You are on page 1of 16

1

DRAFT
Climate, Consensus, and Contrarians1
Jay Odenbaugh Department of Philosophy Environmental Studies Lewis and Clark College jay@lclark.edu

I. Introduction. In debates over global climate change, much is made over the consensus concerning the effects of human-induced greenhouse gas emissions on the Earths temperature. Contrarians correctly note that science is partially structured around dissent and criticism. Thus, they charge scientific consensus is irrelevant and even harmful to scientific inquiry. In this essay, I first present the contrarians argument. Second, I argue this criticism is irrelevant because claims about the scientific consensus concern how policymakers form their beliefs and not scientists themselves. Third, I argue that policymakers should form their beliefs about global climate change based on the scientific consensus when that consensus is reliable indicator of truth and explore when this is so by considering Condorcet Jury Theorems and the structure of Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change. II. Scientific Consensus. Many contrarians, and others of course, correctly note that agreement amongst scientists doesnt make the agreed upon proposition true nor even guarantees that it is true.2 Historian Naomi Oreskes writes,

I wish to thank all those who attended my talk at the twelfth Inland Northwest Philosophy Conference and provided fruitful feedback and questions; specifically Stephen Crowley, Steve Gardiner, Bruce Glymour, Ben Hale, Kristen Intemann, Kristin Shrader-Frechette, Michael ORourke, Matt Slater, Mariam Thalos, Allen Thompson, Michael Trestman, and Dennis Walsh.
2

Naomi Oreskes writes, If the history of science teaches anything, its humility. There are numerous historical examples where expert opinion turned out to be wrong Moreover, in any scientific community, there are always

If the history of science teaches anything, its humility. There are numerous historical examples where expert opinion turned out to be wrong Moreover, in any scientific community, there are always some individuals who depart from generally accepted views, and occasionally they turn out to be right. At present, there is a scientific consensus on global warming, but how do we know its not wrong? (2007, 65) We can summarize this claim as follows: (C) Scientific consensus about a proposition does not make or guarantee that it is true. Why accept (C)? Because, as Oreskes notes, in the history of science there are propositions which had near unanimous acceptance but which were latter shown to be false. For example, scientists believed that the Earth was at the center of our solar system, continents do not drift, and that species are not related by common descent. Examples such as these suffice to show that propositions are not made true by unanimous consent.3 Thus, many contrarians believe interest in scientific consensus reflects political concerns as opposed to epistemological ones. Novelist Michael Crichton writes, Lets be clear: the work of science has nothing whatever to do with consensus. Consensus is the business of politics. Science, on the contrary, requires only one investigator who happens to be right, which means that he or she has results that are verifiable by reference to the real world. In science consensus is irrelevant. What is relevant is reproducible results. The greatest scientists in history are great precisely because they broke with the consensus. There is no such thing as consensus science. If its consensus, it isnt science. If its science, it isnt consensus. Period. (http://www.crichton-official.com/speechalienscauseglobalwarming.html)4 Similarly, MIT professor of meteorology and contrarian Richard Lindzen writes,

some individuals who depart from generally accepted views, and occasionally they turn out to be right. At present, there is a scientific consensus on global warming, but how do we know its not wrong? (2007, 65) 3 A technical aside: there are propositions which can be made true by universal assent; namely those whose truth conditions concern universal assent. However, those very propositions are not made true by universal assent to them. Also, on one type of pragmatist theory of truth, a proposition is true just in case it would be agreed with by fully informed and fully rational inquirers who had an indefinite amount of time to investigate them.
4

For a popular argument for these sorts of claims, see Horner (2007) especially his chapter five and fiction writer Michael Crichtons critique of climate change science in his novel State of Fear.

With respect to science, the assumption behind consensus is that science is a source of authority and that authority increases with the number of scientists. Of course, science is not primarily a source of authority. Rather, it is a particularly effective approach to inquiry and analysis. Skepticism is essential to science; consensus is foreign. (Horner 2007, 86) Both Crichton and Lindzen make the same mistake of course just because scientists agree that a proposition is true doesnt make it true. However, this obvious point is consistent with the fact that most scientists believe a proposition is true can be good evidence for others to believe that proposition. In Lindzens terms, if science is an effective approach to inquiry and analysis this may give us good reason to treat scientists agreement as authoritative. Lastly, contrarian writer Chris Horner writes, There is no scientific consensus that extreme or damaging global warming will occur or that Man is the principal or even a quantifiable determinant of climate, let alone that global warming would be a bad thing (past warmings yes, including warmer than the present have always been positive; dark ages have tended to coincide with cooling phases). In fact, it is difficult to identify another issue of scientific inquiry over which the debate rages more intensely. (2007, 82) Horner provides us with a bait-and-switch; ignore the consensus surrounding the proposition under discussion and suggest there is no consensus regarding a different one. As we shall see, there is a consensus regarding humans having a discernable effect on the Earths climate independent of whether these effects will be catastrophic.5 To be very clear, both dissent and consensus matter to scientific practice.6 First, it is in the interest of any research group that their hypotheses be confirmed and it is in the interest of their opposition that those hypotheses be disconfirmed. Given this dynamic, critical engagement

It is also helpful to note that there is also a consensus regarding climate change economics as well. First, the costs of inaction are greater than action and that the costs of dealing with anthropogenic climate change will be a tiny fraction of GDP.
6

I am indebted to an anonymous reviewer for noting this point.

occurs and dissent is a crucial element in weeding out reliable from unreliable work, truths from falsehoods (Hull 1988, Kitcher 1993). Second, science, and its progress, requires consensus. Research programs require a large degree of agreement amongst scientists regarding aims, methods, and theories. Without such agreement, research could not take place since there would not be common questions, strategies, representations of the phenomena, and tools to evaluate those representations. Likewise, rational transitions between programs necessitates there are agreed upon elements which can used to make rational decisions regarding the disputed elements and recent work concerning the history of science demonstrates such piecemeal transitions (Laudan 1986). When theories are in dispute one must use agreed upon methods to pick the better theory, when there is a disagreement regarding proper methodology one must use aims to determine the best means, and so on. Contrarians should not deny the proper importance of agreement and dissent in science. In the next section, I want to document the consensus that exists regarding anthropogenic climate change and thereafter I will carefully articulate why this consensus matters. III. Global Climate Change Consensus. To zero in on the debate, lets use the following claim: (GW) Average surface temperatures are increasing in part because of human greenhouse gas emissions. Naomi Oreskes (2004) forcefully argues there is close to complete agreement amongst professional climate scientists regarding (GW)s truth. She and her graduate students surveyed over 928 abstracts of articles published in peer-reviewed journals with the search term global climate change through the Institute of Scientific Informations Web of Science. Each essay was placed in one of six categories: (1) those explicitly endorsing the consensus position, (2) those explicitly refuting the consensus position, (3) those discussing methods and techniques for

measuring, monitoring, or predicting climate change, (4) those discussing potential or documenting actual impacts of climate change, (5) those dealing with paleoclimatic change, and (6) those proposing mitigation strategies. Ultimately what they found was there were no papers of category (2).

Figure 1 A Web of Science analysis of 928 abstracts using the keywords global climate change. No papers in the sample provided scientific data to refute the consensus position on global climate change (Oreskes 2004).

That is, she found no essay which disagreed with the claim Global climate change is occurring, and human activities are at least part of the reason why. There are variety of criticisms leveled at Oreskes study. One criticism raised by Roger Pielke Jr. (2005) is that the Oreskes study does not represent the variance consistent with those who agree with the IPCCs reports. That is, one can agree with (GW) but disagree over many other propositions concerning global climate change. This is perfectly correct but irrelevant to the studys methods and findings which concern the focal proposition (GW). Others have suggested some duplicity on Oreskes part given that in the 2004 paper she claimed they searched with the terms climate change which would have turned up ten thousand papers but this a simple mistake which was later corrected in Science. Most importantly, one might argue that consistency with the proposition Global climate change is occurring, and human activities are at

least part of the reason why is insufficient to demonstrate agreement with the proposition. Oreskes provides the correct response to this point. If a conclusion is widely accepted, then it is not necessary to reiterate it within the context of expert discussion. Scientists generally focus their discussions on questions that are still disputed or unanswered rather than on matters about which everyone agrees. (2007, 72)7 Similarly, one would not see common descent argued for or explicitly affirmed in an essay in Evolution or American Naturalist; it is taken for granted. Hence, if one only included support by those papers which provide explicit acceptance, then it would underestimate the acceptance of evolution and by analogy global climate change as in part human-caused. Lest one think this study is a fluke or non-representative, consider the following recent study done by Doran and Zimmerman (2009). They sent a survey to 10, 257 earth scientists. The individuals surveyed came from a database (Keane and Martinez (2007)) of geosciences faculty, researchers at state geological facilities associated with local universities, researchers at U.S. research facilities (U.S. Geological Survey, NASA, and NOAA) and the U.S. Department of Energy national laboratories (2009, 21). Of the questions asked, their essay discusses two: 1. When compared with pre-1800s levels, do think that mean global temperatures have generally risen, fallen, or remained relatively constant? 2. Do you think human activity is a significant contributing factor in changing mean global temperatures? Here are their results for question (2).

Michael Crichton writes, Finally, I would remind you to notice where the claim of consensus is invoked. Consensus is invoked only in situations where the science is not solid enough. Nobody says the consensus of scientists agrees that E = mc2. Nobody says the consensus is that the sun is 93 million miles away. It would never occur to anyone to speak that way (http://www.crichton-official.com/speech-alienscauseglobalwarming.html). This is false. The empirical evidence regarding evolution by common descent is solid and yet evolutionary biologists do refer to the consensus regarding it in response to creationists and IDers.

Figure 2 Response distribution to survey question (2) and the general survey data come from a 2008 Gallop poll (Doran and Zimmerman 2009).

Their results showed that 90% answered risen to (1) and 82% answer yes to (2). Of those who listed climate science as their area of expertise and who published more than 50% of their recent peer reviewed papers in this area, 96.2% (76/79) answered risen to (1) and 97.4% (75/77) to (2).8 One response to such work is So what? We know that there are dissenters with regard to (GW). Why does their opinion not receive differential weighting? One common argument given for dismissing contrarians views has been offered in Ross Gelbspans book The Heat is On (1997). Gelbspan documents how contrarian scientists have been funded by the oil and gas industry and many in this industry have generally been skeptical of (GW).9 The conclusion he reaches is that these contrarians deny (GW) for financial gain and as such they should be ignored.
8

It is interesting to note that amongst meteorologists, those that answered yes to (2) are 64% (23/36). Meterologists however study very different scales than climatologists; we generally do ask not cellular biologists whether the theory of evolution is true.
9

Recently, due to the work of Joseph Romm, the term contrarian has been sometimes replaced with the terms denier and delayer with regard to global climate change. A denier denies the truth or justification for (GW). A delayer accepts (GW) but claims that we are impotent to do anything about it, it would be too expensive, or there are more ethical and/or efficient ways of using our GNPs. Examples of these two positions would be Patrick Michaels and Bjorn Lomborg. A contrarian is typically a denier but some are delayers.

Lets consider one example. Patrick Michaels was a professor of Environmental Science at the University of Virginia. He is affiliated with the George C. Marshall Institute and the Cato Institute both of which are conservative think tanks. Gelbspan and others claim that he has received more than $115,000 from coal and energy interests. A quarterly publication World Climate Review which Michaels founded was funded by the contrarian group Western Fuels. Finally, he was paid $100,000 by the electric utility Intermountain Rural Electric Association which also is contrarian in nature. This is a suggestive argument; however, it is a circumstantial ad hominem. That is, we are conflating the truth of the denial of (GW) and Michaels associations. To correct the Gelbspan argument we would need to show that Michaels denies (GW) because of the money he has received which requires more evidence than Gelbspan has supplied.10 Having said this, one can argue indirectly that contrarians denial of (GW) is indicative of bias. If someone trained in climate science offers arguments whose premises are poorly supported and contrary evidence is commonplace amongst said scientists, then this is evidence that they are distorting the facts. For example, it is common for contrarians to argue that since we cannot successfully predict weather more than twelve days hence, we shouldnt trust the projections of global circulation models. Likewise, many offer alternative explanations of the recent warming such as a solar variability hypothesis. However, in both cases, there are ready responses to these claims with which climate scientists are familiar. For example, some contrarians find locales where temperature data show a decrease in temperatures rather than an increase; however, such isolated data sets are not terribly relevant to the claim that humans are causing an increase in average surface temperatures. Likewise, though the sun has been more
10

I thank Kristin Shrader-Frechette for thoughtful comments on this point. Naomi Oreskes and Erik Conway (2008) attempt to fill in such an argument exploring strategies of the George C. Marshall Institute.

active in the last sixty years than in the last 1150 years, the correlation between solar activity and temperature has disappeared since the 1970s (Usoskin et. al. (2005), Lockwood et. al. (2007)). Hence, an increase in average surface temperature cannot be accounted for by changes in solar activity. IV. Why (and When) Consensus Matters. As I noted above, agreement and dissent are absolutely essential to science. However, contrarians fail to clearly distinguish between two different epistemic communities climate scientists and policymakers. Climate scientists attempt to determine the truth value of (GW) in light of the empirical evidence. However, when policymakers are making decisions in which the truth value of (GW) is relevant, things are importantly different. Why? Because policymakers do not have the relevant expertise in the matters of interest.11 Suppose you are not a climate scientist but are a policymaker; should you believe (GW)? Well, if the majority of climate scientists do believe it and you are in no position to seriously evaluate the evidence on your own, then it seems that you should. Your evidence will not directly involve tree rings, glacial retreat, ice cores, boreholes, satellite measurements, computer simulations, etc. since you dont understand these topics. Rather, you must determine who is a reasonable authority on the issue and form your beliefs in accordance with their

11

Richard Lindzen writes, [N]onscientists generally do not want to bother with understanding the science. Claims of consensus relieve policy types, environmental advocates and politicians of any need to do so. Such claims also serve to intimidate the public and even scientists especially those outside the area of climate dynamics. (http://www.opinionjournal.com/extra/?id=110008597). I am in no position to say whether non-scientists want to understand science or not and consensus claims neednt relieve policymakers from having any need to do so. However, Lindzen does not take seriously the competing claims on policymakers time. Regardless of policymakers scientific aptitudes, how is one to become well-versed in climate change physics, environmental economics, and green technology along with healthcare policy, international terrorism, and so on?

10

opinion.12 Still, as with (C) above, consensus doesnt guarantee a proposition is true, so when is a consensus regarding some proposition like (GW) a reliable indicator of its truth? In order to explore the issue, consider the following simple model. Suppose the probability that every expert i is correct about a proposition P being true or false is ri, for all i, 1 > ri > , and the correctness of a expert js opinion is probabilistically independent of every other expert i. It can be shown that if the majority of n experts believe that P is correct, then the probability of their opinion being correct is greater than ri and that as n increases the probability that they are correct gets larger and larger and in the limit is one. This is an instance of Condorcets jury theorem.13 But there are two problems with applying this model to the climate change case. First, we assume that each expert has the same greater than chance of correctly determining a propositions truth value and this is unlikely. Second, it is unreasonable to assume that each experts judgment is independent of every other statistically speaking. For example, scientists encounter and evaluate much of the same information, utilize similar methods, have shared aims, and may even mimic the opinions of others. In an unpublished manuscript, James Hawthorne has generalized Condorcets Jury Theorem in which these assumptions are relaxed (see Ladha (1992) and Estlund (1994) as well). Lets consider Hawthornes work first and then his response to each of these worries. Hawthornes Condorcet Jury Theorem depends on four factors: number of experts n, the average competence level r, the variance of r, s2, and the covariance of individual competence
12

I should note that this point is not unique to the environmental sciences, far from it. For example, the epistemic justification for many of our beliefs depends on the reliability of authorities (Goldman 1999). For example, most of us could not prove the fundamental theorem of calculus which shows how the differentiation and integration are related. However, in our mathematical work, we presuppose that it is true and can be shown so.
13

Strictly speaking, we must assume n > 2 and is odd. However, the latter simplification can be easily relaxed. I thank Bruce Glymour and an anonymous reviewer for providing useful discussion on Condorcets Jury Theorem and ways of relaxing its assumptions.

11

levels.14 As before, let us consider two mutually exclusive and exhaustive propositions P and Q (though we could generalize even here). The competence level of an expert i with regard to Ps truth is the probability ri that they accept P when P is true Pr[(pi = 1)/P] = ri. Similarly, Pr[(qi = 1)/Q] when i accepts Q. Let n be the total number of experts and so the average competence level is r
n i 1 i

r / n . The variance s2 in r is determined in the usual way. The covariance

measures the association of expert i and js votes, or rji. Formally, rji If j and i vote independently, then rji = rjri since Pr[( p j On the other hand, if rji rjri, then Pr[( p j

Pr[( p j

1 & pi

1) / P] .
1) .

1 & pi 1) / P]

1) / P] Pr( p j Pr( p j

1) Pr( pi

1 & pi

1) Pr( pi

1) . Thus,

rji rj ri measures the degree to which i and j tend to vote in agreement. If rji rj ri

0 , then i has

no influence on j and cov = 0; otherwise, i may have positive or negative influence on j. Finally, as it turns out, n, r, s2, and cov are related by the following equation (where 2 is the variance of expected value of r),
2

[r (1 r ) / n] ( s 2 / n) [(n 1) / n] cov

Let %p =

n i n

pi / n be the fraction of votes for P. When %p > then the majority have voted in

favor of P and if %p < , then the majority have voted for Q. By inspecting the equation above, Pr[(%p > )/P) 1 when n is large, r is greater than , and cov is small; that is, the majority will probably correctly accept P. Hawthornes generalized Condorcet Jury Theorem discharges the above idealizations. First, the theorem depends on the average competence level r and does not require that each ri >
14

Here I use slightly different notation than Hawthorne for exegetical purposes. It is also worth noting he proves several different Condorcet Jury Theorems including one where the distribution of the votes for a proposition k/n where k is the number of votes for the proposition and n is the number voters is normally distributed.

12

or are the same and their variance is expressed by s2. Second, his theorem holds even when cov 0; that is, when experts i and js opinions are dependent provided n or r is relatively large. One important issue to note is that is that probabilistic dependence between voters occurs when the fact that i believes or votes P affects js believing or voting P. The fact that i and j encounter and evaluate the same information, use similar methods, or have common aims does not imply probabilistic dependence. To be clear, I havent argued that the assumptions of the Condorcet model are true of the community of climate scientists. I have attempted to demonstrate that the idealizations that appear to challenge the models applicability can be relaxed and that if the models assumptions were true, then it would be explain why the consensus would be evidence of the truth of (GW). That is, I have provided a how possibly explanation. If the assumptions of Hawthornes Condorcet Jury Theorem were met (and it is not unreasonable to suppose they are), then this would bring about a majority who are likely to be correct. To argue that the Condorcet model provides a how-actually explanation would require a lot more empirical evidence than I have offered. Nevertheless, we see that a majority not even a consensus is likely to be correct about a propositions truth when they are numerous, exhibit better than chance average competence level, and opinions are relatively independent. Not every consensus is truth indicative but some are. If the consensus regarding climate change is truth indicative, then policy-makers should apportion their degrees of belief in (GW) with respect to this consensus. The Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC) is just such an organization that represents this consensus. The IPCC is one of the largest science-related projects ever created. It does not conduct research of its own; rather, it evaluates the work of scientists around the world and then synthesizes this

13

work for policymakers in a report and a summary. The Panel of delegates from 194 countries elect the IPCC Chair and Bureau and governments and organizations nominate experts who are chosen by the Bureau. There are three working groups. Working Group I considers the physical science behind climate change. Working Group II considers the impacts, adaption, and vulnerability due to climate change. Working Group III considers mitigation or how we can reduce the climate change which will occur. Each working group involves Coordinating Lead Authors (CLAs) customarily one is from a developed country and another is from a developing country who coordinate their respect chapters. The Lead Authors (LAs) work in a team to produce the content of their chapters and are supported by a variety of Contributing Authors (CAs) all of whom work primarily in the peer-reviewed literature which is as current as possible. Once the authors prepare a 1st-order draft, it is reviewed by as wide ranging group of experts which are picked on the basis of their expertise or are nominated by governments and organizations and who evaluate the draft on the basis of its accuracy and completeness. The comments themselves are collated by the Technical Support Unit. A 2nd-order draft is written in light of the criticisms along with a first draft of the Summary for Policymakers and is given to expert reviewers and governments when the comments are considered and collated again. The final draft is submitted for acceptance by the Working Group responsible for preparing it as the revised Summary for Policymakers is subject to a line-by-line approval process. Finally, the Panel approves the Summary registering any disagreement.15

15

Each report is subject to one the following evaluations. Approval means that the material has been subjected to line by line discussion and agreement. It is the procedure used for the Summary for Policymakers of the Reports. Adoption is a process of endorsement section by section. It is used for the Synthesis Report and overview chapters of Methodology Reports. Acceptance signifies that the material has not been subject to line by line nor section by section discussion and agreement, but nevertheless presents a comprehensive, objective and balanced view of the subject matter. (http://www.ipcc.ch/organization/organization_procedures.htm)

14

As we can see, each IPCC assessment involving enormous numbers of scientists. The IPCC Fourth Assessment Report (AR4) included more than 2500 scientific expert reviewers, more than 800 contributing authors, and more than 450 lead authors. Of these, the Working Group 1 report (including the summary for policy makers) included contributions by 600 authors from 40 countries, and over 620 expert reviewers, a large number of government reviewers, and representatives from 113 governments. It should also be noted that the IPCC is not the only organization who have stated that humans are having an effect on our climate through greenhouse gas emissions. The American Academy of Science, the American Meteorological Association, the American Geophysical Union, and the American Association for the Advancement of Science have issued similar statements.16 So, here is one way consensus matters consensus matters amongst experts when it is the reliable indicator of the truth of a proposition which is relevant to the decisions of policymakers. A consensus is reliable indicator of truth when it occurs amongst a majority which is sufficiently large, where the average competence level is greater than chance, and where the experts generally vote their understanding of the best evidence. Scientific consensus, contrary to contrarians, does not threaten the process of science. Dissent is crucial for as we say normal science. Contrarians should continue their criticism and battle it out in peer reviewed journals (which they generally do not do). However, when it comes to non-expert opinion and specifically environmental policy, consensus matters a lot. This point simply pivots on drawing a distinction
16

Stephen Gardiner has argued in conversation that the opinions of the IPCC are often more conservative than basic climate science would suggest. This is due in large part to the very nature of how agreement amongst actors is produced. If this is correct, then the IPCC will often understate the seriousness of global climate change impacts. On this point, Timothy Flannery writes, Yet in spite of the IPCCs faults, its assessment reports, which are issued every five years, carry weight with the media and government precisely because they represent a consensus view. If the IPCC says something, you had better believe it and then allow for the likelihood that things are far worse than it says they are (2006, 246).

15

between the epistemic community of scientists and that of policymakers. When Michael Crichton writes, When did skeptic become a dirty word in science? When did a skeptic require quotation marks around it? he clearly is confusing the two.17 V. Conclusion. In this essay, I have presented the contrarians argument against consensus science. Second, I argued that we should distinguish between those beliefs or degrees of belief of scientists themselves or policy-makers. Third, I argued that policy-makers should form their beliefs or degrees of belief in accordance with climate scientists themselves reflecting the consensus position that is well-documented. Bibliography Crichton, M. (2003) Aliens cause global warming, http://www.crichton-official.com/speechalienscauseglobalwarming.html. Doran, P. T. and M. Kendall Zimmerman (2009) Examining the Scientific Consensus on Climate Change, EOS, Transactions of the American Geophysical Union 90: 22. Estlund, D. (1994) 1994.Opinion Leaders, Independence, and Condorcets Jury Theorem. Theory and Decision 36:131 162. Flannery, T. (2006) The Weather Makers. Atlantic Monthly Press. Gelbspan, R. (1997) The Heat is On: High Stakes Battle Over Earths Climate. Harper Collins. Goldman, A. (1999) Knowledge in a Social World, Oxford: Oxford University Press. Hawthorne, J. (Unpublished) Voting in Search of the Public Good: the Probabilistic Logic of Majority Judgments Horner, C. (2007) A Politically Incorrect Guide to Global Warming (and Environmentalism). Regnery Publishing, Inc. Hull, D. L. (1988) Science as a Process: An Evolutionary Account of the Social and Conceptual Development of Science Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
17

http://www.crichton-official.com/speech-alienscauseglobalwarming.html.

16

Keane, C. M., and C. M. Martinez (Eds.) (2007), Directory of Geoscience Departments 2007, 45th ed., Am. Geol. Inst., Alexandria, Va. Kitcher, P. (1993) The Advancement of Science Oxford: Oxford University Press. Ladha, K. (1992) The Condorcet Jury Theorem, Free Speech, and Correlated Votes, American Journal of Political Science, 36: 617-634. Lockwood, M. and C. Frolich (2007) Recent oppositely directed trends in solar climate forcings and the global mean surface air temperature, Proc. R. Soc. A doi:10.1098/rspa.2007.1880, Published online. Oreskes, N. (2004) The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change, Science 306: 1686. _____. (2007) The Scientific Consensus on Climate Change: How Do We Know Were Not Wrong? in Joseph F. DiMento, Pamela Doughman, Climate Change. MIT Press Oreskes, N. and E. Conway (2008) Challenging Knowledge: How Climate Science Became a Victim of the Cold War in Robert Proctor and Londa Schiebinger, Agnotology: The Makign and Unmaking of Ignorance. Stanford University Press. Pielke, Jr., R. (2005) Consensus about climate change? Science, 308: 952-953. Usoskin, I. G.; M. Schssler, S. K. Solanki, and K. Mursula (2005) Solar activity over the last 1150 years: does it correlate with climate? Proceedings of the 13th Cambridge Workshop on Cool Stars, Stellar Systems and the Sun, (eds.) by F. Favata, G. A. J. Hussain, and B. Battrick, ESA SP-560, European Space Agency.

You might also like