You are on page 1of 11

MARÍA JOSÉ ALCARAZ LEÓN

Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? The Role


of Aesthetic Properties in the Constitution
of Non-aesthetic Value

abstract
The relationship between aesthetic value and other moral and cognitive values has been a key theme within contemporary
aesthetic discussion. In this article, I explore once again the implications of this relationship, but from what I think might be
a different angle. With few exceptions, notably Dominic Lopes, most of the contributions to this issue have dealt with the
impact that moral or cognitive values could possibly have on the overall aesthetic value of a work of art. In this article, I
explore instead how aesthetic properties or merits could play a role in explaining moral and cognitive properties. To do so, I
first offer some examples that I think may reasonably exemplify the phenomenon we are considering. Second, I argue that a
proper account of interactionism should meet at least two constraints: the relevance constraint and the autonomy constraint.
Finally, I try to clarify how it is possible that aesthetic properties substantially contribute to other values by appealing to the
notions of expression and the affective character of aesthetic properties.

The relationship between aesthetic value and In tune with Lopes’s proposal, I explore the
other moral and cognitive values has been a key possibility that aesthetic properties or merits
theme within contemporary aesthetic debates. play a significant role in explaining moral and
In particular, there has been a rich discussion cognitive value. Thus, I am sympathetic to
about how, if at all, moral or cognitive values Lopes’s attempt to defend interactionism, but I
of artworks can impinge upon their aesthetic or expand its scope to other artifacts and show that
artistic value. Different positions have entered interactionism is compatible with Particularism.2
the frame ranging from Radical Autonomism to In this sense, I concentrate upon the various
Radical Moralism or Ethicism.1 In this sense, the ways in which aesthetic properties may partly
relationship between aesthetic and non-aesthetic explain our attribution of moral or cognitive
value has been understood mostly as a one-way value to artworks as well to nonartistic artifacts
relationship. While moral and cognitive values and human behavior. To illuminate the sort of
have been regarded as partly responsible for the contribution that aesthetic properties can make
aesthetic greatness of a particular work, little to the emergence of other non-aesthetic features,
attention has been paid to the way in which some I appeal to the affective character of aesthetic
cognitive or moral values can be partly determined properties.
by aesthetic aspects. A significant exception to I argue that the role that aesthetics properties
this approach is Dominic Lopes’s (2005) defense may play in explaining other non-aesthetic prop-
of interactionism, which pays attention to the way erties is not a matter of chance or coincidence.
in which aesthetic merits can have an impact on Rather, aesthetic properties play this role—or at
pictorial artworks’ moral or cognitive properties. least it is possible that they play it—because their
The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism 76:1 Winter 2018
C 2018 The American Society for Aesthetics
22 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

affective character provides an explanation for to this relationship have looked at the representa-
such a role. Finally, if the analysis is cogent, it could tional arts, notably literature.3
be shown that, in some evaluative judgments, aes- In this section, I would like to show that interac-
thetic properties partly explain the presence of tionism may apply to a wider scope of objects and
moral and cognitive value. phenomena—such as nonartistic artifacts, pieces
But, before addressing the main issue of this ar- of behavior, or character traits—and that the focus
ticle, some clarifications could be required. Since upon artworks might narrow our understanding of
the main problem concerns what role, if any, aes- this phenomenon. Second, I explore the different
thetic properties or values may have in the expla- kinds of contributions that aesthetic (de)merits
nation of other non-aesthetic properties or values, can make to other moral or cognitive values.
we need to specify which aspects exactly are to be Finally, I also defend, partly relying on the variety
the focus of attention in order to clarify this rela- of cases displayed, that interactionism is not only
tionship. What kind of items are exactly the items compatible with the view called Particularism, but
that enter into this relation: do we talk about aes- that it requires it.
thetic properties, values, or merits? To what do Before introducing some examples that I think
these elements contribute? To moral and cogni- might illustrate this kind of relation and since
tive properties, values, or merits? Although there moral and cognitive merits will be mentioned
are important distinctions between, for example, continuously, I should say how to understand
aesthetic properties and aesthetic values, I address these nonaesthetic properties whose emergence
the problem without entering into these distinc- is, at least in the cases I am interested in, partly
tions. The main issue here is whether an object’s explained by the aesthetic dimension of the work.
aesthetic aspects can have a role in explaining Since I think interactionism applies not only to
other non-aesthetic features. The phenomenon artworks but to a wider range of representations,
will be characterized, then, as broadly as possible. artifacts, actions, and so on, it seems the notion
And I offer examples involving aesthetic proper- of a moral or cognitive (de)merit must be wide
ties, values, and merits. To which of these we refer enough to find its home in all these different
will be determined by the particular case under kinds of objects. Nevertheless, I take for granted
examination. While in some cases the relationship that what makes for a moral value in a represen-
will be better exemplified by the contribution that tational work might be different from what makes
aesthetic properties make to other non-aesthetic it that a piece of music is sentimental or a building
aspects, in others the moral worth, or merit, we aggressive. My aim is not to offer a precise charac-
attribute to a particular work can be grounded terization of what constitutes a moral or cognitive
upon the aesthetic merit we also find in it. My (de)merit or property in each case. Rather, I
aim is to show that, whatever the differences be- assume these kinds of attributions are part of our
tween properties and values, the issue of how the current characterization of artworks, representa-
aesthetic contributes to the non-aesthetic can be tions, actions, and so on. And I explain the extent
addressed consistently. Although elucidating this to which these attributions are partly explained by
contribution will in some cases require evaluative the aesthetic dimension of the items in question.
discourse and in others descriptive one, the key Now, if we try to illustrate interactionism with
issue is, I believe, that the aesthetic dimension of a some examples, it seems that the natural realm
work, object, or action can play a particular role in to begin with is representational arts. At least, if
the emergence of other non-aesthetic properties. we pay attention to the literature on this subject,
the typical examples are works of art. However,
as I have mentioned above, I think we can often
find examples of interactionism that fall outside
i. varieties of interactionism artistic media and that, therefore, indicate that this
relation has a wider scope.
Interactionism has been mostly discussed in Artifacts such as mathematical proofs or dia-
the context of art appreciation. More narrowly, grams can be good examples of the contribution
Lopes’s proposal is in principle limited to the field that aesthetic properties can make to cognitive
of pictorial appreciation and evaluation. Likewise, value.4 Although it is not completely uncontro-
most of the authors who have paid some attention versial, there is a certain agreement on the idea
Alcaraz León Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? 23

that the cognitive value of a mathematical proof These examples show, in my view, that interac-
might be partly improved by its formal beauty. tionism has a wider scope than most thinkers have
For some recent work on this issue, see especially assumed.6
McAllister (2005). Mathematicians and philoso- If we turn now to the arts, we can also see
phers alike have remarked that the elegance and that interactionism, although clearly exempli-
beauty of a mathematical proof may increase its fied within the representational arts, is not
cognitive value insofar as it presents mathemati- limited to them. Examining examples from
cal relations in a way that makes them clearer and different artistic media can provide some initial
more graspable. In this sense, two equally right support to approaching this issue as broadly
mathematical proofs will possess the same truth- as possible. I begin with a clear example of
value in terms of the content afforded but differ- representational painting, and I offer examples of
ent cognitive values in terms of the availability or different artistic media, both representational and
clarity with which the content is delivered. Hence, nonrepresentational.
the alleged cognitive value that simple, but elegant Chardin’s still life paintings have been fre-
and clear, mathematical proofs possess seems to quently described as possessing a moral grandeur,
be strongly connected to these aesthetic proper- which other works belonging to the same genre
ties. Moreover, this could probably be true in the lack. This aspect of Chardin’s work is related
case of scientific theories as well. The simplicity to his characteristic pictorial display of objects.
and elegance with which a theory is formulated Although most of the elements that feature in
usually contributes to its cognitive value not in the Chardin’s still lifes are inanimate beings, they of-
sense of making the content of the theory true but ten look as if they were something alive—as if the
in the sense of providing a better grasp of the facts objects were almost on the verge of moving. Of-
and relationships described within the theory. ten, this quality has been described by saying that
A different scenario in which we can identify the objects of Chardin’s paintings look more like
this role that aesthetic properties may play in people moving on a stage than like mere inert ob-
an explanation of other cognitive and moral jects. This dramatic quality explains why Chardin’s
properties pertains to the way we perceive and still life paintings, in spite of belonging to an un-
judge people’s behavior. Thus, aesthetic features dervalued genre, were so much cherished in his
of the way an action is performed or the aesthetic time. In a sense, he endowed the depicted ob-
aspects of personality and character may also be jects with a human quality that, in turn, elevated
significant here. Our moral judgments usually go the subject matter to another better-considered
beyond assessing the moral value of particular ac- genre.
tions. They also assess character traits or features But, how do we move from noticing this as-
of personality that may, in turn, also be grounded pect of Chardin’s still lifes to the claim about the
on an aesthetic dimension. An edgy character moral depth made visible in his paintings? How
can be linked to restless, unpurposive behavior; can simple, domestic objects invite thoughts usu-
a friendly and honest approach is usually seen ally associated with higher pictorial motives, such
in spontaneous, graceful, bodily movements. In as human action or human presence? It seems that
fact, sometimes, the moral worth of an action can this moral depth or quality cannot be simply ex-
be manifested by what we could identify as the plained by the fact that Chardin rendered ordinary
aesthetic or expressive aspects of the action. objects with a human-like appearance—albeit, as
Consider two agents performing a similar ac- I argue, this is important, too. What makes for the
tion, which, considering the situation, amounts to moral depth in Chardin is how his endowing of
the right thing to do. However, while one of the these objects with a human appearance serves as
subject’s performances is dry and mechanical, the a kind of visual metaphor for human dignity. His
other seems to be delicate and well adjusted. Even paintings show a kind of dignity that, because it is
if the outcome of these two actions is the same, we instantiated in humble, ordinary objects, achieves
could have some reasons to praise the latter in a a deeper sense for the viewer. Chardin’s mode of
way that will not be possible with the former. That depicting the objects in the pictorial space is one
is, the aesthetic character with which the agent per- of the main resources for achieving this effect. In
forms the action can improve an action’s overall fact, one of the features that seems to contribute
value.5 to this overall effect is the way Chardin typically
24 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

arranged the pictorial space; he rendered it as if Other nonrepresentational works, such as ab-
it were a theatrical stage where action could take solute or pure music, could similarly be said to
place. In doing so, a simple vase, a bunch of fruit, possess certain moral properties by virtue of the
or a dead ray—whose abdominal side seems to be expressive and aesthetic qualities the composer
looking at us—acquired a dramatic presence that endows the piece with (see Alcaraz León 2012).
became a personal mark of Chardin’s work. For a Thus, for example, Rêve d’amour by Liszt, whose
salient interpretation of Chardin’s work in terms excessive sentimental character could be regarded
of the notions of absorption and theatricality see as a moral defect of the piece, could be shown to be
Fried (1980). dependent upon the expressive resources devel-
Similarly, the delicacy of Chardin’s brushstroke oped by the composer.9 For example, the increase
and the atmospheric treatment of light and color in intensity in the development of the theme con-
are partly responsible for the profoundness of trasts with the final pianissimo section. This re-
his still lifes and for the peculiar sense of live- source allows the exploration of the same melody
liness that Proust (1988) so much praised and under different expressive characters: while it is
which Diderot (1995) found somehow magical. much more extroversive in the development of the
Thus, the moral dimension usually ascribed to melodic theme (thanks to the fast tempo and the
Chardin’s paintings is strongly grounded in their forte dynamics), the slowing down of the tempo
aesthetic character; for this dimension depends and the pianissimo in the final bars endows the
not on the representation of a clear moral scene melody with an intimate character. Finally, the
but on the aesthetic qualities we experience the rubatto effect that typically characterizes the in-
ordinary objects depicted as possessing. Com- terpretation of this piece endows the theme with
monplace pots and cutlery, ordinary pieces of a hesitant, but longing, character. One could say
bread and fruit become—through features such that Liszt conveys sentimentality right across the
as theatricality, dramatization, atmospheric qual- musical spectrum.
ities, and delicate brushstrokes—dignified and Although I have mostly presented cases where
morally charged. I think that a significant aspect of aesthetic qualities seem to contribute positively to
Chardin’s achievement has also to do with the fact the emergence of other values—except the cases
that the objects in his still lifes become dignified from the nonrepresentational arts—I think we can
without losing their ordinariness. Chardin’s pots, also find examples where an aesthetic merit may
vases, and goods are dignified without being sub- be regarded as deterring the cognitive or moral
limated or merely transformed into metaphoric value of a work, artifact, and so on.
devices. The beautification of appalling scenes or of
If we now look at some examples of nonrepre- depraved characters may just make this sort of
sentational art, we can easily find examples where contribution. In this sense, the alleged aesthetic
the relationship between the aesthetic character merit will not, as in the former examples, lead
of the work and its moral or cognitive value seem to other moral and cognitive merits. Rather,
to be intimately connected. Thus, for example, it will increase the immoral character of the
the authoritarian character7 of a building or representation. Thus, the alleged beauty of Leni
an architectural element, such as the façade of Riefenstahl’s fascist cinematic propaganda pur-
the Palazzo delle Espozisioni on the occasion portedly increases its malevolent effect.10 In this
of the Exhibition of the Fascist Revolution that sense, it has been pointed out that some positive
took place in 1932–1934, seems to be noticeably aesthetic properties—especially beauty—may be
grounded upon its aesthetic appearance. It is the partly responsible for moral and cognitive demer-
aesthetic dimension of the façade, its overwhelm- its. Typical examples will be the aesthetization of
ing solidness and grandeur, which endowed it violence or of crude images of victims of natural
with such moral quality.8 Its sober color and its disasters.11 Feminist thinkers have also pointed
location relative to other surrounding buildings to the way in which the aesthetization of women
also stroke the viewer’s aesthetic sensibility in a leads to their objectification and to the promotion
way that led to an experience of authority. Finally, of a dominant male perspective. One of the sem-
its verticality was emphasized by the solidity of inal works defending this idea is John Berger’s
the buttresses and made the viewer feel the power Ways of Seeing (1972). In this book, he shows how
the building was designed to embody. certain pictorial treatments of women’s nudity
Alcaraz León Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? 25

could promote treating it as an object for male the formal distortions are an aesthetic demerit or
desire. that distortion is ethically bad tout court. It is only
In these cases, aesthetic positive features may meant to point out the negative affective charac-
be put at the service of making palatable what is ter that a distorted form usually implies. The point
horrendous or despicable and, hence, of produc- of this example is to show how some qualities that
ing some moral harm upon those whose image is we would characterize as possessing a negative
perversely misused. Thus, it can be claimed that affective component can, nevertheless, contribute
it is precisely by virtue of the image’s aesthetic positively to the presence of an insightful and,
properties that it can be morally condemned: its hence, cognitively valuable representation.
immoral quality relies precisely upon its aesthetic These examples do not aim at providing a
“success.” general claim about the role this kind of aesthetic
Finally, we could also try to think of examples in feature can play in other works of art. The un-
which a negative aesthetic property or an aesthetic easiness with which the viewer may contemplate
demerit could contribute positively or negatively the human figures depicted in Bacon’s work or in
to the moral or cognitive value of an artwork or Goya’s paintings and which, I believe, are partly
artifact. Although the latter cases may seem eas- grounded upon the formal and aesthetic resources
ier to exemplify—for the negative contribution of of these painters’ pictorial style might be exclusive
an aesthetic demerit seems less puzzling than a to their work. This is, I think, unproblematic;
positive one—we can offer some examples that il- all that is required is that we can show how the
lustrate how an aesthetic demerit may be partly aesthetic dimension of the experience afforded by
responsible for a cognitive or moral value. these paintings is essential to its cognitive value.
Let us start with the easiest cases first. It Other works may use similar devices but in a
seems uncontroversial that a poor or formulaic completely different manner, and, therefore, they
description in a novel will render the novel’s may produce other effects in the viewer. But that
characters stereotypical and lacking depth. So, a particular aesthetic device can play different
the cognitive insight of the novel can be clearly roles in different artworks does not imply we
diminished by an aesthetic flaw. Similarly, the should give up on the idea that within a particular
moral sentimentality usually ascribed to the work—and in virtue of the affective character it
pictorial genre of Sentimental Realism is directly endows that particular work with—it can make a
grounded upon a formulaic way of drawing hu- significant contribution to the emergence of other
man figures, which tend to beautify the hopeless non-aesthetic qualities.
condition of the characters and to give them Having reflected upon the variety of objects,
an attractive and tender appearance that runs both artistic and nonartistic, and of the rela-
against the truthful depiction of misery. tionships between aesthetic (dis)value and other
But negative aesthetic qualities can also be moral and cognitive (dis)values, I think it may be
part of what makes a work cognitively valuable easier to defend the view, at least based upon the
or morally sound. Looking at a specific example, examples offered, that we should understand in-
it could be claimed that Goya’s distorted figures teractionism along Particularist terms. That is, I
in his Dark Paintings (or in Bacon’s portraits) think that there seems to be no principle we can
and the corresponding disturbing aesthetic expe- properly embrace to uphold the fact that aesthetic
rience that follows from them is what upholds its merits or demerits always contribute in the same
insightful character; in the sense that it is through way to the presence of other moral or cognitive
the aesthetic distortion of the human figure that values. We have seen that a positive aesthetic fea-
the viewer may come to be aware of a range of ture can both support moral (or cognitive) value
physical and psychological experiences whose and disvalue and that negative aesthetic features
communication would not have been successful do not always contribute negatively when they are
if the paintings were aesthetically pleasant. Thus, grounding other moral and cognitive properties.
negative aesthetic qualities can be partly responsi- Hence, I think we should embrace a Particular-
ble for the revelatory character of some artworks ist view about the relationship between aesthetic
and hence contribute to both their moral and and other moral and cognitive merits. That is, we
cognitive value. It should be said that the negative should assume that no principles or rules could de-
qualification here is not meant to indicate that termine what kind of contribution can be found.
26 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Aesthetic virtues may increase moral depravation artwork is not linked to its aesthetic character
and negative aesthetic experiences may contribute in any significant way. For example, I may come
to moral or cognitive insight. Also, similar aes- to know about the usual size and structure of a
thetic devices might play different roles depend- traditional Japanese house by reading Kokoro
ing on the work in which they appear and their (Sōseki 1914). While this may be considered a
significance given other features they relate to. cognitive value of the work, it is certainly not one
the work possesses because of any of its aesthetic
properties, for I can easily imagine this property
ii. a proper account of interactionism to be possessed by works lacking the aesthetic
properties of Kokoro. On the other hand, the
I think that in order to offer a proper account of insightful character that a literary description
interactionism two requirements are to be met. may possess can be intimately linked to the words
On the one hand, if aesthetic properties are to chosen by the narrator and to the descriptive
be able to play the explanatory role we assume rhythm that determines the mode in which the
they play, we need to show that it is precisely by reader has access to the character’s features.
virtue of possessing a particular aesthetic char- The sort of access and, hence, knowledge we have
acter that a work, artifact, and so on possesses about the character’s mind in Thomas Bernhard’s
some other moral or cognitive (de)merit and not novel The Loser (1983) is inextricably linked to
merely that these properties are coincidental. On the abundance of run-on sentences, obsessive
the other hand, a proper account of interactionism repetitions, and unexpected changes of the verbs’
should not undermine aesthetic autonomy; that tenses. In this second case, it seems more evident
is, it should not involve aesthetic properties no that the novel’s insightful character strongly de-
longer being autonomous. In what follows I ex- pends upon the aesthetic aspects that result from
plain the importance of these two requirements the literary procedure. Our access to the narrative
for a sound defense of interactionism. voice’s psychological profile is intimately linked to
The first one, which I call the ‘relevance con- the formal aspects that build it up. After examin-
straint,’ neutralizes one possible worry about the ing these two examples we can at least offer some
philosophical accuracy of the analysis offered. It resistance to the worry about the trivial contribu-
could be thought that interactionism is trivially tion of aesthetic properties to cognitive and moral
true if the moral and cognitive properties of art- values.
works are partly explained by aesthetic qualities The second condition that a proper account
simply because they are part of the properties that of interactionism should meet is what I call the
artworks possess and are, hence, articulated within ‘autonomy constraint.’ That is, we should be able
a particular artistic medium. After all, it is uncon- to account for the contribution that aesthetic
troversial that moral and cognitive properties of qualities make to other kinds of non-aesthetic
artworks, as well as other representational or ex- value while accommodating the idea of aesthetic
pressive properties, are the result of the artist’s autonomy.
work.12 Since such an interpretation will render The autonomous character of aesthetic judg-
interactionism trivially true and, hence, vacuous, ments is related, at least in Kant’s seminal work
we need to articulate it in a way that lets us distin- Critique of Judgement (1790), to two different, but
guish between genuine cases of an aesthetic con- somehow related, ideas. An aesthetic judgment is
tribution to other non-aesthetic values and cases autonomous in the sense that it is nonconceptual
where cognitive and moral merits are merely given or not governed by any principles or rules; that is
in an artwork. That is, we need to be able to distin- to say it is grounded solely on the experience of
guish cases in which the moral or cognitive proper- the object evaluated. In another sense, Kant refers
ties are truly informed by the aesthetic character to the autonomy of the judgment of taste when he
of the work and cases where such a contribution claims that no one’s opinion may be a determining
is missing. factor for rectifying one’s judgment, assuming this
It does not seem difficult, in principle, to is rightly grounded in a response of disinterested
identify examples of both types. If we focus on pleasure. I think that if we focus upon the first of
cognitive value, for example, we can easily imag- these ideas, endorsing the autonomous character
ine a case where the knowledge conveyed by an of an aesthetic judgment or experience does not
Alcaraz León Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? 27

necessarily involve the rejection of the central value (or independently from the experience
tenet of interactionism. And this is so for two it affords), there is room for autonomy within
reasons: the first is that, at least within the limited interactionism.
scope of our problem, there is nothing incompat- Autonomy is thus vindicated in spite of the
ible between, on the one hand, the autonomy of recognition that some other properties may play
aesthetic properties or values and, on the other, some role in how the object is experienced. The
its contribution to reasons supporting attribution minimal condition for the autonomy of taste is pre-
of other values. For, insofar as the aesthetic served. And, thus, the sort of interactionism that I
character of the work is not derived from other am trying to characterize can meet the autonomy
values, the requirements for the autonomy of constraint.
aesthetic judgment will be met. But even if I was
trying to defend interactionism as Lopes does,13
there is another consideration that can refute the iii. expression and the affective character
incompatibility between aesthetic autonomism of aesthetic properties
and interactionism. This consideration appeals
to a possible interpretation of the a-conceptual Having these remarks in mind, I offer, in what
character of aesthetic judgments. According to follows, some flesh to the view defended in this ar-
this interpretation, we can acknowledge that ticle. In order to meet the first requirement stated
concepts may to some extent determine our above, we should be able to show that some moral
perceptual experience without fully determining or cognitive properties typically experienced in
its aesthetic character. That is, there may be or attributed to artworks are, at least partly, ex-
conceptual aspects that partly determine our plained by aesthetic properties. How can we show
aesthetic experience without threatening the idea that this relation obtains nontrivially? What as-
that aesthetic value is autonomous in the minimal pects of aesthetic properties can help us to explain
sense required.14 For example, the fact that I see this role?
a particular object as an Abstract Expressionist I think we can focus upon the affective charac-
painting—that is, under the concept, or category, ter of aesthetic properties and its role in explaining
of Abstract Expressionist Painting—rather than the expressive dimension of art (artifacts, actions,
as a randomly marked surface that happened to and so on) in order to offer a cogent answer to
have that appearance by being left on the artist’s these questions.
studio floor can make a difference to my aesthetic The common view about what it is to ascribe
experience; however, the aesthetic value of each moral properties to artworks or representations
work, and the resulting judgment, will still depend in general focuses upon the notion of expression.
on my experience of it; and no prior knowledge Moral content can be rightly located in an artwork
of the category under which I should look at it not by focusing upon its representational content
will by itself establish its aesthetic value. Thus, but by examining the attitudes that the artwork
while acknowledging that perceptual experience embodies, or expresses, toward the content pre-
may be somehow conceptually constrained, sented. Those moral attitudes can be grasped, in
we could claim that this is indeed so in a way turn, by identifying the responses that the artwork
that does not undermine aesthetic autonomy. prescribes to the reader, viewer, or listener. (This
Aesthetic autonomy will be undermined if, by would not imply that the viewer has to actually
the mere application of a concept or, in our feel the emotions prescribed. It suffices that she
case, by the presence of a particular moral value, perceives the work as demanding (or prescribing)
the resulting aesthetic experience could be fully those emotions.) It is, then, by focusing upon the
anticipated. However, that I perceive something expressive aspects of a work that we can come to
in such a way that it conforms to a concept or assess its moral content. Thus, the alleged immoral
as exhibiting some moral property still leaves character of a representation that, for example,
room for the autonomy of aesthetic experience glorifies violence hangs not onto the representa-
as long as the resulting judgment depends upon tion of violent acts as such but on the prescribed
the experience of that object and not on the positive response to something that should be
concept by itself. Insofar as the aesthetic value of rejected.15 It is by virtue of prescribing an immoral
the work is not determined a priori by its moral response—for responding positively to violence
28 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

seems clearly wrong—that the work can be said to Thus, for example, Goya’s Disasters’ powerful
be immoral or to possess negative moral value.16 moral criticism is partly due to the affective re-
Now, a way to show how this picture of the sponse triggered by aesthetic properties such as
moral character of an artwork can pave the way its chaotic composition, its somber character, or
for the role of aesthetic properties in the configu- its unsublimating perspective. Its moral character
ration of other moral properties is to make clear is not primarily due to the represented content but
the role that aesthetic properties may play in ex- to the affective attitude with which the content is
plaining a work’s expressive content and, there- presented—which, in turn, explains the core of
fore, in the formation of its moral content.17 the prescribed response to the viewer. And this
To do so, it might be necessary to provide some affective attitude is mainly conveyed through the
view of what artistic expression is and in what aesthetic characterization of the subject. This was
sense expressive content can be rightly embedded also the case with the still life paintings we referred
in the aesthetic character of a work. Although, to above. The moral dignity of Chardin’s still lifes
given the scope of this article, such a task may be was, as we pointed out, due to aesthetic qualities
unaccomplished, I would like to offer some ex- such as theatricality or subtle atmospheric effects.
amples that may render the relationship between The aesthetic presentation of the objects depicted
the aesthetic qualities of a work and its expressive endowed them with a human-like presence with-
character clearer. That is, I would like to motivate out depriving them of their everyday character.
the idea that the expressive character of a work The kind of regard projected onto these humble
of art, as a work of art, results from the work’s items invites the viewer to adopt a respectful and
aesthetic character. quiet attitude. It is significant, I think, that some of
A simple way to show that there may be a the most salient commentators of Chardin’s still
connection between the aesthetic aspects and the lifes tend to invoke silence as a way to describe
expressive character of a work in the way I am sug- the experience afforded by these pictorial scenes.
gesting is by underlying how the affective dimen- (See, for example, Diderot 1995.)
sion of a work’s aesthetic character contributes Expressive failures might, conversely, be
to its expressive content and, through this, to its responsible for moral attributions such as
moral character. Since the phenomenon of expres- sentimentality.19 The moral assessment of Ilya
sion is typically linked to the affective dimension Repin’s painting What a Freedom! (1903) is nega-
of an object, action, or representation, we can ar- tive precisely because the aesthetic features with
ticulate the role that aesthetic properties can play which the theme is endowed seem to prescribe
in explaining other values by focusing on their an enthusiastic response the viewer may find ex-
characteristic affective dimension. By the affec- cessive or forced.20 As a result, a sensitive viewer
tive dimension of aesthetic properties, I refer to may find that the affective engagement that the
the idea that grasping this kind of property typ- work prescribes is undeserved or inappropriate.
ically has an affective or responsive dimension. And, hence, the sentimental character of the
For example, to see that something is garish in- painting—that is, its moral flaw—can be shown
volves affectively responding in a certain way to to be dependent upon its expressive and aesthetic
the work.18 failure. The affective response that actually
The aesthetic properties of a work can, thus, results from the aesthetic plainness of the work
contribute to its expressive character insofar as runs against the intended expressive content of
they are typically grasped affectively. It is through the work and, thus, makes it fail in this respect.
the affective dimension usually attached to aes- Although the examples offered so far are picto-
thetic properties that their contribution to the ex- rial and, more specifically, depictive, we can spec-
pressive character of a work can be intimated. A ulate that the relationship between the aesthetic
graceful line or a vacillating melody can elicit af- dimension of a work and its expressive character
fective responses in the viewer or the listener that, may also hold in cases where the work possesses
in turn, play a role in grasping the work’s partic- expressive content without representing anything
ular expressive content. And, since expression is in particular. Architecture or pure music could
the mode through which a work’s moral content also provide good examples. Thus, condemning a
becomes articulated, we can easily show its depen- pompous mansion in the middle of a rather hum-
dence upon the aesthetic character of the work. ble but nicely built village can be partly explained
Alcaraz León Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? 29

by the mansion’s assertive and exhibitionist char- a comprehensive specification of our experience
acter, which, in turn, results from its aesthetic of a work as possessing certain moral or cognitive
properties, such as sumptuousness and intended features may require having grasped its aesthetic
impressiveness. Although it becomes less frequent dimension and the way in which this aspect in-
that we similarly condemn ordinary objects with forms other properties that are graspable in the
the same strength as we might condemn Repin’s work or object.
sentimentalism or a mansion’s presumptuousness, This conclusion also aspires not only to cover
I think one can also make sense of the inadequacy artistic examples but also cases in which we could
of a certain dress or of a certain form of speech, reasonably appeal to an aesthetic property or
given a particular context. However, for reasons of quality in order to justify our attribution of a cog-
space I will not expand more on these examples.21 nitive or moral (de)merit. In this sense, the view
The possible contribution that aesthetic prop- proposed aims at being as comprehensible as pos-
erties can therefore make to the emergence of sible and to explain in what sense particular moral
other non-aesthetic properties, such as moral or judgments about, say, an action may legitimately
cognitive ones, is then clarified by paying atten- appeal to aesthetic aspects of the performing of
tion to their characteristic affective character and, the action.
furthermore, to the way in which this affective If the notion of expression is robust enough
character is involved in the expressive dimension in order to articulate the relationship that I have
of a particular work or representation. explored, we could conclude that, in some cases,
aesthetic properties partly explain the presence of
moral and cognitive value.22
iv. final remarks
MARÍA JOSÉ ALCARAZ LEÓN
In this article I have argued that aesthetic Department of Philosophy
properties can be properly cited in an account of University of Murcia
other non-aesthetic properties, such as moral or Murcia, Spain
cognitive ones. To do so, I began by offering some
internet: mariajo@um.es
examples of the kind of explanatory contribution
that aesthetic properties may make to other
non-aesthetic properties. After examining several
examples, I argued that we should aspire to an references
explanation of the phenomenon that is compat-
ible with a Particularist view of the relationship Alcaraz León, Marı́a José. 2012. “Music’s Moral Character.”
Teorema 31: 179–191.
between the aesthetic and the non-aesthetic. Berger, John. 1972. Ways of Seeing. London: Penguin.
Second, I have pointed out two necessary Bernhard, Thomas. 1991 [1983].The Loser. Translated by Jack
requirements that a cogent account of interac- Dawson. New York: Knopf.
Bradley, A. C. 1959. “Poetry for Poetry’s Sake.” In Oxford
tionism should meet: the relevance constraint and Lectures on Poetry, 2nd edition, 4–32. London: Macmillan.
the autonomy constraint. In my view, a proper Budd, Malcolm. 2008. “The Pure Judgement of Taste as an
explanation of interactionism should respect the Aesthetic Reflective Judgement.” In Aesthetic Essays, 105–
121. Oxford University Press.
view known as ‘aesthetic autonomy’ and provide Dancy, Jonathan. 1999. “Defending Particularism.” Metaphilos-
an explanation of the fact that grasping aesthetic ophy 30: 25–32.
properties can be a condition for grasping other . 2004. Ethics without Principles. Clarendon Press.
non-aesthetic properties. D’Arms, Justin, and Daniel Jacobson. 2000. “The Moralistic
Fallacy: On the ‘Appropriateness’ of Emotions.” Philosophy
Finally, I have appealed to the notion of and Phenomenological Research 61: 65–90.
expression in order to flesh out the idea that aes- Deveraux, Mary. 1998. “Beauty and Evil: The Case of Leni
thetic properties can play a significant role as rea- Riefenstahl’s Triumph of the Will.’’ In Aesthetics and Ethics,
edited by Jerrold Levinson, 227–256. Cambridge University
sons for the presence of other non-aesthetic prop- Press.
erties. As I have shown, the affective character Diderot, Denis. 1995. Diderot on Art: The Salon of 1765 and
of aesthetic qualities can be appealed to in order Notes on Painting (Vol. I), and Diderot on Art: The Salon of
1767 (Vol. II). Translated by John Goodman. Yale University
to explain how a work’s artistic content, includ-
Press.
ing its expressive character and hence some of its Fried, Michael. 1980. Absorption and Theatricality: Painting and
moral or cognitive values, can be explained. Thus, Beholder in the Age of Diderot. University of Chicago Press.
30 The Journal of Aesthetics and Art Criticism

Gaut, Berys. 1998. “The Ethical Criticism of Art.” In Aesthet- between aesthetic sensibility and moral disposition has a
ics and Ethics: Essays at the Intersection, edited by Jerrold long history. Both Kant and Schiller pointed out that aes-
Levinson, 182–203. Cambridge University Press. thetic sensibility contributed to, or disposed us to, good ac-
. 2009. “Morality and Art.” In A Companion to Aesthet- tion. In “The Moral Utility of Aesthetic Manners,” Schiller
ics, 2nd edition, edited by Stephen Davies, Kathleen Marie defended “that a strong and pure feeling for the beautiful
Higgins, Robert Hopkins, Robert Stecker, and David E. ought to exercise a salutary influence upon the moral life”
Cooper, 428–431. Malden, MA: Wiley-Blackwell. (1884, 126).
Goldie, Peter, and Elisabeth Schellekens (eds.). 2007. Philoso- 6. At this stage of the argument, these examples are pre-
phy and Conceptual Art. Clarendon Press.
sented merely as a way to illustrate as widely as possible the
. 2009. Who’s Afraid of Conceptual Art. London:
phenomenon we are interested in. They are intended, first,
Routledge.
Greenberg, Clement. 1939. “Avant-Garde and Kitsch.” Partisan to show that the phenomenon can be instantiated in many
Review 6(5): 34–49. different kinds of objects, both artistic and nonartistic, and,
Kant, Immanuel. 1952 [1790]. Critique of Judgement. Translated second, to motivate the case for a role of aesthetic proper-
by James Creed Meredith. Oxford University Press. ties in the explanation of other sorts of properties. Since the
Lopes, Dominic McIver. 2005. Sight and Sensibility: Evaluating examples are merely presented but not fully explained, they
Pictures. Clarendon Press. cannot be considered as conclusive but merely as indicating
McAllister, James W. 2005. “Mathematical Beauty and the Evo- that the phenomenon might be worth exploring. Some of
lution of the Standards of Mathematical Proof.” In The Visual them will be further developed alongside the following dis-
Mind II, edited by Michele Emmer, 15–34. MIT Press. cussion, but others have been presented as mere indications
Pérez Carreño, Francisca. 2014. “Sentimentality as an Ethical in favor of the idea that the aesthetic aspect of a particular
and Aesthetic Fault.” Proceedings of the European Society work, object, or action can have an impact upon other of
for Aesthetics 6: 286–304. their non-aesthetic properties.
Proust, Marcel. 1988. “Chardin: The Essence of Things.” In 7. Although it could be said that here the authoritative
Writers on Artists, edited by Daniel Halpern, 102–106. San character could be considered as an aesthetic quality, I think
Francisco: North Point Press.
the sense in which this quality also has a moral dimension
Schiller, Friedrich. 1884 [1796].“The Moral Utility of Aesthetic
remains in place. In this sense, even if some adjectives may
Manners.” In Aesthetical and Philosophical Essays, translator
be taken to possess a twofold character in the sense that they
anonymous, 126–135. Boston: S. E. Cassino.
Scruton, Roger. 1980. The Aesthetics of Architecture. Princeton may be understood as possessing an aesthetic and a moral
University Press. dimension, I think there is still room to see in which way
Shelley, James. 2003. “The Problem of Non-Perceptual Art.” the moral character attributed to the building is articulated
British Journal of Aesthetics 43: 363–378. through other aesthetic features that can be easily identified
Sōseki, Natsume. 2010 [1914]. Kokoro. Translated by Meredith and that invite no confusion as to their status as aesthetic
McKinney. London: Penguin. qualities.
8. For other approaches to the issue of morality in ar-
chitecture see Architecture-Philosophy (Vol. 2, no. 1, Win-
1. For a classical defence of Autonomism, see Bradley ter 2016): http://isparchitecture.com/volume-2-number-1/.
(1959). Concerning Ethicism, see Gaut (1998). Also, Scruton (1980).
2. Although the view called Particularism has its home 9. For a defense of the idea that sentimentality can be
domain in moral philosophy or meta-ethics and has been considered both a moral and an aesthetic defect see Pérez
prominently defended by Dancy (1999, 2004), I try to defend Carreño (2014). According to the account offered by Pérez
the view that, if aesthetic properties can contribute to an Carreño, sentimentality in art can be considered as a moral
explanation of other non-aesthetic properties, we need to defect because it results from an expressive failure, that is,
understand this kind of contribution in a way that rejects from a failed attempt to express something truthfully. Thus,
the need—and, more strongly, the possibility—of finding sentimentality could be regarded as a form of insincerity
principles that articulate this relationship. at the level of the expressive content of the work. If we
3. I think the reason why interactionism has been consider sentimentality under this light, it is easier to see
mostly discussed in relation to literary works has to do with how the aesthetic resources displayed in Liszt’s composition
the usual attribution of moral value to literature as opposed contribute to this moral flaw of his work.
to, say, music or architecture. 10. Although I am aware that discussion over this work
4. I understand ‘artifact’ here in a very broad sense. For cannot be covered in a single footnote, I think that the focus
example, I consider that things such as a mathematical proof of the article can throw some new light upon the puzzlement
are artifacts, albeit of an intellectual character. that Riefenstahl’s work has often produced. In this respect,
Although there has been some discussion about aesthetic it should be noticed that much of the literature around this
properties that can be attributed to artifacts that we do not work has focused upon the relationship between the im-
become acquainted with through perceptual experience, I moral content it conveys and its aesthetic worth. The initial
assume that, at least within a broader understanding of the setting of the problem was due to Deveraux (1998), who
notion of aesthetic properties, some conceptual entities such wondered whether the work could be less aesthetically suc-
as mathematical proofs may possess aesthetic properties. cessful given its immoral character. However, there is no re-
Significant defenders of a broad view of aesthetic experience search, at least to my knowledge, that focuses upon whether
are Shelley (2003) and Goldie and Schellekens (2007, 2009). the immoral character of the work is partly caused by its aes-
5. Although my approach to the relationship between thetic success. This is the alternative I would like to explore.
moral and aesthetic value is in some crucial aspects dis- I think that looking at how the work’s aesthetic value can
tinct from classical approaches to this issue, the proximity increase its malice can offer some insight into works whose
Alcaraz León Aesthetics Makes Nothing Happen? 31

puzzling character seem to be related to the fact that they are in a particular work contributes to immorality or not. Once
both aesthetically valuable but morally revolting. The work’s we have assessed the moral character of the prescribed
menacing message is even more menacing because the way response, however, I think that we can generally assume
the message is conveyed, the aesthetic means through which that the morality or immorality of those responses is what
it is presented to the viewer, are good aesthetic means. That determines the moral character of the work. I owe this
is, its malicious character and its dangerous effect are partly clarification to a comment by an anonymous referee.
supported by the aesthetic success of the work. 16. Although I will not enter into the discussion of what
11. Aesthetization is usually considered a moral flaw di- counts as a merited or unmerited response toward the repre-
rectly caused by the inappropriate use of aesthetic resources. sented content of an artwork or representation, I will assume
Aesthetization often involves embellishing or making ap- that the moral or immoral character of an artwork or repre-
pealing something that should not be shown as pleasant. sentation is grounded upon the moral or immoral character
This is why it is often mentioned when deceitful methods of the response prescribed toward the events represented.
are employed in politics or when political reasoning is sub- In this sense, I will avoid the discussion about whether all
stituted for aesthetic appeal. In a sense this phenomenon immoral responses are unmerited. That is, whether it might
could be a paradigmatic case of the significant contribution be the case that a particular response might be immoral but
that aesthetic properties or features can make to other non- merited by the work. For two prominent defenders of the
aesthetic features. It is precisely through the embellishing opposing views that articulate this debate, see Gaut (2009)
of a theme that should not be presented under an appealing and D’Arms and Jacobson (2000).
light that the representation becomes immoral. 17. Although I refer mostly to artworks in this section,
12. This worry is referred to by Lopes (2005) as I think what it is said about expression in art can also be
“aesthetic saturation.” Aesthetic saturation is the view that extended to other expressive devices, including behavior.
“for any type of non-aesthetic evaluation, V, some aesthetic 18. I would like to clarify that the way in which the char-
evaluations imply or are implied by some V-evaluation” acteristic affectivity of aesthetic properties is understood
(Lopes 2005, 7). Clearly, this view will render interactionism here does not involve endorsing the view that all aesthetic
vacuous, and that is why Lopes rejects it. I regard my concepts are evaluative or that their canonical use is sys-
proposal in this article as related to Lopes’s attempt to tematically linked to a positive or negative response. In this
defend what he calls interactionism and, in particular, what sense, while I think that grasping the garishness of a picture
he terms as “aesthetic articulation,” that is, the view that may in some cases lead to a negative aesthetic judgment of
“there are some types of non-aesthetic evaluations, V, such the picture, there may be cases in which a work’s garishness
that some aesthetic evaluations imply or are implied by is a reason for its aesthetic merit. In any case, perceiving
some V-evaluations” (8). In this sense I attend to the way something as garish involves responding affectively to that
in which aesthetic evaluations (or, more generally, aesthetic feature.
properties) may imply other non-aesthetic values. However, 19. See Pérez Carreño (2014).
for reasons that will become apparent in this article, I 20. Following Greenberg’s (1939) assessment of
depart from Lopes’s characterization of interactionism. Repin’s work as sentimental and kitsch, we can consider
13. That is, following Lopes’s formulation that aes- this particular work as an example of an expressive failure
thetic evaluations may imply other non-aesthetic values but in the sense that the response that it effectively triggers in the
also that some non-aesthetic values may imply aesthetic sensitive viewer is not one of complacency but of despisal.
evaluations. 21. For a consideration of how the moral character of
14. For a similar understanding of aesthetic autonomy pure music can be grounded in its expressive character see
see Budd (2008). Alcaraz León (2012).
15. It could be questioned that prescribing a positive 22. This article has been funded by the Program
response to violence or other dreadful events generally Jóvenes Lı́deres en Investigación de la Fundación Séneca-
involves prescribing an immoral response. Maybe the Agencia de Ciencia y Tecnologı́a de la Región de Murcia
prescribed response is prescribed in a manner that triggers (18958/JLI/13) “El valor estético y su interacción con otros
further thoughts about how we usually respond to violence valores en la práctica apreciativa” and (FFI2015-64271-
and, therefore, has a further moral insightful character. It P) “Experiencia estética de las artes y complejidad de la
might require a case-by-case study to determine whether percepción” (Ministerio de Economı́a y competitividad)
the prescription of a positive response to dreadful events 2016–2020.

You might also like