You are on page 1of 31

American Economic Association

The Equity Premium: It's Still a Puzzle


Author(s): Narayana R. Kocherlakota
Source: Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. 34, No. 1 (Mar., 1996), pp. 42-71
Published by: American Economic Association
Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2729409 .
Accessed: 25/02/2011 13:11

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at .
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at .
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=aea. .

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact support@jstor.org.

American Economic Association is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal
of Economic Literature.

http://www.jstor.org
Journal of Economic Literature,
Vol. XXXIV (March 1996), pp. 42-71

The Equity Premium: It's Still a Puzzle

NARAYANAR. KOCHERLAKOTA
Federal Reserve Bank of Minneapolis
I thank Rao Aiyagari, John Campbell, Dean Corbae, John Heaton, Mark Huggett, Beth In-
gram, John Kennan, Deborah Lucas, Barbara McCutcheon,Rajnish Mehra, Gene Savin, Steve
Williamson, Kei-Mu Yi, and the refereesfor their input in preparing this manuscript. I thank
Edward R. Allen III, Ravi Jagannathan, and Deborah Lucas for our many interesting and
enlightening conversations on the subject of asset pricing over the years. Finally, I thank Lars
Hansen for teaching me how to think about the issues addressed in this paper. None of the
preceding should be viewed as responsiblefor the opinions and errors contained within. The
views expressed herein are those of the authors and not necessarily those of the Federal
Reserve Bank of Minneapolisor the Federal Reserve System.

I. Introduction ferences in the degree to which a secu-


rity's return covaries with the typical in-
OVER THE LAST one hundred years, vestor's consumption. If this covariance
the average real return to stocks in is high, selling off the security would
the United States has been about six per- greatly reduce the variance of the typical
cent per year higher than that on Trea- investor's consumption stream; in equi-
sury bills. At the same time, the average librium, the investor must be deterred
real return on Treasury bills has been from reducing his risk in this fashion by
about one percent per year. In this pa- the security'spaying a high averagereturn.
per, I discuss and assess various theore- There is a crucial problem in making
tical attempts to explain these two differ- this qualitative explanation of cross-sec-
ent empirical phenomena: the large tional differences in asset returns opera-
"equity premium" and the low "risk free tional: what exactly is "the typical inves-
rate." I show that while there are several tor's consumption"? The famous Capital
plausible explanations for the low level Asset Pricing Model represents one an-
of Treasury returns, the large equity pre- swer to this question: it assumes that the
mium is still largely a mystery to econo- typical investor's consumption stream is
mists. perfectly correlated with the return to
In order to understand why the sample the stock market. This allows financial
means of the equity premium and the analysts to measure the risk of a financial
risk free rate represent "puzzles," it is security by its covariance with the return
useful to review the basics of modern as- to the stock market (that is, a scaled ver-
set pricing theory. It is well known that sion of its "beta"). More recently,
the real returns paid by different Douglas Breeden (1979) and Robert Lu-
financial securities may differ consider- cas (1978) described so-called "repre-
ably, even when averaged over long sentative" agent models of asset returns
periods of time. Financial economists in which per capita consumption is per-
typically explain these differences in av- fectly correlated with the consumption
erage returns by attributing them to dif- stream of the typical investor. (See also
42
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 43

Mark Rubinstein 1976; and Breeden and large equity premium implies that inves-
Robert Litzenberger 1978.) In this type tors are highly risk averse, the standard
of model, a security's risk can be mea- models of preferences would in turn im-
sured using the covariance of its return ply that they do not like growth very
with per capita consumption. much. Yet, although Treasury bills offer
The representative agent model of as- only a low rate of return, individuals de-
set pricing is not as widely used as the fer consumption (that is, save) at a suffi-
CAPM in "real world" applications (such ciently fast rate to generate average per
as project evaluation by firms). However, capita consumption growth of around
from an academic economist's perspec- two percent per year. This is what Weil
tive, the "representative agent" model of (1989) calls the risk free rate puzzle: al-
asset pricing is more important than the though individuals like consumption to
CAPM. Representative agent models be very smooth, and although the risk
that imbed the Lucas-Breeden paradigm free rate is very low, they still save
for explaining asset return differentials enough that per capita consumption
are an integral part of modern macro- grows rapidly.
economics and international economics. There is now a vast literature that
Thus, any empirical defects fn the repre- seeks to resolve these two puzzles. I be-
sentative agent model of asset returns gin my review of this literature by show-
represent holes in our understanding of ing that the puzzles are very robust: they
these important subfields. are implied by only three assumptions
In their seminal (1985) paper, Rajnish about individual behavior and asset mar-
Mehra and Edward Prescott describe a ket structure. First, individuals have
particular empirical problem for the rep- preferences associated with the "stan-
resentative agent paradigm. As men- dard" utility function used in macro-
tioned above, over the last century, the economics: they maximize the expected
average annual real return to stocks has discounted value of a stream of utilities
been about seven percent per year, while generated by a power utility function.
the average annual real return to Trea- Second, asset markets are complete: indi-
sury bills has been only about one per- viduals can write insurance contracts
cent per year. Mehra and Prescott (1985) against any possible contingency. Finally,
show that the difference in the covari- asset trading is costless, so that taxes and
ances of these returns with consumption brokerage fees are assumed to be insig-
growth is only large enough to explain nificant. Any model that is to resolve the
the difference in the average returns if two puzzles must abandon at least one of
the typical investor is implausibly averse these three assumptions.
to risk. This is the equity premium puz- My survey shows that relaxing the
zle: in a quantitative sense, stocks are three assumptions has led to plausible
not sufficiently riskier than Treasurybills explanations for the low value of the risk
to explain the spread in their returns. free rate. Several alternative preference
Philippe Weil (1989) shows that the orderings are consistent with it; also, the
same data presents a second anomaly. existence of borrowing constraints push
According to standard models of individ- interest rates down in equilibrium. How-
ual preferences, when individuals want ever, the literature provides only two ra-
consumption to be smooth over states tionalizations for the large equity pre-
(they dislike risk), they also desire mium: either investors are highly averse
smoothness of consumption over time to consumption risk or they find trading
(they dislike growth). Given that the stocks to be much more costly than trad-
44 [ournal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)
ing bonds. Little auxiliaryevidence exists stock returns. As Andrew Atkeson and
to support either of these explanations, Christopher Phelan (1994) point out,
and so (I would say) the equity premium without this knowledge we cannot hope
puzzle is still unresolved. to give a meaningful answer to R. Lucas'
The Lucas-Breeden representative (1987) question about how costly in-
agent model is apparently inconsistent dividuals find business cycle fluctua-
with the data in many other respects. tions in consumption growth. Thus,
Sanford Grossman and Robert Shiller the two puzzles are signs of large gaps
(1981) (and many others) argue that as- in our understanding of the macroecon-
set prices vary too much to be explained omy.
by the variation in dividends or in per Given the lack of a compelling expla-
capita consumption. Hansen and Ken- nation for the large equity premium, the
neth Singleton (1982, 1983) point out article will at times read like a litany of
that in forming her portfolio, the repre- failure. I should say from the outset that
sentative investor appears to be ignoring this is misleading in many ways. We have
useful information available in lagged learned much from the equity premium
consumption growth and asset returns. puzzle literature about the properties of
Robert Hall (1988) argues that consump- asset pricing models, about methods of
tion does not respond sufficiently to estimating and testing asset pricing mod-
changes in expected returns. John Coch- els, and about methods of solving for the
rane and Hansen (1992) uncover several implications of asset pricing models. I
anomalies, including the so-called De- believe that all of these contributions are
fault-Premium and Term Structure Puz- significant.
zles. For better or for worse, though, this
This paper will look at none of these article is not about these innovations. In-
other puzzles. Instead, it focuses exclu- stead, I focus on what might be called
sively on the risk free rate and equity the bottom line of the work, "Do we
premium puzzles. There are two ratio- know why the equity premium is so
nalizations for limiting the discussion in high? Do we know why the risk free rate
this way. The first is simple: my conver- is so low?" It is in answering the first of
sations with other economists have con- these questions that the literature falls
vinced me that these puzzles are the short.
most widely known and best under- The rest of the paper is structured as
stood of the variety of evidence usually follows. The next section describes the
arrayed against the representative agent two puzzles and lays out the fundamental
models. modelling assumptions that generate
The second rationalization is perhaps them. Section III explores the potential
more controversial: I claim that these for explaining the two puzzles by chang-
two puzzles have more importance for ing the preferences of the representative
macroeconomists. The risk free rate agent. Section IV looks at the implica-
puzzle indicates that we do not know tions of market frictions for asset re-
why people save even when returns are turns. Section V concludes.'
low: thus, our models of aggregate sav-
ings behavior are omitting some crucial
element. The equity premium puzzle 1 In writing this paper, I have benefited greatly

demonstrates that we do not know from reading four other review articles by Andrew
Abel (1991), Aiyagari (1993), Cochrane and Han-
why individuals are so averse to the sen (1992), and Heaton and D. Lucas (1995b). I
highly procyclical risk associated with recommend all of them highly.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 45
0.14 ,

0.10

0.06

0
0.02

-0.02

-0.06

-0.10 I I
1880 1900 1920 1940 1960 1980
time
Figure 1. Annual Real Per Capita Consumption Growth

II. What Are the Puzzles? Plots of the data are depicted in Figures
1-3; all of the series appear station-
1. Aspects of the Data
ary and ergodic (their statistical proper-
The equity premium and risk free ties do not appear to be changing over
rate puzzles concern the co-movements time).
of three variables: the real return to Table 1 contains some summary statis-
the S & P 500, the real return to short tics for the three variables. There are
term nominally risk free bonds,2 and three features of the table that give rise
the growth rate of per capita real con- to the equity premium and risk free rate
sumption (more precisely, nondurables puzzles. First, the average real rate of re-
and services). In this paper, I use the turn on stocks is equal to seven percent
annual United States data from 1889-
1978 originally studied by Mehra and
Prescott (1985) (see the Appendix for does not eliminate the puzzles. Hansen and Sin-
details on the construction of the data).3 gleton (1983) and Aiyagari (1993) find that similar
phenomena characterize post-World War II
monthly data in the Unites States. Amlan Roy
(1994) documents the existence of the two puzzles
2 Ninety day Treasury bills from 1931-1978, in post-World War II quarterly data in Germany
Treasury certificates from 1920-31, and 60-day to andJapan. It may not be too strong to say that the
90-day Commercial Paper prior to 1920. equity premium and risk free rate puzzles appear
3 In what follows, I use only the Mehra-Prescott to be a general feature of organized asset markets.
data set. However, it is important to realize that (Jeremy Siegel, 1992, points out that the equity
the puzzles are not peculiar to these data. For ex- premium was much lower in the 19th century.
ample, Kocherlakota (1994) shows that adding ten However, consumption data is not available for
more years of data to the Mehra-Prescott series this period.)-
46 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)
0.6 I Il

0.4

0.2 -

0
-0.0

-0.20

-0.4 I
1880 1900 1920 1940 1960 1980
time
Figure 2. AnnualReal Returnto S & P 500

0.25

0.20

0.15

0.10

-0.10

-0.20I I
1880 1900 1920 1940 1960 1980
time
Figure 3. AnnualReal Returnto NominallyRisk Free Short Termn
Debt
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 47

TABLE1
2. The Original Statement of the Puzzles
SUMMARYSTATISTICS
UNITED STATESANNUAL DATA, 1889-1978
In their 1985 paper, Mehra and
Prescott construct a simple model that
SampleMeans makes well-defined quantitative predic-
Rst 0.070 tions for the expected values of the real
Rbt 0.010 returns to the S & P 500 and the three
Ct/Ct-i 0.018 month Treasury bill rate. There are
SampleVariance-Covariance three critical assumptions underlying
Ct/Ct l
Rst Rbt their model. The first is that in period
Rst 0.0274 0.00104 0.00219
0.00104 0.00308 -0.000193 t, all individuals have identical prefer-
Rlt
CVCt-1 0.00219 -0.000193 0.00127 ences over future random consumption
streams represented by the utility func-
In this table, Ct/Ct-iis real per capita consumption tion:
growth,Rt is the real returnto stocksandRbis the real
returnto Treasurybills. Et Es=OPS(Ct+S)10a/(l-a), a 2 ? (1)

where {ct})1 is a random consumption


stream. In this expression, and through-
per year while the average real rate of out the remainder of the paper, Et repre-
return on bonds is equal to one percent sents an expectation conditional on infor-
per year. Second, by long-term historical mation available to the individual in
standards, per capita consumption period t. Thus, individuals seek to maxi-
growth is high: around 1.8 percent per mize the expectation of a discounted
year. Finally, the covariance of per cap- flow of utility over time.
ita consumption growth with stock re- In the formula (1), the parameter f is
turns is only slightly bigger than the co- a discount factor that households apply
variance of per capita consumption to the utility derived from future con-
growth with bond returns. sumption; increasing f leads investors to
In some sense, there is a simple expla- save more. In contrast, increasing oc has
nation for the higher average return of two seemingly distinct implications for
stocks: stock returns covary more with individual attitudes toward consumption
consumption growth than do Treasury profiles. When ox is large, individuals
bills. Investors see stocks as 'a poorer want consumption in different states to
hedge against consumption risk, and so be highly similar: they dislike risk. But
stocks must earn a higher average return. individuals also want consumption in dif-
Similarly, while individuals must have ferent dates to be similar: they dislike
saved a lot to generate the high con- growth in their consumption profiles.
sumption growth described in Table 1, The second key assumption of the
there is an explanation of why they did Mehra-Prescott model is that people can
so: as long as individuals discount the trade stocks and bonds in a frictionless
future at a rate lower than one percent market. What this means is that an indi-
per year, we should expect their con- vidual can costlessly (that is, without sig-
sumptions to grow. The data does not nificant taxes or brokerage fees) buy and
contradict the qualitative predictions of sell any amount of the two financial as-
economic theory; rather, as we shall see, sets. In equilibrium, an individual must
it is inconsistent with the quantitative not be able to gain utility at the margin
implications of a particular economic by selling bonds and then investing the
model. proceeds in stocks; the individual should
48 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

not be able to gain utility by buying or representative individual (with coeffi-


selling bonds. Hence, given the costless- cient of relative risk aversion no larger
ness of performing these transactions, an than the most risk averse individual and
individual's consumption profile must no smaller than the least risk averse indi-
satisfy the following two first order con- vidual) which satisfies the first order
ditions: conditions (2a) and (2b). The key is that
asset markets must be complete: indi-
=
I- R1b1)} 0.
Et (ct+llct)-a(Rts+ (2a) viduals in the United States must have a
(b sufficiently large set of assets available
1}== 1.
,BEt{(ct+llct)?CRtb 1. (2b)
for trade that they can diversify any idio-
In these conditions, RIsis the gross return syncratic risk in consumption. When
to stocks fromperiod (t - 1) to period t, markets are complete, we can construct
while Rb is the gross return to bonds a "representative" agent because after
fromperiod (t - 1) to periodt. trading in complete markets, individuals
These first order conditions impose become marginally homogeneous even
statistical restrictions on the comove- though they are initially heterogeneous.
ment between any person's pattern of We can summarize this discussion as
consumption and asset returns. The third follows: Mehra and Prescott assume that
critical feature of Mehra and Prescott's asset markets are frictionless, that asset
analysis, though, is that they assume the markets are complete, and that the resul-
existence of a "representative"agent. Ac- tant representative individual has prefer-
cording to this assumption, the above ences of the form given by (1). However,
conditions (2a) and (2b) are satisfied not Mehra and Prescott also make three
just for each individual's consumption, other, more technical, assumptions.
but also for per capita consumption. First, they assume that per capita con-
There is some confusion about what sumption growth follows a two state
kinds of assumptions underlie this substi- Markov chain constructed in such a way
tution of per capita for individual con- that the population mean, variance, and
sumption. It is clear that if all individuals autocorrelation of consumption growth
are identical in preferences and their are equivalent to their corresponding
ownership of production opportunities, sample means in United States data.
then in equilibrium, all individuals will They also assume that in period t, the
in fact consume the same amount; thus, only variables that individuals know are
under these conditions, substituting per the realizations of current and past con-
capita consumption into conditions (2a) sumption growth. Finally, they assume
and (2b) is justified. Many economists that the growth rate of the total divi-
distrust representative agent models be- dends paid by the stocks included in the
cause they believe this degree of homo- S & P 500 is perfectly correlated with
geneity is unrealistic. the growth rate of per capita consump-
However, while this degree of homo- tion, and that the real return to the
geneity among individuals is sufficient to (nominally risk free) Treasury bill is per-
guarantee the existence of a repre- fectly correlated with the return to a
sentative agent, it is by no means neces- bond that is risk free in real terms.
sary. In particular, George Constan- These statistical assumptions allow
tinides (1982) shows that even if Mehra and Prescott to use the first order
individuals are heterogeneous in prefer- conditions (2a) and (2b) to obtain an
ences and levels of wealth, it may be pos- analytical formula that expresses the
sible to find some utility function for the population mean of the real return to the
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 49

S & P 500 and the population mean real PE{(Ct+j1Ct)-aRtb 1= 1. (2b)


return to the three month Treasury bill
in terms of the two preference parame- (The variable Ct stands for per capita
ters , and a. Using evidence from mi- consumption.) We can estimate the ex-
croeconometric data and introspection, pectations or population means on the
they restrict f3 to lie between 0 and 1, left hand side of (2a') and (2b') using the
and oc to lie between 0 and 10. Their
main finding is that for any value of the sample means of:
preference parameters such that the ex- est+1= I(Ct+j1Ct)-a(Rst+j - Rtb 1)1
pected real return to the Treasury bill is
less than four percent, the difference in etb+ = P {(Ct+j/Ct)-cRb+ }1
the two expected real returns (the "eq- given a sufficiently long time series of
uity premium") is less than 0.35 percent. data on Ct?i and the asset returns.4
This stands in contrast to the facts de- Table 2 reports the sample mean of est
scribed earlier that the average real re- for various values of oc;for all values of oc
turn to Treasury bills in the United less than or equal to 8.5, the sample
States data is one percent while the aver- mean of es is significantly positive. We
age real return to stocks is nearly six per- can conclude that the population mean
cent higher. of es is in fact positive for any value of ox
Mehra and Prescott conclude from less than or equal to 8.5; hence, for any
their analysis that their model of asset such o, the representative agent can gain
returns is inconsistent with United States at the margin by borrowing at the Treas-
data on consumption and asset returns. ury bill rate and investing in stocks.5 This
Because the model was constructed by
4 Throughout this paper, I will be evaluating
making several different assumptions,
various representative agent models by using ver-
presumably the fit of the model to the sions of (2a') and (2b') as opposed to (2a) and
data could be improved by changing any (2b). While (2a,b) certainly imply (2a',b'), there
of them. In the next section, I restate are a host of other implications of (2a,b): the law
of iterated expectations "averages"over all of the
the equity premium puzzle to show implications of (2a) and (2b) to arrive at (2a') and
why the three final assumptions about (2b'). Focusing on (2a) and (2b) is in keeping with
the statistical behavior of consumption my announced goal in the introduction of just
looking at the equity premium and risk free rate
and asset returns are relatively unimpor- puzzles.
tant. Hansen and Jagannathan (1991) and Cochrane
and Hansen (1992) reinterpret the equity pre-
3. A More Robust Restatement of the mium puzzle and the risk free rate puzzles using
the variance bounds derived in the former paper.
Puzzles Note that, as Cochrane and Hansen (1992) empha-
size, the variance bound is an even weaker impli-
As we saw above, the crux of the cation of (2a) than (2a') is (in the sense that (2a')
Mehra-Prescott model is that the first implies the variance bound while the converse is
order conditions (2a) and (2b) must be not true).
5 Breeden, Michael Gibbons, and Litzenberger
satisfied with per capita consumption (1989) and Grossman, Angelo Melino, and Shiller
growth substituted in for individual con- (1987) point out that the first order conditions
sumption growth. Using the Law of Iter- (2a) and (2b) are based on the assumption that all
consumFtion within a given year is perfectly sub-
ated Expectations, we can replace the stitutab e; if this assumption is false, there is the
conditional expectation in (2a) and (2b) possibility of time aggregation bias. However,
with an unconditional expectation so Hansen, Heaton, and Amir Yaron (1994) show that
as long as the geometric average of consumption
that: growth rates is a good approximationto the arith-
metic average of consumption growth rates, the
E{(Ct+jCt)-?(Rts - Rb = (2a') presence of time aggregation should only affect
50 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

TABLE 2
the investor's degree of risk aversion
THE EQUITY PREMIUM PUZZLE rises.6
Table 3 reports the sample mean of eb
a t-stat for various values of oc and , = 0.99. It
0.0 0.0594 3.345 shows that for , equal to 0.99 and oc
0.5 0.0577 3.260 greater than one, the representative
1.0 0.0560 3.173 household can gain at the margin by
1.5 0.0544 3.082 transferring consumption from the fu-
2.0 0.0528 2.987
2.5 0.0512 2.890
ture to the present (that is, reducing its
3.0 0.0496 2.790 savings rate). This is the risk free rate
3.5 0.0480 2.688 puzzle. High values of oximply that indi-
4.0 0.0464 2.584 viduals view consumption in different
4.5 0.0449 2.478 periods as complementary. Such indi-
5.0 0.0433 2.370
5.5 0.0418 2.262
viduals find an upwardly sloped con-
6.0 0.0403 2.153 sumption profile less desirable because
6.5 0.0390 2.044 consumption is not the same in every pe-
7.0 0.0372 1.934 riod of life. As a result, an individual
7.5 0.0357 1.824 with a high value of oxrealizes more of a
8.0 0.0341 1.715
8.5 0.0326 1.607
utility gain by reducing her savings rate.
9.0 0.0310 1.501 Note that the risk free rate puzzle comes
9.5 0.0295 1.395 from the equity premium puzzle: there is
10.0 0.0279 1.291 a risk free rate puzzle only if ox is re-
quired to be larger than one so as to
In this table, e- is the samplemean of et =(Ct,11Ct)-a match up with the high equity pre-
(Rt, - Rb+i)and a is the coefficient of relative risk mium.7
aversion.Standarderrorsare calculatedusing the im-
plicationof the theory that et is uncorrelatedwith etak 6 This intuition becomes even more clear if one
for all k; however,they are little changedby allowinget assumes that ln(Ct+1/Ct),ln(Rs1), and ln(Rb+1)are
to be MA(1)instead.This latterapproachto calculating jointly normally distributed. Then, equations (2a)
standarderrorsallowsfor the possibilityof time aggre- and (2b) become:
gation(see Hansen,Heaton,andYaron1994).
E(rt - rtb)- cCov(gt,rs-rt2)
+ O.5Var(ret)
+ 0.5Var(rbt)
= 0 (2a)
ln(f) - oxE(gt)+ E(rt) + 0.5(ccVai(gt)
is the equity premium puzzle. Intui-
- 20cCov(gt,rt) + Var(rb)}= 0 (2B)
tively, while the covariance between b
(g,?b
where (gt, (ln(Ct/Ct-1), 1n(Rs),ln(Rt )). In the
stock returns and per capita consump- rS, rtl,
data, Cov(gt, rt) is essentially zero. Because
tion growth is positive (see Table 1), it is E(rts- rt) is so large, either cc or Cov(gt,s) must be
not sufficiently large to deter the repre- large in order to satisfy (2a).
sentative investor with a coefficient of As with (2a) and (2b), the sample analogs of (2a)
and (2b) can only be satisfied by setting P equal to
relative risk aversion less than 8.5 from a value larger than one and cc equal to a value
wanting to borrow and invest in stocks. greater than 15. See N. Gregory Mankiw and
Note that the marginal benefit of selling Stephen Zeldes (1991) for more details.
See Edward Allen (1990), Cochrane and Han-
Treasury bills and buying stocks falls as sen (1992), and Constantinides (1990) for similar
presentations of the two puzzles.
Stephen Cecchetti, Pok-sang Lam, and Nelson
Tables 2-3 through the calculation of the standard Mark (1993) present the results of joint tests of
errors. Using their suggested correction makes (2a',b'). I present separate t-tests because I think
little difference to the t-statistics reported in doing so provides more intuition about the failings
either Table. (Indeed, Corr(et et-k)is small for all of the representative agent model. Of course,
k < 10.) there is nothing wrong statistically with doing two
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 51

TABLE 3
order condition (2b'). (See Kocherlakota,
THE RISK FREE RATE PUZZLE 1990a, for a demonstration of how com-
petitive equilibria can exist even when ,
a e t-stat > 1.) It is necessary to set ox to such a
0.0 0.0033 0.0567 large value because stocks offer a huge
0.5 -0.0081 -1.296 premium over bonds, and aggregate con-
1.0 -0.0162 -2.233 sumption growth does not covary greatly
1.5 -0.0239 -2.790 with stock returns; hence, the repre-
2.0 -0.0313 -3.100
2.5 -0.0382 -3.263
sentative investor can be marginally in-
3.0 -0.0448 -3.339 different between stocks and bonds only
3.5 -0.0510 -3.360 if he is highly averse to consumption
4.0 -0.0569 -3.348 risk. Similarly, the high consumption
4.5 -0.0624 -3.312 growth enjoyed by the United States
5.0 -0.0675 -3.259
5.5 -0.0723 -3.195
since 1890 can be consistent with high
6.0 -0.0768 -3.123 values of oc and the risk free rate only if
6.5 -0.0808 -3.043 the representative investor is so patient
7.0 -0.0846 -2.959 that his "discount" factor , is greater
7.5 -0.0880 -2.871 than one.
8.0 -0.0910 -2.779
8.5 -0.0937 -2.685
Thus, the equity premium and risk
9.0 -0.0960 -2.590 free rate puzzles are solely a product of
9.5 -0.0980 -2.492 the parametric restrictions imposed by
10.0 -0.0997 -2.394 Mehra and Prescott on the discount fac-
tor , and the coefficient of relative risk
In this table, e is the samplemean of et =O(ct+l/c0-X aversion ox.Given this, it is important to
(Rb- 1) and a is the coefficientof relativerisk aver- understand the sources of these restric-
sion. The discount factor 3 is set equal to 0.99. The
standarderrorsare calculatedusing the implicationof tions. The restriction that the discount
the theory that et is uncorrelatedwith et-kfor all k; factor , is less than one emerges from
however,they are little changed by allowinget to be introspection: most economists, includ-
MA(1)instead.This latterapproachto calculatingstan- ing Mehra and Prescott, believe that an
dard errorsallowsfor the possibilityof time aggrega- individual faced with a constant con-
tion (see Hansen,Heaton,andYaron1994).
sumption stream would, on the margin,
like to transfer some consumption from
the future to the present.
It is possible to find parameter set- The restriction that ox should be less
tings for the discount factor , and the than ten is more controversial. Mehra
coefficient of relative risk aversion oxthat and Prescott (1985) quote several micro-
exactly satisfy the sample versions of econometric estimates that bound ox
equations (2a') and (2b'). In particular, from above by three. Unfortunately, the
by setting a = 17.95, it is possible to sat- only estimate that they cite from finan-
isfy the equity premium first order con- cial market data has been shown to be
dition (2a'); by also setting f = 1.08, it is severely biased downwards (Kocherlak-
possible to satisfy the risk free rate first ota 1990c). In terms of introspection, it
has been argued by Mankiw and Zeldes
separate t-tests, each with size ax,as long as one (1991) that an individual with a coeffi-
keeps in mind that the size of the overall test cient of relative risk aversion above ten
could be as low as zero or it could be as high as would be willing to pay unrealistically
20x.(There may be a loss of power associated with
using sequential t-tests but power does not seem to large amounts to avoid bets. However,
be an issue in tests of representativeagent models!) they consider only extremely large bets
52 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

(ones with potential losses of 50 percent could simply be a result of sampling er-
of the gambler's wealth). In contrast, ror. Similarly, Mehra and Prescott as-
Shmuel Kandel and Robert Stambaugh sume that the growth rate of the divi-
(1991) show that even values of ocas high dend to the S & P 500 is perfectly
as 30 imply quite reasonable behavior correlated with the growth rate of per
when the bet involves a maximal poten- capita consumption. Simon Benninga
tial loss of around one percent of the and Aris Protopapadakis (1990) argue
gambler's wealth. that this might be responsible for the
Because of the arguments offered by conflict between the model and the data.
Kandel and Stambaugh (1991) and Ko- However, in Tables 2 and 3, the equity
cherlakota (1990c), some economists premium and risk free rate puzzles are
(see, among others, Craig Burnside still present when the representative in-
1994; Campbell and Cochrane 1995; vestor is faced with the real return to the
Cecchetti and Mark 1990; Cecchetti, S & P 500 itself, and not some imaginary
Lam, and Mark 1993; and Hansen, portfolio with a dividend that is perfectly
Thomas Sargent, and Thomas Tallarini correlated with consumption.
1994) believe that there is no equity pre- Finally, we can see that the exact na-
mium puzzle: individuals are more risk ture of the process generating consump-
averse than we thought, and this high de- tion growth is irrelevant. For example,
gree of risk aversion is reflected in the Cecchetti, Lam, and Mark (1993), and
spread between stocks and bonds. How- Kandel and Stambaugh (1990) have both
ever, it is clear to me from conversations proposed that allowing consumption
and from knowledge of their work that a growth to follow a Markovswitching pro-
vast majority of economists believe that cess (as described by James Hamilton
values for oc above ten (or, for that mat- 1989) might explain the two puzzles. Ta-
ter, above five) imply highly implausible bles 2 and 3, though, show that this con-
behavior on the part of individuals. (For jecture is erroneous:8 the standard t-test
example, Mehra and Prescott (1985, is asymptotically valid when consump-
1988) clearly chose an upper bound as tion growth follows any stationary and
large as ten merely as a rhetorical flour- ergodic process, including one that is
ish.) D. Lucas (1994, p. 335) claims that Markovswitching.9
any proposed solution that "does not ex-
plain the premium for cc < 2.5 . . . is ... 8 See Abel (1994) for another argument along

likely to be widely viewed as a resolution these lines.


9 Some readers might worry that the justifica-
that depends on a high degree of risk tion for Tables 2-3 is entirely asymptotic. I am
aversion." She is probably not exaggerat- sympathetic to this concern. I have run a Monte
ing the current state of professional Carlo experiment in which the pricing errors et
and et are assumed to be i.i.d. over time and have
opinion. a joint distribution equal to their empirical joint
Tables 2 and 3 show that any model distribution. In this setting, the Monte Carlo re-
that leads to (2a',b') will generate the sults show that the asymptotic distribution of the
t- statistic and its distribution with 100 observa-
two puzzles. This helps make clear what tions are about the same.
the puzzles are not about. For example, However, there is a limit to the generality of
while Mehra and Prescott ignore sam- Tables 2 and 3. One could posit, as in Kocher-
lakota (1994) and Thomas Rietz (1988), that there
pling error in much of their discussion, is a low probability of consumption falling by an
Tables 2 and 3 do not. This allays the amount that has never been seen in United States
concerns expressed by Allan Gregory and data. With power utilhty,investors are very averse
to these large falls in consumption, even if they
Gregor Smith (1991) and Cecchetti, are highly unlikely. Hence, investors believe that
Lam, and Mark (1993) that the puzzles stocks are riskier and bonds are more valuable
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 53

Thus, Tables 2 and 3 show that there generalization of the "standard"prefer-


are really only three crucial assumptions ence class (1). In these Generalized Ex-
generating the two puzzles. First, asset pected Utility preferences, the period t
markets are complete. Second, asset utility Ut received by a consumer from a
markets are frictionless. (As discussed stream of consumption is described re-
above, these two assumptions imply that cursively using the formula:
there is a representative consumer.) Fi-
nally, the representative consumer's util- Ut = {cl-P + pEtUt47l}(lP)/(la)}l/(lP) (3)
ity function has the power form assumed
by Mehra and Prescott (1985) and satis- Thus, utility today is a constant elasticity
fies their parametric restrictions on the function of current consumption and fu-
discount factor and coefficient of relative ture utility. Note that (1) can be ob-
risk aversion. Any model that seeks to re- tained as a special case of these prefer-
solve the two puzzles must weaken at ences by setting ox= p.
least one of these three assumptions. Epstein and Zin point out a crucial
attribute of these preferences. In the
III. Preference Modifications preferences (1), the coefficient of rela-
tive risk aversion oc is constrained to be
The paradigm of complete and fric- equal to the reciprocal of the elasticity
tionless asset markets underlies some of of intertemporal substitution. Thus,
the fundamental insights in both finance highly risk averse consumers must view
and economics. (For example, the consumption in different time periods
Modigliani-Miller Theorems and the ap- as being highly complementary. This is
peal of profit maximization as an objec- not true of the GEU preferences (3). In
tive for firms both depend on the com- this utility function, the degree of risk
pleteness of asset markets.) Hence, it is aversion of the consumer is governed
important to see whether it is possible to by ox while the elasticity of inter-
explain the two puzzles without aban- temporal substitution is governed by
doning this useful framework. To do so, 1/p. Epstein and Zin (1991) argue that
we must consider possible alterations in disentangling risk aversion and inter-
the preferences of the representative in- temporal substitution in this fashion
dividual; in this section, I consider three may help explain various aspects of as-
different modifications to the prefer- set pricing behavior that appear anoma-
ences (1): generalized expected utility, lous in the context of the preferences
habit formation, and relative consump- (1).
tion effects. To see the usefulness of GEU prefer-
1. Generalized Expected Utility ences in understanding the equity pre-
mium puzzle and the risk free rate puz-
In their (1989) and (1991) articles,'0 zle, suppose there is a representative
Larry Epstein and Stanley Zin describe a investor with preferences given by (3)
who can invest in stocks and bonds.
than appears to be true when one looks at infor- Then, the investor's optimal consump-
mation in the 90-year United States sample; the
t-statistics are biased upwards. While this explana- complementary analyses of the implications of this
tion is consistent with the facts, it has the defect type of generalized expected utility for asset pric-
of being largely nontestable using only returns and ing.
consumption data. (See Mehra and Prescott, 1988, There are other ways to generalize expected
for another critique of this argument.) utility so as to generate interesting implications for
1OWeil (1989), Kandel and Stambaugh (1991), asset prices-see Epstein and Tan Wang (1994)
and Hansen, Sargent, and Tallarini (1994) provide and Epstein and Zin (1990) for examples.
54 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

tion profile must satisfy the two first or- The first order condition (4a') tells us
der conditions: that using GEU preferences will not
change Table 2: for each value of oc, the
Rt1) = 0 (4a)
Et{Uf;-1a(Ct+llCt)-'(Rs1-RI marginal utility gain of reducing bond
holdings and investing in stocks is the
(01-041(-00
PEt {(Et Utl+-]a) same whether the preferences lie in the
= 1.
Uf;+O'(Ct+llCt)-PRt+1} (4b) expected utility class (1) or in the gener-
alized expected utility class (3). In con-
Note that the marginal rates of substitu-
trast, Table 4 shows that it is possible to
tion depend on a variable that is funda-
resolve the risk free rate puzzle using
mentally unobservable: the period (t + 1)
the GEU preferences. In particular, for
level of utility of the representative
, = 0.99, and various values of cc in the
agent (and the period t expectations of
set (0, 18], Table 4 presents the value of
that utility). This unobservability makes
p that exactly satisfies the first order
it difficult to verify whether the data are
condition (4b).
consistent with these conditions.
The intuition behind these results is
To get around this problem, we can
simple. The main benefit of modelling
exploit the fact that it is difficult to pre-
preferences using (3) instead of (1) is
dict future consumption growth using
that individual attitudes toward risk and
currently available information (see Hall
growth are no longer governed by the
1978). Hence, I assume in the discussion
same parameter. However, the equity
of GEU preferences that future con-
premium puzzle arises only because of
sumption growth is statistically indepen-
economists' prior beliefs about risk aver-
dent of all information available to the
sion; hence, this puzzle cannot be re-
investor today.11 Under this restriction,
solved by disentangling attitudes toward
it is possible to show that utility in pe-
risk and growth. On the other hand, the
riod (t + 1) is a time and state invariant
connection between risk aversion and in-
multiple of consumption in period (t +
tertemporal substitution in the standard
1). We can then apply the Law of Iter-
preferences (1) is the essential element
ated Expectations to (4a) and (4b) to ar-
rive at:
EtI(Ct+11Ct) YP(R+1) 1t+1- Rt+j) = 0 (*)
PiE{(Ct+j1Ct)-O1(Rts+-Rb
= (4a') Et{5'Y(Ct+llCt) 'YP(Rtm+l)'Yl(Rb}+ (I*)
1

13[E ((-PA/1-W
1-0a] where y = (1 - a)/(l - p). In (*) and (**), Rm is the
(Ct+j/Ct) gross real return to the representative investor's
Ef(Ct+,/Ct)-xRtb 11= 1. (4b') entire portfolio of assets (including human capital,
housing, etc.). This representation has the desir-
See Kocherlakota (199Gb) for a precise able attribute of being valid regardless of the in-
formation set of the representative investor (so we
derivation of these first order condi- don't have to assume that consumption growth
tions.12 from period t to period (t + 1) is independent of
all information available to the investor in period
11 This assumption of serial independence is t). Unfortunately, the variable Rt is not observ-
also employed by Abel (1990), Epstein and Zin able. Epstein and Zin (1991) use the value-
(1990), and Campbell and Cochrane (1995). Kan- weighted return to the NYSE as a proxy, but of
del and Stambaugh (1991), Kocherlakota (1990b), course this understates the true level of diversifi-
and Weil (1989) have shown that the thrust of the cation of the representative investor and (poten-
discussion that follows is little affected by allowing tially) greatly overstates the covariability of her
for more realistic amounts of dependence in con- marginal rate of substitution with the return to the
sumption growth. stock market. As a result, using this proxy variable
12 Epstein and Zin (1991) derive a different rep- leads one to the spurious conclusion that GEU
resentation for the first order conditions (4a) and preferences can resolve the equity premium puz-
(4b) of the representative investor: zle with low levels of risk aversion.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 55

ences (1), this forces intertemporal


'TABLE4
RESOLVINGTHE RISK FREE RATE PUZZLE
substitution to be low. The GEU prefer-
WITH GEU PREFERENCES ences can explain the risk free rate
puzzle by allowing intertemporal substi-
a I/C li/p tution and risk aversion to be high simul-
0.500 2.000 23.93 taneously.13
1.000 1.000 14.91
1.500 0.6667 10.62 2. Habit Formation
2.000 0.5000 8.126
2.500 0.4000 6.493
3.000 0.3333 5.345 We have seen that the risk free rate
3.500 0.2857 4.494 puzzle is a consequence of the demand
4.000 0.2500 3.840 for savings being too low when individu-
4.500 0.2222 3.322 als are highly risk averse and have pref-
5.000 0.2000 2.903
5.500 0.1818 2.557 erences of the form (1). The GEU pref-
6.000 0.1667 2.267 erence class represents one way to
6.500 0.1538 2.022 generate high savings demand when in-
7.000 0.1429 1.811 dividuals are highly risk averse. There is
7.500 0.1333 1.629 another, perhaps more intuitive, ap-
8.000 0.1250 1.469
8.500 0.1176 1.330 proach. The standard preferences (1) as-
9.000 0.1111 1.206 sume that the level of consumption in
9.500 0.1053 1.096 period (t - 1) does not affect the mar-
10.00 0.1000 0.9974 ginal utility of consumption in period t.
10.50 0.09524 0.9091 It may be more natural to think that an
11.00 0.09091 0.8295
11.50 0.08696 0.7574 individual who consumes a lot in period
12.00 0.08333 0.6920 (t - 1) will get used to that high level of
12.50 0.08000 0.6325 consumption, and will more strongly
13.00 0.07692 0.5781 desire consumption in period t; mathe-
13.50 0.07407 0.5283 matically, the individual's marginal util-
14.00 0.07143 0.4826
14.50 0.06897 0.4406 ity of consumption in period t is an
15.00 0.06667 0.4018 increasing function of period (t -1) con-
15.50 0.06452 0.3660 sumption.
16.00 0.06250 0.3329 This property of intertemporal prefer-
16.50 0.06061 0.3022 ences is termed habitformation. The ba-
17.00 0.05882 0.2737
17.50 0.05714 0.2472 sic implications of habit formation for
18.00 0.05556 0.2226 asset returns (as explained by Constan-
13Weil (1989) emphasizes that GEU prefer-
In this table, the first column is the coefficient of ences cannot explain the risk free rate puzzle if
relativeriskaversioncc,the secondcolumnis the corre- one forces the coefficient of relative risk aversion
spondingelasticityof intertemporalsubstitutionif pref- to be "reasonable" (say, approximately 1). He
erencesare of the form(1), and the thirdcolumnis the shows that under this restriction, then the elastic-
value of 1/p that satisfiesthe risk free rate first order ity of intertemporal substitution must be very
condition(4b') given that preferencesare of the form large to be consistent with the risk free rate. (See
(3), C = 0.99 and cchas the value specifiedin the first Table 4 for a confirmation.) This large elasticity of
intertemporal substitution appears to contradict
column. the results of Hall (1988), who shows that the esti-
mated slope coefficient is very small in a regres-
sion of consumption growth on expected real in-
of the risk free rate puzzle. To match terest rates (although Weil, 1990, points out that it
is difficult to see a direct linkage between Hall's
the equity premium, risk aversion has to regression coefficients and the parameters that de-
be high. But in the standard prefer- scribe the GEU preferences).
56 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

tinides 1990; and Heaton 1995) can be erences, this means that the formula for
captured in the following simple model. the marginal utility depends on the indi-
Suppose that there is a representative vidual's (possibly unobservable) informa-
agent with preferences in period t repre- tion. As in that context, it is convenient
sented by the utility function: to assume that consumption growth from
period t to period (t + 1) is unpre-
- 1 - > 0. (5)
Et ( ct+s-t)l
o3ss(ct+s A), dictable. Then the ratio of marginal utili-
Thus, the agent's momentary utility is a ties is given by:
decreasing function of last period's con- MUt+l/MUt= {(Pt+iPt- 40) a
sumption: it takes more consumption to-
day to make him happy if he consumed - X((pt+jpt)-OE((p- X)-01/
more yesterday.
The individual's marginal utility with {(pt - ) a - X(pt) aE(p - X)y (8)
respect to period t consumption is given
by the formula: where pt= Ctt/Ct-1. This allows us to eas-
ily estimate MUt+1/MUt by using the sam-
MUt = (ct - Act-,) a - PXEt(ct+l- Xct) . (6) ple mean to form an estimate of the un-
conditional expectations in the formula
Thus, the marginal utility of period t (8).
consumption is an increasing function of With the preference class (1), it is not
period (t - 1) consumption. Note that possible to simultaneously satisfy equa-
there are two pieces to this formula for tions (2a') and (2b') without driving ,
marginal utility. The first term captures above one. This is not true of prefer-
the fact that if I buy a BMW rather than ences that exhibit habit formation. For
a Yugo today, then I am certainly better example, suppose we set , = 0.99. Un-
off today; however, the second piece like the preference class (1), it is then
models the notion that having the BMW possible to find preference parameters to
"spoils" me and reduces my utility from satisfy both (7a') and (7b'). In particular,
all future car purchases. if we set a = 15.384 and X = 0.174, then
The individual's optimal consumption the sample analogs of both first order
portfolio must satisfy the two first order conditions are exactly satisfied in the
conditions that make him indifferent to data.14
buying or selling more stocks or bonds:
14 Instead of (7a',b'), Wayne Ferson and Con-
- Rb = 0 (7a) stantinides (1991) work with an alternative impli-
PEt{(MUt+j/MUt)(Rs+1 cation of (7a,b):
PEt{(MUt+j1MUt)Rtb1)1 = I1 %
(7b)
=+ E1MUtZt1(Ct-XCt-1)a1

where MUt is defined as in (6). We can = rElMUt+1Rt+1Zt/(Ct-XCt_1)a (*)


apply the Law of Iterated Expectations where Rt+iis the gross return to an arbitraryasset,
to obtain: and Zt is an arbitrary variable observable to the
econometrician and to the agent at time t. This
(7a') condition has the desirable property that it does
IE{(MUt+j/MUt)(Rs+1- Rb =
not involve terms that are unobservable to the
econometrician. However, (*) is a different type of
IE{(MUt+j/MUt)Rb+1)} = 1. (b') implication of optimal behavior from (4a,b) or
(2a,b) because it is not just an averaged version of
The problem with trying to satisfy (7a,b) (even when Zt is set equal to 1). In order to
(7a') and (7b') is that MUt depends on be consistent across preference orderings, I work
with (7a,b).
the investor's ability to predict future In the context of a calibrated general equilib-
consumption growth. As with GEU pref- rium model, Constantinides (1990) generates a
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 57

There are two implications of this given amount of consumption depends


result. First, habit formation does not on per capita consumption.'5
resolve the equity premium puzzle: it I will work with a model that combines
is still true that the representative in- features of Abel's and Gali's formula-
vestor is indifferent between stocks and tions. Suppose the representative indi-
bonds only if she is highly averse to vidual has preferences in period t:
consumption risk. On the other hand,
habit formation does help resolve the Et Es=oW3sctl+facx 1/(1-aX)) oc> 0 (9)
iJCX
risk free rate puzzle-it is possible to where ct+s is the individual's level of con-
satisfy (7a') and (7b') without setting ,3 sumption in period (t + s) while Ct+,is
larger than one. The intuition behind the level of per capita consumption in
this finding is simple. For any given level period (t + s) (in equilibrium, of course,
of current consumption, the individual the two are the same). Thus, the individ-
knows that his desire for consumption ual derives utility from how well she is
will be higher in the future because con- doing today relative to how well the av-
sumption is habit forming; hence, the in- erage person is doing today and how well
dividual's demand for savings increases the average person did last period. If the
relative to the preference specification individual is a jealous sort, then it is
(1). natural to think of y and X as being nega-
3. Relative Consumption: "Keeping tive: the individual is unhappy when oth-
up with the Joneses" ers are doing well. If the individual is
patriotic, then it is natural to think of y
The standard preferences (1) assume and X as being positive: the individual is
that individuals derive utility only from happy when per capita consumption for
their own consumption. Suppose, the nation is high.
though, that as James Duesenberry The representative individual treats
(1949) posits, an individual's utility is a per capita consumption as exogenous
function not just of his own consumption when choosing how much to invest in
but of societal levels of consumption. stocks and bonds. Hence, in equilibrium,
Then, his investment decisions will be the individual's first order conditions
affected not just by his attitudes toward take the form:
his own consumption risk, but also by his
attitudes toward variability in societal Et{(Ct+l/Ct)7-01(CJCt-,)'-(Rst+1
consumption. Following up on this intui- -Rb = 0 (lOa)
tion, Abel (1990) and Jordi Gali (1994)
examine the asset pricing implications of
= 1.
PEt{(Ct+l/Ct)Y7(C/Ct_l)XRb+i} (lOb)
various classes of preferences in which
the utility an individual derives from a We can apply the law of iterated expec-
tations to derive the two conditions:
large equity premium and a low risk free rate by E{(Ct+11Ct)Y-01(Ct1Ct_-l)(Rsts+
assuming that the representative agent's utility
function has a large va,ue of X and a low value of - Rb = 0 (lOa')
cc. However, it is important to keep in mind that
when X is large, the individual requires a large
level of consumption in order to just survive; he = 1.
1E)(Ct+1bCt)y-o(C1Ct_1)Rb} (lOb')
will pay a lot to avoid small consumption gambles
even if cc is low. Thus, Constantinides' proposed 15 See Campbell and Cochrane (1995) and
resolution of the puzzles requires individuals to be James Nason (1988) for models which feature both
very averse to consumption risk (although, as he relative consumption effects and time-varying risk
shows, not to wealth risk). aversion.
58 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

For any specification of the discount sury bill return, individuals who see con-
factor ,3 and the coefficient of relative sumption in different periods as so com-
risk aversion oc,it is possible to find set- plementary will be happy with the steep
tings for y and X such that the puzzles consumption profile seen in United
are resolved in that the sample analogs States data only if their "discount"factor
of (lOa') and (lOb') are satisfied. For ex- is above one.
ample, suppose X = 0.99. Then, if (o - y) Several researchers have explored the
= 19.280, and X = 3.813, the sample ana- consequences of using broader classes of
logs of (lOa') and (lOb') are satisfied ex- preferences. Broadly speaking, there are
actly. two lessons from this type of sensitivity
This model offers the following expla- analysis. First, the risk free rate puzzle
nation for the seemingly large equity can be resolved as long as the link be-
premium. When y is large in absolute tween individual attitudes toward risk
value, an individual's marginal utility of and growth contained in the standard
own consumption is highly sensitive to preferences (1) is broken. Second, the
fluctuations in per capita consumption equity premium puzzle is much more ro-
and therefore strongly negatively related bust: individuals must either be highly
to stock returns. Thus, even if oxis small averse to their own consumption risk or
so that the "representative" investor is to per capita consumption risk if they are
not all that averse to individual consump- to be marginally indifferent between in-
tion risk, she does not find stocks attrac- vesting in stocks or bonds.
tive because she is highly averse to per It seems that any resolution to the eq-
capita consumption risk. uity premium puzzle in the context of a
However, the presence of contempora- representative agent model will have to
neous per capita consumption in the rep- assume that the agent is highly averse to
resentative investor's utility function consumption risk. Per capita consump-
does not help explain the risk free rate tion is very smooth, and therefore does
puzzle: if X is set equal to zero, (lOa') not covary greatly with stock returns. Yet
and (lOb') become equivalent to (2a') people continue to demand a high ex-
and (2b'). We know from our analysis of pected return for stocks relative to
those equations that if X = 0, it is neces- bonds. The only possible conclusion is
sary to drive ,Blarger than one in order that individuals are extremely averse to
to satisfy (lOb') given that (lOa') is satis- any marginal variation in consumption
fied. The positive effect of lagged per (either their own or societal).
capita consumption on current marginal
utility increases the individual's demand IV. IncompleteMarketsand TradingCosts
for savings and allows (lOa') to be satis-
In this section, I examine the ability of
fied with a relatively low value of ,B
models with incomplete markets and
4. Summary various sorts of trading frictions to ex-
plain the asset returns data.'6 Unlike the
Mehra and Prescott (1985) require the
preferences of the representative indi- 16 Throughout my discussion, I ignore the exist-

vidual to lie in the "standard"class (1). ence of fiat money. Pamela Labadie (1989) and
Alberto Giovannini and Labadie (1991) show that
We have seen that these preferences can motivating a demand for money via a cash-in-
be made consistent with the large equity advance constraint does not significantly alter the
premium only if the coefficient of rela- asset pricing implications of the Mehra-Prescott
(1985) model. However, a richer model of money
tive risk aversion is pushed near 20. demand might have more dramatic effects on asset
Given the low level of the average Trea- prices.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 59

previous section, which focused solely on more variable than per capita consump-
the decision problem of a "representa- tion growth. As a result, models with in-
tive" agent, the analysis will (necessarily) complete markets offer the hope that
be fully general equilibrium in nature. while the covariance of per capita con-
Because of the complexity of these dy- sumption growth with stock returns is
namic general equilibrium models, their small, individual consumption growth
implications are generated numerically; I may covary enough with stock returns to
find that this makes any intuition more explain the equity premium.
speculative in nature. Dynamic Self-insurance and the Risk
Throughout this section, all investors Free Rate. The intuitive appeal of in-
are assumed to have identical prefer- complete markets for explaining asset re-
ences of the form (1). The "game"in this turns data is supported by the work of
literature is to explain the existence of Weil (1992). He studies a two period
the puzzles solely through the presence model in which financial markets are in-
of incompleteness and trading costs that complete. He shows that if individual
Mehra and Prescott assume away (just as preferences exhibit prudence (that is,
in Section III, the "game"was to explain convex marginal utility-see Miles Kim-
the puzzle without allowing such fric- ball 1990), the extra variability in indi-
tions). vidual consumption growth induced by
the absence of markets helps resolve the
1. Incomplete Markets
risk free rate puzzle. Without complete
Underlying the Mehra-Prescott model markets, individuals must save more in
is the presumption that the behavior of order to self-insure against the random-
per capita consumption growth is a good ness in their consumption streams; the
guide to the behavior of individual con- extra demand for savings drives down
sumption growth. We have seen that this the risk free rate. Weil also shows that if
belief is warranted if asset markets are individuals exhibit not just prudence but
complete so that individuals can write decreasing absolute prudence (see Kim-
contracts against any contingency: indi- ball 1990), the additional variability in
viduals will use the financial markets to consumption growth induced by market
diversify away any idiosyncratic differ- incompleteness also helps to explain the
ences in their consumption streams. As a equity premium puzzle. The extra riski-
result, their consumption streams will ness in individual consumption makes
look similar to each other and to per cap- stocks seem less attractive to an individ-
ita consumption. ual investor than they would to a "repre-
However, in reality, it does not appear sentative" consumer.17
easy for individuals to directly insure Unfortunately, two period models
themselves against all possible fluctua- cannot tell the full story because they
tions in their consumption streams. (For abstract from the use of dynamic trad-
example, it is hard to directly insure one- ing as a form of insurance against risk.
self against fluctuations in labor income.) For example, suppose my salary next
For this reason, most economists believe year is equally likely to be $40,000 or
that insurance markets are incomplete.
Intuitively, in the absence of these kinds 17 Mankiw (1986) shows that if the conditional
of markets, individual consumption variability of individual income shocks is higher
growth will feature risk not present in when the aggregate state of the economy is lower,
then prudence alone is sufficient to generate a
per capita consumption growth and so higher equity premium in the incomplete markets
individual consumption growth will be environment.
60 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

$50,000. If I die at the end of the year zero if there is to be trade in equilib-
and do not care about my descendants, rium.18
then the variability in income has to be As in the two period context, an indi-
fully reflected in my expenditure pat- vidual in this economy faces the possibil-
terns. This is the behavior that is cap- ity of an uninsurable consumption fall.
tured by two period models. On the The desire to guard against this possibil-
other hand, if I know I will live for many ity (at least on the margin) generates a
more years, then I need not absorb my greater demand to transfer resources
income risk fully into current consump- from the present to the future than in a
tion-I can partially offset it by reducing complete markets environment. This ex-
my savings when my income is high and tra demand for saving forces the equilib-
increasing my savings when my income is rium interest rate below the complete
low. markets interest rate.19
To understand the quantitative impli- However, the ability to dynamically
cations of dynamic self-insurance for the self-insure in the infinite horizon setting
risk free rate, it is best to consider a sim- means that the probability of an uninsur-
ple model of asset trade in which there able consumption fall is much smaller
are a large number (in fact, a continuum) than in the two period context. In equi-
of ex ante identical infinitely lived con- librium, the "typical" individual has no
sumers. Each of the consumers has a savings (because net asset holdings are
random labor income and their labor in- zero), but does have a "line of credit"
comes are independent of one another ymin/r. The individual can buffer any
(so there is no variability in per capita short-lived falls in consumption by bor-
income). The consumers cannot directly rowing; his line of credit can be ex-
write insurance contracts against the hausted only by a relatively unlikely long
variability in their individual income "run" of bad income realizations.
streams. In this sense, financial markets (Equivalently, in a stationary equilib-
are incomplete. However, the individuals rium, few individuals are near their
are able to make risk free loans to one credit limit at any given point in time.)
another, although they cannot borrow
18 Christopher Carroll (1992) argues using data
more than B in any period.
from the Panel Study in Income Dynamics that
For now, I want to separate the ef- yminequals zero. In this case, no individual can
fects of binding borrowing constraints ever borrow (because their debt ceiling equals
from the effects of incomplete markets. zero). There can be trade of risk free bonds only if
there is an outside supply of them (say, by the
To eliminate the possibility that the government). Then, the risk free rate puzzle be-
debt ceiling B is ever a binding con- comes an issue of how low the amount of outside
straint, I assume throughout the follow- debt must be in order to generate a plausibly low
value for the risk free rate. There is no clean an-
ing discussion that B is larger than swer to this question in the existing literature.
ymin"r,where Yminis the lowest possible 19Marilda Sotomayor (1984) proves that the in-
realization of income. No individual will dividual demand for asset holdings and for con-
sumption grows without bound over time if the
borrow more than ymin/r;doing so would interest rate equals the rate of time preference-
mean that with a sufficiently long run of the complete markets interest rate. (Her result is
bad income realizations, the individual valid without the assumption of convex marginal
utility as long as the consumption set is bounded
would be forced into default, which is as- from below.) This implies that the equilibrium in-
sumed to be infinitely costly (see Aiya- terest rate must fall below the rate of time prefer-
gari 1994). Market clearing dictates that ence in order to deter individuals from saving so
much. See Zeldes (1989b) and Angus Deaton
for every lender, there must be a bor- (1992) for numerical work along these lines in a
rower; hence, Yminmust be larger than finite horizon setting.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 61

Thus, the extra demand for savings gen- different when shocks to individual labor
erated by the absence of insurance mar- income are permanent instead of transi-
kets will generally be smaller in the infi- tory. Under the assumption of perma-
nite horizon economy than in a two nence, dynamic self-insurance can play
period model. no role: income shocks must be fully ab-
This reasoning suggests that in the in- sorbed into consumption. For example,
finite horizon setting, the absence of in- if my salary falls by $10,000 perma-
come insurance markets may have little nently, then the only way to keep my
impact on the interest rate. The numeri- consumption smooth over time is reduce
cal work of Huggett (1993) and Heaton it by the same $10,000 in every period: I
and D. Lucas (1995b) confirms this in- cannot just temporarily run down my
tuition. They examine infinite horizon savings account to smooth consumption.
economies which are calibrated to ac- Because income shocks must be fully ab-
cord with aspects of United States data sorbed into consumption, the results
on individual labor income and find that from the two period model become
the difference between the incomplete much more relevant. Indeed, Constan-
markets interest rate and the complete tinides and Duffie (1995) show that the
markets interest rate is small.20 absence of labor income insurance mar-
The above discussion assumes that in- kets, combined with the permanence of
dividual income shocks die out eventu- labor income shocks, has the potential to
ally (that is, the shocks are stationary). generate a risk free rate that may be
Constantinides and Darrell Duffie much lower than the complete markets
(1995) point out that the story is very risk free rate.
The issue, then, becomes an empirical
20In fact, they obtain these results in econo- one: how persistent (and variable) are
mies in which some fraction of the agents face
binding borrowing constraints in equilibrium. Re- otherwise undiversifiable shocks to indi-
laxing these borrowing constraints or adding out- vidual income? This is a difficult matter
side debt will serve to further increase the equilib- to sort out because of the paucity of time
rium interest rate toward the complete markets
rate (Aiyagari1994). series evidence available. However, Hea-
There is a caveat associated with the results of ton and D. Lucas (1995a) use data from
Huggett (1993) and Heaton and D. Lucas the Panel Study of Income Dynamics
(1995b)-and with most of the other numerical
work described later in this paper. For computa- and estimate the autocorrelation of idio-
tional reasons, these papers assume that the pro- syncratic2' labor income shocks to be
cess generatingindividualincomeis discrete.This around 0.5. When they examine the pre-
discretizationmayimposean artificiallyhigh lower
bound on income-that is, an artificiallyhigh dictions of the above model using this
value of Ymin. Thus, Heaton and D. Lucas(forth- autocorrelation for labor income (or
coming)assumethat incomecannotfall below 75 even an autocorrelation as high as 0.8),
percentof its meanvalue.Huggett(1993)is more
conservativein assumingthat income cannot fall they find that the equilibrium interest
belowaboutten percentof its meanvalue.In both
cases, finer and moreaccuratediscretizationsmay 21 What matters is the persistence of the undi-
driveYmin lower. versifiable component of labor income. Heaton
Thistechnicaldetailmayhaveimportantconse- and Lucas (1995a) implicitly assume that individu-
quencesfor the numericalresultsbecauseno indi- als can hedge any labor income risk that is corre-
vidualcan ever borrowmore thanymlir. As Yn1n lated with aggregate consumption. Hence, they
falls, there is an increasedprobabilityof a fall in obtain their autocorrelation estimate of 0.5 only
consumptionthat cannot be "buffered"by using after first controlling for aggregate effects upon
accumulatedsavings or by borrowing,and the individual labor income (this may explain why
downwardpressure on the equilibriuminterest their estimate of persistence is so much ower than
raterises.In fact, as Ymingoes to zero,the equilib- that of Glenn Hubbard, Jonathan Skinner, and
riuminterest rate must go to zero (if there is no Zeldes, 1994, who control for aggregate effects
outsidedebt). only through the use of year dummies).
62 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

rate is close to the complete markets sure against all income shocks, then his
rate. consumption would not change at all in
Dynamic Self-insurance and the Eq- response to the surprise movement in his
uity Premium Puzzle. The above analysis income process. Thus, his ability to self-
shows that as long as most individuals insure against income shocks using only
are sufficiently far from the debt ceiling savings can be measured by how close
ymin/r, dynamic self-insurance implies r/(1 + r - p) is to zero. For example, if p
that the equilibrium interest rate in in- = 1, and all shocks are permanent, then
complete markets models is well-ap- r/(1 + r - p) is equal to one; the income
proximated by the complete markets in- shock is fully absorbed into consump-
terest rate. In this section, I claim that a tion, which is very different from the im-
similar conclusion can be reached about plications of the full insurance model. In
the equity premium as long as the inter- contrast, if p < 1, then as r nears zero,
est rate and the persistence of shocks are the implications of the full insurance
both sufficiently low. model and the incomplete markets mod-
The following argument is a crude in- els for movements in individual con-
tuitive justification for this claim, based sumption become about the same. In the
largely on the Permanent Income Hy- United States annual data, we have seen
pothesis. Consider an infinitely lived in- that r is around one percent; hence, even
dividual who faces a constant interest if p is as high as 0.75, consumption is
rate r and who faces income shocks that fairly insensitive to surprise movements
have a positive autocorrelation equal to in labor income. (Recall that Heaton and
p; if p = 1, the shocks are permanent D. Lucas, 1995a, estimate the autocorre-
while if p < 1, their effect eventually lation of undiversifiable income shocks
dies out. Financial markets are incom- to be 0.5.)
plete in the sense that the individual This intuitive argument is borne out
cannot explicitly insure against the in- by the numerical work of Christopher
come shocks. Because of concave utility, Telmer (1993) and D. Lucas (1994; see
the individual wants to smooth consump- also Heaton and D. Lucas 1995a, 1995b;
tion as much as possible. Wouter den Haan 1994; and Albert Mar-
Suppose the individual's income is sur- cet and Singleton 1991). These papers
prisingly higher in some period by 6 dol- examine the quantitative predictions of
lars. Because of the autocorrelation in dynamic incomplete markets models,
the income shocks, the present value of calibrated using individual income data,
his income rises by: for the equity premium. They find that
dynamic self-insurance allows individuals
6+ p6/(1 +r)+ p26/(I +r)2+. to closely approximate the allocations in
=6/(1 - p/(1 + r)) a complete markets environment. The
=6(1 + r)/(1 + r- p). equilibrium asset prices are therefore
similar to the predictions of the Mehra-
The individual wants to smooth con-
Prescott (1985) model.
sumption. Hence, he increases consump-
A critical assumption underlying this
tion in every period of life by the annu-
numerical work is that income shocks
itized value of the increase in his wealth.
have an autocorrelation less than one.
A simple present value calculation im-
Constantinides and Duffie (1995) show
plies that his consumption rises by 8r/(l that if labor income shocks are instead
+ r - p) dollars. permanent, then it is possible for incom-
If the individual were able to fully in- plete markets models to explain the large
Kocherlakota: The Eauitu Premium 63

size of the equity premium. As in the books. In this model, the individual's
case of the risk free rate puzzle, the budget set of consumption choices (c1,
failure of dynamic self-insurance when p c2) is written as:
= 1 means that the model's implications
resemble those of a two period frame- ci < yi + bi
work. C2+ bi(I + r) <y2
To sum up: the assumption that finan- cl ? 0, C2 ? 0
cial markets are complete strikes many
economists as prima facie ridiculous, and where b1 is the level of borrowing in pe-
it is tempting to conclude that it is re- riod 1. The budget set allows the individ-
sponsible for the failure of the Mehra- ual to borrow up to the present value of
Prescott model to explain the United his period two income.
States data on average stock and bond Many economists believe that this
returns. However, as long as investors model of borrowing and lending ignores
can costlessly trade any financial asset an important feature of reality: because
(for example, risk free loans) over time, of enforcement and adverse selection
they can use the accumulated stock of problems, individuals are generally not
the asset to self-insure against idiosyn- able to fully capitalize their future labor
cratic risk (for example, shocks to indi- income. One way to capture this view of
vidual income). The above discussion the world is to add a constraint to the
shows that given this ability to self-in- individual's decision problem, b1 ? B,
sure, the behavior of the risk free rate where B is the limit on how much the
and the equity premium are largely unaf- individual can borrow. If B is less than
fected by the absence of markets as long y2/(l + r), the constrainton b1 may be
as idiosyncratic shocks are not highly binding because the individual may not
persistent. be able to transfer as much income from
period two to period one as he desires.
2. Trading Costs
The restriction b1 < B is called a bor-
In the incomplete and complete mar- rowing constraint. (Short sales con-
kets models described above, it is as- straints are similar restrictions on the
sumed that individuals can costlessly trade of stocks.) The law of supply and
trade any amount of the available securi- demand immediately implies that the
ties. This assumption is unrealistic in equilibrium interest rate is generally
ways that might matter for the two puz- lower if many individuals face a binding
zles. For example, in order to take ad- borrowing constraint than if few indi-
vantage of the possible utility gains asso- viduals do. Intuitively, "tighter"borrow-
ciated with the large premium offered by ing constraints exogenously reduce the
equity, individuals have to reduce their size of the borrowing side of the market;
holdings of Treasury bills and buy more in order to clear markets, interest rates
stocks. The costs of making these trades must fall in order to shrink the size of
may wipe out their apparent utility bene- the lending side of the market.
fits. In this subsection, I consider the im- In keeping with this intuition, the
plications for asset returns of various work of Huggett (1993) and Heaton and
types of trading costs. D. Lucas (1995a, 1995b) demonstrates
Borrowing and Short Sales Con- numerically that if a sizeable fraction of
straints. Consider the familiar two pe- individuals face borrowing constraints,
riod model of borrowing and lending in then the risk free rate may be substan-
most undergraduate microeconomic text- tially lower than the predictions of the
64 lournal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

representative agent model. Using data of stocks must incur a cost pt , in addi-
from the Panel Study on Income Dynam- tion to the price p, to buy a share.
ics, Zeldes (1989a) documents that the In equilibrium, the cost of buying a
large number of individuals with low lev- share of stock cannot be smaller than the
els of asset holdings appear to face such present value of the benefits of owning
constraints. that share for N periods (or there would
However, Heaton and D. Lucas be excess demand for stocks because
(1995a, 1995b) show that borrowing and everyone would want to buy shares).
short sales constraints do not appear to This statement can be expressed mathe-
have much impact on the size of the matically as:
equity premium. There is a sound intui- p(l +T) ?d/(I +rb)+ d/(I +rb)2
tion behind these results: an individual
+ . . . + d/(I + rb)N + p/(1 + rb)N.
who is constrained in the stock market
generally must also be constrained in the This present value expression can be re-
bond market (or vice versa). Otherwise, written as:
the individual could loosen the con-
straint in the bond market by shifting re- rs =dip < (1 + t)rb/{ -(1 + rb)-N.
sources to it from the stock market. Note that the right hand side gets
Hence, just as the average risk free rate smaller as N grows large. Intuitively, as
must fall to clear the bond market when the investor holds the stock for a long
many individuals are constrained, so period of time, he is able to more fully
must the average stock return fall in or- amortize the initial trading cost; the indi-
der to clear the constrained stock mar- vidual is therefore only prevented from
ket.22 making arbitrage profits if stock returns
Transaction Costs. Individualswho try are extremely close to those of bonds.
to engage in asset trade quickly find that Indeed, when N equals infinity, the up-
they face all sorts of transaction costs. per bound on the premium paid by
(These include informational costs, bro- stocks is very tight:
kerage fees, load fees, the bid-ask r8 - rb <trb.
spread, and taxes.) To understand how
transaction costs affect the pricing of se- Thus, if rb = 1 percent, and investors can
curities, consider an investor in a risk buy stocks and hold them forever, then
free world who can invest in two differ- rs can be as large as seven percent in
ent securities, stocks and bonds. Stocks equilibrium only if T is greater than 600
pay a constant dividend equal to d, and percent!
have a constant price equal to p. Because In the above risk free model, an inves-
stocks are a perpetuity, their rate of re- tor could buy and hold a stock for an in-
turn rs, ignoring transaction costs, equals finite number of periods. However, if
dip. Bonds are short-lived and pay a con- the investor instead faces income risk
stant interest rate rb. There is no cost which cannot be directly insured, she is
associated with trading bonds. However, not able to plan on being able to hold
stocks are costly to trade in that a buyer stocks forever. The reason is simple: if
she is ever pushed up against a debt ceil-
22 Followin Hua He and David Modest (1995), ing, so she cannot borrow to fully offset
Cochrane and Hansen (1992) show that this argu- bad income shocks, she will have to sell
ment is exactly correct,when individuals face a the stocks in order to smooth her con-
market wealth constraint that restricts the total
value of their asset portfolio not to fall below some sumption. This cap on the investor's
exogenously specified (negative) number. "holding period" generated by potential
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 65

runs of bad luck raises the possibility it treats per capita consumption growth
that in models with missing income in- as a good proxy for individual consump-
surance markets, transaction costs could tion growth. Yet, Mankiw and Zeldes
have big effects on asset return spreads. (1991) and Michael Haliassos and Carol
However, from our discussion of cali- Bertaut (forthcoming) document that
brated incomplete markets models, we only about 30 percent of individuals in
know that an infinitely lived individual the United States own stocks (either di-
can do a pretty good job of smoothing rectly or through defined contribution
consumption by simply buying and sell- pension funds). This suggests the possi-
ing the asset that is cheaper to trade. bility of market segmentation: that for
Hence, the agent faces only a low prob- whatever reason, only a subset of inves-
ability of needing to sell stocks in order tors are actively involved in asset trade.
to smooth consumption. She can conse- Campbell (1993) points out that it is the
quently contemplate making arbitrage per capita consumption growth of the ac-
profits by buying and holding stocks for tive traders that should be substituted
a long period of time; as we have seen, into first order conditions like (2a) and
this means that stocks cannot pay a (2b), not overall per capita consumption
much higher return than bonds in equi- growth as Mehra and Prescott (1985)
librium. use.
Thus, as Aiyagari and Mark Gertler However, Mankiw and Zeldes (1991)
(1991) and Heaton and D. Lucas (1995a) provide direct evidence that market seg-
find, the only way to explain the equity mentation alone cannot explain the eq-
premium using transaction costs is to as- uity premium. They find that the con-
sert that there are significant differences sumption growth of stockholders does
in trading costs across the stock and covary considerably more with stock re-
bond markets. In my view, there is little turns than the consumption growth of
evidence to support this proposition at nonstockholders. However, the covari-
present, although both Aiyagari and ance is still not large enough: it is only if
Gertler (1991) and Heaton and D. Lucas they are highly risk averse that stock-
(1995b) make some attempts in this di- holders are marginally indifferent be-
rection. To be considered as the leading tween stocks and bonds. There is still an
explanation of the puzzle, more needs to equity premium puzzle when we look at
be done to document the sizes and the consumption of those involved in as-
sources of trading costs (especially for set trade.24
pension funds and other institutional in-
vestors that operate on behalf of stock-
24 Ingram (1990) examines the general equilib-
holders).23
rium implications of a model in which half the
Market Segmentation. A key aspect of agents use all possible information to form their
the Mehra-Prescott (1985) model is that portfolios, whife the other half hold an optimal
"nonchurning"portfolio: they are constrained not
to change the split of assets between stocks and
23 In their partial equilibrium settings, Erzo bonds in response to new information. She finds
Luttmer (1995) and He and Modest (1995) assume that the equity premium is no higher than if all
that all investors fully turn over their port- folios agents were engaged in asset trade, but the risk
relatively frequently (once a month or once a free rate is significantly lower. Presumably, the
quarter) and all at the same time. This assumption "rule of thumb" traders hold too many bonds in
allows them to explain the equity premium with their portfolio because they want to be sure that
relatively small transaction costs; however, it they are insured against "runs"of bad income re-
seems difficult to build a general equilibrium alizations. This drives the equilibrium interest rate
model in which investors would choose to incur downwards, but has little effect on the equity pre-
trading costs so frequently and so simultaneously. mium.
66 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

3. Summary theoretical point of view (and possibly an


empirical one as well), the models will
The Mehra-Prescott (1985) model as- be stronger if they explicitly take into ac-
sumes that asset trade is costless and count the informational problems that
that asset markets are complete. Casual lead to the trading frictions.
observation suggests that both assump-
tions are unduly strong. Unfortunately, V. Discussion and Conclusions
the predictions of the model for the eq-
uity premium and the risk free rate are This paper began by posing two puz-
not greatly affected by allowing markets zles: how can we explain why average
to be incomplete: dynamic self-insurance stock returns are so much higher than
allows individuals to smooth idiosyn- bond returns in the United States data,
cratic shocks without using explicit insur- and why has per capita consumption
ance contracts. It is true (by the law of grown so quickly given that bond returns
supply and demand) that a frequently are so low? As it turns out, there are a
binding borrowing constraint forces the variety of ways to generate more savings
average risk free rate down toward its demand than in the Mehra-Prescott
sample value. The only way to simultane- model and thereby explain the latter
ously generate a sizeable equity pre- phenomenon.
mium, though, is to make trading in the However, the equity premium puzzle
stock market substantially more costly is much more challenging. Throughout
than in the bond market. Under this as- this article, we have seen only two ways
sumption, the premium on stocks repre- to explain the wedge in average returns
sents compensation not for risk (as in the between stocks and bonds. The first is
standard financial theory), but rather for that there is a large differential in the
bearing additional transactions costs. cost of trading between the stock and
The sources of these additional costs re- bond markets. To make this explanation
main unclear. compelling, it is important to ascertain
Despite its general lack of success in the size of actual trading costs in these
explaining the equity premium, this lit- markets, and to provide an explanation
erature has made an important contribu- of why those costs exist. Heaton and D.
tion to our understanding of trade in Lucas (1995b) and Aiyagari and Gertler
markets with frictions. Just as people in (1991) discuss some early steps in this
real life are able to find ways around direction.
government regulation of the economy, The second explanation is that, con-
rational individuals in models are able to trary to Mehra and Prescott's (1985)
find ways around barriers to trade. It original parametric restrictions, individ-
takes an enormous amount of sand in the ual investors have coefficients of relative
gears to disrupt the ability of individuals risk aversion larger than ten (either with
to approximate an efficient allocation of respect to their own consumption or
resources. with respect to per capita consump-
There is, however, a continuing weak- tion).25 As I explained earlier, the prob-
ness in the "market frictions" literature. lem with this exnlanation is that onlv a
Usually, the incompleteness of markets 25 Of course, as mentioned above, to resolve the
and the costliness of trade in these mod- risk free rate puzzle, we cannot only adopt a more
els is motivated by adverse selection or flexible notion of what constitutes reasonable risk
aversion; we must abandon the standard prefer-
moral hazard considerations. Yet, this ences (1) or impose borrowing constraints that
motivation remains informal. From a bind frequently.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 67

handful of economists believe that indi- ture the essential technological forces
viduals are that risk averse. One way to (for example, lack of communication)
support the "high risk aversion" view is that disrupt the process of fully central-
to demonstrate that this apparently ized exchange and thereby generate a
"strange" assumption about human be- demand for money. This same complaint
havior is consistent with data other than of superficiality can also be made of the
the average realization of the equity pre- two types of stories explaining the equity
mium. Until now, little has been done premium.
along these lines, but Tallarini's (1994) In one sense, the accuracy of the
analysis of a "prototypical"real business money demand analogy is depressing:
cycle model using generalized expected monetary theorists are a long way from
utility preferences represents a promis- delivering a definitive model of money
ing first step. demand. On the other hand, the work of
Ten years ago, Mehra and Prescott Robert Townsend (1987) and others in
(1985) wrote in their conclusion that the monetary theory is exciting because it
relatively low rate of return of Treasury shows so clearly what it will take to make
bills, "is not the only example of some true progress in explaining the size of
asset receiving a lower return than that the equity premium. Like fiat money,
implied by Arrow-Debreu general equi- the equity premium appears to be a
librium theory. Currency, for example, is widespread and persistent phenomenon
dominated by Treasury bills with positive of market economies. The universality of
nominal yields yet sizable amounts of the equity premium tells us that, like
currency are held." Thus, they regard money, the equity premium must
the equity premium puzzle as being emerge from some primitive and ele-
analogous to the so-called "rate of return mentary features of asset exchange that
dominance" puzzle that motivates much are probably best captured through ex-
of modern monetary theory. tremely stark models. With this in mind,
I believe that the past decade of work we cannot hope to find a resolution to
has made this analogy even more persua- the equity premium puzzle by continuing
sive: I find that the suggested "solutions" in our current mode of patching the
to the equity premium puzzle closely re- standard models of asset exchange with
semble the approaches used by econo- transactions costs here and risk aversion
mists to generate a demand for money in there. Instead, we must seek to identify
the face of rate of return dominance. what fundamental features of goods and
Thus, the "high risk aversion" story ex- asset markets lead to large risk adjusted
plains the puzzle by some peculiar aspect price differences between stocks and
of individual preferences-which is ex- bonds. While I have no idea what these
actly the way money-in-the-utility-func- "fundamental features" are, it is my be-
tion models explain money demand. The lief that any true resolution to the equity
"transactions costs" story explains that premium puzzle lies in finding them.
bonds are held despite their low rate of
return because they are less costly to Appendix
trade-which is exactly the way transac-
tions costs models explain money de- Apart from two exceptions, the follow-
mand. ing italicized description is taken directly
Generally, both of these types of mod- from Mehra and Prescott (1985, pp.
els of money demand are regarded as ad 147-48).
hoc "reduced forms." They fail to cap- The data used in this study consists of
68 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)

five basic series for the period 1889- This description differs from that of
1978. Thefirst four are identical to those Mehra and Prescott (1985) in two ways.
used by Grossman and Shiller (1981) in First, the figure numbers have been
their study. The series are individually changed to match the numbering in this
described below. paper. Second, Mehra and Prescott
(i) Series P: Annual average Standard (1985) used the formula RFt - (PCt+l -
& Poor's Composite Stock Price Index di- PCt)/PCt for the real return to the rela-
vided by the Consumption Deflator, a tively riskless security. This formula ex-
plot of which appears in Grossman and presses the real rate as being the differ-
Shiller (1981, p. 225, fig. 1). ence between the nominal rate and the
(ii) Series D: Real annual dividendsfor inflation rate. Of course, their formula is
the Standard & Poor's series. only an approximation;I use the correct
(iii) Series C: Kuznets-Kendrik-USNIA ratio formula instead.
per capita real consumption on non-dur- This difference in the formulae creates
ables and services. only small differences in results. For ex-
(iv) Series PC: Consumption deflator ample, they find that the average rela-
series, obtained by dividing real con- tively riskless rate is 0.8 percent. I find it
sumption in 1972 dollars on non-dur- instead to be one percent. They find that
ables and services by the nominal con- the variance of the relatively riskless rate
sumption on non-durables and services. is 0.0032; I find it to be 0.00308.
(v) Series RF: Nominal yield on rela- REFERENCES
tively riskless short-term securities over ABEL, ANDREW B. "Asset Prices Under Habit
the 1889-1978 period; the securities used Formation and Catching Up With the Joneses,"
were ninety-day government Treasury Amer. Econ. Rev., May 1990, 80(2), pp. 38-42.
bills in the 1931-1978 period, Treasury . "The Equity Premium Puzzle," Bus. Rev.:
Fed. Res. Bank Philadelphia, Sept./Oct. 1991,
Certificates for the 1920-1930 period pp. 3-14.
and sixty-day to ninety-day Prime Com- . "Exact Solutions for Expected Rates of
mercial Paper prior to 1920 [the data Return Under Markov Regime Switching: Im-
plications for the Equity Premium Puzzle," J.
was obtained from Homer (1963) and Money, Credit, Banking, Part 1, Aug. 1994,
Ibbotson and Sinquefeld (1978)]. 26(3), pp. 345-61.
These series were used to generate the AIYAGARI,S. RAO. "Explaining Financial Market
Facts: The Importance of Incomplete Markets
series actually utilized in this paper. Se- and Transaction Costs," Fed. Res. Bank Minn.
ries P and D above were used to deter- Rev., Winter 1993,17(1), pp. 17-31.
mine the average annual real return on . "Uninsured Idiosyncratic Risk and Aggre-
gate Saving," Quart. J. Econ., Aug. 1994,
the Standard & Poor's 500 Composite In- 109(3), pp. 659-84.
dex over the ninety-year period of study. AIYAGARI,S. RAO AND GERTLER, MARK. "Asset
The annual return for year t was com- Returns with Transaction Costs and Uninsured
Individual Risk," J. Monet. Econ., June 1991,
puted as (Pt+, + Dt+1 - Pt)/Pt. The returns 27(3), pp. 311-31.
are plotted in fig. 2. Series C was used ALLEN, EDWARD R. "Evaluating Consumption-
to determine the process on the growth Based Models of Asset Pricing." Working Pa-
per. U. of Chicago, 1990.
rate of consumption over the same period ATKESON,ANDREW AND PHELAN, CHRISTOPHER.
* . A plot of the percentage growth rate "Reconsidering the Costs of Business Cycles
of real consumption appear in fig. 1. To with Incomplete Markets," in NBER macro-
economics annual 1994. Eds.: STANLEYFI-
determine the real return on a relatively SCHER AND JULIO ROTEMBERG. Cambridge,
riskless security we used the series RF MA: MIT Press, 1994, pp. 187-207.
and PC. For year t, this is calculated BENNINGA, SIMON AND PROTOPAPADAKIS,ARIS.
"Leverage, Time Preference, and the 'Equity
to be (1 + RFt)PCt/PCt+1.This series is Premium Puzzle'," J. Monet. Econ., Jan. 1990,
plotted in fig. 3. 25(1), pp. 49-58.
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 69
BREEDEN, DOUGLAS T. "An Intertemporal Asset ."'First Order' Risk Aversion and the Eq-
Pricing Model with Stochastic Consumption uity Premium Puzzle," J. Monet. Econ., Dec.
and Investment Opportunities," J. Finan. Econ., 1990, 26(3), pp. 387-407.
Sept. 1979, 7(3), pp. 265-96. . "Substitution, Risk Aversion, and the Tem-
BREEDEN, DOUGLAS T.; GIBBONS, MICHAEL R. poral Behavior of Consumption Growth and As-
AND LITZENBERGER, ROBERT H. "Empirical set Returns II: An Empirical Analysis," J. Polit.
Tests of the Consumption-Oriented CAPM." J. Econ., Apr. 1991, 99(2), pp. 263-86.
Finance, June 1989, 44(2), pp. 231-62. FERSON, WAYNE E. AND CONSTANTINIDES,
BREEDEN, DOUGLAS T. AND LITZENBERGER, GEORGE. "Habit Persistence and Durability in
ROBERT H. "Prices of State-contingent Claims Aggregate Consumption: Empirical Tests," J.
Implicit in Option Prices," J. Bus., Oct. 1978, Finan. Econ., Oct. 1991, 29(2), pp. 199-240.
51(4), pp. 621-51. GALI, JORDI. "Keeping Up with thle Joneses: Con-
BURNSIDE, CRAIG. "Hansen-Jagannathan Bounds sumption Externalities, Portfolio Choice, and
as Classical Tests of Asset Pricing Models," J. Asset Prices," J. Money, Credit, Banking, Feb.
Bus. Econ. Statist., Jan. 1994, 12(1), pp. 57-79. 1994, 26(1), pp. 1-8.
CAMPBELL, JOHN Y. "Intertemporal Asset Pricing GIOVANNINI, ALBERTO AND LABADIE, PAMELA.
Without Consumption Data," Amer. Econ. Rev., "Asset Prices and Interest Rates in Cash-in-Ad-
June 1993, 83(3), pp. 487-512. vance Models," J. Polit. Econ., Dec. 1991,
CAMPBELL, JOHN AND COCHRANE, JOHN. "By 99(6), pp. 1215-51.
Force of Habit: A Consumption-Based Explana- GREGORY, ALLEN W. AND SMITH, GREGOR W.
tion of Aggregate Stock Market Behavior." "Calibration as Testing: Inference in Simulated
NBER Working Paper 4995, 1995. Macroeconomic Models," J. Bus. Econ. Statist.,
CARROLL, CHRISTOPHER D. "The Buffer-Stock July 1991, 9(3), pp. 297-303.
Theory of Saving: Some Macroeconomic Evi- GROSSMAN, SANFORD J.;MELINO, ANGELO AND
dence," Brookings Pap. Econ. Act., 1992, 2, pp. SHILLER, ROBERT J. "Estimating the Continu-
61-135. ous-Time Consumption-Based Asset-Pricing
CECCHETTI, STEPHEN G.; LAM, POK-SANG AND Model," J. Bus. Econ. Statist., July 1987, 5(3),
MARK, NELSON C. "The Equity Premium and pp. 315-27.
the Risk-free Rate: Matching the Moments," J. GROSSMAN, SANFORD J. AND SHILLER, ROBERT
Monet. Econ., Feb. 1993, 31(1), pp. 21-45. J. "The Determinants of the Variability of Stock
CECCHETTI, STEPHEN G. AND MARK, NELSON C. Market Prices," Amer. Econ. Rev., May 1981,
"Evaluating Empirical Tests of Asset Pricing 71(2), pp. 222-27.
Models: Alternative Interpretations," Amer. DEN HAAN, WOUTER. "Heterogeneity, Aggregate
Econ. Rev., May 1990, 80(2), pp. 48-51. Uncertainty, and the Short-Term Interest
COCHRANE, JOHN AND HANSEN, LARS. "Asset Rate." Working Paper, U. of California-San Di-
Pricing Explorations for Macroeconomics," in ego, 1994.
NBER macroeconomics annual 1992. Eds.: HALIASSOS, MICHAEL AND BERTAUT, CAROL.
OLIVIER BLANCHARD AND STANLEY FISCHER. "Why Do So Few Hold Stocks? The View from
Cambridge, MA: MIT Press, 1992, pp. 115-82. Asset Pricing Theory," Econ. J., forthcoming.
CONSTANTINIDES, GEORGE M. "Intertemporal HALL, ROBERT E. "Stochastic Implications of the
Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Consumers Life Cycle-Permanent Income Hypothesis: The-
and Without Demand Aggregation," J. Bus., ory and Evidence," J. Polit. Econ., Dec. 1978,
Apr. 1982, 55(2), pp. 253-67. 86(6), pp. 971-87.
"Habit Formation: A Resolution of the Eq- . "Intertemporal Substitution in Consump-
uity Premium Puzzle," J. Polit. Econ., June tion," J. Polit. Econ., Apr. 1988, 96(2), pp. 339-
1990, 98(3), pp. 519-43. 57.
CONSTANTINIDES, GEORGE M. AND DUFFIE, HAMILTON, JAMES D. "A New Approach to the
DARRELL. "Asset Pricing with Heterogeneous Economic Analysis of Nonstationary Time Se-
Consumers." Working Paper. U. of Chicago, ries and the Business Cycle," Econometrica,
1995. Mar. 1989, 57(2), pp. 357-84.
DEATON, ANGUS. Understanding consumption. HANSEN, LARS PETER; HEATON, JOHN AND
Oxford, UK: Clarendon Press, 1992. YARON, AMIR. "Finite Sample Properties of
DUESENBERRY, JAMES S. Income, saving, and the Some Alternative GMM Estimators." Working
theory of consumer behavior. Cambridge, MA: Paper. U. of Chicago, 1994.
Harvard U. Press, 1949. HANSEN, LARS PETER AND JAGANNATHAN, RAVI.
EPSTEIN, LARRY G. AND WANG, TAN. "Intertem- "Implications of Security Market Data for Mod-
poral Asset Pricing Under Knightian Uncer- els of Dynamic Economies," J. Polit. Econ.,
tainty," Econometrica, Mar. 1994, 62(2), pp. Apr. 1991, 99(2), pp. 225-62.
283-322. HANSEN, LARS PETER; SARGENT, THOMAS AND
EPSTEIN, LARRY G. AND ZIN, STANLEY E. "Sub- TALLARINI,THOMAS. "Pessimism, Neurosis and
stitution, Risk Aversion, and the Temporal Feelings About Risk in General Equilibrium."
Behavior of Consumption Growth and Asset Working Paper. U. of Chicago, 1994.
Returns I: A Theoretical Framework, Econo- HANSEN, LARS PETER AND SINGLETON, KEN-
metrica, July 1989, 57(4), pp. 937-69. NETH. "Generalized Instrumental Variables Es-
70 Journal of Economic Literature, Vol. XXXIV (March 1996)
timation of Nonlinear Rational Expectations LABADIE, PAMELA. "Stochastic Inflation and the
Models," Econometrica, Sept. 1982, 50(5), pp. Equity Premium,"J. Monet. Econ., Sept. 1989,
1269-86. 24(3), pp. 277-98.
. "Stochastic Consumption, Risk Aversion, LUCAS, DEBORAH. "Asset Pricing with Undiversi-
and the Temporal Behavior of Asset Returns, J. fiable Risk and Short Sales Constraints: Deep-
Polit. Econ., Apr. 1983, 91(2), pp. 249-65. ening the Equity Premium Puzzle," J. Monet.
HE, HUA AND MODEST, DAVID M. "Market Econ., Dec. 1994, 34(3), pp. 325-42.
Frictions and Consumption-Based Asset Pric- LUCAS, ROBERT E., JR. "Asset Prices in an Ex-
ing," J. Polit. Econ., Feb. 1995, 103(1), pp. 94- change Economy," Econometrica, Nov. 1978,
117. 46(6), pp. 1429-45.
HEATON, JOHN. "An Empirical Investigation of . Models of business cycles. New York:Basil
Asset Pricing with Temporally Dependent Pref- Blackwell, 1987.
erence Specifications," Econometrica, May LUTTMER, ERZO. "Asset Pricing in Economies
1995, 63(3), pp. 681-717. with Frictions." Working Paper. Northwestern
HEATON, JOHN AND LUCAS, DEBORAH. "Evaluat- U., 1995.
ing the Effects of Incomplete Markets on Risk MANKIW, N. GREGORY. "The Equity Premium
Sharing and Asset Pricing." Working paper, and the Concentration of Aggregate Shocks,"J.
Northwestern U., 1995a. Finan. Econ., Sept. 1986, 17(1), pp. 211-19.
. "The Importance of Investor Heterogene- MANKIW, N. GREGORY AND ZELDES, STEPHEN P.
ity and Financial Market Imperfections for the "The Consumption of Stockholders and Non-
Behavior of Asset Prices," Carnegie-Rochester Stockholders," J. Finan. Econ., Mar. 1991,
Ser. Public Pol., 1995b. 29(1), pp. 97-112.
HOMER, SIDNEY. A history of interest rates. New MARCET, ALBERT AND SINGLETON, KENNETH.
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers U. Press, 1963. "Optimal Consumption-Savings Decisions and
HUBBARD, R. GLENN; SKINNER, JONATHAN AND Equilibrium Asset Prices in a Model with Het-
ZELDES, STEPHEN P. "The Importance of Pre- erogeneous Agents Subject to Portfolio Con-
cautionary Motives in Explaining Individual and straints."Working Paper. Stanford U., 1991.
Aggregate Saving," Carnegie-Rochester Ser. MEHRA, RAJNISH AND PRESCOTT, EDWARD C.
Public Pol., June 1994, 40, pp. 59-125. "The Equity Premium: A Puzzle," J. Monet.
HUGGETT, MARK. "The Risk-Free Rate in Hetero-
Econ., Mar. 1985, 15(2), pp. 145-61.
geneous-Agent Incomplete-Insurance Econo- . "The Equity Risk Premium: A Solution?"
mies," J. Econ. Dynam. Control, Sept./Nov. J. Monet. Econ., July 1988, 22(1), pp. 133-36.
1993, 17(5/6), pp. 953-69. NASON, JAMES. "The Equity Premium and Time-
IBBOTSON, ROGER G. AND SINQUEFIELD, REX A.
Varying Risk Behavior." Working Paper. Fed-
Stocks, bonds, bills, and inflation: Historical Re-
turns (1926-1978). Charlottesville, VA: Finan- eral Reserve Board of Governors, 1988.
NEELY, CHRISTOPHER. "A Reconsideration of the
cial Analysts Research Foundation, 1978.
INGRAM, BETH FISHER. "Equilibrium Modeling Properties of the Generalized Method of Mo-
of Asset Prices: Rationality Versus Rules of ments in Asset Pricing Models." Working Pa-
Thumb,"J. Bus. Econ. Statist., Jan. 1990, 8(1), per. Federal Reserve Bank of St. Louis, 1994.
RIETZ, THOMAS A. "The Equity Risk Premium: A
pp. 115-25.
KANDEL, SHMUEL AND STAMBAUGH, ROBERT F. Solution,"J. Monet. Econ., July 1988, 22(1), pp.
"Expectations and Volatility of Consumption 117-31.
and Asset Returns," Rev. Finan. Stud., 1990, RoY, AMLAN. "MulticountryComparisons of Con-
3(2), pp. 207-32. sumption-Based Capital Asset Pricing Model:
. "Asset Returns and Intertemporal Prefer- Germany, Japan, and U.S.A." Working Paper.
ences," J. Monet. Econ., Feb. 1991, 27(1), pp. U. of London, 1994.
39-71. RUBINSTEIN, MARK. "The Valuation of Uncertain
KIMBALL, MILES S. "PrecautionarySaving in the Income Streams and the Pricing of Options,"
Small and in the Large," Econometrica, Jan. Bell J. Econ., Autumn 1976, 7(2), pp. 407-25.
1990, 58(1), pp. 53-73. SIEGEL, JEREMY J. "The Real Rate of Interest
KOCHERLAKOTA,NARAYANA."On the 'Discount' from 1800-1990: A Study of the U.S. and the
Factor in Growth Economies," J. Monet. Econ., U.K.," J. Monet. Econ., Apr. 1992, 29(2), 227-
Jan. 1990a, 25(1), pp. 43-47. 52.
. "Disentangling the Coefficient of Relative SOTOMAYOR, MARILDA DE OLIVEIRA. "On In-
Risk Aversion from the Elasticity of Intertem- come Fluctuations and Capital Gains,"J. Econ.
poral Substitution: An Irrelevance Result," J. Theory, Feb. 1984, 32(1), pp. 14-35.
Finance, Mar. 1990b, 45(1), pp. 175-90. TALLARINI, THOMAS. "Risk-Sensitive Real Busi-
. "On Tests of Representative Consumer ness Cycles." Working Paper. U. of Chicago,
Asset Pricing Models," J. Monet. Econ., Oct. 1994.
1990c, 26(2), pp. 285-304. TELMER, CHRIS I. "Asset Pricing Puzzles and In-
. "Testing the Consumption CAPM with complete Markets," J. Finance, Dec. 1993,
Heavy-Tailed Pricing Errors." Working Paper. 48(5), pp. 1803-32.
U. of Iowa, 1994. TOWNSEND, ROBERT M. "Asset-ReturnAnomalies
Kocherlakota: The Equity Premium 71
in a Monetary Economy."J. Econ. Theory, Apr. fiable Labor Income Risk," J. Econ. Dynam.
1987, 41(2), pp. 219-47. Control, July/Oct. 1992, 16(3/4), pp. 769-90.
WEIL, PHILIPPE. "The Equity Premium Puzzle ZELDES, STEPHEN P. "Consumption and Liquid-
and the Risk-Free Rate Puzzle," J. Monet. ity Constraints: An Empirical Investigation,"J.
Econ., Nov. 1989, 24(2), pp. 401-21. Polit. Econ., Apr. 1989a, 97(2), pp. 305-46.
"Nonexpected Utility in Macro- "Optimal Consumption with Stochastic
economics," Quart. J. Econ., Feb. 1990, 105(1), Income: Deviations from Certainty Equiva-
pp. 29-42. lence," Quart. J. Econ., May 1989b, 104(2), pp.
. "EquilibriumAsset Prices with Undiversi- 275-98.

You might also like