You are on page 1of 4

This article was downloaded by: [190.47.216.

29]
On: 10 February 2013, At: 17:41
Publisher: Taylor & Francis
Informa Ltd Registered in England and Wales Registered Number: 1072954 Registered office: Mortimer House,
37-41 Mortimer Street, London W1T 3JH, UK

International Journal of General Systems


Publication details, including instructions for authors and subscription information:
http://www.tandfonline.com/loi/ggen20

INTRODUCTORY COMMENTS TO FRANCISCO VARELA' S


CALCULUS FOR SELF-REFERENCE
a a
RICHARD HERBERT HOWE & HEINZ VON FOERSTER
a
Biological Computer Laboratory, University of Illinois, Urbana, Illinois, U.S.A
Version of record first published: 31 May 2007.

To cite this article: RICHARD HERBERT HOWE & HEINZ VON FOERSTER (1975): INTRODUCTORY COMMENTS TO FRANCISCO
VARELA' S CALCULUS FOR SELF-REFERENCE, International Journal of General Systems, 2:1, 1-3

To link to this article: http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/03081077508960827

PLEASE SCROLL DOWN FOR ARTICLE

Full terms and conditions of use: http://www.tandfonline.com/page/terms-and-conditions

This article may be used for research, teaching, and private study purposes. Any substantial or systematic
reproduction, redistribution, reselling, loan, sub-licensing, systematic supply, or distribution in any form to
anyone is expressly forbidden.

The publisher does not give any warranty express or implied or make any representation that the contents
will be complete or accurate or up to date. The accuracy of any instructions, formulae, and drug doses should
be independently verified with primary sources. The publisher shall not be liable for any loss, actions, claims,
proceedings, demand, or costs or damages whatsoever or howsoever caused arising directly or indirectly in
connection with or arising out of the use of this material.
Q Gordon and Breach Science Publishers Ltd.
Int. I . General Syxtems
1975, Vol. 2, pp. 1-3. Printed in Great Britain

INTRODUCTORY COMMENTS TO FRANCISCO VARELA'S


CALCULUS FOR SELF-REFERENCE
RICHARD HERBERT HOWE and HEINZ VON FOERSTER
Biological Computer Laboratory, University of Illinois, Urbana, Illinois, U.S.A.

Etymologically speaking, correct opinion is ortho- doxes, W & R describe seven of the most popular
dox; paradox, however, lies beyond opinion. ones, including Epimenides remark and, of course,
Unfortunately, orthodox attempts to establish the Russell's class of all classes that are not members of
Downloaded by [190.47.216.29] at 17:41 10 February 2013

orthodoxy of the orthodox result in paradox, and, themselves.


conversely, the appearance of paradox within the
orthodox puts an end to the orthodoxy of the "In all the above contradictions (which are merely ~tlcctions
orthodox. In other words, paradox is the apostle of from an infinite number) there is a common characteristic,
sedition in the kingdom of the orthodox. This is a which we may describe as self-reference or reflexiveness. The
remark of Epimenids must include itself in its own scope.
headache, and has been ever since the Cretan If all classes, provided they arc not members of themselves,
philosopher Epirnenides put forth the proposition are members of w this must also apply to w ; and similarly
that "All Cretans are liars". The paradoxical pro- for the analogous relational contradictions".'
position is seditious . because it maintains an
undesirable autonomy vis-a-vis any orthodox Now that the seditious spirit corrupting ortho-
attempt to, apprehend it: when apprehended as doxy in logic was identified as Self-Reference,
true, it turns out to be false; when apprehended as W & R could go about exorcising it. The method,
false, it turns out to be true. known as the Theory of Logical Types, by which
As long as was possibJe, logical orthodoxy the two liberal gentlemen sumssfully performed
attempted to treat such sed~tiousintrusions just as this operation, was simply to prohibit self-
would any other orthodoxy, that is, to dismiss them referential utterances, statements, propositions,
as cranks, as (syntactic) pathologies, (semantic) descriptions, etc.
freaks, in short, as aberrations (of thought). Para- This prohibition not only eliminates the potenti,al
dox survived in the kingdom of the orthodox only for formulating paradoxes of the above kind, it also
by virtue of the asylum granted it as an entertain- eliminates the potential for contaminating utter-
ment'for the learned, much as in happier times the ances, statements, propositions, descriptions, etc.
insane were displayed for the amusement of the with the properties of those who utter, state,
curious. propose, describe, etc. In other words, implicit in
This comfortable state of affairs, however, the Theory of Types is the proviso that is the '
abruptly changed when Bertrand RusseH dis- ultimate protector of the Claim to Objectivity:
covered that paradox is central-and not peripheral "The properties of the observer shall not enter into
-to all logical inquiry, that is, it affects the general the description of his observations."*
validity of logical formalism per se, and must be The logic of our Western industrial corporate
dealt with at the outset in any logical theory. society (with limited liability) is unidirectional,
Consequently, already in the introductory 'chap- deductive, competitive, and hierarchical, and the
ters of the Principia Mathematical Whitehead and keystones of its paradigms are the Claim to
Russell ( W & R) address themselves to logical Objectivity and the Theory of Types, which exclude
problems that arise with "certain contradictions" in principle the autonomy of paradox and of the
(i.e., the paradoxes) and to remedies that bring individual. In the scientific revolution that we now
about their solution: "An analysis of the paradoxes create and experience, however, we perceive a shift
to be -avoided shows that they all result from a from causal unidirectional to mutualistic systemic
certain kind of vicious circle."' In order for their thin~ung,~.' from a preoccupation with the
readers to appreciate the similarity of these para- properties of the observed to the study of the
2 COMMENTS TO VARELA'S CALCULUS

properties of the o b s e r ~ e r .The


~ initiator of this paradox and " . . . the famous argument of Godel
shift was Kant, who placed the autonomy of the may, evidently, be thought of as an application of
y.PPl.4
observer at the center of his philosophy, thus
making this autonomy responsible for the pro- The immediate precursor of Francisco Varela's
perties of the observed.' It can bc no coincidence Calculus for Self-Reference(CRS)and, most likely,
that the realization of this shift in our contemporary a necessary prerequisite for understanding it, is.
scientific paradigm takes place just as the relation- of course, G. Spencer Brown's Laws of Form.15
ship of (individual) autonomy to (social) responsi- Although a skeleton of the form of these laws is
bility has become intensely problematical. One given by Vareia in the appendix to his paper, those
manifestation of this shift is our rapid recovery of unfamiliar with this formalism should get hold of
the significance of both paradox and self-reference, Laws of Form for the sake of enjoying an amazing
and of their intrinsic relationship. book and for relishing Varela's Calculus.
For instance, in psychiatry the significance of The train of thoughts leading to CRS is initiated
the relationship paradolr-self-reference, which in by G . Spencer Brown's Calculus of Indications
one context may have destructive, but in another (CI), which is implemented with ultimate parsimony
context constructive consequences has been pointed by a single operator marked 1 (a "distinctor"),
Downloaded by [190.47.216.29] at 17:41 10 February 2013

out again and again by George Bateson.'? In the which does several things at one time. Since we
destructive (pathological) case, a paradoxical cannot make an indication without drawing a
interpersonal (e.g., mother-daughter) relation distinction, when this mark is taken as a token for
exists, the "double bind", in which autonomy of indicating the state distinguished by the distinctor,
one partner (daughter) is encouraged by the other then 1is zn "indicator" (for the state so marked is
(mother) on one level of discourse, but denied on now the marked state); a "signal" (signalling
another (say, the interpretive) level; the (con- distinction); and an "intentor" (since use of any
trolled) breakdown of the "metalogue" causes the signal is intent). The state not marked with the
victim to withdraw affectively, and other schizo- mark 1is the unmarked state.
phrenic symptoms develop." Rules for concatenating this operator to give a
On the other hand, stress experienced through primary arithmetic are determined by two axioms
the irresolvability of paradox in known domains (no other ones are needed):
(c.g., two incongruent flat retinal images of the
" s k e w scene) necessitates creating new dimensions Axiom 1. The law of calling.
("depth"). The value of a call made again is the value of the call.
That is to say, if a name is called and then is called
"A parndox is a contradiction in which you take sides- again, the value indicated by the two calls taken
both sides. Each half of the paradox p r o m the other . . . together is the value indicated by one of them.
..
if you s w a t out one of these paradom YOU embark. on a That is to say, for any name, to recall is to call.
voynge, which may include hallucinations and tram . . .
But you come out knowing something you didn't know (In notation:
before, something about the nature of where you arc in the
universe"."
the "form of condensation.")
Even in the context of inquiries into the structure
of logical form it became evident that dogmatic Axiom 2. The law of crossing.
prohibitions as expressed in the Theory of Logical The value of a crossing made again is not the ualue of
Types are untenable in a general theory of logical the crossing.
fonns. For instance, according to Curry and Feys:' ' That is to say, if it is intended to cross a boundary
"We can no longer 'explain' a paradox by running and then it is intended to cross it again, the value
away from it; we must stand and took it in the eye." indicated by the two intentions taken together is the
And, indeed, these authors not only looked para- value indicated by none of them.
doxes in the eye, but also constructed a whole class That is to say, for any boundary, to recross is not
of operators, t l ~ e"paradoxical combinators," one to cross.
of which, Y, called "the paradoxical combinator," (In notation:
may be used to construct logico-mathematical 7s
objects of a more or less paradoxical nature. For
instance, Y may be used to construct Russell's the "form of cancellation.")
COMMENTS TO VARELA'S CALCULUS 3

With two initials shift from objectivity to subjectivity but rather to


Initial 1. Position initiate an ethics, for he clearly saw that without
autonomy there could be no responsibility and
1- = hence no ethics.' Ethics-and not subjectivity-is
Initial 2. Transposition the complement of objectivity. Lying-and not
' r n l =mI
objectivity-is the problem and the force of the
r paradox of the Cretan liar. With his calculus of
the primary algebra is established. the paradoxical, the sel f-referential, the autono-
Letf(X) be the form of an algebraic expression, mous, Varela has opened for the first time the
then expressions of arbitrary length can be estab- possibility of a Calculus of Responsibility.
lished recursively (where Xi = f(Xi+l) and, e.g.,
f 2 ) ( x i=) f(f(Xi)) etc.):
REFERENCES
y = f '"'(X,). I. A. N. whitehead and B. Russell, Principio Mathematico,
Second Edition, University Press, Cambridge, 1925.
Downloaded by [190.47.216.29] at 17:41 10 February 2013

For n -+ these become recursive expressions 2. lbid, p. 37.


of indefinite length, and because of the identity 3. lbid, p. 61.
4. R . Abramovitz er 01.. Cybernetics of Cybernetics,
y = lirn f("-')(X,-,) = lim f'"'(Xn) B.C.L. Report No. 73.38, Biological Computer Labora-
n-m n-m
tory, University of Illinois, Urbana, 1974, p. 374.
the function may re-enter its own scope to give, 5. T. Kuhn, Tlre Structrrre of Sciertti/ic Revolurions,
University of Chicago Press, Chicago, 1961.
when so collapsed 6. W. R. Ashby, "Systems and their informational
rncasures." In: Tretld~ irr Cerreral Sysrems Theory,
edited by G . J. Klir, John Wiley, New York, 1972,
the formal equivalent to Russell's paradox pp. 78-97.
7. S. Beer, Decbiorr uric1 Conrrol, John Wiley, New York,
f =A 1964.
8. H. R. Maturana, Bio/ogy oJ~Cognitio)t,B.C.L. Report
Thanks to the ingenious notation, the bi-stable No. 9.0, Biological Computer Laboratory, University
nature of such expressions becomes transparent, of l l l i ~ ~ o iUrbana,
i, 1970.
9. 1. Kant, Kririlik k r reir~en Vernurtfr, Kiiniglich Preus-
forcing a new logical dimensiok which Spencer- sische Akallemie der Wissenschaften, Berlin, 1903.
Brown interprets as Time. 10. C. Baleson, Steps to or1 Ecolofy o j Mind, Ballantine,
Starting from precisely this point, Varella goes Ncw York, 1972.
through Russell's argument backwards, interpreting 11. G.Bateson, D. D. Jackson, J. Haley, and J. H. Weak-
land, "Toward a theory of schizophrenia," Behavior01
this bi-stability as indicating indication: self- Scietrre, 1, No. 4, 1956.
indication, self-reference, autonomy, which he 12. S. Brand, "Both sides of the necessary paradox (Con-
indicates by the stylized symbol of the snake eating verutions with Gregory Bateson)." I n : I1 Cyberrtetic
its own tail: Frorltiers, by S. Brand, Random House, New York,
1974, pp. 9-36.
13. H. B. Curry and R. Feys, Combinarory Logic, North
Holland, Amsterdam, p. 5.
The calculus now being developed from the 14. Ibid, p. 178.
calculus of indication augmented by the state of 15. G. Spencer-Brown, Lrr~nso j Form, First edition : George
self-indica:ion or otttono_my has not only logical Allen and Unwin. London, 1969. Second edition:
Julian Press, New York, 1972.
but also epistemological significance. In placing 16. 1. Kant, Grwrdlegutrg zur Metapllysik der Sirten.
the autonomy of the observer at the center of his Koniglich Preussische Akadernie dcr Wissenschaften,
philosophy, Kant's intention was not to effect a Berlin, 1903.

You might also like