You are on page 1of 6

Resolving ZenoÕs Paradoxes

For millennia, mathematicians and philosophers have tried


to refute Zeno’s paradoxes, a set of riddles suggesting that motion
is inherently impossible. At last, a solution has been found

by William I. McLaughlin

O
nce upon a time Achilles met a Both men were citizens of the Greek tance, no matter how small, always re-
tortoise in the road. The tor- colony of Elea in southern Italy. In ap- mains. It is important to note that he
toise, whose mind was quicker proximately 445 B.C., Parmenides and does not say that inÞnitely many stretch-
than his feet, challenged the swift hero Zeno met with Socrates in Athens to ex- es cannot add up to a Þnite distance
to a race. Amused, Achilles accepted. change ideas on basic philosophical (glancing at the geometry of an inÞ-
The tortoise asked if he might have a issues. The event, one of the greatest nitely partitioned line shows immedi-
head start, as he was truly much slow- recorded intellectual encounters (if it ately, without any sophisticated calcula-
er than the demigod. Achilles agreed really took place), is commemorated in tions, that an inÞnite number of pieces
happily, and so the tortoise started oÝ. PlatoÕs dialogue Parmenides. Parmen- sum to a Þnite interval). Rather the force
After taking quite a bit of time to fasten ides, a distinguished thinker nearly 65 of ZenoÕs objection to the idea of mo-
one of his sandalÕs ankle straps, Achil- years old, presented to the young Soc- tion comes from the obligation to ex-
les bolted from the starting line. In no rates a startling thesis: ÒrealityÓ is an plain how an inÞnite number of actsÑ
time at all, he ran half the distance that unchanging single entity, seamless in crossing one intervalÑcan be serially
separated him from the tortoise. With- its unity. The physical world, he argued, completed.
in another blink, he had covered three is monolithic. In particular, motion is Zeno made a second attack on the
quarters of the stretch. In another in- not possible. Although the rejection of conceptual underpinnings of motion
stant, he made up seven eighths and in plurality and change appears idiosyn- by viewing this Þrst argument from a
another, Þfteen sixteenths. But no mat- cratic, it has, in general outline, proved slightly diÝerent perspective. His sec-
ter how fast he ran, a fraction of the attractive to numerous scholars. For ex- ond paradox is as follows: Before an
distance remained. In fact, it appeared ample, the Òabsolute idealismÓ of the object, say, an arrow, gets to the half-
that the hero could never overtake the Oxford philosopher F. H. Bradley (1846Ð way mark of its supposed journey (an
plodding tortoise. 1924) has points in common with the achievement granted in the preceding
Had Achilles spent less time in the Parmenidean outlook. case), it must Þrst travel a quarter of
gym and more time studying philoso- This portrayal of the world is contrary the distance. As in ZenoÕs Þrst objec-
phy, he would have known that he was to our everyday experience and rele- tion, this reasoning can be continued
acting out the classic example used to il- gates our most fundamental percep- indeÞnitely to yield an inÞnite regress,
lustrate one of ZenoÕs paradoxes, which tions to the realm of illusion. Parmen- thus leading to his insistence that mo-
argue against the possibility of all mo- ides relied on ZenoÕs powerful argu- tion could never be initiated.
tion. Zeno designed the paradox of ments, which were later recorded in the ZenoÕs third paradox takes a diÝerent
Achilles and the tortoise, and its com- writings of Aristotle, to support his case. tack altogether. It asserts that the very
panion conundra (more about them lat- For two and a half millennia, ZenoÕs concept of motion is empty of content.
er), to support the philosophical theo- paradoxes have provoked debates and Zeno invites us to consider the arrow
ries of his teacher, Parmenides. stimulated analyses. At last, using a at any one instant of its ßight. At this
formulation of calculus that was devel- point in time, the arrow occupies a re-
oped in just the past decade or so, it is gion of space equal to its length, and no
possible to resolve ZenoÕs paradoxes. motion whatsoever is evident. Because
WILLIAM I. MCLAUGHLIN is a technical The resolution depends on the concept this observation is true at every instant,
manager for advanced space astro- of inÞnitesimals, known since ancient the arrow is never in motion. This ob-
physics at the Jet Propulsion Laboratory times but until recently viewed by many jection, in a historical sense, proved
in Pasadena, Calif., where he has worked thinkers with skepticism. the most troublesome for would-be
since 1971. He has participated in many
explainers of ZenoÕs paradoxes.
projects for the U.S. space program, in-

T
cluding the Apollo lunar-landing pro- he tale of Achilles and the tortoise Many philosophers and mathemati-
gram, the Viking mission to Mars, the In- depicts one of ZenoÕs paradoxes, cians have made various attempts to
frared Astronomical Satellite (IRAS ) and usually denoted ÒThe Dichoto- answer ZenoÕs objections. The most di-
the Voyager project, about which he wrote myÓ: any distance, such as that between rect approach has simply been to deny
an article for Scientific American in No- the two contenders, over which an ob- that a problem exists. For example, Jo-
vember 1986. He received a B.S. in elec- ject must traverse can be halved ( 1 Ú 2, hann Gottlieb Waldin, a German profes-
trical engineering in 1963 and a Ph.D. 1
Ú 4, 1 Ú 8 and so on) into an inÞnite num- sor of philosophy, wrote in 1782 that
in mathematics in 1968, both from the
ber of spatial segments, each represent- the Eleatic, in arguing against motion,
University of California, Berkeley. Mc-
Laughlin conducts, in addition, research ing some distance yet to be traveled. assumed that motion exists. Evidently
in epistemology. As a result, Zeno asserts that no motion the good professor was not acquainted
can be completed because some dis- with the form of argument known as

84 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc.


reductio ad absurdum: assume a state
of aÝairs and then show that it leads to
an illogical conclusion.
Nevertheless, other scholars made
progress by wrestling with how an in-
Þnite number of actions might occur in
the physical world. Their explanations
have continually been intertwined with
the idea of an inÞnitesimal, an interval
of space or time that embodies the
quintessence of smallness. An inÞni-
tesimal quantity, some surmised, would
be so very near zero as to be numeri-
cally impotent; such quantities would
elude all measurement, no matter how
precise, like sand through a sieve.
Giovanni Benedetti (1530Ð1590), a
predecessor of Galileo, postulated that
when an object appeared to be frozen
in midair to Zeno, he was in fact seeing
only part of the action, as though one
were watching a slide show instead of a
movie. Between the static images Zeno
saw were inÞnitesimally small instants
of time in which the object moved by
equally small distances.
Others sidestepped the issue by ar-
guing that intervals in the physical world
cannot simply be subdivided an inÞnite
number of times. Friedrich Adolf Tren-
delenburg (1802Ð1872) of the Universi-
ty of Berlin built an entire philosophical
system that explained human percep-
tions in terms of motion. In doing so,
he freed himself from explaining mo-
tion itself.
Similarly, in this century, the English
philosopher and mathematician Alfred
North Whitehead (1861Ð1947) con-
structed a system of metaphysics based
on change, in which motion was a spe-
cial case. Whitehead responded to
ZenoÕs objections by insisting that
events in the physical world had to
have some extent; namely, they could
not be pointlike. Likewise, the Scottish
philosopher David Hume (1711Ð1776)
wrote, ÒAll the ideas of quantity upon
which mathematicians reason, are noth-
ing but particular, and such as are sug-
gested by the senses and imagination

FALLING APPLE? Zeno would argue that


because the apple appears to be frozen
in midair at each instant of its sup-
posed descent, it is never in motion.
Moreover, Zeno would assert that there
is no proof that the apple will ever reach
the ground. Before it arrives there, it
must first fall half of the distance be-
tween the manÕs hand and the ground.
After that, it must fall half of the re-
maining distance and half of that again,
and so on. How can it be that some frac-
tional distance does not always remain
between the apple and the ground? Us-
ing similar logic, Zeno would question
whether an apple can even begin to fall.

Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc. SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 85


were intuitively drawn to these objects
because they seem to provide a micro-
scopic view of the details of motion.
Edward Nelson of Princeton University
created the tool we found most valu-
able in our attack, a brand of nonstan-
dard analysis known by the rather arid
name of internal set theory (IST). Nel-
sonÕs method produces startling inter-
pretations of seemingly familiar math-
ematical structures. The results are
similar, in their strangeness, to the
structures of quantum theory and gen-
eral relativity in physics. Because these
two theories have taken the better part
of a century to gain widespread accep-
tance, we can only admire the power of
NelsonÕs imagination.
Nelson adopted a novel means of
deÞning inÞnitesimals. Mathematicians
typically expand existing number sys-
tems by tacking on objects that have
desirable properties, much in the same
way that fractions were sprinkled be-
tween the integers. Indeed, the number
system employed in modern mathe-
matics, like a coral reef, grew by accre-
tion onto a supporting base: ÒGod made
RACE between Achilles and the tortoise illustrates one of ZenoÕs paradoxes. Achilles the integers, all the rest is the work of
gives the tortoise a head start. He must then make up half the distance between man,Ó declared Leopold Kronecker
them, then three fourths, then seven eighths and so on, ad inÞnitum. In this way, it (1823Ð1891). Instead the way of IST is
would seem he could never come abreast of the sluggish animal. to ÒstareÓ very hard at the existing num-
ber system and note that it already con-
tains numbers that, quite reasonably,
and consequently, cannot be inÞnitely tions. InÞnitesimals left their mark dur- can be considered inÞnitesimals.
divisible.Ó ing the 17th and 18th centuries as well Technically, Nelson Þnds nonstan-
Either way, the subject of inÞnitesi- in the development of diÝerential and dard numbers on the real line by add-
mals (and whether they exist or not ) integral calculus. Elementary textbooks ing three rules, or axioms, to the set of
generated a long and acrimonious liter- have long appealed to Òpractical inÞ- 10 or so statements supporting most
ature of its own. Until recently, most nitesimalsÓ to convey certain ideas in mathematical systems. (Zermelo-Fraen-
mathematicians thought them to be a calculus to students. kel set theory is one such foundation.)
chimera. The Irish bishop George Ber- When analysts thought about rigor- These additions introduce a new term,
keley (1685Ð1753) is noted principally ously justifying the existence of these standard, and help us to determine
for his idealistic theory, which denied small quantities, innumerable diÛcul- which of our old friends in the number
the reality of matter, but he, too, wres- ties arose. Eventually, mathematicians system are standard and which are non-
tled with inÞnitesimals. He believed of the 19th century invented a techni- standard. Not surprisingly, the inÞnites-
them ill conceived by the mathemati- cal substitute for inÞnitesimals: the so- imals fall in the nonstandard category,
cians of the time, including Newton. called theory of limits. So complete was along with some other numbers I will
ÒThey are neither Þnite quantities, nor its triumph that some mathematicians discuss later.
quantities inÞnitely small, nor yet noth- spoke of the ÒbanishmentÓ of inÞnites- Nelson deÞnes an inÞnitesimal as a
ing. May we not call them ghosts of de- imals from their discipline. By the number that lies between zero and ev-
parted quantities?Ó He observed fur- 1960s, though, the ghostly tread of in- ery positive standard number. At Þrst,
ther: ÒWhatever mathematicians may Þnitesimals in the corridors of mathe- this might not seem to convey any par-
think of ßuxions [rates of change], or matics became quite real once more, ticular notion of smallness, but the
the diÝerential calculus, and the like, a thanks to the work of the logician Abra- standard numbers include every con-
little reßexion will shew them that, in ham Robinson of Yale University [see crete number (and a few others) you
working by those methods, they do not ÒNonstandard Analysis,Ó by Martin Da- could write on a piece of paper or gen-
conceive or imagine lines or surfaces vis and Reuben Hersh; SCIENTIFIC AMER- erate in a computer: 10, pi, 1 Ú 1000 and
less than what are perceivable to sense.Ó ICAN, June 1972]. Since then, several so on. Hence, an inÞnitesimal is greater
Indeed, mathematicians found inÞn- methods in addition to RobinsonÕs ap- than zero but less than any number,
itesimals hard to skirt in the course of proach have been devised that make however small, you could ever conceive
their discoveries, no matter how dis- use of inÞnitesimals. of writing. It is not immediately appar-
tasteful they found them in theory. ent that such inÞnitesimals do indeed

W
Some historians believe the great Archi- hen my colleague Sylvia Miller exist, but the conceptual validity of IST
medes (circa 287Ð212 B.C.) achieved and I started our work on has been demonstrated to a degree
some of his mathematical results using ZenoÕs paradoxes, we had the commensurate with our justiÞed belief
inÞnitesimals but employed more con- advantage that inÞnitesimals had be- in other mathematical systems.
ventional modes for public presenta- come mathematically respectable. We Still, inÞnitesimals are truly elusive

86 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc.


entities. Their elusiveness rests on the er? Or could motion comprise a series small, its inverse will be very large (in
mathematical fact that two concrete of intermediate steps or else a process the standard realm, the inverse of one
numbersÑthose having numerical con- outside of time and space altogether? millionth is one million). This type of
tentÑcannot differ by an inÞnitesimal The possibilities are inÞnite, and none nonstandard number is called an un-
amount. The proof, by reductio ad ab- can be veriÞed or ruled out since an in- limited number. The unlimited num-
surdum, is easy: the arithmetic diÝer- Þnitesimal interval can never be moni- bers, though large, are Þnite and hence
ence between two concrete numbers tored. Credit for this rebuttal is due to smaller than the truly inÞnite numbers
must be concrete (and hence, standard). Benedetti, Trendelenburg and White- created in mathematics. These unlimit-
If this diÝerence were inÞnitesimal, the head for their earlier insights, which can ed numbers live in a kind of twilight
deÞnition of an inÞnitesimal as less now be formalized by means of IST. zone between the familiar standard
than all standard numbers would be vi- We can answer ZenoÕs Þrst two objec- numbers, which are Þnite, and the in-
olated. The consequence of this fact is tions more easily than we did the third, Þnite ones.
that both end points of an inÞnitesimal but we need to use another mathemati- If, as demonstrated in IST, every in-
interval cannot be labeled using con- cal fact from IST. Every inÞnite set of Þnite set contains a nonstandard num-
crete numbers. Therefore, an inÞnitesi- numbers contains a nonstandard num- ber, then the inÞnite series of check-
mal interval can never be captured ber. Before drawing out the Zenonian points Zeno used to gauge motion in his
through measurement; inÞnitesimals implications of this statement, it is nec- Þrst argument must contain a mixed,
remain forever beyond the range of essary to talk about the two other types nonstandard number. In fact, as ZenoÕs
observation. of nonstandard numbers that are read- inÞnite series of numbers creeps closer
ily manufactured from inÞnitesimal to one, a member of that series will

S
o how can these phantom num- numbers. First, take all the inÞnitesi- eventually be within an inÞnitesimal dis-
bers be used to refute ZenoÕs para- mals, which by deÞnition are wedged tance from one. At that point, all suc-
doxes? From the above discus- between zero and all the positive, stan- ceeding members of the series will be
sion it is clear that the points of space dard numbers, and put a minus sign nonstandard members of the cluster
or time marked with concrete numbers in front of each one. Now there is a about one, and neither Zeno nor anyone
are but isolated points. A trajectory and symmetrical clustering of these small else will be able to chart the progress
its associated time interval are in fact objects about zero. To create ÒmixedÓ of a moving object in this inaccessible
densely packed with inÞnitesimal re- nonstandard numbers, take any stan- region.
gions. As a result, we can grant ZenoÕs dard number, say, one half, and add to

T
third objection: the arrowÕs tip is caught it each of the nonstandard inÞnitesi- here is an element of irony in us-
ÒstroboscopicallyÓ at rest at concretely mals in the grouping around zero. This ing inÞnity, ZenoÕs putative weap-
labeled points of time, but along the act of addition translates the original on, to deßate his claims. To re-
vast majority of the stretch, some kind cluster of inÞnitesimals to positions on fute ZenoÕs Þrst paradox, we need only
of motion is taking place. This motion either side of one half. Similarly, every state the epistemological principle that
is immune from Zenonian criticism be- standard number can be viewed as hav- we are not responsible for explaining
cause it is postulated to occur inside ing its own collection of nearby, non- situations we cannot observe. ZenoÕs
inÞnitesimal segments. Their ineÝabili- standard numbers, each one only an inÞnite series of checkpoints contains
ty provides a kind of screen or Þlter. inÞnitesimal distance from the stan- nonstandard numbers, which have no
Might the process of motion inside dard number. numerical meaning, and so we reject
one of these intervals be a uniform ad- The third type of nonstandard num- his argument based on these entities.
vance across the interval or an instan- ber is simply the inverse of an inÞnites- Because no one could ever, even in prin-
taneous jump from one end to the oth- imal. Because an inÞnitesimal is very ciple, observe the full domain of check-

Topology of the Real Line

–(N + 1) – N –3 –2 –1 0 1 2 N N+1
5

T he real numbers consist of the integers ( positive and


negative whole numbers), rational numbers (those
that can be expressed as a fraction) and irrational num-
yet are greater than zero. Mixed nonstandard numbers,
shown grouped around the integer 5, result from adding
and subtracting infinitesimal amounts to standard num-
bers (those that cannot be expressed as a fraction). The bers. In fact, every standard number is surrounded by
real numbers can be represented as points on a straight such mixed, nonstandard neighbors. Unlimited nonstan-
line known as the real line (above). dard numbers, represented as N and N + 1, are the invers-
The mathematician Edward Nelson of Princeton Univer- es of infinitesimal nonstandard numbers. Each unlimited
sity labeled three types of numbers as nonstandard with- number is greater than every standard number and yet
in this standard number system. Infinitesimal nonstandard less than the infinite real numbers. The nonstandard real
numbers are smaller than any positive standard number numbers prove useful in resolving Zeno’s paradoxes.

Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc. SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 87


points that his objection addresses, the number of standard numbers would venience, consider only those members
objectionable behavior he postulates for seem to be true, but surprisingly, it is of F that fall between 0 and 1. Let time
the moving object is moot. Many de- not. In developing IST, Nelson needed 0 be the instant when we start tracking
scriptions of motion in the microrealm to Þnesse the conventional way mathe- a moving object. The second instant
other than that containing the full se- maticians form objects. A statement in when we might try to observe the ob-
ries of checkpoints could apply, and IST is called internal if it does not con- ject is at time f1, where f1 is the small-
just because his particular scenario tain the label Òstandard.Ó Otherwise, the est member of F that is greater than 0.
causes conceptual problems, there is statement is called external. Mathema- Ascending through F in this fashion,
no reason to anathematize the idea of ticians frequently create subsets from we eventually reach time fn , where fn is
motion. His second argument, attempt- larger sets by predicating a quality that the largest member of F less than 1. In
ing to show that an object can never characterizes each of the objects in the one more step, we reach 1 itself, the
even start to move, suÝers from the subsetÑthe balls that are red or the in- destination in this example. In order to
same malady as the Þrst, and we reject tegers that are even. In IST, however, it walk through a noninÞnitesimal dis-
it on like grounds. is forbidden to use external predicates, tance, such as the span from 0 to 1 us-
such as standard, to deÞne subsets; the ing inÞnitesimal steps, the subscript

W
e have resolved ZenoÕs three stricture is introduced to avoid contra- n of fn must be an unlimited integer.
paradoxes using some techni- dictions. For example, imagine the set The process of motion then is divided
cal results from IST and the of all standard numbers in F. This set into n + 1 acts, and because n + 1 is
principle that nonstandard numbers would be Þnite because it is a subset of also Þnite, this number of acts can be
are not suitable for describing matters a Þnite set. It would therefore have a completed sequentially.
of fact, observed or purported. Still, least member, say, r. But then r Ð 1 Of the possible observing times iden-
more can be said regarding the matter would be a standard number less than tiÞed earlier, the objectÕs progress could
than just the assurance that ZenoÕs ob- r, when r was supposed to be the small- be reported solely at those instants
jections do not preclude motion. In- est standard number. Thus, we cannot corresponding to certain standard num-
deed, we can construct a theory of mo- say the standard numbers are Þnite or bers in F. (By the way, f1 and fn would
tion using a very powerful result from inÞnite in extent, because we cannot be nonstandard, as they are inÞnitesi-
IST. The theory yields the same results form the set of them and count them. mally close to 0 and 1, respectively.) For
as do the tools of the calculus, and yet Nevertheless, the Þnite set F, though example, although we can express a
it is easier to visualize and does not fall constrained as to how it can be visual- standard number to any Þnite (but not
prey to ZenoÕs objections. ized, is useful for constructing our the- unlimited) number of decimal places
A theorem proved in IST states that ory of motion. This theory can be ex- and use this approximation as a mea-
there exists a Þnite set, call it F, that pressed quite simply as stepping surement label, we cannot access the
contains all the standard numbers! The through F, where each member of F unlimited tail of the expansion to alter
corollary that there are only a Þnite represents a distinct moment. For con- a digit and thus deÞne a nonstandard,

Calculus by Means of Infinitesimals

T o see the relation between


infinitesimals and differen-
tial calculus, consider the sim- 50
0 is the desired average velocity,
32 + 16dt.
Because 16dt is but an infi-
ple case of a falling stone. The nitesimal amount, undetectable
distance the stone has traveled 100 for all intents and purposes, it
in feet can be calculated from can be considered equal to 0.
FEET

the formula s = 16t 2, where t 150 Thus, after one second of travel,
equals the time elapsed in sec- the formula yields the stone’s
onds. For example, if a stone 200 instantaneous velocity as 32
has fallen for two seconds, it feet per second.
250
will have traveled 64 feet. This manipulation, of course,
Suppose, however, one wish- resembles those used in tra-
300
es to calculate the instantane- 0 1 2 3 4 ditional, differential calculus.
ous velocity of the stone. The SECONDS There the small residue 16dt
average speed of a moving ob- cannot be dropped at the end
ject equals the total distance it travels divided by the total of the calculation; it is a noninfinitesimal quantity. Instead,
amount of time it takes. By using this formula over an in- in this calculus, it must be argued away using the theory
finitesimal change in the total distance and time, one can of limits. In essence, the limit process renders the interval
calculate a fair approximation of an object’s instantaneous of length dt sufficiently small so that the average velocity
velocity. is arbitrarily close to 32. As before, the instantaneous ve-
Let dt represent an infinitesimal change in time and ds locity of the stone after one second of travel equals 32
an infinitesimal change in distance. The computation for feet per second. Similarly, judicious use of infinitesimal re-
the velocity of the stone after one second of travel, then, gions facilitates the computation of the area of complicat-
will be as follows: The time frame under consideration ed regions, a basic problem of integral calculus. Some
ranges from t = 1 to t = 1 + dt. The position of the stone think the newer calculus is pedagogically superior to cal-
during that time changes from s = 16(1) 2 to s = 16(1 + dt )2. culus without infinitesimals. Nevertheless, both methods
The total change in distance, 32dt + 16dt 2, divided by dt, are equally rigorous and yield identical results.

88 SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc.


THE MEASURERS, a 17th-century Dutch painting attributed cise measurements become, however, infinitesimal amounts
to Hendrik van Balen, illustrates the words of the Roman poet will forever escape our grasp, since any useful unit of mea-
Horace: ÒThere is measure in all things.Ó No matter how pre- sure must correspond to some standard number.

inÞnitesimally close neighbor. Only con- solution to an ancient puzzle? Possibly, the sky is dark at night despite stars in
crete standard numbers are eÝective as but there are several directions in which every direction, or James Clerk Maxwell,
measurement labels; the utility of their it might prove extensible. summoning a meddling, microscopic
nonstandard neighbors for measure- Aside from its mathematical value, demon to batter the second law of ther-
ment is illusory. IST is ripe with epistemological import, modynamics. Likewise, ZenoÕs argu-
as this analysis has shown. It might ments have stimulated examinations of

M
uch is superßuous in this theo- well be modiÞed to constitute a general our ideas about motion, time and space..
ry of motion, and much is left epistemic logic. Also, inÞnitesimal in- The path to their resolution has been
unsaid. It suÛces, however, in tervals, or their generalization, would eventful.
the sense that it can easily be translat- promise a technical resource to house
ed into the symbolic notation of the in- WhiteheadÕs so-called actual entities,
tegral or diÝerential calculus, common- the generative atoms of his philosophi-
FURTHER READING
ly used to describe the details of motion cal system. Finally, the current theory
[see box on opposite page]. More impor- of motion and the predictions of quan- A HISTORY OF GREEK PHILOSOPHY, Vol.
tant in the present context, the Þnite- tum physics are not dissimilar in that 2: THE PRESOCRATIC TRADITION FROM
PARMENIDES TO DEMOCRITUS. W. K.
ness of the set F enables us to jump they both restrict the observation of cer-
Guthrie. Cambridge University Press,
over the pitfalls in ZenoÕs Þrst two para- tain events to discrete values. Of course, 1965.
doxes. His third objection is dodged as this theory of motion is not a version ZENO OF ELEA. Gregory Vlastos in The
before: motion in real time is an un- of quantum mechanics (nor relativity Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Edited by
known process that takes place in in- theory, for that matter). Because the Paul Edwards. Macmillan Publishing
Þnitesimal intervals between the stan- theory resulted from a thought experi- Company, 1967.
dard points of F; the nonstandard points ment on ZenoÕs terms, it holds no di- NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS. Martin Davis
and Reuben Hersh in ScientiÞc Ameri-
of F are irrelevant given that they can- rect connection to present physical the-
can, Vol. 226, No. 6, pages 78Ð86; June
not be observed. ory. Moreover, the speciÞc rules inher- 1972.
For many centuries, ZenoÕs logic stood ited from IST are probably not those INTERNAL SET THEORY: A NEW APPROACH
mostly intact, proving the refractory na- best suited to describe reality. Modern TO NONSTANDARD ANALYSIS. Edward
ture of his arguments. A resolution was physics might adapt the IST approach Nelson in Bulletin of the American Math-
made possible through two basic fea- by modifying its rule system and intro- ematical Society, Vol. 83, No. 6, pages
tures of IST: Þrst, the ability to partition ducing Òphysical constants,Ó perhaps 1165Ð1198; November 1977.
an interval of time or space into a Þnite by assigning parameters to the set F. AN EPISTEMOLOGICAL USE OF NONSTAN-
DARD ANALYSIS TO ANSWER ZENOÕS OB-
number of ineÝable inÞnitesimals and, But maybe not. Still, the simplicity
JECTIONS AGAINST MOTION. William I.
second, the fact that standardly labeled and elegance of such thought experi- McLaughlin and Sylvia L. Miller in Syn-
pointsÑthe only ones that can be used ments have catalyzed research through- these, Vol. 92, No. 3, pages 371Ð384;
for measurementÑare isolated objects out the ages. Notable examples include September 1992.
on the real line. Is our work merely the Heinrich W. M. Olbers, questioning why

Copyright 1994 Scientific American, Inc. SCIENTIFIC AMERICAN November 1994 89

You might also like