You are on page 1of 18

Critical Theory

Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

DOI: https://doi.org/10.15388/SocMintVei.2017.1.10879

Tom Driver

Isaiah Berlin, Michel Foucault


and the Politics of Neoliberal Freedom
Abstract. Starting with a historical inquiry into the notion of freedom as a political concept, in this
article I argue that neoliberal freedom has attempted to satisfy demands associated with two quite distinct
forms of freedom, representing a new understanding of the concept. Drawing on Isaiah Berlin’s lecture on
the two conceptions of liberty – positive freedom to and negative freedom from – I consider their apparent
heterogeneity, stemming from alternate relations towards individuals, and forming the basis of opposing
political systems. Against this opposition, the neoliberal notion of freedom, as developed in the early works
of liberal economists and their vision of a social market economy, is marked by a synthesis of politics and
the economy, one that enables social regulation in conformity with market demands. Reflecting Foucault’s
argument that power operates through both productive and repressive practices, neoliberal freedom poses
a new understanding of subjectivity, where individuals become ‘entrepreneurs of the self ’. By connecting
personal freedom to rational action in the competitive marketplace, neoliberal culture can claim to grant
both negative freedoms from the state and enabling freedoms to be a rational subject. With brief reference
to contemporary political events, I point out some of the problems and implications of this form of freedom.
Keywords: Isaiah Berlin, Michel Foucault, freedom, power, neoliberalism, homo economicus.
Raktažodžiai: Isaiah Berlin, Michel Foucault, laisvė, galia, neoliberalizmas, homo economicus.

Introduction of a political, economic and institutional kind –


in short, at the level of historical-sociological
In this article, I offer a critical reflection on
relations. An important facet of the problems
the modern, politicised conception of freedom.
posed by contemporary state securitisation to
I emphasise its politicised character partly to
the concept of political freedom stems from
highlight its complex relation to a multiplicity the fragility of the concept and its direct rela-
of disciplines, institutions and individuals, and tion to both power and ethics. It is in contrast
partly to avoid any assumption of freedom as to the exceptional use of administrative state
an abstract or transcendental given, a universal power (now the norm in political discourse)
a priori. This approach enables me to consider that the dominant market concept of freedom
freedom as practical concept, one productively was developed. This development is a product
and repressively involved in concrete struggles of a specifically historical moment, and of the

80
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

idea that the concept can be split into a binary prehensive view of, since it functions ‘like a sign
opposition, consisting of positive freedom (to and embodies a collective proposition’ (ibid.).
do) and negative freedom (from interference). Resisting concise definition, symbolic practices
With this opposition and its relation to society and collective propositions exist within certain
and subjectivity in mind, I will argue that the socio-cultural paradigms, precluding any as-
concept of freedom represented by neoliberal sumption of freedom as transcendental and
marketisation is markedly different, cutting universal. Therefore, as we begin to specify the
across imagined political or ideological divi- concept, we can deduce two interpretations of
sions. As well as Isaiah Berlin’s text and its freedom; one relating to freedom in its abstract,
interlocutors, the paper will draw on Michel legal form, and the other relating to its histori-
Foucault’s 1978–79 lectures at the College De cal, sociological and therefore political form. Its
France, and on the theory and practices of legal form is represented by the wider juridical
neoliberalism. structures of a society, whereas its political form
Olivier Clain traces the etymology of the manifests itself in the corresponding cultural
term ‘freedom’ or ‘liberty’1 to the Latin word​ practices and social relations, enabled or sanc-
libertatem (the accusative of libertas), which tioned by the law.
refers to a ‘free man’ in contrast to a slave. Clain In my interpretation, what character-
further notes that in Indo-European languages ises freedom, in both its abstract and concrete
the root term ‘lib’, as found in words such as forms, is power. Different forms of power are
‘liberal’ or ‘libido’, stems from the Latin word simultaneously at work in different ways, us-
libertas and its sense of ‘doing what one likes’ ing different vehicles, which brings us to the
(2016; 12–13). The implication here is that only writings of Foucault. Mitchell Dean describes
certain individuals – those with the sufficient Foucault’s work as constituting a ‘triangle’ of
resources and mental and physical capabili- power consisting of sovereign, disciplinary and
ties – are able to achieve recognition, pursue bio-power, none of which takes precedence
desires and experience freedom: freedom, once (2010; 122). The question of freedom was
recognised as a form of privilege, comes to be central to Foucault’s later thought, seen in his
regarded as a scarce good (Bauman 1988; 27). ethical work regarding the care of the self and
Notably, Clain goes on to show that throughout the subject’s relation to power. During a late
its history freedom has operated as a symbolic lecture, Foucault (2008; 63) loosely defined
practice (Clain 2016; 10). Because of this, his- freedom as ‘never anything other – but this is
torical and sociological relations necessarily a great deal already – than an actual relation
condition its practice, and freedom becomes a between governors and governed’. Similarly, in
‘cultural entity’ that we may not have a com- The Subject and Power essay, it is argued that ‘at

1 Throughout, these two terms shall be used interchangeably, with any necessary clarification pro-
vided as required.


81
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

the very heart of the power relationship, and with a certain risk that is put into play through
thought and, indeed, through language where
constantly provoking it, are the recalcitrance
the contemporary ordering of being is brought
of the will and the intransigence of freedom’ to its limit. (2000; 10)
(Foucault 2000a; 342). Thus to Foucault the
relationship between power and freedom is not For Foucault, contained in the theoretical
solely repressive, where power simply consumes structure of the verb to be is the practical and
freedom; rather, ‘freedom may well appear as ontological possibility that ‘language could
the condition for the exercise of power’ (ibid.). overflow its boundaries and affirm being’
This understanding of power allows a distinc- (2002; 366). Going beyond what is prescribed
tion to be drawn between relations of power that by dominant discourse, by norms, the concept
are mobile, strategic and reversible, and states of of freedom opens up radical possibilities for
domination, underscored by force and coercion. transformation. This is particularly so if we
Foucault demonstrated that power is every- understand subjectivity not as a substance but
where, but this should not be translated fatal- a form (Foucault 2000b; 290), and consider
istically at the expense of agency or resistance. the ontological significance of the verb to be
The distinction between relations of power and alongside the imperative command of freedom,
states of domination allows one to assess the which would be expressed as ‘to be free’. In this
ethical and the dangerous in certain discourses, sense, conceptions of freedom derive, as they
policies and practices. It then becomes pos- always have, from ontological questions and
sible to transform power relations in order to views of subjectivity (Berlin 1969; 10).
reduce the prevalence of domination (ibid.). Political freedom poses questions such as
As Foucault puts it, ‘if there are relations of ‘who and why should I obey’, and ‘what are
power in every social field, this is because there the means and ends of social and political life?’
is freedom everywhere’ (ibid.; 292). Ethical Again, in conceptualising freedom I do not wish
concern for oneself is thus the conscious practice to characterise it as an objective, transcendental
of freedom. Foucault goes as far as to describe given, since ‘we have to know the historical
freedom as the ‘ontological condition for ethics’ conditions that motivate our conceptualisation’
(ibid.; 284) – that is, as an ethos, which affects (Foucault 2000; 290). I will therefore begin
our relations with others and the world, not to with a discussion of Berlin’s 1969 essay The Two
mention the self in relation to itself. This issue Conceptions of Liberty, the aim being to bring
is at once philosophical and political. This issue out a broader historical-political context for the
of freedom’s ontological significance is captured discussion of freedom. Further, I see Berlin’s
eloquently by Judith Butler when she asks: work as directly relevant to contemporary po-
litical issues, perhaps most notably the chaotic
‘What, given the contemporary order of being, attempts by Western powers to impose their
can I be?’ If, in posing this question, liberty is at
stake, it may be that staking liberty has some- concept of freedom on Iraq, and the resurgence
thing to do with what Foucault calls virtue, of nationalist politics. Berlin’s purpose was to

82
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

affirm Western ideological principles at the from the wider public sphere. Minimally, this
height of the Cold War, and to make clear the entails that government ensures only the state’s
heteronomy of the two concepts, namely ‘freedom security and allows for the ‘liberty of religion,
from’ and ‘freedom to’. These are considered to opinion, expression, property’, arbitrary inva-
be distinct and to stem from ‘two profoundly sion of which would be despotism (ibid.; 5).
divergent and irreconcilable attitudes to the Negative freedom implies political organisa-
ends of life’ and the self (Berlin 1969; 28). tion without an overarching telos that society
Both seek to be interpreted and applied as must be orientated towards achieving (Plant
absolute values, and Berlin concedes that moral- 2009; 6). The alternative is the free market
ly and historically both hold ‘an equal right which, deemed unknowable in its totality by
to be classed among the deepest interests’ of any master plan, functions as an institutional
civilisation (ibid.; 29). In my view, the contrary safeguard against the arbitrary use of sovereign
movements that Berlin identifies here impart power. Philosophically, this implies that our
a markedly different understanding to the empirical knowledge of experience and the
concept of freedom, one which may be seen as ends of life, be it divine, spiritual or politi-
a prelude to the notion of neoliberal freedom. cal, must not be closed off or pre-prescribed.
As Berlin argues, ‘the belief that some single
Negative Freedom formula can in principle be found whereby all
‘Negative freedom’ relates to the limitations the diverse ends of men can be harmoniously
set by state activity and its relationship with realised is demonstrably false’ (Berlin 1969;
the economy. To be free, in the negative sense, 30). In prescribing an absolute end, akin to a
means ‘not being interfered with by others. The cosmological destiny, fraught attempts to realise
wider the area of non-interference the wider it will inevitably involve the sacrifice of other
my freedom’ (ibid.; 3). Understood as ‘freedom ends. The implications are that the ends of life
from’, the concept has been central to moral and hoped for by men, women and groups are many
political philosophy. Berlin notes its centrality and varied, and are not necessarily compatible
to classical liberalism, covering British thinkers with one another (ibid.). In order to balance
such as John Locke, John Stuart Mill and Adam this incommensurability, negative freedom is
Smith and also French writers such as Benjamin less to do with bold, revolutionary ideas or
Constant and Alexis de Tocqueville, all of whom self-actualising empowerment than with the
share the belief ‘that there ought to exist a cer- independence of the governed, pure and simple.
tain minimum area of personal freedom which Oppression is not seen as stemming from
must on no account be violated’ (ibid.; 4). a volatile economy and the reactions to it, but
Against the abuse of power by dictators, or the from the mere accumulation of power itself
ill-founded ‘tyranny of the majority’, negative (ibid.; 27). To prevent this, liberalism became
freedom seeks to establish a clear frontier ca- an international instrument that, through the
pable of separating the private life of individ­uals expanding European marketplace, allowed

83
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

for the internal self-limitation of state power dominant, rational self (associated with posi-
(Foucault 2008; 13). Crucially, the market is tive freedom), Berlin juxtaposes the ‘empirical’
conceived as the guarantor of freedom, justice and ‘heteronomous’ self, characterised by
and progress, expressed in the liberal notion of irrational impulses and ‘uncontrolled desires
laissez-faire, French for ‘let go’, and symbolising for the pursuit of immediate pleasures’ (ibid.;
a direct political challenge to state control over 9). Subjects are understood as being driven by
the economy. Intervention from the state could economic self-interest – that is as isolated and
only be disruptive to the professed ‘natural calculative, and thus as best suited to the free-
order’ and ‘harmony’ of the marketplace and market. This is the figure of homo economicus,
international trade (Landreth and Colander the ‘bartering savage’ (Polanyi 2001 [1944]; 46);
2001). This internal limitation of state power, on this view the subject is an economic object
which must instead consult the discipline of of exchange, governed by materialist desires
political economy for legitimacy and truth, is and less concerned with idealism, altruism or
a significant change in the operations of power the collective good.
(Foucault 2008; 14). The ‘free-market of ideas’
is a disciplinary form of power, against the Positive Freedom
sovereign power of the monarch or police state. Whilst, without a prescribed telos, nega-
Hence, Foucault stressed the intimate connec- tive liberty may be most commensurate with
tion between liberal freedom and the discipline cultural and religious tolerance (Berlin 1969;
of political economy (ibid.). With foundations 31), there are limits to an individualist, negative
in the pursuit of unlimited economic growth conception of freedom (Taylor 1979). Firstly,
and utilitarian calculus (Clain 2016; 6), the it is unable to provide beings with an affirma-
implication is an empirical view of politics and tive, meaningful understanding of themselves
subjectivity. Political and economic knowledge or culture, beyond the calculative materialism
make possible questions of economic truth, as of economic discourse. Berlin points this out,
well as the need to limit state reason. Hence- conceding that ‘it is true that to offer political
forth the market itself becomes a principal site rights, or safeguards against intervention by
of verification (ibid.); it becomes a discursive the State, to men who are half-naked, illiterate,
regime for political and legal truth. underfed and diseased is to mock their condi-
In contrasting the two conceptions of tion’ (Berlin 1969; 4). Furthermore, he argues
freedom, and with their corresponding episte- that the connection between negative freedom
mological foundations in mind, Berlin makes and democracy is far more tenuous than many
use of the analogy of a divided self (Berlin liberal thinkers would like to accept, noting that
1969; 8–10). With negative freedom, an ideal the demand for a private sphere of individual
ontology is deduced from the episteme of the liberty may be sufficiently satisfied by a tyran-
market and the moral philosophy of liberal nical regime or forms of autocracy (ibid.; 8).
economists. Against the ‘higher nature’ of the Out of this difficulty, there developed the legal

84
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

and, it must be noted, revolutionary approach situation of civil war in response to the state of
to freedom. Expressed as ‘freedom to or be’, exception in Giorgio Agamben’s sense is one
positive freedom, consists in ‘being one’s own example (Agamben 2005; 10).
master’ (ibid.). This is an affirmative, enabling Berlin further argues that positive freedom is
idea, primarily concerned with enabling indi- grounded in a foundational idealism, traceable
v­iduals, groups or society itself to perform and back to the Platonic notion of ideal forms, and
embody freedom. gaining its fullest expression in G. W. F. Hegel
Positive freedom begins from juridical law (Berlin 1969; 29). In particular, what will en-
and the inalienable, imprescriptible natural able the realisation of an ideal political system
rights of citizens. Together, these codify the is rational knowledge of the historical process,
extension and goal of state action, through a and rational understanding of ourselves and in-
constitution of the sovereign (Foucault 2008; stitutions. On this view positive freedom, or the
39). Jean Jacques Rousseau theorised this as The ‘universal spirit’ of world history (Hegel 2011
Social Contract (1999 [1762]), stressing the sov- [1837]) will enable the creation of a ‘perfectly
ereignty of the people, whom the government harmonious society’, via rationally intelligible
must serve through adherence to the ‘general laws administered by the sovereign (Berlin
will’ (ibid.; 69–70); what is being posited here 1969; 15). As is well known, while for Hegel
is an inviolable agreement that must not be the nation state signified the culmination and
transgressed by government or its citizens, embodiment of this freedom, Karl Marx would
affording both rulers and ruled liberty and assert the need for further political and institu-
security (ibid.): here human beings are ‘born tional development. Hence positive freedom
free’, demanding that our subjection to power implies a politics of strong state intervention
be rationally justified. For Berlin, ‘freedom in the market, associated with nationalist and
is obedience’ on Rousseau’s view, but ‘obedi- socialist forms of government in the form of
ence to a law which we prescribe to ourselves’ protectionism, regulations, tariffs, redistributive
(Berlin 1969; 11). Thus all citizens and groups taxes and so on.
have a ‘share in the public power’ (ibid.; 26): Underpinning this idea and the desire for
this juridical, collective will, situated over and self-mastery, is the argument that political life
above any particular government, is the radical, must have a telos, and must therefore be ordered
potentially dangerous feature of positive free- according to a rational plan. A teleocratic or-
dom. The reason for this, as the Jacobins who der of this kind requires political organisation
drew on Rousseau’s ideas amply demonstrated, to be subordinate to an overarching end goal
is obvious. This will to freedom, analogous to a (Plant 2008; 7). For Berlin this view rests on
‘right of resistance’, enables one to call for the a metaphysical belief that reason governs the
revolutionary overthrow of government or the universe; thus correct planning will ‘coincide
renewal of society, if the current order is seen with full freedom’ (Berlin 1969; 18). The idea
as violating the inalienable rights of subjects: a that there exists one final, total formula for all

85
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

of social life, is akin to theological notions of that across swathes of Europe the liberal ideal of
the Promised Land to come. Indeed, Berlin negative liberty had been rejected in favour of
likens this ideal state to the ‘Garden of Eden planning and authoritarian state control meant
before the Fall of Man’, an Eden from which that post-war liberalism would have to recon-
we have been expelled, but which is still longed- sider political freedom. As a result, any form of
for (ibid.; 16). Assuming oneself to have the state intervention that tried to subordinate indi-
key to history, to have solved the riddles of the viduals to a plan and direct the market came to
universe, is a great power, for which no sacrifice be viewed as a threat to freedom (Hayek 1990;
is too great. To the rational metaphysician, 258). The English poet and social critic, Hilaire
the empirical epistemology of negative liberty Belloc, was a forerunner of this line of thought:
and the market, which abandons the notion in The Servile State (2007 [1912]) he argued
of final unity in the ends of life is, in Berlin’s that whilst capitalism was unstable, attempts
words, ‘a piece of crude empiricism’ (ibid.; 29). to balance and reform it would undermine and
For Berlin this argument, used by all dictators destroy the freedom it had established. The book
and tyrants to justify their actions, is worthy of was cited and praised by Friedrich von Hayek in
condemnation, the logic being that ‘I must do The Road to Serfdom (2001 [1944]; 13), and sets
for men (or with them) what they cannot do out the essentials of the neoliberal objection to
for themselves’ (ibid.; 19). This brings us back any form of state power over individuals and the
to Berlin’s distinction between the divided self economy. Whether in the form of Roosevelt’s
and the rational, transcendental ‘higher self’ New Deal in the US, European Keynesianism
of positive freedom, which must take charge or Nazi labour camps, any attempt to regulate
of one’s lower, ‘empirical self’: to dispense with capitalism is thought to pose a danger to per-
one’s alienated self in favour of one’s higher self sonal freedom: as administrative intervention
is an expression of the desire to be a rational in the economy expands, the supposed politi-
subject and not a mere empirical object. On this cal inevitability is that freedom is threatened
schema, to coerce and force the empirical self and eventually undermined (Foucault 2008;
into a correct order of conduct and behaviour 110–111).2
is not tyranny but liberation (ibid.; 18). Rather than seeing the state as providing
freedom to the market, the early neoliberal
Neoliberal Freedom thinkers reversed the formula, seeing the market
The early neoliberal thinkers were respond- as providing freedom to the state (ibid.). This
ing to the political crises of the 1930s. The fact conception of freedom is not, however, simply

2 Foucault notes how Wilhelm Röpke, an early neoliberal economist, published a bold analysis of
the Labour Party’s Beveridge plan, which established the welfare state and the National Health
Service. Röpke’s basic argument is that Britain was simultaneously at war with the Nazis while
being in the process of repeating their political and economic formula.

86
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

classical liberalism revived (Burchell 1996), a objectives to long-term legal principles – that
point which is central to my argument against is, legal safeguards against the state abusing its
Berlin’s presentation of positive and negative power, in the form of a legislative assembly.
liberty as heterogeneous, clearly separate ide- Therefore, ‘if a law gave the government un-
als. Rather the idea that the market is endowed limited power to act as it pleased, all its actions
with a natural essence, regarded by Walter would be legal, but it would certainly not be
Eucken as a ‘naive naturalism’, is explicitly under the rule of law’ (ibid.; 205). However,
rejected (Oksala 2016; 116). Implied in this within this framework, states may pursue a
line of criticism is an attempt to move beyond range of interventions that facilitate the market,
negative liberty and its limitations on state in- including such commonly associated policies
tervention, which resulted from a recognition as neoliberal globalisation, economic liberal-
of the need to take account of subjective legal isation, privatisation, transnational trade deals
demands. In The Constitution of Liberty, Hayek and flexible migration. The point is that inter-
expresses this new attitude towards freedom in ventions by the state, to be legitimate, must
writing that: encourage the market, and must not directly
the old formulae of laissez faire or non-interven- encroach on it. As the social market economy,
tion do not provide us with an adequate criteri- neoliberalism has a strong and active social
on for distinguishing between what is and what policy of intervention. It is ‘free’ in the negative
is not admissible in a free system. There is ample
scope for experimentation and improvement sense from central planning, but simultaneously
within that permanent legal framework which presses outwards a wide array of positive, legal
makes it possible for a free society to operate controls, designed to orient individuals and
most efficiently. (1990 [1960]; 231)
their social environment towards the market
Plainly the terms ‘experimentation’ and (Callinicos 2006).3 Carl Friedrich wrote of the
‘improvement’ pertain to the neoliberal idea neoliberals that they ‘see economics as “embed-
that the capitalist market does not have a fixed, ded” in politics [...] convinced that economic
knowable essence; rather the market is the prod- and political systems are interrelated’ (1955;
uct of an economic-institutional framework, 511). In this sense neoliberalism is regulatory
which must ensure the limitations of state power and interventionist, a ‘positive’ or ‘sociological’
and the subordination of short-term, political liberalism (Foucault 2008; 129–150).

3 In societies that have come under neoliberal influence, this approach to governmental activity can

be glimpsed across almost all sectors of public life. To give a small-scale example, the approach can
be seen in the literature on the increasing marketisation of higher education over recent decades,
where bureaucratic policies of state management are driven by the economic logic of productivity
and competition, but implemented in a manner resembling an authoritarian command system.
In this process, there is no strict ideology or plan but active environmental intervention in accor-
dance with the market, in which higher education resembles employment training, with students
embodied as entrepreneurs. See Craig Brandist (2014).


87
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

Louiza Odysseos calls this process the Likewise, in Foucault’s work on power, the
‘governmentalisation’ of the state, where law important issue is not whether there is or is not
is used to contract the state but expand the power, but the how of its workings. In practice,
practice of government, with a view to making neoliberalism closely conforms to Foucault’s
subjects ‘self-governable’ (Odysseos 2010). For notion of disciplinary power (Foucault 1977).
Odysseos, the example of human rights, can Through training, examination and normalisa-
be seen as part of neoliberalism’s ontogenesis tion, the purpose of discipline is for the opti-
or development, where global, humanitarian mum circulation of power and control, with
calls for human rights reinforce the ‘discourses, a view to increasing the efficiency of society
knowledge productions’, and ‘law-making’ of (ibid.). Panopticism is the mechanism that
neoliberalism, in other words its own conditions ensures this ‘infinitesimal distribution’ of power
for freedom (ibid.; 750). More specifically, calls relations (ibid.; 216), inducing individuals to
for a state to allow equality before the law or self-monitor and correct their own behaviour.4
the right to a fair trial are in practice accom- Indeed neoliberal freedom, taken as a blueprint
panied by demands for market liberalisation for a type of government, is ‘imbued with the
or for consent to freedom of enterprise. Here property of panopticism’ (De Angelis 2001; 36),
basic, positive freedoms and human rights are the two fulfilling various overlapping functions.
legally enshrined, provided they function lat- In The Birth of Biopolitics, Foucault (2008;
erally alongside neoliberalism’s internal rule of 66–68) draws attention to the importance of
maximising the market (ibid.; 755). Through disciplinary control as an instrument in the
the production of enabling legal and limiting liberal art of government, one allowing for the
economic conditions, then, the market aspires production and extension of freedom through
to a synthetic conception of freedom. To quote mechanisms of additional control and interven-
Hayek on the indistinctions between forms of tion. He notes that ‘Control is no longer just the
freedom; ‘though in some of the other senses it necessary counterweight to freedom, as in the
may be legitimate to speak of different kinds of case of panopticism: it becomes its mainspring’
freedom, “freedoms from” and “freedoms to”, in (ibid.; 67, my emphasis). The aim of neoliberal
our sense “freedom” is one, varying in degree but policies is not to negatively deregulate the state’s
not in kind’ (Hayek 1990 [1960]; 12). What efforts to control the market, but to positively
we may glimpse here is a style of governmental re-regulate individuals and the social environ-
coercion, where what becomes significant is not ment in conformance with the operation of the
what is touched by the state but how it does this. market. In this sense, freedom is ‘bound up’

4 It should be remembered that Jeremy Bentham was not primarily an architect but a utilitarian
economist and public legal theorist. As such, for him panopticism was not an isolated phenomena
with regional specificities; rather it was a general blueprint for society and, crucial to my argu-
ment, for a type of government.

88
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

with and produced by disciplinary techniques with other political rationalities’ (2007; 4).
(ibid.). Irreducible to any one sovereign power, The implication is that neoliberalism should
it rests on the assumption that the state ‘has not be reduced to an ideological distortion,
an imperfect knowledge of individual plans’ imposed on individuals by a ruling class.
(De Angelis 2001; 25), and that it must com- Nor should it be expanded to an ‘economic
pensate for this imperfection through other tsunami’ of planetary regulation, through
mechanisms. As Hayek himself worded it, in the de-territorialised flows of global markets
a Foucauldian manner, ‘coercion, then, may (ibid.; 3–4). Instead, Ong rightly argues that
sometimes be avoidable only because a high neoliberalism governs through a technical as-
degree of voluntary conformity exists, which semblage, one which ‘highlights the situated
means that voluntary conformity may be a interplay of motion and contingency, of tech-
condition of a beneficial working of freedom’ nology and ethics, of opportunity and risk’
(1990 [1960]; 12). (ibid.; 5). The social application and economic
Looking for ways to augment their eco- function of new technologies is entwined with
nomic and military power, states became more dominant political practices and policies. The
and more interested in individuals insofar as development of new digital technologies,
they could be governed to assist in this pro- within a wider framework of neoliberalism,
gramme. The task of regulating society and means that they are effective techniques in
individual behaviour, however, which was political relations towards individuals. Judea
initially the preserve of the police, became dis- Pearl’s Bayesian belief network program is
persed into the general social milieu (Foucault an illustrative example of this (Arbib 2001).
2000b; 408–409). In this regard, we should Primarily concerned with the development of
draw attention to the increasing importance artificial intelligence, programs such as this are
of technology in liberal forms of government, an essential component for digital networking,
technology plainly being one of the main used to monitor, predict and control swathes of
means ‘by which the individual could be inte- data, desires and information now at the heart
grated into the social entity’, ideally forming a of cyberspace and the global free market. Such
symbiotic relationship, ‘a political rationality programs aim to ‘model the environment as a
linked to a political technology’, as Foucault collection of stable component mechanisms’
puts it (ibid.; 410, 416).5 Aihwa Ong has (ibid.; 159), where their ‘causal networks’
also noted the importance of technology in function via a conceptualisation of the self as a
neoliberalism, regarding it as a ‘technology cognitive processor of probabilistic reasoning
of governing “free subjects” that co-exists (Pearl 1988).

5 Foucault generally uses the term ‘technology’ to refer to ‘technique’, suggesting for instance that
we should not view liberal utilitarianism as a crude projection of ideology onto politics but a radi-
cal ‘technology of government’ (Foucault 2008; 41).


89
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

To give another example, in information demands and scientific/technological discover-


systems, Hayek’s idea of the market as a self- ies. This is especially evident if we consider the
regulating system has been influential for the importance of technology in enabling political
design of ‘decentralised’, self-regulating infor- networks of international financialisation.
mation systems (Eymann et al. 2003), which
rely implicitly on a model of subjective agency The Individual as Rational
based on economic discourse. Through certain Entrepreneur
modifications to information systems, ‘it is pos- In Berlin’s (1969) account of positive
sible to adapt personal behaviour, to the typical freedom, individuals were conceived of as
market behaviour’ (ibid.; 1819). The panoptic collective citizens akin to homo juridicus: as
principle, ‘to see without being seen’, induc- rational subjects of law endowed with natural
ing the desired behaviour, is a central tenet rights. Against this, the negative conception of
in the functioning of the neoliberal market. freedom presented a more private, economic
Technical, disciplinary freedoms enable and understanding of individuals; the central figure
make up the productive, affirmative character here is homo economicus, the empirical object of
of a market-based, digital culture. Surveil- utility and exchange. On a classical view, these
lance and the competitive marketplace ‘use two figures are politically distinct. However,
projections of real life activity as data to feed there is an important shift in the neoliberal
the mechanism of control and co-ordination’ account, where individuals are regarded not
(De Angelis 2001; 35). Bulk surveillance and as objects of exchange but as competitive en-
population classification are indispensable for terprising subjects. Rigorous competition is to
a global economy increasingly reliant on access be the primary, regulatory principle of society.
to information networks and digital data to This means that ‘what is sought is not a society
function. This act of reducing and quantify- subject to the commodity-effect, but a society
ing individuals to marketable data, efficiently subject to the dynamic of competition. Not a
used by e-marketing firms, at the same time supermarket society, but an enterprise society’
serves to expand practices of freedom, enabling (Foucault 2008; 147). The ideal of homo eco-
more consumer choice and communica- nomicus is at the core of this enterprise. Con-
tive possibilities. Joseph Schumpeter (1992 ceiving of individuals as enterprise-units, rather
[1942]) himself argued that adaptability to than solely as producers or consumers, forms
technological innovation, driven by entrepre- the bedrock of neoliberal analysis. As Andrew
neurial growth, was central to the free-market Dilts points out, ‘entrepreneurial activities and
model. This association, helped to establish a investments are the most important practices
global political discourse, which is not static of the neoliberal self’ (2011; 137), with a po-
and unchanging but, within a broader, legal tentially infinite array of activities that can be
framework, is rather mobile, able to transform utilised. This new conception of subjectivity
and reorganise itself according to new consumer was key to Foucault’s whole reading of neolib-

90
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

eralism not as an ideology or theory but as a being a metaphor for the worker as investor
‘governmental rationality’ (ibid.; 131). (Davenport 1999; xiii). As Theodore W. Schultz
At this point, we must recall Foucault’s pointed out, when they abstractly theorise cap-
comments on freedom that we began with, ital-income ratios in strictly quantitative terms,
where it was noted that care for the self, hav- economists fail to account for the most vibrant,
ing a productive, ethical relation to oneself, growing and qualitative factor, human capital
symbolised the conscious practice of freedom. itself (Schultz 1961). Of course the economists’
Foucault’s decision to dedicate his 1978–79 aim is to seek to incorporate cultural values, gen-
course to the question of neoliberal subjectivity eral knowledge and creative skills into economic
should remind us of its significance; seeing this theory and policy. Schultz gives the example of
new model as the ‘interface of government and post-World War reconstruction, when he and
the individual’ (Foucault 2008; 253), I believe, other liberal economists assessed the economic
brings to light the distinct overlaps and entwine- costs and implications of wartime losses for
ment of the positive and negative demands growth and recovery. Despite the all too visible
for freedom, and allows us to connect human and real destruction of ‘factories laid flat, the
freedom to rational action in the competitive railroad yards, bridges, and harbors wrecked’,
marketplace. As Dilts incisively argues: ‘cities in ruin’, Schultz admits that their assess-
the neoliberal analysts look out at the world
ments were significantly off the mark (ibid.;
and do not see discrete and identifiable firms, 6–7). To account for this overestimation of the
producers, households, consumers, fathers, economic costs he maintains that what was lack-
mothers, criminals, immigrants, natives, adults,
ing was an acknowledgment of human capital,
children, or any other ‘fixed’ category of human
subjectivity. They see heterogeneous human the technical knowledges, creative abilities and
capital, distinct in their specific attributes, abili- moral commitments of individuals involved in
ties, natural endowments, skills. They see entre- reconstruction. Economists seek to incorporate
preneurs of the self. (Dilts 2011; 138)
human capital – productive, everyday practices
To be an ‘entrepreneur of the self’ requires that are qualitative by nature – into economic
individuals to be mindful and consciously aware discourse. The result is inextricably associated
of their actions. To be a marketable, successful with the development of immaterial, informa-
enterprise, one must be individually responsible, tional, technologically-based societies.
economically profitable and hostile to author- Foucault went as far as to call the develop-
ity that does not stem from the market. It is ment of human capital theory an ‘epistemologi-
for this reason that Trent H. Hamann points cal transformation’ (2008; 222). Such theory
out that Foucault was ‘deeply interested in the entails a shift from classical economics, based
space opened up by neo-liberal subjectivity, as on the mechanisms of exchange and utility,
a refusal of sovereign subjectivity’ (2009; 48). to ‘the nature and consequences of what they
The theory of Human Capital is a central [the neoliberals] call substitutable choices’
feature of this new understanding of the self, (ibid.) – practical, lived choices in the everyday


91
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

lifeworld, which are to be conceptualised as relations instrumentally, within an entrepre-


valuable economic assets. Labour power is neurial framework. Underscored by the com-
not a passive element in production, separate pulsory logic of competition, this framework
from the individual, and only recognised as a explicitly seeks to incorporate individuals into
material, measured quantitatively through time economic discourse as active subjects rather than
(Dilts 2011; 134). Against the fixed, objective static objects (Foucault 2008; 223). Foucault
categories of economic theory,6 neoliberal notes the underlying desire here to reconstruct
analysis seeks to understand economic processes ‘warm, moral and cultural values’ against the
as active subjective choices. This tendency gener- ‘cold mechanism of competition’ (ibid.; 242).
ates multiple ‘terminological shifts’ that enable That is to say, investment in human capital
qualitative human activity to be conceptualised seeks to prevent feelings of alienation or pow-
through the language of ‘capital, investment erlessness by harbouring points of integration
and entrepreneurship’ (ibid.; 135). To give a and anchorage in the social environment, ones
few examples, from the viewpoint of exchange, that legitimate and encourage one’s ‘entrepre-
labour abets a ‘wage’, a return for the time given neurial self ’. To achieve this, active market in-
as labour power. In enterprise terms, however, terventions (such as the privatisation of public
labour produces an ‘income’, a return on the in- life) seek to reproduce signs and consent to
vestment of human capital made by the worker, neoliberal freedom, normalising competitive,
which may in turn be re-invested productively market relations between individuals. At the
in the form of consumption or some form of macro level, this can be seen in World Bank
immaterial activity that provides satisfaction prescriptions of ‘political entrepreneurialism’,
to the individual. Gary S. Becker called this which shift the focus from the production of
conversion ‘productive consumption’, stressing goods to ‘the production of educated subjects’
the importance of understanding how individu- (Ong 2007; 5). Or at the micro level, as already
als rationally allocate their time, with a view to mentioned, there is the everyday dominance
future ‘returns’ on their investments of human of digital data and self-tracking, which serve
capital (1965; 503). The key point here is that as free labour for tech companies and online
neoliberalism is not an analysis of the market, marketing services, while promoting individual
but of individuals in the market. investment, competitiveness, rewards and pun-
As a result, it becomes possible to character- ishments as the productive exercise of cultural
ise an individual’s everyday formal and informal freedom (Till 2014).

6 For the classical liberals, labour represents an abstract number of hours worked by an individual.
Marx’s critique of this abstraction, his labour theory of value, stresses the exploitation at work in
the transition from the practical labour of the worker to the abstraction of productive processes.
For neoliberal thinkers, however, this view still ultimately falls back on a realist conception that
labour could be restored to its true value.

92
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

For the rational entrepreneur, there is an jor incapacity [...] an inability to master the
important link between technological innova- totality of the economic world’ (ibid.). Adam
tion and the idea of human capital. As Ong Smith called this the ‘invisible hand’, which in
rightly puts it, the function of this link is ‘to placing emphasis on the word ‘invisible’ can be
administer people for self-mastery’ (2007; 4). interpreted as a political metaphor – indeed as a
Schultz himself advocated the integration of quasi-theological metaphor for the natural order
‘the innate abilities of man’ into an ‘all-inclusive (Baumol 1991; 246) – and which can easily be
concept of technology’ (Foucault 2008; 236f ). transfigured as the dominant idea that the eco-
Given this, the higher self, the demand to be nomic world can be subject neither to a master
recognised as a rational being, becomes an es- plan nor to the collective good. Political order
sential component in the neoliberal experience and sovereignty are thus rendered subservient to
of freedom. Yet this is an irrational use of rea- the market. As Foucault has it, economics is an
son, when considered outside of the discursive ‘atheistic discipline’, ‘without God’ or ‘totality’,
grid of the market. Dilts notes that Becker which poses a direct challenge to the exercise of
himself explicitly argued that economic analysis juridical power over economic processes (2008;
of individual behaviour does not require ‘actual 282). Political movements such as nationalism,
rationality’, since it can still function ‘with a socialism and, I would argue, our own contem-
wide array of irrational behaviour’, provided porary neoliberal state of securitisation, devel-
that individuals act ‘as if ’ they are rational oped historically as a reaction and an attempt to
(Dilts 2011; 138). Hence, economic analysis reconcile this absence of an economic sovereign.
can be sweepingly applied to irrational, em- Such movements are political attempts to solve
pirical desires and unethical conduct, with the the ‘essential incompatibility’ between the mul-
qualification that individuals see themselves as tiplicity of economic subjects and the totalising
active, rational entrepreneurs. unity of the juridical sovereign (ibid.).
Foucault (2008) traces homo economicus Applying the tools of micro-economic
back to early English empiricism and its theory analysis to all areas of social life, the market
of human subjectivity as having its own irreduc- remains the principal site of political ‘truth’.
ible will – that is, well before the emergence The empirical knowledge thereby produced
of economics as a specialist discipline. For discursively refutes nationalist/socialist argu-
Foucault this is the first appearance in modern ments for sovereignty or re-organisation, which
philosophy of the idea of a subjective will, one would, philosophically speaking, be regarded as
which challenges that of sovereignty, be it in ‘untrue’. Provided individual agency conforms
the form of God, monarch or despotic ruler to the broader legal framework of the market,
(ibid.; 292). What we are concerned with here it is not pre-determined or bound to any state
is an economic figure, one not concerned with plan and can be considered a product of one’s
limiting sovereign power but with stripping own, free and rational choice. This is why in an
and appropriating parts of it, revealing a ‘ma- economic, empirical sense of self, alongside,

93
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

flexibility and choice are central to the experi- Conclusion


ence of neoliberal freedom (Bondi and Laurie
Relations of power necessarily contain the
2005; 398–399). Freedom on this schema is
possibility of freedom and resistance. Our
synonymous with choice, simultaneously en-
subjective experience of freedom, how we relate
abling an individual to ‘rationally’ allocate their
to ourselves, to one another and to power, is a
investments and pursue their desires, reflected
pressing issue today. For Foucault the failure of
in lifestyles, cultural practices and consump-
political ideas should not lead to a non-political
tive choices (Dilts 2011; 143). The neoliberal
way of thinking, but rather to an investigation
figure of homo economicus acts here as an atomic
into the ways by which we think politically.
island of rationality in an otherwise irrational,
Failure is not inscribed in political theories or
dispersed and unknowable sea of economic
ideas themselves but in ‘the type of rationality
activities (Foucault 2008; 282).
in which they are rooted’ (Foucault 2000b;
Societies and economies are now made up
of enterprise-units linked to neoliberalism and 417). For Foucault, the ‘political double bind’
its programme of rationality for society and the of Western political reason was to be found in
economy (ibid.; 225). As Foucault notes in The the ‘individualisation and the simultaneous
Care of the Self, ‘it is the modality of a rational totalisation of structures of modern power’
being, that establishes and ought to determine (Agamben 1998; 5).
in their concrete form, relations between the At the level of the individual, disciplin-
governors and the governed’ (1988; 91). That is ary power is not necessarily repressive, but
to say, in modernity, political freedom is judged potentially productive; in this article, I have
practically, via the space afforded to human sought to draw attention to the individualising
reason. Under the regime of neoliberal freedom, power of neoliberal freedom, while remaining
this modality is the rational, entrepreneurial self, highly critical of neoliberalism itself. Moreover,
negatively free from the state and positively free while power can be regarded as a relation that
to compete and produce its own life, income, produces freedom, we should remember that
investment and consumptive choices. It com- relations of power can become states of domi-
bines philosophical elements from what are clas- nation. Different forms of power coexist, even
sically considered heteronomous concepts of the if one form may appear more prevalent. There
self and freedom. Here, two divergent ends of are not societies of sovereign power, followed
life, Berlin’s divided self, are collapsed into one by disciplinary power or bio-power. Rather
another. This concord between the two is not these forms dovetail, interact and make use of
without tension, however; in my view, we see one another (Dean 2010; 122). Sovereignty is
here precisely the enduring and global dynamic closely related to bio-power, to political control
of neoliberalism, as a political rationality, with over life and the biological health of the popula-
a foothold in the discourses of both Left and tion. This raises political questions concerning
Right in politics. security and the concept of ‘deviant behaviour’,

94
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

‘the dangerous individual’ and ‘suspect popula- policies rely on for effective use, such as intense
tions’. It is here that we can identify some real surveillance and population classification, are
problems with the neoliberal concept of free- indistinguishable from the everyday commercial
dom, ones which challenge its understanding practices of the market. Predominantly these
of the self and reignite questions of sovereignty. are freely practiced by individuals, and not
These challenges can be seen in the normalisa- directly reducible to repressive state policy,
tion of the state of exception and the growth even though they enable and legitimate it.
of far-right nationalism. While these issues Here, disciplinary practices of freedom extend
are complex and contingent, the expansion of and are clearly embedded within broader, sys-
state sovereignty over individuals is a consistent tems of bio-power and apparatuses of security,
political phenomenon. Think of the phrase, which in turn reinforce sovereign policies of
‘Take back control’, which is surely a desire and social control.
aspiration for more sovereign power. The original vision of positive freedom,
Neoliberalism was predicated on the uncon- meant becoming empowered; through collec-
ditional separation of powers, which is supposed tive action it was possible to change society and
to ensure that nation states cannot transgress the world for the better. In enabling individuals
the bounds of law. In Hayek’s own words, ‘a to ‘self-actualise’, strictly as enterprise-machines,
free society certainly needs permanent means of in an economic framework that strips the state
restricting the powers of government, no matter of influence and application, neoliberal freedom
what the particular objective of the moment is limited. Such freedom is unable to provide
may be’ (1990 [1960]; 182). In our current for a richer understanding of ourselves and
situation, under the guise of security and the purpose in the world. Neither can it give due
need to ‘defend freedom’, coercive state policies ethical consideration to the violence and volatil-
have been passed that allow for the rule of law ity of political policies and economic processes,
to be subordinate to state objectives concern- particularly in times of crises.
ing the elusive concept of ‘terror’. Policies that
give states exceptional powers of surveillance, Acknowledgements
detention, and the potential to abandon and I would like to thank those who responded to
reduce citizens and refugees to ‘bare life’ (Agam- my paper at the CTRG symposium ‘Critical and
ben 1998) or ‘illegal aliens.’ These powers can Philosophical Issues after Post-Structuralism’ held
make democracies analogous to authoritarian at Leeds Beckett University, on which this article
systems. However, their implementation, or the is based. I would also like to thank A. Salem and
conditions for them, has been consented to by Joseph Backhouse-Barber for their help with and
parties from all across the political spectrum, comments on earlier drafts of the article. I am also
and treated as a pragmatic issue rather than grateful to Conrad Russell for his engaging and
as a deeply important legal and philosophical thought-provoking seminars, part of the master’s
issue. Further, the practices that many coercive module ‘Critical Methodologies’ at Leeds Beckett.

95
Critical Theory Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890

REFERENCES

Agamben, Giorgio. 1998. Homo Sacer: Sovereign edu/wp-content/uploads/2016/06/Clain_The-


Power and Bare Life. Stanford, CA: Stanford Univer- Ideal-of-Freedom-in-Modern-Times-and-Beyond.
sity Press. pdf> (Accessed: 16 June, 2017).
Agamben, Giorgio. 2005. State of Exception. Davenport, Thomas O. 1999. Human Capital,
Chicago: University of Chicago Press. What It Is and Why People Invest It. San Francisco,
Bauman, Zygmunt. 1988. Freedom. Milton CA: Jossey-Bass Inc. Publishers.
Keynes: Open University Press. De Angelis, Massimo. 2001. ‘Market Order
Baumol, William J. 1991. ‘A Glimpse of the In- and Panopticism’, Paper presented at the Heterodox
visible Hand’ in Graham Keith Shaw (ed.) Econom- Economics Conference, University of East London.
ics, Culture and Education: Essays in Honour of Mark [Online]. Available at: <http://libcom.org/files/
Blaug. Cheltenham, England: Edward Elgar. Panopticon.pdf> (Accessed: 20 June, 2017).
Becker, Gary S. 1965. ‘A Theory of the Al- Dean, Mitchell. 2010. Governmentality. Power
location of Time’, The Economic Journal 75  (299): and Rule in Modern Society. London: SAGE Publi-
493–517. cations.
Belloc, Hilaire. 2007 [1912]. The Servile State. Dilts, Andrew. 2011. ‘From ‘Entrepreneur of
New York: Cosimo Books the Self’ to ‘Care of the Self’: Neo-liberal Govern-
Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. ‘Two Concepts of Liberty’ mentality and Foucault’s Ethics’, Foucault Studies 12:
in Isaiah Berlin. Four Essays on Liberty. London and 130–146.
New York: Oxford University Press. Eymann, Torsten; Muller, Gunter; Sackmann,
Bondi, Liz; Laurie, Nina. 2005. ‘Introduction Stefan; Pippow, Ingow. 2003. ‘Hayek’s Catallaxy:
to the Special Issue: Working the Spaces of Neolib- A Forward-looking Concept for Information Sys-
eralism: Activism, Professionalisation and Incorpo- tems?’, Ninth Americas Conference for Information
ration’, Antipode 37 (3): 398–399. Systems: 1813–1822. [Online]. Available at: <http://
Brandist, Craig. 2014. ‘A very Stalinist man- www.pippow.de/Download/Catallaxy.pdf> (Ac-
agement model’, Times Higher Education (May cessed: 20 June, 2017).
29, 2014) [Online]. Available at: <http://www. Foucault, Michel. 1977. Discipline and Punish:
timeshighereducation.com/comment/opinion/a- The Birth of the Prison. New York: Penguin Books.
very-stalinist-management-model/2013616.arti- Foucault, Michel. 1988. The History and Sexual-
cle> (Accessed: 20 June, 2017). ity Vol. 3; The Care of the Self. New York: Vintage
Burchell, Graham. 1996. ‘Liberal Government Books.
and Techniques of the Self’ in Andrew Barry, Thom- Foucault, Michel. 2000a. Power: Essential Works
as Osborne and Nikolas Rose (eds.) Foucault and Po- of Foucault 1954–84, Volume 3. London: Penguin
litical Reason: Liberalism, Neo-Liberalism and Ration- Books.
alities of Government. London: UCL Press: 19–36. Foucault, Michel. 2000b. Ethics: Essential Works
Butler, Judith. 2000. ‘What is Critique? An Es- of Foucault 1954–84, Volume 1. London: Penguin
say on Foucault’s Virtue’ Published Online. [Online]. Books.
Available at: <http://eipcp.net/transversal/0806/ Foucault, Michel. 2002. The Order of Things.
butler/en> (Accessed: 20 June, 2017): 212–227. London: Routledge.
Callinicos, Alex. 2006. Universities in a Neolib- Foucault, Michel. 2008. The Birth of Biopoli-
eral World. London: Bookmarks. tics, Lectures at the College De France 1978–79. New
Clain, Olivier. 2016. ‘The Ideal of Freedom in York: Picador.
Modern Times and Beyond. On Liberalism and Ne- Friedrich, Carl. 1955. ‘The Political Thought of
oliberalism’, [Unpublished paper online]. Available Neo-Liberalism’, American Political Science Review
at: <http://live-critical-theory.pantheon.berkeley. 49 (2): 509–525.

96
Sociologija. Mintis ir veiksmas 2017/1 (40), (Online) ISSN 2335-8890 Critical Theory

Hamann, Trent H. 2009. ‘Neoliberalism, Gov- telligent Systems: Networks of Plausible Inference. San
ernmentality, and Ethics’, Foucault Studies 6: 37–59. Francisco, CA: Morgan-Kaufmann.
Hayek, Friedrich. 1990 [1960]. The Constitution Pearl, Judea. 2001. ‘Bayesian Networks’ in Mi-
of Liberty. London: Routledge Publishers. chael Arbib. Handbook of Brain Theory and Neural
Hayek, Friedrich. 2001 [1944]. The Road to Networks. Boston, MA: MIT Press.
Serfdom. London: Routledge Classics. Plant, Raymond. 2009. The Neo-liberal State.
Hegel, Georg Wilhelm Friedrich. 2011 [1837]. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
The Philosophy of World History. Canada: University Polanyi, Karl. 2001 [1944]. The Great Transfor-
of Toronto Libraries. mation: The Political and Economic Origins of Our
Landreth, Harry; Colander, David. 2001. The Time. Boston, MA: Beacon Press.
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques. 1999 [1762]. The Social
History of Economic Thought, 4th ed. Boston, MA:
Contract. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Houghton Mifflin.
Schultz, Theodore W. 1961. ‘Investment in Hu-
Odysseos, Louiza. 2010. ‘Human Rights, Lib-
man Capital’, The American Economic Review 51 (1):
eral Ontogenesis and Freedom: Producing a Subject 1–17.
for Neoliberalism?’, Journal of International Studies Schumpeter, Joseph. 1992 [1942]. Capitalism,
38 (3): 747–772. Socialism and Democracy. London: Routledge Press.
Oksala, Johanna. 2016. ‘Foucault, Husserl and Taylor, Charles. 1979. ‘What’s wrong with Neg-
the Philosophical Roots of German Neoliberalism’, ative Liberty’ in Alan Ryan (ed.) The Idea of Freedom.
Continental Philosophy Review 49 (1): 115–126. Essays in Honour of Isaiah Berlin. Oxford: Oxford
Ong, Aihwa. 2007. ‘Neoliberalism as a Mobile University Press: 175–193.
Technology’, Transactions of the Institute for British Till, Chris. 2014. ‘Exercise as Labour: Quan-
Geographers 32 (1): 3–8. tified Self and the Transformation of Exercise into
Pearl, Judea. 1988. Probabilistic Reasoning in In- Labour’, Societies 4: 446–462.

SANTRAUKA
ISAIAH BERLINAS, MICHELIS FOUCAULT IR NEOLIBERALIOS LAISVĖS POLITIKA
Pradedant istorine laisvės sąvokos apžvalga, šiame straipsnyje siekiama parodyti, kad neoliberalios laisvės
idėja pasiūlo naują šios sąvokos turinį. Joje bandoma suderinti skirtingus poreikius, kylančius iš dviejų neta-
pačių laisvės sampratų, aprašytų Isaiah Berlino. Dvi laisvės sampratos – pozityvi laisvė veikti kažką ir negaty-
vi laisvė nepriklausyti nuo kažko – skiriasi ne tik savo požiūriu į individą, bet ir savo implikacijomis į politi-
nių sistemų struktūrą. Kitaip negu ši priešprieša, neoliberalios laisvės samprata, kurią randame ankstyvuose
liberalų ekonomistų darbuose apie socialinę rinkos ekonomiką, pasižymi ekonomikos ir politikos sinteze,
kur socialinis reguliavimas subordinuojamas rinkos poreikiams. Pasitelkus Foucault argumentus, kad galia
veikia naudodamasi produktyviomis ir represyviomis praktikomis, neoliberalią laisvę galima suvokti kaip
koncepciją, siūlančią naują subjekto savimonės apibrėžtį, kur individai tampa „savivokos antrepreneriais“.
Konkurencinėje rinkoje neoliberali kultūra susaisto asmeninę laisvę su racionalia elgsena, o tai jai leidžia sy-
kiu reikalauti negatyvios laisvės (valstybės nesikišimo) ir įgalina racionalaus subjekto laisvą pasirinkimą. Šios
laisvės formos problemos ir implikacijos iliustruojamos pasitelkiant nuorodas į dabarties politikos įvykius.

School of Social Sciences


Leeds Beckett University
Calverley Building, Portland Way
Leeds LS1 3HE, UK
Email: t.driver4545@student.leedsbeckett.ac.uk


97

You might also like