic respondents, F(1, 110) =
perceived likelihood and judged desirability, weighted 6.00, p < .05, who exhibited a “sour grapes” tendency to
linear contrast tests were performed separately for each rate Gore as less desirable as his election seemed less
of the three different partisan groups (Republicans, probable. Nonpartisans showed no significant rational-
Democrats, and nonpartisans). For Republican respon- ization tendencies, F(1, 83) = .95, ns, presumably
dents, the weighted linear contrast test attained conven- because they were not sufficiently motivationally
tional levels ofstatistical significance, F~1,78) =16.37, p < invested in the outcome of a Bush-Gore election.
.001. As can be seen in Figure 1, Republicans demon-
Discussion
strated a strong monotonic tendency to rate Bush as
more desirable as the perceived likelihood of a Bush vic- Findings from Study 1 indicate that when people are
tory increased and, conversely, to rate him as less desir- confronted with an outcome that is highly involving,
able as the perceived likelihood of his winning their judgments of the desirability of that outcome are
decreased, thereby supporting the “sour grapes” ratio- brought into congruence with perceptions of likeli-
nalization hypothesis. For Democratic respondents, the hood. Messages involving predictions of electoral out-
weighted linear contrast was marginally significant, P~1, comes made by expert sources influenced both Republi-
110) = 16.83, p = .07. Democrats exhibited a modest can and Democratic respondents’ ratings of the
“sweet lemon” tendency to rate Bush as more desirable desirability of Bush and Gore presidencies. Specifically,
as his election seemed more probable (see Figure 1) For .
we have provided some support for the “sour grapes”
nonpartisans, the linear contrast test revealed no evi- rationalization that people tend to derogate a previously
dence of rationalization ofthe anticipated outcome,$1, attractive outcome as it becomes less probable and, per-
83) = 1.48, ns. haps more surprisingly, for the “sweet lemon” rational-
Gore desirability ratings. Univariate analysis of variance ization that people tend to elevate an initially unattrac-
revealed a strong main effect of outcome likelihood, F(4, tive outcome as it becomes more probable. This study
271) = 4.16, p < .005, indicating that a Gore presidency also suggests that the use of rationalization is restricted
was perceived as significantly more desirable as the antic- to people who are highly motivated by personally conse-
ipated likelihood of his winning increased. A huge main quential outcomes, whether those outcomes are consid-
effect of partisanship, F(2, 271) = 86.77, p < .001, con- ered to befavorable or unfavorable (see also Pyszczynski,
firmed that Gore was rated as much less desirable by 1982). Nonpartisans exhibited no tendency to rational-
Republicans than by Democrats or nonpartisans. The ize anticipated electoral outcomes, either because they
interaction between outcome likelihood and partisan- had no strongly preferred candidate or because they
ship was found to be marginally significant, F(8, 271) = knew that their third party candidate had no chance of
1.84, p < .07. winning.
Kay et al. / ANTICIPATORY RATIONALIZATION 1307

However, as is often the case with field studies, several sensus information from being conveyed along with the
methodological concerns cotild be raised. First, the information regarding likelihood, perceptions of likeli-
political context in which this study occurred was clearly hood were induced bymanipulating the perceived prob-
“one-of-a-kind.” It was perhaps the strangest and closest ability that a select committee of university officials (not
election in U.S. history and one might well suspect that the student body) would implement a specific outcome.
our results lack generalizability. Second, we assumed By examining hypothetical increases and decreases in
that nonpartisans would be less motivationally involved tuition, we were able to further investigate the possibility
than partisans in the outcome of a Bush-Gore election, that anticipated rationalizations do not merely serve as
but this assumption may have been wrong. Third, parti- disappointment buffers for initially attractive outcomes,
sans and nonpartisans may have differed in other ways as Pyszczynski (1982) has argued, but can occur in the
that were not controlled. Fourth, because some of the presence of any motivationally charged outcome, even
questionnaires were collected directly from individual outcomes that are initially unattractive (see Elster, 1983;
participants, it is conceivable that impression manage- Jost, 1995; Lane, 1962). Thus, we hypothesized that a
ment concerns contributed to the pattern of results. And highly attractive large tuition decrease would become
finally, our manipulation of perceived likelihood was less desirable as it becomes less likely (a “sour grapes”
confounded with consensus information, which has rationalization) and that a highly unattractive large tui-
been shown to be a powerful determinant of attitude tion increase should become mdre desirable as it
change (e.g., Cialdini, 2001; Stangor, Sechrist, & Jost, becomes more likely (a “sweet lemon” rationalization).
2001). To address all of these concerns, we conducted a
Method
second study in which we examined studentresponses to
a typical university policy decision, manipulated motiva- RESEARCH PARTICIPA
tional involvement directly rather than relying on Research participants for Study 2 were 203 students
self-reports, collected the data in an anonymous from an introductory psychology class at Stanford Uni-
mass-testing situation, and used a manipulation of per- versity. The participants included 72 men, 122 women,
ceived likelihood that was unrelated to perceived and 9 participants who elected not to convey gender
consensus. information. Ages ranged from 18 to 22 years. All of the
students participated in the experiment in exchange for
STUDY 2 class credit.
We have argued that past attempts to provide support PROCEDURE
for both “halves” of the rationalization postulate have
Participants were instructed that the purpose of the
failed because they did not adequately account for the
research was to gauge freshman and sophomore opinion
role of motivational involvement in the rationalization
regarding a pending matter oftuition policy at Stanford.
process (McGuire & McGuire, 1991; Pyszczynski, 1982).
Theywere then presented with 1 of 12 versions of the fol-
In Study 2, universitystudents in a mass-testing situation
lowing statement, according to a 2 (outcome valence:
rated the desirability of tuition increases or decreases
tuition increase vs. tuition decrease) x 2 (motivational
that were either large or small in magnitude and low,
medium, or high in perceived likelihood. Thus, the involvement: large vs. small change) x 3 (likelihood: low
research design was a 2 (outcome valence: tuition vs. medium vs. high) experimental design:
increase vs. tuition decrease) x 2 (motivational involve-
According to national trends and Stanford’s current eco-
ment: large vs. small change) x 3 (likelihood: low vs.
nomic situation, the University board of Trustees esti-
medium vs. high) between-subjects factorial. It was mate that there is a 20% [or5O% or8O%] likelihood that
hypothesized that the motivationally involving (large) undergraduate students will see a very large [or smallIJ
tuition increases and decreases both would be increas- increase [ordecrease] in their tuition over the next 3 years.
ingly rationalized as their likelihood increased, whereas
the less motivationally engaging (small) tuition Participants were asked to rate how desirable or undesir-
increases and decreases would not. able it would be for them personally if this was to occur.
With this procedure, we experimentally manipulated Ratings were made on a 15-point scale, ranging from 1
the level of motivational involvement (i.e., by using both (extremely undesirable) to 8 (neither desirable nor undesirable)
large and small tuition changes) rather than simply to 15 (extremely desirable).
assuming that people fall into different motivational cat-
MANIPULATION CHECKS (USING A DIFFERENTSAMPLE)
egories based on group memberships. To minimize any
potential impression-management concerns, all partici- It was deemed necessary to verify that our relatively
pants completed the questionnaires simultaneously in subtle experimental manipulations of perceived likeli-
an anonymous mass-testing situation. To prevent con- hood and motivational involvement were indeed having
1308 PERSONALITY AND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

their intended effects, but we were concerned that ask- what extent will it affect you personally?” (b) “To what
ing study respondents to explicitly repeat information extent do you feel that you (i.e., the student body)
• contained in the experimental questionnaire would should have a say in atuition change of this size?” and (c)
arouse suspicion and potentially bias their ratings of out- “How much ofan impact do you feel this tuition change
come desirability. Therefore, a separate and comparable would have on the current student body?” These ques-
sample of Stanford undergraduate students (N = 183) tions were answered on a 9-point scale with labels rang-
was exposed to the same experimental manipulations as ing from it will not affect me at all to it will affect me a great
in the main study and then asked to respond (under pri- dealfor item 1, no say at auto a very large say for item 2,
vate, anonymous conditions) to three items checking on and no impact at all to a very large impact for item 3. An
the manipulation of perceived likelihood and three index was computed by taking the mean of these three
items checking on the manipulation of motivational items (a= .65).
involvement. - We then conducted a univariate analysis of variance
Perceived likelihood. The three items used as manipula- with the same independent variables mentioned above
and the dependent variable of perceived involvement
tion checks for perceived likelihood were as follows: (a)
(the mean score on the three manipulation check
“How likely do you believe it is that this tuition change
items). As expected, there was a significant main effect of
will happen?” (b) “How likely do you feel it is that Stan-
involvement condition, F( 1, 171) = 56.44, p< .001. Partic-
ford undergraduate tuition will remain relatively
ipants reported feeling more personally affected by the
unchanged over the next 3 years?” (reverse-scored) and
“very large” tuition changes (M= 6.53) than by the “very
(c) “In your opinion, how much of a chance do you
small” tuition changes (M= 5.41). There was also a main
believe there is that this tuition change will actually
effect of valence, F( 1, 171) = 5.21, p < .05, indicating that
occur?” These questions were answered on a 9-point
tuition increases were rated as more involving (M= 6.22)
scale,which had labels ranging from not atall likely to very
than were tuition decreases (M= 5.68). No othermain or
likely for items 1 and 2 and not much of a chance to a very
interaction effects were obtained.
good chance for item 3. An index was computed by taking
the mean of these three items (a = .83). Results
We then conducted a univariate analysis ofvariance in
which the dependent variable was perceived likelihood Effects of demographic variables. There were no main
(the mean score on the three manipulation check effects of age or gender on the desirability ratings, and
items). Dummy codes for the experimental variables of there were no interactions between these demographic
perceived likelihood, valence (i.e., tuition increases vs. variables and any of the experimentally manipulated
tuition decreases), and involvement (i.e., very large vs. variables. Therefore, age and gender were dropped
very small change) were entered as independent vari- from subsequent analyses.
ables. A significant main effect of likelihood condition
Effects of valence, outcome, and likelihood. A 2 x 2 x 3
was obtained, F~2,171) = 48.88, p < .001, indicating that
between-subjects analysis of variance was performed to
self-reports of perceived likelihood were indeed affected
examine the affects of motivational involvement (small
by manipulations of outcome likelihood in the intended
vs. large tuition changes), outcomevalence (increases vs.
direction. (Mean ratings of perceived likelihood were
decreases in tuition), and perceived likelihood (20% vs.
4.26, 4.63, and 6.0.0 in the 20%, 50%, and 80% condi-
50% vs. 80%) on desirability ratings of the potential out-
tions, respectively.)
come. Not too surprisingly, there was a huge main effect
In addition, amain effect ofvalence indicated that tui-
of valence, F(1, 191) = 291.15, p < .OQ1, indicating that
tion increases were generally perceived as more likely
tuition decreases were always rated as more desirable
(M= 6.24) than were tuition decreases (M= 3.64), F(1,
than tuition increases. As hypothesized, the analysis
171) = 106.77,p< .001. Valence did not interact with the
yielded a significant two-way interaction between per-
likelihood manipulation, P~2,171) = .36, suggesting that
ceived likelihood and motivational involvement, F(2,
the likelihood manipulation exerted comparable effects
191) = 5.82, p < .005. The three-way interaction was not
in both valence conditions. For both tuition increases
significant, F(2, 191) = .32, p = .73. Regardless of their
and decreases, mean scores on the manipulation check
valence, all highly involving outcomes were rationalized.
increased sequentially from the 20% to 50% to 80% con- Thus, large (but not small) changes were rationalized
ditions. No other main or interaction effects were whether they involved tuition increases or decreases (see
obtained. Figure 3). Because we hypothesized that people would
Motivational involvement. The three items used as engage in both “sweet lemon” and “sour grapesZ’ types of
manipulation checks for motivational involvement were rationalizations, we also conducted separate- ‘internal
as follows: (a) “If this tuition change does happen, to analyses for tuition increases and de&ea es~
Kay et al. / ANTICIPATORY RATIONALIZATION 1309

1.36, p < .001, indicating that a large tuition increase was


10
always seen as less desirable than a small tuition
‘S
•. ... . ./‘ • —.— High Involvement decrease. The predicted two-way interaction involving
likelihood and involvement also attained statistical sig-
8 ~ .. -. - - Low Involvement
nificance, F(2, 109) = 3.28, p < .05.
Separate weighted linear contrast tests were once
~7.—
again performed for participants assigned to highversus
6
20% 50% 80% low involvement conditions (see means in Figure 4).
Perceived Likelihood Under conditions of high involvement, a significant lin-
ear relationship between perceived likelihood and
Figure 3 Desirability ratings of tuition changes (increases and de. judged desirability indicated that an aversive tuition
creases combined) under high versus low involvement.
increase was rated as less undesirable (or more desir-
able) as its likelihood increased, F(1, 53) = 16.24, p
.001, providing evidence of a “sweet lemon” rationaliza-
tion. Participants assigned to the low involvement condi-
tion showed no such linear association between likeli-
r~t~tion hood and desirability, F(1, 56) = .18,~ns.
•~D~~Low
Involvement/Tuition
Discussion
9 • Increase
High These findings, which extend and replicate those of
1 7 0.~. Involvement/Tuition
Decrease Study 1, suggest that when confronted with information

~: - . ~ ~,~::ent!ruition
concerning likelihood, people do indeed rationalize
motivationally significant anticipated outcomes. Of
interest, people engage in the rationalization of undesir-
able as well ~asdesirable outcomes (e.g., Elster, 1983;Jost,
1995; Lane, 1962). Our experimental methods demon-
20% 50% • 80%
strate a causal connection: Changes in perceived likeli-
Perceived Likelihood of a Tuition hood lead to changes in judged desirability. Further-
Increase
more, the effects of perceived likelihood in Study 2 are
Figure 4 Desirabilityratings oftuitionincreases and decreases under not attributable to the effects of consensus information
high versus low involvement. (e.g., Cialdini, 2001; Stangor et al., 2001).

Rationalization of tuition decreases. A univariate analysis GENERAL DISCUSSION


of variance was performed to examine the effects of
motivational involvement and perceived likelihood on An abundance of research on cognitive dissonance
desirability ratings of a tuition decrease (a favorable out- theory demonstrates that people tend to rationalize
behavioral outcomes for which they are personally
come). Theanalysis yielded only an interaction between
involvement and likelihood, F~2,82) = 3.04, p = .05. responsible (Aronson, 1973/1989; Brehm, 1956;
Festinger, 1957; Frenkel & Doob, 1976). The present
Means are illustrated in Figure 4.
research, drawing also on system justification theory
To interpret the interaction, separate weighted linear
(Jost& Banaji, 1994) and the dynamic theory of thought
contrast tests were performed for participants assigned
systems (McGuire & McGuire, 1991), demonstrates that
to high versus low involvement conditions on judged
people begin to rationalize likely, uncontrollable events
desirability. When motivational involvement was high, a
before they happen. In two studies, using both
significant linear effect of likelihood was observed on
real-world and experimentally manipulated outcomes,
desirability ratings, F(1, 43) = 37.75, p < .001, indicating
we have demonstrated that people rationalize antici-
that tuition decreases werejudged to be less desirable as
pated outcomes in response to their perceived
they became less likely (a “sour grapes” rationalization).
likelihood.
When involvement was low, no such linear trend was
Our evidence supports the operation of a “sour
observed, F(1, 39) = .25, ns. grapes” rationalization, whereby an initially attractive
Rationalization oftuition increases. Univariate analysis of outcome (i.e., the election of one’s preferred candidate
variance was performed to examine the effects of or a tuition decrease) becomes less desirable as it
involvement and likelihood on desirability ratings of a becomes less likely (e.g., Elster, 1983; Pyszczynski, 1982).
tuition increase as well (i.e., an unfavorable outcome) A . In addition, we have providedevidence for the more elu-
main effect of involvement was observed, 1~1,109) = sive “sweet lemon” rationalization, whereby an initially
1310 PERSONALITY AND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

unwanted outcome (i.e., the election of an opposing selectively process information to arrive at desired con-
candidate or a tuition hike) becomes more desirable as clusions (Kruglanski, 1996; Kunda, 1990; Sherman,
its likelihood increases (e.g., Jost, 1995; Lane, 1962; 1991). To suggest that the process is a motivated one
McGuire & McGuire, 1991). In the case of both attractive does not mean that it is driven by a conscious “will” (see
and unattractive outcomes, we have determined that Bargh, Gollwitzer, Lee-Chai, Barndollar, & Trotschel,
anticipatory rationalizations occur only with 2001). We are not arguing that participants in the high
motivationally involving outcomes. It now seems likely involvement conditions were more consciously “moti-
that previous failures to find support for the rationaliza- vated” than participants in the low involvement condi-
tion hypothesis (especially the “sweet lemon” variety) tions to shift their desirability ratings into aligriment with
may be attributable to a relative lack of motivational their likelihood beliefs. Rather, we speculate that motiva-
involvement on the part of research participants (e.g., tional involvement activates a more tightly associated
McGuire & McGuire, 1991; Pyszczynski, 1982). cognitive network, so that changes in attitudes are more
No support was obtained for the “underdog effect” in consequential when motivation is high than~low (see
politics (Ceci & Kain, 1982), and only partial support was McGuire & McGuire, 1991). This is one sensible way to
obtained for the “bandwagon effect” (Mehrabian, 1998; conceptualize the dynamic interaction that occurs
Simon, 1954). There was no evidence that making an ini- between cognitive and motivational processes (e.g.,
tially attractive outcome seem less likely had the effect of Sherman, 1991). Clearly, future research is needed to
enhancing commitment, liking, or differentiation from elucidate the specific psychological mechanisms at work.
the opposition, as several alternative theories would pre- Third, morework is needed to determine whether the
dict (Batson, 1975; Cialdini, 2001; Festinger et al., 1956; affective functions and consequences of the “sour
Tajfel & Turner, 1986). Although people may have grapes” and “sweet lemon” rationalizations are identical.
“savored” desirable events as they became more likely, Although McGuire and McGuire (1991) suggested that
they did not appear to “dread” likely undesirable events, both types of anticipatory rationalizations probably
as Elster and Loewenstein (1992) hypothesized. Rather, serve to help people meet general “autistic” or “hedonic”
we found that people enhanced the subjective value of needs, the two processes may differ in important ways.
probable events and diminished the subjective value of Specifically, it is at least conceivable that “sour grapes”
improbable events, regardless of their valence. rationalizations would be more associated with pessimis-
tic thinking styles (e.g., Zullow, Oettingen, Peterson, &
LIMITATIONS AM) FUTUREDIRECTIONS Seligman, 1988), whereas “sweet lemon” rationalizations
Although the studies reported here extend our might be more associated with optimism (e.g., Taylor &
appreciation of the ways in which people are “rationaliz- Brown, 1988). If this is true, then the two types of ratio-
ing animals” (Aronson, 1973/1989), there are several nalizations may turn out to have very different conse-
limitations that should be addressed in future research. quences for coping and mental health (e.g., Aspinwall &
First, we know that in the social and political world peo- Taylor, 1992).
ple do not always adapt themselves to unwelcome reali- A fourth, more minor methodological limitation of
ties. The historical record shows that whereas cases of our research is that perceived likelihood was con-
rebellion and revolution are relatively infrequent com- founded with social consensus in Study 1 (but not Study
pared to more prevalent tendencies toward stability and 2) and motivational involvement was confounded with
acquiescence, they certainly do occur (Gurr, 1970; the magnitude of the anticipated change in Study 2 (but
Moore, 1978). Thus, more research is needed to deter- not Study 1). Although we believe that these variables
mine the limits of rationalization. Marx and Engels often do covary in the “real world” for psychological as
(1848/1977) theorized that the working poor would well as social reasons, it would be worthwhile to further
only strive to overthrow “existing social conditions” disentangle these variables in future experimental stud-
when they recognized that they had “nothing to lose but ies. Such contributions would presumably also aid in
their chains” (p. 246). This formulation puts the empha- identifying boundary conditions on the phenomenon of
sis on the severity of deprivation (and its clear percep- rationalization of the status quo.
tion), which could be explored in other studies. IMPLICATIONS FOR THE STABILITY OF
Second, we have demonstrated that “sour grapes” and IADIVIDUALS AM) SYSTEMS
“sweet lemon” rationalizations do occur in anticipation
of nonvolitional political and policy outcomes, but our Despite the limitations of our two studies, the implica-
methods have not shed much light on the specific cogni- tions of “sour grapes” and “sweet lemon” anticipatory
tive mechanisms implicated in these processes. It seems rationalizations for the stability and functioning ofsocial
reasonable to suggest that rationalization is a specific and political systems are significant indeed (see also
case of motivated reasoning, according to which people Elster, 1983;Jost, 1995; Lane, 1962). When news organi-.
Kay et al. / ANTICIPATORYRATIONALIZATION 1311

zations publish pre-election poll results it may or may not REFERENCES


change actual voting behavior (Simon, 1954), but our Allison, S. T., Mackie, D. M., & Messick, D. M. (1996). Outcome biases
first study suggests that it might lead people to begin in social perception: Implications for dispositional inference, atti-
adapting to the outcome by rationalizing the merits of tude change, stereotyping, and social behavior. Advances itt Experi-
mentalSocial Psychology, 28, 53-93.
the leading candidate and the demerits of the trailing Aronson, E. (1989). The rationalizing animal. In H. J. Leavitt, L. R.
candidate. In fact, it may be that democratic institutions Pondy, & D. M. Boje (Eds.), Readings in managerialpsychology (4th
work well to the extetit that people are able and moti- ed.,pp. 134-144). Chicago: University ofChicago Press. (Original
work published 1973)
vated to rationalize electoral outcomes, especially those Aspinwall, L. G., & Taylor, S. E. (1992). Modeling cognitive adapta-
outcomes that might have initially seemed unattractive. tion: A longitudinal investigation on the impact of individual dif-
The results of our second study indicate that all systems, ferences and coping on college adjustment and performance.
Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology, 63, 989-1003.
even autocratic systems, probably benefit from rational- Bargh, J. A., Gollwitzer, P. M., Leè-Chai, A., Barndollar, K., &
izations made by their constituents (see also Kuran, Trotschel, R. (2001). The automated will: Nonconscious activa-
1998). It seems quite likely that decision-making authori- tion and pursuit ofbehavioral goals.Journal ofPersonality and Social
Psychology, 81, 1014-1027.
ties and those in power often benefit from the types of Batson, C. D. (1975). Rational processing or rationalization? The
rationalizations displayed by our respondents (see also effect of disconfirming information on a stated religious belief.
Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology, 32, 176-184.
Haines &Jost, 2000;Jost et al., in press). Beasley, R. K., & Joslyn, M. R. (2001). Cognitive dissonance and
In general, the tendency to rationalize what is yet to post-decisionattitude change in six presidential elections. Political
come—especially when it is highly involving or conse- Psychology, 22, 521-539.
Brehm, J. W. (1956). Post-decisional changes in desirability of alter-
quential—is probably a highly adaptive process, as are natives. Journal ofAbnormal and Social Psychology, 52, 384-389.
many other cognitive-motivational biases (e.g., Kunda, Ccci, S.J., & Kain, E. L. (1982) .Jumping on the bandwagon with the
1990; Taylor & Brown, 1988). As McGuire and McGuire underdog: The impact of attitude polls on poll behavior. Public
Opinion Quarterly, 46, 228-242.
(1991) argued, mental adjustments of this kind probably Cialdini, R. B. (2001), Influence: Science and practice. Boston: Allyn &
help individuals to cope with uncertainty in the social Bacon.
environment. An election study conducted by Gilbert Cooper,J., & Fazio, R. H. (1984). A new look at dissonance theory.
Advances in Experimental Social Psychology, 17, 229-266.
et al. (1998, Study 3) is also worth mentioning in this Eiser, J. K., & Eiser, C. (1975). Prediction of environmental change:
connection. With regard to the 1994 Texas gubernato- Wish-fulfillment revisited. EuropeanJournal of Social Psychology, 5,
rial race between George W. Bush and Ann Richards, 315-322.
Elster,J. (1983). Sour grapes: Studies in thesubversion ofrationality. Cam-
Gilbert et al. (1998) found that Democrats adapted bridge, UK. Cambridge University Press.
more successfully to the outcome than they expected Elster,J., & Loewenstein, G. (1992). Utility from memory and antici-
pation. In G. F. Loewenstein &J. E. Elster (Eds.), Choice over time
and rated Bush in more favorable terms after the elec- (pp. 213-234). New York: Russell Sage.
tion than before. Although there was no attempt to Festinger, L. (1957). A theory of cognitive dissonance. Stanford, CA: Stan-
directly examine rationalization processes (either antici- ford University Press.
Festinger, L., & Carlsmith, J. M. (1959). Cognitive consequences of
pated or in retrospect) in the Gilbert et al. (1998) study, forced compliance. Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology, 58,
their interpretation in terms of the capacity of the “psy- 203-210.
chological immune system” to adapt to surprising or Festinger, L., Riecken, H. W., & Schachter, S. (1956). When prophecy
fails. Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press.
unwanted outcomes is consistent with our account. Frenkel, O.J., & Doob, A. N. (1976). Post-decision dissonance at the
What our findings suggest, especially when taken in polling booth. CanadianJournal ofBehavioral Science, 8, 347-350.
conjunction with those of McGuire (1960), Pyszczynski Gilbert, D. T., & Ebert,J.Ej. (2001). Decisions and revisions: The
affective forecasting of changeable outcomes.Journal ofPersonality
(1982), and Gilbert et a!. (1998), is that people are and Social Psychology, 82, 503-514.
remarkably able and willing to adapt to whatever is likely Gilbert, D. T., Pinel, E. C., Wilson, T. D., Blumberg, S.J., & Wheatley,
T. (1998). Immune neglect: Asource ofdurability bias in affective
to transpire, so that they begin rationalizing the status forecasting.JournalofPersonality and Social Psychology, 75,617-638.
quo ewen before it becomes reality. As “Michael,” the Ginsberg, B., & Weissberg, R. (1978). Elections and the mobilization
character played by Jeff Goldblum in the film The Big of popular support. Journal ofPolitical Science, 22, 3 1-55.
Granberg, Ii, & Brent, E. (1983). When prophecy bends: The prefer-
Chil4 observed wryly, “I don’t know anyone who could ence-expectation link in U.S. presidential elections, 1952-1980.
get through a day without two or three juicy rationaliza- Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 45, 477-491.
tions.” Multiplying this insight in light of our electoral Granberg, D., & Nanneman, T. (1986). Attitude change in an elec-
toral context as a function of expectations not being fulfilled.
study, we might similarly conclude that few presi- PoliticalPsychology, 7, 753-765.
dent-elects could make it to inauguration day without Gurr, T. R. (1970) Why men rebel. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University
the increased support coming from each opponents’ Press.
Haines, E. L., &Jost,J. T. (2000). Placating the powerless: Effects of
two or three rationalizations, some of which must be as legitimate and illegitimate explanation on affect, memoryand ste-
juicy as the sweetest of lemons. reotyping. SocialJustice Research, 13, 2 19-236.
1312 PERSONALITYAND SOCIAL PSYCHOLOGY BULLETIN

Jost,J. T. (1995). Negative illusions: Conceptual clarificatidn and psy- Moore, B., Jr. (1978) Injustice: The social bases of obedience and revolt.
chological evidence concerning false consciousness. Political Psy- New York: M. E. Sharp.
chology, 16, 397-424. Nadeau, R., & Blais, A. (1993) Accepting the election outcome: The
Jost, J. T., & Banaji, M. R. (1994). The role of stereotyping in sys- effect ofparticipation on losers’ consent. BritishJournal ofPolitical
tem-justification and the production offalse consciousness. British Science, 23, 553-563.
Journal ofSocial Psychology, 33, 1-27. Proust, M. (1993). Thefugitive. New York: Modern Library.
Jost,J. T., Peiham, B. W., Sheldon, 0., & Sullivan, B. N. (in press). Pyszczynski, T. (1982). Cognitive strategies for copingwith uncertain
Social inequality and the reduction of ideological dissonance on outcomes. Journal of Research in Personality, 16, 386-399.
behalf of the system: Evidence of enhanced system justification Rasinski, K., Tyler, T. R., & Fridkin, K. (1985). Exploring the function
among the disadvantaged. EuropeanJournal ofSocial Psychology. of legitimacy: Meditating effects of personal and institutional
Kruglanski, A. W. (1996). Motivated social cognition: Principles of legitimacy on leadership endorsement and system support. Jour-
the interface. In E. T. Higgins & A. W. Kruglanski (Eds.), Socialpsy- nal of Personality and Social Psychology, 49, 395-407.
chology: Handbook of basicprinciples. New York: Guilford. Regan, D. T., & Kilduff, M. (1988). Optimism about elections: Disso-
Kunda, Z. (1990). The case for motivated reasoning. PsychologicalBul- nance reduction at the ballot box. Political Psychology, 9, 101-107.
letin, 108, 480-498. Rothbart, M. (1970). Assessing the likelihood ofa threatening event:
Kuran, T. (1998). Social mechanisms of dissonance reduction. In P. English Canadians’ evaluation of the Quebec separatist move-
Hedstrom & R. Swedberg (Eds.), Social mechanisms: An analytical ment. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology, 15~109-117.
approach to social theory. (pp. 147-171). New York: Cambridge Uni- Sherman, S.J. (1991). Thought systems for the past as well as for the
versity Press. future. In R. S. Wyer,Jr., & T. K. SruIl (Eds.),Advancesin social cog-
Lane, R. (1962). The fear of equality. In R. E. Lane (Ed.),Political ide- nition (Vol. W, pp. 173-195). Hillsdale, NJ: Lawrence Erlbaum.
ology: Why theAmerican common man believes whathe does (pp. 57-81). Simon, H. A. (1954). Bandwagon and underdog effects and the possi-
New York: Free Press. bility ofelection predictions. Public Opinion Quarterly, 18,245-253.
Lind, E. A., & Tyler, T. R. (1988). The social psychology ofproceduraljus- Stangor, C., Sechrist, G. B., &Jost,J. T. (2001) .Changing racialbeliefs
tice. New York: Plenum. by providing consensus information. Personality and Social Psychol-
Lyubomisky, S., & Ross, L. (1999) Changes in attractiveness of ogy Bulletin, 27, 486-496.
elected, rejected, and precluded alternatives: A comparison of Staw, B. (1976). Knee-deep in the big muddy: A study ofescalating
happyand unhappy individuals.Journal ofPersonality and Social Psy- commitment to a chosen course ofaction. OrganizationalBehavior
chology, 76, 988-1007. and Human Performance, 16, 27-44.
Marx, K., & Engels, F. (1848/1977). The communist manifesto. In D. Tajfel, H., & Turner,J. C. (1986). The social identity theory of inter-
McLellan (Ed.) Karl Marx: Selected writings (pp. 221-247). Oxford, group behavior. In S. Worchel & W. G. Austin (Eds.), Thepsychology
UK: Oxford University Press. of intergroup relations (pp. 7-24). Chicago: Nelson-Hall.
McGuire, W.J. (1960). Asyllogistic analysis of cognitive relationships. Taylor, S. E., & Brown,J. D. (1988). Illusion and well-being: A social
In M.J. Rosenberg, C. I. Hovland, W.J. McGuire, R. P. Abelson, & psychological perspective on mental health. PsychologicalBulletin,
J. W. Brehm (Eds.), Attitude organization and change (pp. 65-111). 103, 193-210.
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press. Wyer, R. S. (1970). Aprobabilistic analysis of the relationships among
McGuire, W.J., & McGuire, C. V. (1991). The content, structure, and beliefs and attitudes. Psychological Review, 77, 100-120.
operation ofthoughtsystems. In R. S. Wyer,Jr., & T. K. Srull (Eds.), Zullow, H. M., Oettingen, G., Peterson, C., & Seligman, M.E.P.
Advances in social cognition (Vol. W, pp. 1-78). Hillsdale, NJ: Law- (1988). Pessimistic explanatory style in historical record. American
rence Erlbaum. - Psychologist, 43, 673-682.
Mehrabian, A. (1998). Effects of poll reports on voter preference.
Journal ofApplied Social Psychology, 23, 2119-2130. Received May 30, 2001
Miller, D. T., Taylor, B., & Buck, M. L. (1991). Gender gaps: Who Revision accepted March 14, 2002
needs to be explained?Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology,
61, 5-12.

You might also like